You are on page 1of 13

Darrin M.

McMahon

From the happiness of virtue


to the virtueof happiness:
400 b.c.–a.d. 1780

I t is only right that Dædalus should de- “By the principle of utility is meant that
principle which approves or disapproves
vote an issue to happiness, seeing that
its publisher was chartered with the of every action whatsoever, according to
“end and design” of cultivating “every the tendency which it appears to have to
art and science which may tend to ad- augment or diminish the happiness of
vance the interest, honour, dignity, and the party whose interest is in question,”
happiness of a free, independent, and he was merely giving voice to what was
virtuous people.” already an eighteenth-century common-
Its publisher, of course, is the Ameri- place. To many enlightened souls on
can Academy of Arts and Sciences, both sides of the Atlantic, the need to
founded in 1780 at a time when Ameri- promote happiness had assumed the
cans–newly independent and free– status of a self-evident truth.
were demanding that their institutions, That this truth, for all its self-evidence,
like their government, serve a purpose, was a relatively recent discovery–the
that they be useful. And to many eigh- product, give or take a decade, of the
teenth-century minds, there was simply preceding one hundred years–is im-
no better test of usefulness than ‘utili- portant. For though happiness itself
ty’–the property of promoting happi- already possessed a long history by the
ness. The English philosopher Jeremy eighteenth century, the idea that insti-
Bentham is often credited with ½rst ar- tutions should be expected to promote
ticulating the creed. But when he ob- it–and that people should expect to re-
served in 1776 in his lawyerly prose that ceive it, in this life–was a tremendous
novelty.
It involved nothing less than a revolu-
Darrin M. McMahon is Ben Weider Associate tion in human expectations, while rais-
Professor of European History at Florida State ing, in turn, a delicate question. Just
University. He is the author of “Enemies of the who, precisely, was worthy of happi-
Enlightenment: The French Counter-Enlighten- ness? Was it ½t for all? Was happiness
ment and the Making of Modernity” (2001) and a right or a reward? And what, for that
the forthcoming “Happiness: A History” (2005). matter, did the curious word really
mean?
© 2004 by the American Academy of Arts The answers to such questions take us
& Sciences to the heart of an eighteenth-century

Dædalus Spring 2004 5


Darrin M. contradiction that remains with us to self-evident truth than a truth unexam-
McMahon the present day. ined, one that seemingly required no evi-
on
happiness dence at all.
I t may already have been noted that im- It was Aristotle, in the fourth century
b.c.e., who ½rst put the matter most
plicit in the few lines from the Acade-
my’s charter is another central assump- forcefully. Happiness, he expounded at
tion regarding happiness, though in this length in the Nichomachean Ethics, is an
case the assumption is far older than the “activity of the soul that expresses vir-
eighteenth century. If we leave aside for tue.” For Aristotle, all things in the uni-
now the meaning of “interest, honour, verse have a purpose, a function, an end
and dignity,” we can see most clearly (telos). And that end, he says, is what
that the Academy is asked not simply to gives expression to the highest nature
cultivate every art and science that ad- and calling of the thing. In the famous
vances happiness, but every art and sci- example, the noble end of the acorn is to
ence that advances the happiness of a become a thriving oak, and in the same
“free, independent, and virtuous peo- way the function of the harpist is to play
ple.” The people in question are the the harp (and of the excellent harpist to
citizens of the United States. And the play it well).
implicit assumption is that those living But can we say that there is a function
in bondage or sin are not worthy of speci½c to human beings in general?
happiness. In light of the fact that slav- Aristotle believes that we can, and he
ery was long considered but a species identi½es it as reason. Reason is what
of sin, and freedom but a product of liv- distinguishes us from plants, nonhuman
ing well, I want to focus solely on the animals, and nonliving things, and so
remaining term–virtue–sketching in our purpose must involve its fruitful cul-
what follows a genealogy of its close tivation. Living a life according to reason
links to happiness. is for Aristotle the human function, and
The belief in the intimate association living an excellent life–reasoning well
of happiness and virtue was widely throughout its course and acting accord-
shared in the eighteenth century. The ingly–is for him a virtuous life. Achiev-
same man who coupled liberty and the ing such a life will bring us happiness,
pursuit of happiness so closely in the which thus represents our highest call-
Declaration of Independence could later ing, our ultimate purpose, the ½nal
state without equivocation that “Happi- end to which all others are necessarily
ness is the aim of life, but virtue is the subordinate.
foundation of happiness.” Jefferson’s Happiness for Aristotle is not a fleet-
collaborator on the draft of the Declara- ing feeling or an ephemeral passion. It
tion and an early member of the Ameri- is, rather, the product of a life well lived,
can Academy, Benjamin Franklin, simi- the summation of a full, flourishing exis-
larly observed in 1776 that “virtue and tence, sustained to the end of one’s days,
happiness are mother and daughter.” “a complete life.”
This assumption had for many the status It follows naturally enough that Aris-
of a received truth. But the evidence for totle affords at least some place to the
it was not at all recent. role of fortune–chance–in influencing
On the contrary, it had accumulated our happiness. For no one would count a
so steadily, so imperceptibly over the man happy, he acknowledges, “who suf-
course of centuries as to become less a fered the worst evils and misfortunes.”

