You are on page 1of 22

Chapter 8

Uncertainty and Risk


Exercise 8.1 Suppose you have to pay $2 for a ticket to enter a competition.
The prize is $19 and the probability that you win is
1
3
. You have an expected
utility function with n(r) = log r and your current wealth is $10.
1. What is the certainty equivalent of this competition?
2. What is the risk premium?
3. Should you enter the competition?
Outline Answer:
1. Given the probabilities and payos we have the following expected utility
if the person enters the lottery
cn(r) =
1
3
log (10 2 + 19) +
2
3
log (10 2)
=
1
3
log (27) +
2
3
log (8)
= log 3 + log 4 = log 12
So the certainty equivalent is $12.
2. The expected wealth at the end of the period is
cr =
1
3
[10 2 + 19] +
2
3
[10 2]
=
27
3
+
16
3
=
43
3
= 14
1
3
So the risk premium is $14
1
3
$12 = $2
1
3
.
3. If the person does not enter the lottery he has just his initial wealth, $10.
So, in view of the answer to part (a) it makes sense to enter the lottery.
115
Microeconomics CHAPTER 8. UNCERTAINTY AND RISK
Exercise 8.2 You are sending a package worth 10 000AC. You estimate that
there is a 0.1 percent chance that the package will be lost or destroyed in tran-
sit. An insurance company oers you insurance against this eventuality for a
premium of 15AC. If you are risk-neutral, should you buy insurance?
Outline Answer:
No you should not. Your expected loss is 10 euros whereas the premium is
15 euros.
c _Frank Cowell 2006 116
Microeconomics
Exercise 8.3 Consider the following denition of risk aversion. Let 1 :=
(r
!
,
!
) : . be a random prospect, where r
!
is the payo in state .
and
!
is the (subjective) probability of state . , and let cr :=

!2

!
r
!
,
the mean of the prospect, and let 1

:= (`r
!
+ [1 `]cr,
!
) : . be a
mixture of the original prospect with the mean. Dene an individual as risk
averse if he always prefers 1

to 1 for 0 < ` < 1.


1. Illustrate this concept in (r
red
, r
blue
)-space and contrast it with the concept
of risk aversion used in the text
2. Show that this denition of risk aversion need not imply convex-to-the-
origin indierence curves.
Outline Answer:
1. See Figure 8.1.
x
BLUE
x
RED
P
P
-
P

Figure 8.1: Nonconvex indierence curve


2. Let 1 be the prospect and 1 its mean. 1

can be any point in the line


joining them. The denition implies that moving along this line towards
1 puts the person on a successively higher indierence curves. In Figure
8.1 it is clear that this condition is consistent with there being indierence
curves that violate the convex-to-the-origin property locally.
c _Frank Cowell 2006 117
Microeconomics CHAPTER 8. UNCERTAINTY AND RISK
Exercise 8.4 Suppose you are asked to choose between two lotteries. In one
case the choice is between 1
1
and 1
2
,and in the other case the choice oered is
between 1
3
and 1
4
, as specied below:
1
1
: $1, 000, 000 with probability 1
1
2
:
_
_
_
$5, 000, 000
$1, 000, 000
$0
with probability 0.1
with probability 0.89
with probability 0.01
1
3
:
_
$5, 000, 000
$0
with probability 0.1
with probability 0.9
1
4
:
_
$1, 000, 000
$0
with probability 0.11
with probability 0.89
It is often the case that people prefer 1
1
to 1
2
and then also prefer 1
3
to 1
4
.
Show that these preferences violate the independence axiom.
Outline Answer:
Let there be only three possible states of the world: red, blue and green,
with probabilities 0.01, 0.10, 0.89 respectively. Then the payos in the four
prospects can be written
red blue green
1
1
1 1 1
1
2
0 5 1
1
3
0 5 0
1
4
1 1 0
where all the entries in the table are in millions of dollars. Note that 1
1
and 1
2
have the same payo in the green state; 1
3
and 1
4
form a similar pair, except
that the payo in the green state is 0. Axiom 8.2 states that if 1
1
is preferred
to 1
2
than any other similar pair of prospects (1, 1, .) and (0, 5, .) ought also
to be ranked in the same order, for arbitrary .: but this would imply that 1
4
is preferred to 1
3
, the opposite of the preferences as stated.
Note also that if the preferences had been such that 1
4
was preferred to 1
3
then the independence axiom would imply that 1
1
was preferred to 1
2
.
c _Frank Cowell 2006 118
Microeconomics
Exercise 8.5 This is an example to illustrate disappointment. Suppose the
payos are as follows
r
00
weekend for two in your favourite holiday location
r
0
book of photographs of the same location
r

sh-and-chip supper
Your preferences under certainty are r
00
~ r
0
~ r

. Now consider the following


two prospects
1
1
:
_
_
_
r
00
r
0
r

with probability 0.99


with probability 0
with probability 0.01
1
2
:
_
_
_
r
00
r
0
r

with probability 0.99


with probability 0.01
with probability 0
Suppose a person expresses a preference for 1
1
over 1
2
. Briey explain why
this might be the case in practice. Which of the three axioms State Irrelevance,
Independence, Revealed Likelihood, is violated by such preferences?
Outline Answer:
It is possible that, given the information that the rst event (with payo r
00
)
has not happened you would then prefer r

to r
0
: photographs of your favourite
holiday spot may be too painful once you know that the holiday is not going to
happen. So you may prefer 1
1
over 1
2
.
These preferences violate the independence axiom. To see this, note that,
by the revealed likelihood axiom, since r
0
is strictly preferred to r

, it must be
the case that 1
0
2
is strictly preferred to 1
0
1
, where
1
0
1
:
_
r
0
r

with probability 0
with probability 1
1
0
2
:
_
r
0
r

with probability 0.01


with probability 0.99
But 1
0
1
and 1
0
2
can be written equivalently as
1
0
1
:
_
_
_
r

r
0
r

with probability 0.99


with probability 0
with probability 0.01
1
0
2
:
_
_
_
r

r
0
r

with probability 0.99


with probability 0.01
with probability 0
By the independence axiom if 1
0
2
is strictly preferred to 1
0
1
, then 1
2
must be
strictly preferred to 1
1
.
c _Frank Cowell 2006 119
Microeconomics CHAPTER 8. UNCERTAINTY AND RISK
Exercise 8.6 An example to illustrate regret. Let
1 := (r
!
,
!
) : .
1
0
:= (r
0
!
,
!
) : .
be two prospects available to an individual. Dene the expected regret if the
person chooses 1 rather than 1
0
as

!2

!
max r
0
!
r
!
, 0 (8.1)
Now consider the choices amongst prospects presented in Exercise 8.4. Show
that if a person is concerned to minimise expected regret as measured by (8.1),
then it is reasonable that the person select 1
2
when 1
1
is also available and then
also select 1
4
when 1
3
is available.
Outline Answer:
Denote the regret in (8.1) by r (1, 1
0
).
If I choose 1
2
when 1
1
is also available then the regret is
r (1
2
, 1
1
) = 0.1 [0] + 0.89 [0] +.01 [1]
= 10, 000
Whereas, had I chosen 1
1
when 1
2
was available, then the regret would have
been
r (1
1
, 1
2
) = 0.1 [4, 000, 000] + 0.89 [0] +.01 [0]
= 400, 000
If I choose 1
4
when 1
3
is also available then the regret is
r (1
4
, 1
3
) = 0.1 [0] + 0.89 [0] +.01 [0]
= 0
Whereas, had I chosen 1
3
when 1
4
was available, then the regret would have
been
r (1
3
, 1
4
) = 0.1 [0] + 0.89 [0] +.01 [5, 000, 000]
= 50, 000
c _Frank Cowell 2006 120
Microeconomics
Exercise 8.7 An example of the Ellsberg paradox . There are two urns marked
Left and Right each of which contains 100 balls. You know that in Urn L
there exactly 49 white balls and the rest are black and that in Urn R there are
black and white balls, but in unknown proportions. Consider the following two
experiments:
1. One ball is to be drawn from each of L and R. The person must choose
between L and R before the draw is made. If the ball drawn from the chosen
urn is black there is a prize of $1000, otherwise nothing.
2. Again one ball is to be drawn from each of L and R; again the person must
choose between L and R before the draw. Now if the ball drawn from the
chosen urn is white there is a prize of $1000, otherwise nothing.
You observe a person choose Urn L in both experiments. Show that this
violates the Revealed Likelihood Axiom.
Outline Answer
The implication of the revealed likelihood axiom is that there exist subjective
probabilities
!
. The result is proved by showing that it the stated behaviour
is inconsistent with the existence of subjective probabilities.
In this case the revealed likelihood axiom implies that for each urn there is
a given subjective probability of drawing a black ball
L
(left-hand urn) and
R
(right-hand urn) such that preferences can be represented as