6 Dædalus Spring 2004


To do so would be to defend a “philoso- ness. To fall from divine favor–or to fall The history
pher’s paradox.” under the influence of an evil spirit–was of happiness
In conceding this role to chance as a to be dysdaimon or kakodaimon–‘unhap-
determinant of happiness, Aristotle, on py’ (dys/kako=bad), or more colorfully,
the one hand, is simply admitting with ‘in the shit,’ a not altogether inappro-
his characteristic level-headedness the priate play on the Greek kakka (shit/
limits on our ability to determine our turds).2 In a world governed by super-
fate. In a world of uncertainty, anything natural forces, human happiness was a
might happen before the end–a truth, plaything of the gods, a spiritual force
Aristotle af½rms, that is well captured beyond our control. When viewed
in the celebrated phrase of the legislator through mortal eyes, the world’s hap-
Solon, “Call no man happy until he is penings–and so our happiness–could
dead.” Yet on the other hand, by seek- only appear random, a function of
ing to circumscribe the role of chance chance.
in the ½rst place–to cow it into submis- Central to the outlook of Hesiod and
sion by virtue’s superior force–Aris- Homer, with strong echoes in many of
totle was also participating in a much the lamentations of Greek tragedy, this
broader philosophical shift, one that conception of happiness would prove
directly challenged Solon’s ancient remarkably stubborn. We need only
wisdom. think of the word itself: in every Indo-
In order to fully appreciate this chal- European language, the modern words
lenge, it is helpful to look for a moment for happiness, as they took shape in the
at the principal word in ancient Greek late Middle Ages and early Renaissance,
for happiness, eudaimonia, one of a con- are all cognate with luck. And so we get
stellation of closely related terms that ‘happiness’ from the early Middle Eng-
includes eutychia (lucky), olbios (blessed; lish (and Old Norse) happ–chance, for-
favored), and makarios (blessed; happy; tune, what happens in the world–and the
blissful).1 In some ways encompassing Mittelhochdeutsch Glück, still the modern
the meaning of all of these terms, eudai- German word for happiness and luck.
mon (happy) literally signi½es ‘good spir- There is the Old French heur (luck;
it’ or ‘good god,’ from eu=good and dai- chance), root of bonheur (happiness),
mon=demon/spirit. In colloquial terms, and heureux (happy); and the Portuguese
to be eudaimon was to be lucky, for in a felicidade, the Spanish felicidad, and the
world fraught with constant upheaval, Italian felicità–all derived ultimately
uncertainty, and privation, to have a from the Latin felix for luck (sometimes
good spirit working on one’s behalf was
the ultimate mark of good fortune. Even 2 The kak- root (bad) in Greek bears no direct
linguistic relationship to the kakk- root (caca;
more it was a mark of divine favor, for turds). Yet the classical Greeks used kak- words
the gods, it was believed, worked as generic forms of cursing to signify ‘damn,’
through the daimones, emissaries and or perhaps even more strongly, ‘oh shit,’ thus
conductors of their will. And this, in the rendering the pun plausible if not immediately
pre-Socratic world, was the key to happi- apparent in formal terms. I am grateful to Jef-
frey Henderson of Boston University for shar-
1 On this subject, see Cornelius de Heer, ing his expertise on this matter. On the Greek
Makar, Eudaimon, Olbios, Eutychia: A Study of penchant for such punning in general, see Hen-
the Semantic Field Denoting Happiness in Ancient derson’s wonderful The Maculate Muse: Obscene
Greek to the End of the Fifth Century b.c. (Am- Language in Attic Comedy, 2nd ed. (New York:
sterdam: Adolf M. Hakkert, 1969). Oxford University Press, 1991).

Dædalus Spring 2004 7


Darrin M. fate). Happiness, in a word, is what hap- come what may. Happiness is a function
McMahon
on pens to us. If we no longer say that we of the will, not of external forces. And
happiness are kakodaimon when things don’t go so, extending this logic to its end point,
our way, we still sometimes acknowl- Cicero is able to conclude that even the
edge, rather more prosaically, that “shit most extreme physical suffering should
happens.” not thwart the happiness of the true
Despite this linguistic tenacity, most Stoic sage. “Happiness . . . will not trem-
people today are probably uncomfort- ble, however much it is tortured.” The
able with the idea that happiness might good man can be happy even on the
lie in the roll of the dice. And at least rack.
part of the reason for that uneasiness
can be traced to Aristotle and his central
contention that our behavior is the larg-
L ike Aristotle, the great majority of the
founding fathers of both the American
est single factor in determining our hap- Republic and the American Academy
piness. Taking his cue from both Soc- would likely have dismissed such talk
rates and Plato before him, Aristotle as the defense of a philosopher’s para-
avowed faith in human agency, in our dox. Yet in its very exaggeration the ex-
ability to control our fortune by control- ample illustrates perfectly the wider–
ling our actions and responses to the and widely shared–classical view that
happenings of the world. happiness and pain were by no means
Aristotle’s efforts, in this regard, were mutually exclusive.4 Happiness itself
part of a much broader movement to was not a function of feeling, but a
ensure the inviolability of a flourishing function of virtue. And as such it fre-
life in the face of external contingency quently required denial, sacri½ce, even
and chance. As Martha Nussbaum has suffering. To anyone in the eighteenth
shown, Greek culture of the fourth and century who had received a classical
½fth centuries b.c.e., in fact, was ob- education–which is to say, the vast
sessed with precisely this dilemma: how majority of educated men and wom-
to ensure happiness despite what may en–this was a powerful set of received
happen to us, despite the unpredictability assumptions.
of luck.3 And of course Cicero and Epictetus
The same question continued to pre- were not the only sources of the assump-
occupy the Romans, and indeed it is the tion that happiness sometimes required
response of the Stoic philosophers Cic- suffering, since a very different sort of
ero and Epictetus that best illustrates the man had also equated happiness with
extent of that new faith in human agen- pain. That man was Jesus Christ, and his
cy. Whereas Aristotle and others had left instrument of torture, his rack, was the
at least some room for the play of chance cross.
in determining happiness, Cicero and Admittedly, the image of a mutilated
Epictetus attempted to rule out its influ- corpse, suspended by nails from planks
ence altogether. If the man of virtue is of wood, and surrounded by weeping
the happy man, they argued, then the women, does not call happiness immedi-
man of perfect virtue should be happy ately to mind. One will certainly be for-
3 See Martha C. Nussbaum, The Fragility of
Goodness: Luck and Ethics in Greek Tragedy and 4 This, I would argue, is true even of Epicure-
Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University anism, although the case is certainly complicat-
Press, 1986). ed. For more on Epicurus, see below.

8 Dædalus Spring 2004


given for harboring similar reservations direct connection to the gods. More The history
of happiness
about the religious tradition that grew importantly, it was the word that had
up around this lugubrious symbol. With already been chosen by the authors of
reason, it might seem, has Christianity the Septuagint, the Greek translation of
been called the worship of sorrow. the Jewish Bible (the Christian Old Tes-
And yet, we need only recall Christ’s tament), in their rendering of the classi-
frequent injunction to “rejoice and be cal Hebrew beatitudes, the so-called
glad” to appreciate that the appeal of Ashrel. As Thomas Carlyle was later
this new faith lay in more than simply moved to observe, “There is something
its invitation to take part in the suffering higher than happiness, and that is bless-
and sacri½ce of its central founder. The edness.”
promise of redemption through suffer- The authors of the New Testament
ing–and the promise of a happiness beatitudes would certainly have agreed.
greater than could ever be imagined on Here is Matthew:
Earth–animated the tradition from the
outset. Blessed [beati/makarios] are the poor in
Consider, for example, the nature of spirit, for theirs is the kingdom of heav-
Christ’s promise in the Gospels, and par- en.
ticularly the ringing good news of the Blessed are those who mourn, for they will
Sermon on the Mount and the Sermon be comforted.
on the Plain as recorded, respectively, by Blessed are the meek, for they will inherit
Matthew and Luke in the second half of the earth. . . .
the ½rst century a.d. Blessed are those who hunger and thirst
Each begins with a series of ‘beati- for righteousness, for they will be ½lled.
tudes,’ so named because of the Vul- Blessed are the merciful, for they will
gate translation of the Greek term with receive mercy.
which they open. Beati in Latin, makarios Blessed are the pure in heart, for they will
in Greek–the terms are often rendered see God.
in English as ‘blessed,’ although ‘happy’ Blessed are the peacemakers, for they will
would serve equally well, as indeed it be called children of God.
does in some English and various other Blessed are those who are persecuted for
translations, such as in French, where righteousness’s sake, for theirs is the
heureux from the Old French heur is used kingdom of heaven.
in the cannon. What is critical, though, (Matthew 5:3–11)
is the original Greek term itself–criti- And here is Luke:
cal, on the one hand, in that the term is
not eudaimon, a word that any educated Blessed [beati/makarios] are you who are
speaker of Greek in the ½rst century poor, for yours is the kingdom of God.
would have immediately associated with Blessed are you who are hungry now, for
the tradition of classical philosophy; but you will be ½lled.
critical, on the other, in that makarios Blessed are you who weep now, for you
was itself a term employed frequently will laugh.
by classical authors, including Aristotle Blessed are you when people hate you and
and Plato, to signify ‘happy’ or ‘blessed.’ when they exclude you, revile you, and
More exalted than eudaimon, without the defame you on account of the Son of
same emphasis on chance, makarios sig- Man.
ni½ed an even loftier state, implying a