black
(r
black
, r
white
) + [1 ]
white
(r
black
, r
white
) (8.2)
where =
L
or
R
and r
black
and r
white
are the payos if a black ball or a
white ball are drawn respectively.
Note that the representation (8.2) does not impose either the State Irrel-
evance Axiom (which would require that
black
() and
white
() be the same
function) or the Independence axiom (which would require that
black
() be a
function only of r
black
etc.). Nor does it impose the common-sense requirement
that
L
= 0.49. All we need below is the very weak assumption that preferences
are not perverse:

black
(1000, 0)
white
(1000, 0) (8.3)
and

black
(0, 1000) <
white
(0, 1000) (8.4)
Condition (8.3) simply says that if the $1000 prize is attached to a black ball
then the utility to be derived from having selected a black ball is higher than
selecting a white ball; condition (8.4) is the counterpart when the prize attaches
to the white ball..
Experiment 1 suggests that

black
(1000, 0) + [1
L
]
white
(1000, 0)

R

black
(1000, 0) + [1
R
]
white
(1000, 0) (8.5)
c _Frank Cowell 2006 121
Microeconomics CHAPTER 8. UNCERTAINTY AND RISK
while experiment 2 suggests that

black
(0, 1000) + [1
L
]
white
(0, 1000)

R

black
(0, 1000) + [1
R
]
white
(0, 1000) (8.6)
We can see that (8.5) implies

L
[
black
(1000, 0)
white
(1000, 0)]
R
[
black
(1000, 0)
white
(1000, 0)]
from which we deduce that, given (8.3),
L

R
. However (8.5) implies

L
[
black
(0, 1000)
white
(0, 1000)]
R
[
black
(0, 1000)
white
(0, 1000)] .
So that, given (8.4), we would have
L
<
R
a contradiction. Therefore the
revealed likelihood axiom must be violated.
c _Frank Cowell 2006 122
Microeconomics
Exercise 8.8 An individual faces a prospect with a monetary payo represented
by a random variable r that is distributed over the bounded interval of the real
line [a, a]. He has a utility function cn(r) where
n(r) = a
0
+a
1
r
1
2
a
2
r
2
and a
0
, a
1
, a
2
are all positive numbers.
1. Show that the individuals utility function can also be written as ,(cr, ar(r)).
Sketch the indierence curves in a diagram with cr and ar(r) on the
axes, and discuss the eect on the indierence map altering (i) the para-
meter a
1
, (ii) the parameter a
2
.
2. For the model to make sense, what value must a have? [Hint: examine
the rst derivative of n.]
3. Show that both absolute and relative risk aversion increase with r.
Outline Answer:
1. Clearly
cn(r) = a
0
+a
1
c(r) +a
2
1
2
[(c(r))
2
ar(r)].
Marginal utility is a
1
a
2
r.
2. For this to be non-negative we must have c(r) _ a
1
,a
2
hence the in-
dierence curves are depicted with c(r) as good, ar(r) as bad and
'1o = 2 [a
1
,a
2
c(r)] .
3.
n
x
(r) = a
1
+a
2
r
n
xx
(r) = a
2
c(r) =
n
xx
(r)
n
x
(r)
=
a
2
a
1
+a
2
r
c(r) =
1
r
max
r
(r) =
1
r
max
,r 1
where and 0 _ r _ r
max
:=
a
1
a
2
.
c _Frank Cowell 2006 123
Microeconomics CHAPTER 8. UNCERTAINTY AND RISK
Exercise 8.9 A person lives for 1 or 2 periods. If he lives for both periods he
has a utility function given by
l (r
1
, r
2
) = n(r
1
) +cn(r
2
) (8.7)
where the parameter c is the pure rate of time preference. The probability of
survival to period 2 is , and the persons utility in period 2 if he does not
survive is 0.
1. Show that if the persons preferences in the face of uncertainty are repre-
sented by the expected-utility functional form