Dædalus Spring 2004 9


Darrin M. Rejoice in that day and leap for joy, for “Call no man happy until he is dead.”
McMahon
on
surely your reward is great in heaven. In the Christian account, happiness was
happiness (Luke 6:20–22) death–a proposition that dealt a power-
ful blow to the vagaries of earthly for-
Much, of course, could be said about
tune, while at the same time transform-
these curious passages, now nearly two
ing the end of human life from a bound-
thousand years old. But let it suf½ce here
ary into a gateway. Whereas in the classi-
to emphasize the promise of imminent
cal account, happiness encompassed the
reward for those living virtuously in the
span of a lifetime, Christian beatitude
here and now. The merciful, the pure in
was in½nite. And whereas classical hap-
heart, the meek–all who pursue justice
piness remained a comparatively cere-
and the way of the Lord–will be given
bral affair–cool, deliberative, rational,
their due, granted mercy, a direct audi-
balanced–Christian happiness was un-
ence with God, intimacy in his family,
abashedly sensual in its imagined ecsta-
and the rich legacy of his kingdom. The
sies. Feeling, intense feeling, was what
hungry shall be ½lled, the mournful shall
flowed forth with Christ’s blood, trans-
laugh, their gifts will be great in heaven.
formed in the miracle of the Eucharist
And though all are enjoined to rejoice
from the fruit of intense pain to the
now in this expectation–to “leap for
sweet nectar of rapture.
joy”–this is essentially a proleptic hap-
And yet, for all their essential differ-
piness, a happiness of the future, what
ences, there were important similarities
Augustine would later call the “happi-
between the classical and Christian con-
ness of hope.”
ceptions. In each tradition, happiness
This Christian conception was tremen- remained an exalted state, a precious
reward for great sacri½ce, commitment,
dously powerful. For the happiness
and pain. The consummation, the
promised in the beatitudes, and subse-
crowning glory of a well-lived life, hap-
quently elaborated in Christian tradi-
piness would be granted only to the wor-
tion, was at once speci½c in its sugges-
thy, the virtuous, the god-like happy few.
tions of rich reward and extremely, luxu-
As Christianity was fused ever closer
riantly vague. Here the imagination
with the intellectual inheritance of the
could be set free to revel in the delights
classical pagan authors, these similari-
of the kingdom of God, to fantasize the
ties were only strengthened. It is no co-
total ful½llment that would justify one’s
incidence that when Augustine put pen
earthly pains. All the milk and honey of
to paper shortly after his conversion to
Jewish deliverance was joined to a new
Christianity in 386, he entitled his ½rst
prospect of ecstatic, erotic communion
work De Beata Vita, The blessed or happy
with God, of gazing lovingly into his
life. True, he treats there the theme that
eyes, “face to face,” as the Apostle Paul
he would develop with such eloquence
had promised. The words themselves–
in the Confessions and The City of God–
release, rapture, passion, bliss–are re-
that perfect happiness, in this life, is sim-
vealing. Whether in heaven or the New
ply not possible, because of original sin.
Jerusalem, the happiness of paradise
Nonetheless, the work is a classical dia-
would be entire and eternal, endless
logue, with a message bearing the deep
and complete.
imprint of Plato and Cicero: that the
Even better, the beati½c vision offered
“search for higher happiness, not merely
a seductive rejoinder to Solon’s saying
its actual attainment, is a prize beyond

10 Dædalus Spring 2004


all human wealth or honor or physical “the pleasure of profligates,” but rather The history
of happiness
pleasure.”5 Augustine’s continual assur- the simple satisfaction of a mind and
ance that although “we do not enjoy a body at peace. This was a message that
present happiness” we can “look for- less severe Christians could ½nd amena-
ward to happiness in the future with ble. And with the changing attitudes to-
steadfast endurance,” kept this once ward pleasure that bubbled up from the
classical, now Christian, end directly in twelfth-century ‘renaissance’ through
the sights of all who wandered as pil- the Rinascimento itself, increasing num-
grims on the deserts of life. bers of them did.
One could make similar observations The fact is important, for it highlights
with respect to various other pillars of a tension that had existed in the Chris-
church doctrine, citing Boethius, say, tian conception of happiness from the
from his influential sixth-century De start. On the one hand an earthly exis-
Consolatione Philosophiae, in which he tence that demanded denial and renun-
repeatedly insists that the “entire thrust ciation, the embrace of suffering as imi-
of the human will as directed to various tatio Christi and the just deserts for origi-
pursuits is to hasten towards happi- nal sin. And on the other, the promise
ness.” And of course there is Aquinas, of a reward that was often pleasurable–
who in stitching the rediscovered clas- sensual–in the extreme. Heaven may
sics of Aristotle–and particularly the always have seemed a paradise, but be-
Nichomachean Ethics–into the tapestry ginning in the thirteenth century, its lux-
of the medieval church ensured that uries achieved new levels in the Chris-
Aristotle’s highest end would endure, tian imagination. “In that ½nal happi-
with only minor alterations, as the ness every human desire will be ful½lled,”
Christian telos for centuries to come. Aquinas observes in the Summa against
By the end of the Renaissance, in fact, the Gentiles, and men and women will
Christianity and classicism had grown know “perfect pleasure,” the “perfect
so closely intertwined on the subject of delight of the senses,” to say nothing
happiness that works of Christian Sto- of those of the mind. No pleasure, no
icism, Christian Platonism, Christian pleasure at all, would be lacking–even,
Aristotelianism, and even Christian Epi- Aquinas speci½ed (to the later delight of
cureanism tackled the subject in depth.6 Nietzsche) the pleasure of enjoying oth-
The existence particularly of Christian ers’ pain. Beati in regno coelesti videbunt
Epicurean tracts on happiness may seem poenas damnatorum, ut beatitude illis
odd, even a contradiction in terms. Yet it magis compleaceat. The saved would
is too often forgotten that Epicurus him- feast on the sight of the sufferings of
self was an unimpeachable ascetic who the damned.
taught that “genuine pleasure” was not
C reative speculation on the Christian
5 This is a phrase from Cicero’s lost manu- meaning of happiness multiplied during
script, Hortensius, which Augustine knew well. the High Renaissance. In works like
See Henry Chadwick, Augustine, Past Masters Lorenzo Valla’s On Pleasure (1431) and
series (Oxford and New York: Oxford Univer- the monk Celso Maffei’s Pleasing Expla-
sity Press, 1986), 24.
nation of the Sensuous Pleasures of Paradise
6 See Charles Trinkhaus, Adversity’s Noblemen: (1504), to name only two, little was left
The Italian Humanists on Happiness (New York: to the imagination, with accounts brim-
Columbia University Press, 1940). ming over with the delights that awaited

Dædalus Spring 2004 11


Darrin M. the faithful in the world to come.7 Clas- rible violence of the ensuing Religious
McMahon
on sical descriptions of Elysium, the Blessed Wars did little to minimize pain. Yet it
happiness Isles, and the pagan Golden Age were should also be stressed that for all their
freely adapted to give spice to the after- emphasis on human depravity, Calvin
life, as were Christians’ own accounts of and Luther were by no means ill dis-
the Paradise before the Fall, where, as posed to pleasure. The damned might
Augustine had stressed, “true joy [had] well be “vessels of wrath,” in Calvin’s
flowed perpetually from God.” The Re- words, but for those in whom the work-
naissance imagination thus ranged freely ings of grace could be detected, the
forward to the joys that would come, joys of the new Adam were at hand.
and backward to those that had been. As Luther felt moved to observe in
But the impulse to do so in such graphic his preface to St. Paul’s Letter to the
detail clearly came from the present. The Romans:
imagined pleasures beyond, that is, were
This kind of trust in and knowledge
a reflection of the greater acceptance of
of God’s grace makes a person joyful,
pleasure in the here and now.
con½dent, and happy with regard to
The reasons for such a broad shift are
God and all creatures. This is what the
of course complex. But in terms of ideas,
Holy Spirit does by faith.
an important place must be given to
Aquinas and his fellow Christian Aris- Calvin, for his part, observed in the Insti-
totelians. For by de-emphasizing the tutes of the Christian Religion that God’s
total, vitiating effects of original sin, grace was the alchemy that could trans-
and emphasizing the place of virtue as form human misery–including poverty,
man’s telos, they carved out a space for wretchedness, exile, ignominy, impris-
cultivating and improving earthly life. onment, and contempt–into gold.
To be sure, perfect happiness (beatitudo “When the favor of God breathes upon
perfecto) would still come only with us, there is none of these things which
death by grace. But in the meantime, may not turn out to our happiness.”8
one could prepare for it by cultivating The trick of course was to be certain of
imperfect happiness (felicitas or beatitudo God’s grace and forgiveness, a certainty
imperfecto) along the ladder that led to that in theory at least could never be
human perfection. It was by climbing– had. But as Max Weber famously ob-
pulling oneself upward–on the heights served, one could always be on the look-
of just such a liberal theology that Chris- out for signs. Did it not make sense to
tian humanists like Erasmus and Thom- see earthly happiness as an indication
as More were able to conceive of an that one might be headed in the direc-
earthly existence that was rather more tion of everlasting content? Not only
than a vale of tears. fortune was evidence of good fortune.
In some respects, it is true, the Protes- The ability to take pleasure in the won-
tant Reformation–with its recovery of a
dour, Augustinian theology of sin–tend- 8 On the subject of happiness in Calvin’s
ed to put a damper on this open indul- thought, see Heiko A. Oberman, “The Pursuit
gence of pleasure. And certainly the ter- of Happiness: Calvin between Humanism
and Reformation,” in Humanity and Divinity in
7 See the concise account in Colleen McDan- Renaissance and Reformation: Essays in Honor of
nell and Bernhard Lang, Heaven: A History (New Charles Trinkaus, ed. John W. O’Malley, Thomas
Haven: Yale University Press, 2001), esp. chap. M. Izbicki, and Gerald Christianson (Leiden,
5, “The Pleasures of Renaissance Paradise.” The Netherlands: E. J. Brill, 1993).