!2

!
n(x
!
) (8.8)
then the persons utility can be written as
n(r
1
) +c
0
n(r
2
) . (8.9)
What is the value of the parameter c
0
?
2. What is the appropriate form of the utility function if the person could live
for an indenite number of periods, the rate of time preference is the same
for any adjacent pair of periods, and the probability of survival to the next
period given survival to the current period remains constant?
Outline Answer:
1. Consider the persons lifetime utility with the consumption r
1
and r
2
in the two periods. If the person survives into the second period utility
is given by n(r
1
) + cn(r
2
) otherwise it is just n(r
1
). Given that the
probability of the event survive to second period is expected lifetime
utility is
[n(r
1
) +cn(r
2
)] + [1 ] n(r
1
) .
On rearranging we get
n(r
1
) +cn(r
2
) , (8.10)
in other words the form (8.9) with c
0
= c.
2. Apply the argument to one more period. Now there is consumption
r
1
,r
2
, r
3
in the three periods and the probability of surviving into period
t + 1 given that you have made it to period t is still . Consider the
situation of someone who survives to period 2. The person gets utility
n(r
2
) +cn(r
3
) (8.11)
if he survives to period 3 and n(r
2
) otherwise. His expected utility for
the rest of his lifetime, contingent on having reached period 2 is therefore
[n(r
2
) +cn(r
3
)] + [1 ] n(r
2
)
= n(r
2
) +cn(r
3
) (8.12)
c _Frank Cowell 2006 124
Microeconomics
So now view the situation from the position of the beginning of the lifetime.
The person gets utility
n(r
1
) +c [n(r
2
) +cn(r
3
)] (8.13)
if he makes it through to period 2, where the expression in square brackets
in (8.13) is just the rest-of-lifetime expected utility if you get to period 2,
taken from (8.12); of course if the person does not survive period 1 he gets
just n(r
1
). So, using the same reasoning as before, from the standpoint
of period 1 lifetime expected utility is now
[n(r
1
) +c [n(r
2
) +cn(r
3
)]]
+[1 ] n(r
1
) .
Rearranging this we have
n(r
1
) +cn(r
2
) +
2
c
2
n(r
2
) . (8.14)
It is clear that the same argument could be applied to T 2 periods and
that the resulting utility function would be of the form
n(r
1
) +cn(r
2
) +
2
c
2
n(r
2
) +... +
T
c
T
n(r
2
) . (8.15)
In other words we have the standard intertemporal utility function with
the pure rate of time preference c replaced by the modied rate of time
preference c
0
:= c.
c _Frank Cowell 2006 125
Microeconomics CHAPTER 8. UNCERTAINTY AND RISK
Exercise 8.10 A person has an objective function cn(j) where n is an increas-
ing, strictly concave, twice-dierentiable function, and j is the monetary value
of his nal wealth after tax. He has an initial stock of assets 1 which he may
keep either in the form of bonds, where they earn a return at a stochastic rate
r, or in the form of cash where they earn a return of zero. Assume that cr 0
and that Prr < 0 0.
1. If he invests an amount , in bonds (0 < , < 1) and is taxed at rate t
on his income, write down the expression for his disposable nal wealth j,
assuming full loss oset of the tax.
2. Find the rst-order condition which determines his optimal bond portfolio
,

.
3. Examine the way in which a small increase in t will aect ,

.
4. What would be the eect of basing the tax on the persons wealth rather
than income?
Outline Answer:
1. Suppose the person puts an amount , in bonds leaving the remaining
1 , of assets in cash. Then, given that the rate of return on cash is
zero and on bonds is the stochastic variable r, income is
[1 ,] 0 +,r = ,r
If the tax rate is t then, given that full loss oset implies that losses and
gains are treated symmetrically, disposable income is
[1 t] ,r
and (disposable) nal wealth is
r = [1 ,]
[cash]
+ ,
[value of bonds]
+ [1 t] ,r
[income]
= 1 + [1 t] ,r. (8.16)
Note that r is a stochastic variable and could be greater or less than initial
wealth 1.
2. The individuals optimisation problem is to choose , to maximise cn(r).
Using (8.16) the FOC for an interior solution is
c (n
x
(r) [1 t] r) = 0,
which implies
c (n
x
(r)r) = 0. (8.17)
Solving this determines ,