12 Dædalus Spring 2004


ders of God’s creation was also an en- after,” rendering “a man’s condition The history
of happiness
couraging sign. happy, safe, and sure,” emphasized the
In this respect, it is fair to say that just Puritan millenarian Thomas Brooks.12
as Epicurus was hardly epicurean, Prot- By the time of the Restoration, even
estants and Puritans were much less pu- High Church authors were penning pop-
ritanical than is often supposed. The ular tracts on the art of contentment, as
sanctioning of sexual pleasure within if to give credence to an earlier author’s
marriage, the “af½rmation of ordinary claim that “happinesse is the language
life” entailed in the enjoinder to seek of all.” “We must look through all things
God in all things, and the constant re- upon happinesse,” this author observed,
minder that the Creator’s perfect cre- “and through happinesse upon all
ation appeared ugly only to those who things.”13
saw it through sinful eyes–all this went
some way toward establishing the prop-
osition that pleasure might be taken as a
The claims of these seventeenth-centu-
ry British divines bring us very close to
sign of grace, that happiness might be a the truly momentous proposition that
direct reflection of the virtuous Chris- pleasure and happiness might be consid-
tian soul.9 ered good in and of themselves. And it
Thus, the Reverend Thomas Coleman, should not surprise us that one of the
preaching before the English Parliament ½rst authors to entertain this bold sug-
on August 30, 1643, likened his country- gestion–John Locke–evolved directly
men’s struggle against Charles I to the out of this same religious milieu.
ancient Israelites’ “long pursuit of hap- The son of a Puritan who had fought
pinesse,” arguing that they might be for Cromwell in the English Civil War,
con½dent in attaining their end.10 It was Locke himself, to be sure, was no or-
a felicitous phrase, and in the coming thodox Calvinist. And whatever insight
years Englishmen of a variety of persua- he may have gleaned from Christian
sions employed it regularly, echoing the sources regarding happiness was no
conviction of the author of the 1641 tract doubt amply supplemented by his im-
The Way to Happiness on Earth that this mersion in Newtonian science and his
was where our journey began.11 “The understanding of Epicurus (as inter-
being in a state of Grace will yield . . .
both a Heaven here, and Heaven here- 12 Thomas Brooks, Heaven on Earth, or, A Seri-
ous Discourse Touching a Well-Grounded Assurance
9 The phrase “af½rmation of ordinary life” of Men’s Everlasting Happiness and Blessedness
is that of Charles Taylor, The Sources of the Self: (London: Printed for John Hancock, Senior and
The Making of Modern Identity (Cambridge, Junior, 1657), preface.
Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1989).
13 Richard Holdsworth, The Peoples Happinesse.
10 Thomas Coleman, The Christian’s Course A Sermon Preached in St. Maries in Cambridge,
and Complaint, Both in the Pursuit of Happinesse Upon Sunday the 27 of March, Being the Day of His
Desired, and for Advantages Slipped in that Pur- Majesties Happy Inauguration (Cambridge: Roger
suit: A Sermon Preached to the Honorable House Daniel, 1642), 2, 5–6. Holdsworth was master
of Commons on the Monthly Fast Day, August 30, of Emanuel College and vice chancellor of the
1643 (London: Christopher Meredith, 1643). university. Richard Allestree’s The Art of Con-
tentment (Oxford: At the Theater, 1675) went
11 Robert Crofts, The Way to Happinesse on through over twenty editions and was still in
Earth Concerning Riches, Honour, Conjugall Love, print in the nineteenth century. Allestree, a
Eating, Drinking (London: Printed for G. H., leading royalist divine, was the provost of
1641). Eaton.