= ,

(t, 1), the optimal bond purchases that


depends on the tax rate and initial wealth as well as the distribution of
returns and risk aversion.
c _Frank Cowell 2006 126
Microeconomics
3. Take the FOC (8.17). Substituting for r from (8.16) and dierentiating
with respect to t we get
c
_
n
xx
(r)
_
,

r +
0,

0t
[1 t] r
_
r
_
= 0,
c
_
n
xx
(r)r
2
_
,

+
0,

0t
[1 t]
__
= 0.
so that
,

+
0,

0t
[1 t] = 0
0,

0t
=
,

1 t
.
An increase in the tax rate increases the demand for bonds.
4. Final wealth is initial wealth plus income. If the tax is on wealth then
disposable nal wealth is
r = [1 t] 1 + [1 t] ,r (8.18)
instead of (8.16). Clearly the FOC (8.17) remains essentially unaltered
(the new tax just reduces total wealth). Dierentiating the FOC with r
dened by (8.18) we now nd
c
_
n
xx
(r)
_
1 ,

r +
0,

0t
[1 t] r
_
r
_
= 0,
1c (n
xx
(r)r) + c
_
n
xx
(r)r
2
_
,

+
0,

0t
[1 t]
__
= 0.
This implies
,

1
c (n
xx
(r)r)
c (n
xx
(r)r
2
)
+
0,

0t
[1 t] = 0.
0,

0t
[1 t] = ,

+1
c (n
xx
(r)r)
c (n
xx
(r)r
2
)
.
0,

0t
=
,

1 t
+
1
1 t
c (n
xx
(r)r)
c (n
xx
(r)r
2
)
.
The rst term on the right-hand side is positive; as for the second term,
the denominator is negative and the numerator is positive, given DARA.
So the impact of tax on bond-holding is now ambiguous.
c _Frank Cowell 2006 127
Microeconomics CHAPTER 8. UNCERTAINTY AND RISK
Exercise 8.11 An individual taxpayer has an income j that he should report to
the tax authority. Tax is payable at a constant proportionate rate t. The taxpayer
reports r where 0 _ r _ j and is aware that the tax authority audits some tax
returns. Assume that the probability that the taxpayers report is audited is
, that when an audit is carried out the true taxable income becomes public
knowledge and that, if r < j, the taxpayer must pay both the underpaid tax and
a surcharge of : times the underpaid tax.
1. If the taxpayer chooses r < j, show that disposable income c in the two
possible states-of-the-world is given by
c
noaudit
= j tr,
c
audit
= [1 t :t] j +:tr.
2. Assume that the individual chooses r so as to maximise the utility function
[1 ] n(c
noaudit
) +n(c
audit
) .
where n is increasing and strictly concave.
(a) Write down the FOC for an interior maximum.
(b) Show that if 1 : 0 then the individual will denitely under-
report income.
3. If the optimal income report r

satises 0 < r

< j:
(a) Show that if the surcharge is raised then under-reported income will
decrease.
(b) If true income increases will under-reported income increase or de-
crease?
Outline Answer:
If the individual reports r then he pays tax tr i.e. he underpays an amount
t [j r]. So
1. If the under-reporting remains undetected then
c
noaudit
= j tr
= j tj +t [j r]
and if the audit takes place then
c
audit
= j tr [1 +:] t [j r]
= [1 t :t] j +:tr
2. The individual maximises
cn(c) = [1 ] n(j tr) +n([1 t :t] j +:tr)
Dierentiating this we have
0cn(c)
0r
= t [1 ] n
c
(j tr) +:tn
c
([1 t :t] j +:tr)
where n
c
() denotes the rst derivative of n.
c _Frank Cowell 2006 128
Microeconomics
(a) If there is an interior maximum at r

then the following FOC must


hold
[1 ] n
c
(j tr

) = :n
c
([1 t :t] j +:tr

) .
(b) If the person reports fully then
0cn(c)
0r

x=y
= t [1 ] n
c
(j tj) +:tn
c
([1 t] j)
= [1 :] tn
c
(j tj)
Given that t and n
c
are positive it is clear that the above expression
is negative if 1 : 0. Therefore the individuals expected
utility would increase if he reduced r below j.
3. Dierentiating the FOC with respect to : and rearranging we get
t [1 ] n
cc
(j tr