Dædalus Spring 2004 13


Darrin M. preted by the French priest Pierre Gas- sumption. Moral sense theorists like
McMahon
on sendi, whose writings Locke studied Frances Hutcheson and Jean-Jacques
happiness closely). Quite rightly, as a consequence, Burlamaqui shared it, as did the Uni-
historians have long emphasized the lat- tarian Joseph Priestly and the psycholo-
ter influences in shaping Locke’s work, gist David Hartley. David Hume main-
particularly the Essay Concerning Human tained as much, right alongside the
Understanding (1689), in which he pres- French philosophers Helvétius and
ents his celebrated conception of the Condillac and the Italian legal theorist
mind as a tabula rasa, born without in- Cesare Beccaria. And of course there
nate ideas or the corruptions of original was Bentham with his felici½c calculus
sin, animated by sensations of pleasure of pleasure and pain, to say nothing of
and pain. Jefferson and Franklin.
In the famous chapter “Power” in All of these men, as it happens, were
book 2 of that work, Locke uses the deeply indebted to Locke’s Essay. But by
phrase “the pursuit of happiness” no the second half of the eighteenth centu-
fewer than four times. And he indeed ry, even many who were not tended to
employs a variety of Newtonian meta- share its key assumptions.14 The anony-
phors–stones that fall, tennis balls hit mous author of True Pleasure, Chearful-
by racquets, and billiard balls struck by ness, and Happiness, The Immediate Conse-
cues–to describe the ways in which quence of Religion, published in Philadel-
human beings are propelled, and propel phia in 1767, gave no evidence of having
themselves, through the space of their read the wise Mr. Locke. But he un-
lives. The force that moves them, we doubtedly believed with him that God
learn, the power that draws them near, delighted to see his creatures happy,
is the desire for happiness, which acts and that pleasure itself was a very good
through the gravitational push and pull thing. Christ, he argued, was a ‘Happy
of pleasure and pain. We are drawn by Christ,’ who had revealingly performed
the one and repulsed by the other, and it his ½rst miracle at a wedding, where not
is right that this is so. For in Locke’s di- coincidentally there was feasting, danc-
vinely orchestrated universe, pleasure is ing, and ample wine. The heavenly
providential; it is a foretaste of the good- Father, surely, did not frown on mirth;
ness of a God who desires the happiness he smiled fondly upon it.
of his creatures. “Pleasure in us,” it fol- This author was probably more upbeat
lows, “is that we call good, and what is than most. But he was not alone in pro-
apt to produce pain in us, we call evil.” claiming earthly happiness to be a direct
And happiness in its full extent is simply consequence of religion. By the latter
“the utmost pleasure we are capable of.” part of the late eighteenth century, in
Here, then, was the monumental for- fact, Christian writers on both sides of
mulation. Redeeming pleasure, it un- the Atlantic–Protestant and Catholic
abashedly coupled good feeling with alike–were churning out works that
the good. made precisely this claim, arguing that
Its influence on the eighteenth cen-
tury was profound. There was virtue 14 On the importance of Locke and the prima-
cy of pleasure in the eighteenth century, see
in pleasure, Locke’s readers came to be- Roy Porter, “Enlightenment Pleasure,” in Plea-
lieve, and pleasure in virtue. Being good sure in the Eighteenth Century, ed. Roy Porter and
meant feeling good. Arguably, there was Marie Mulvey Roberts (New York: New York
no more widespread Enlightenment as- University Press, 1996).

14 Dædalus Spring 2004


Christianity was an excellent means to a able to shield themselves for so long The history
of happiness
much coveted earthly end. In this way, from an uncomfortable truth. Namely,
religion itself took part in the great Utili- as Immanuel Kant would point out with
tarian current that swept the century, such force at the end of the century, that
sweeping up all things in its midst. And “making a man happy [was] quite differ-
if happiness and pleasure–good feeling ent from making him good.” Kant, writ-
and amusement–were now expected ing in the Groundwork of the Metaphysics
even of religion in this life, they could be of Morals (1785), used the term ‘happy’
required of most anything. Increasingly in its eighteenth-century sense, as plea-
they were, making unprecedented de- sure or good feeling–and clearly he was
mands on places, professions, laws, re- right. For if the proposition that doing
lationships, governments, scienti½c good (living virtuously) meant feeling
academies–even essays on happiness, good (being happy) was always debat-
of which there were more written in the able, it was far more dubious still that
eighteenth century than in any previous feeling good meant being good. Virtue,
age. Kant reaf½rmed, with an air of common
sense, was sometimes painful. And those
I t bears repeating how radical this who were happy, who felt good, were
sometimes bad.
transformation was. For henceforth reli-
gion would be asked not only to serve He might easily have added that by the
salvation, but to serve what in a secular- logic of the pleasure/pain calculus, not
izing culture was treated ever more like only was it good to feel good, but it was
an end in itself: earthly happiness. Al- bad to feel bad. Sadness, by this mea-
ready in the early nineteenth century sure, would be a sin, and those who ex-
Tocqueville could point out that when perienced it would justly feel guilty for
listening to American preachers it was doing so. It may be that in our own day
dif½cult to be sure “whether the main we are close to this point. But in the
object of religion is to procure eternal eighteenth century, the proposition
felicity in the next world or prosperity would still have shocked. The question
in this.” He would have much more is why–why did not more people think
dif½culty today. through the implications and the logic
It has long been a truism of modern of one of the century’s most dominant
historiography that this shift from the ethical impulses?
happiness of heaven to the happiness One answer is that they did not want
of Earth was a product of the Enlighten- to–all ages, after all, have their willful
ment, the consequence of its assault blind spots, our own day no less than
on revealed religion and its own valida- the 1760s–and certainly it was nice to
tion of secular pleasure. I would not dis- believe that feeling good and being
pute the main lines of this interpreta- good were mostly one and the same.
tion, but as I have tried to suggest here, But most men and women in the eigh-
it is also the case that the shift toward teenth century were simply not able to
happiness on Earth occurred within think through the implications of their
the Christian tradition as well as with- increasingly contradictory assumptions
out. about happiness–not able, that is, to
And this fact is important, for it helps see with the piercing vision of a Kant the
to account for the ways in which eigh- contradictions that lay at the heart of the
teenth-century men and women were century’s newly self-evident truths.

Dædalus Spring 2004 15


Darrin M. Admittedly, there were radicals who in the legacy of Christian virtue–so as
McMahon
on pushed the logic of the pleasure/pain not to efface completely the line that
happiness calculus to its ultimate extreme. Julien separated being good from feeling good.
Offray de La Mettrie, for one, or the The eighteenth century still lived on this
Marquis de Sade, for another, argued inheritance–but we might say that it
that if pleasure was good, and pain lived on borrowed time.
was bad, then the most intense forms
of pleasure–sexual or even criminal–
should be embraced with virtuous gusto.
To his immense credit, John Locke
understood this dilemma, saw with a
“Renounce the idea of another world; perspicacity and foresight that rivaled
there is none,” Sade observes in his Kant’s own the problems raised by the
“Dialogue Between a Priest and a Dying novel pursuits he set in motion. In the
Man” (1782). “But do not renounce the very chapter “Power” of the Essay Con-
pleasure of being happy and of making cerning Human Understanding, Locke
for happiness in this.” If the world, in acknowledged, with more than a nod to
short, could offer nothing better than his Calvinist past, that what prevented
pleasure, then should not pleasure be his system from devolving into a simple
pursued to the hilt? And what was more relativism of feeling was the prospect
pleasurable, Sade wanted to know, than that one would judge the virtue of pres-
a good fuck? ent pleasures and present pains–ab-
Such exceptions, however, prove the staining and acting accordingly–on the
rule. For Sade and La Mettrie were writ- basis of future pleasures to come. This
ten off as pariahs, decried as scandalous, was “the reasonableness of Christian-
condemned as immoral, accused of lack- ity.” As he emphasized again, with rea-
ing virtue. Their pleasure was not happi- sonableness, in a later work of that
ness, contemporaries charged, but ego- name:
tism, immorality, indulgence, and vice.
Open [men’s] eyes upon the endless
But the assumption that many fell back
unspeakable joys of another life and their
on to level this charge was not the cen-
hearts will ½nd something solid and pow-
tury’s newly self-evident conception of
erful to move them. The view of heaven
happiness as utilitarian pleasure. They
and hell will cast a slight upon the short
fell back instead on the teachings about
pleasures and pains of this present state,
happiness that had accumulated slowly
and give attractions and encouragements
over the centuries, amassed by Hebrews
to virtue, which reason and interest, and
and Hellenes, classicists and Christians:
the care of ourselves, cannot but allow and
that happiness and virtue, happiness and
prefer. Upon this foundation, and upon
right action, happiness and godliness did
this only, morality stands ½rm.15
indeed walk in step, but that the journey
was often dif½cult, demanding sacri½ce, By contrast, Locke conceded in the chap-
commitment, even pain. That happi- ter “Power” of the Essay Concerning Hu-
ness, if it came at all, was not a right of man Understanding, “Were all the Con-
being human, but a reward, the product cerns of Man terminated in this Life,
of a life well lived. then why one followed Study and
In the eighteenth century there were
15 John Locke, The Reasonableness of Christiani-
still enough Stoics and close readers of ty, as Delivered in the Scriptures, ed. I. T. Ramsey
the Bible–men and women steeped in (Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press,
classical teachings on happiness and rich 1958), 70.

16 Dædalus Spring 2004


Knowledge, and another Hawking and The history
of happiness
Hunting; why one chose Luxury and
Debauchery, and another Sobriety and
Riches,” would simply be “because
their Happiness was placed in different
things.” “For if there be no Prospect
beyond the Grave, the inference is cer-
tainly right, Let us eat and drink, let us
enjoy what we delight in, for tomorrow
we shall die.”
In such a world, why men and wom-
en should read the publications of the
American Academy if it did not feel
good to do so–or perform any number
of other virtuous tasks–was not imme-
diately apparent.

Dædalus Spring 2004 17

You might also like