)
0r

0:
:
2
tn
cc
([1 t :t] j +:tr

)
0r

0:
= n
c
([1 t :t] j +:tr

) +:t [r

j] n
cc
([1 t :t] j +:tr

)
(a) Therefore
0r

0:
=
n
c
(c
audit
) +:t [r

j] n
cc
(c
audit
)
t
(8.19)
where
:= [1 ] n
cc
(j tr

) :
2
n
cc
([1 t :t] j +:tr

) 0
Given that n
c
0, r

< j and n
cc
< 0 it is clear that the numerator
of (8.19) is positive.r

increases with : so t [j r

] decreases.
(b) Dierentiating the FOC with respect to j we get
[1 ] n
cc
(j tr

)
_
1 t
0r

0j
_
= :n
cc
([1 t :t] j +:tr

)
_
[1 t :t] +:t
0r

0j
_
.
Therefore we have
0r

0j
=
: [1 t :t] n
cc
(c
audit
) [1 ] n
cc
(c
noaudit
)
t [[1 ] n
cc
(c
noaudit
) +:
2
n
cc
(c
audit
)]
0 [j r

]
0j
= 1 +
: [1 t :t] n
cc
(c
audit
) [1 ] n
cc
(c
noaudit
)
[[1 ] tn
cc
(c
noaudit
) +:
2
tn
cc
(c
audit
)]
0 [j r

]
0j
=
1 t
t
[1 ] n
cc
(c
noaudit
) :n
cc
(c
audit
)
[[1 ] n
cc
(c
noaudit
) +:
2
n
cc
(c
audit
)]
This is of ambiguous sign unless we assume DARA in which case it
is positive.
c _Frank Cowell 2006 129
Microeconomics CHAPTER 8. UNCERTAINTY AND RISK
Exercise 8.12 A risk-averse person has wealth j
0
and faces a risk of loss
1 < j
0
with probability . An insurance company oers cover of the loss at
a premium i 1. It is possible to take out partial cover on a pro-rata basis,
so that an amount t1 of the loss can be covered at cost ti where 0 < t < 1.
1. Explain why the person will not choose full insurance
2. Find the conditions that will determine t

, the optimal value of t.


3. Show how t will change as j
0
increases if all other parameters remain
unchanged.
Outline Answer:
1. Consider the persons wealth after taking out (partial) insurance cover
using the two-state model (no loss,loss). If the person remained unin-
sured it would be (j
0
, j
0
1); if he insures fully it is (j
0
i, j
0
i). So
if he insures a proportion t for the pro-rata premium wealth in the two
states will be
([1 t] j
0
+t [j
0
i] , [1 t] [j
0
1] +t [j
0
i])
which becomes
(j
0
ti, j
0
ti [1 t] 1)
So expected utility is given by
cn = [1 ] n(j
0
ti) +n(j
0
ti [1 t] 1)
Therefore
0cn
0t
= [1 ] in
y
(j
0
ti) + [1 i] n
y
(j
0
ti [1 t] 1)
Consider what happens in the neighbourhood of t = 1 (full insurance).
We get
0cn
0t

t=1
= [1 ] in
y
(j
0
i) + [1 i] n
y
(j
0
i)
= [1 i] n
y
(j
0
i)
We know that n
y
(j
0
i) 0 (positive marginal utility of wealth) and, by
assumption, 1 < i. Therefore this expression is strictly negative which
means that in the neighbourhood of full insurance (t = 1) the individual
could increase expected utility by cutting down on the insurance cover.
2. For an interior maximum we have
0cn
0t
= 0
which means that the optimal t

is given as the solution to the equation


[1 ] in
y
(j
0
t

i) + [1 i] n
y
(j
0
t

i [1 t

] 1) = 0
c _Frank Cowell 2006 130
Microeconomics
3. Dierentiating the above equation with respect to j
0
we get
[1 ] in
yy
(j
0
t

i)
_
1 i
0t

0j
0
_
+[1 i] n
yy
(j
0
t

i [1 t

] 1)
_
1 [i 1]
0t

0j
0
_
= 0
which gives
0t

0j
0
=
[1 ] in
yy
(j
0
t

i) [1 i] n
yy
(j
0
t

i [1 t

] 1)
[1 ] n
yy
(j
0
t

i) i
2
+ [1 i]
2
n
yy
(j
0
t

i [1 t

] 1)
The denominator of this must be negative: n
yy
() is everywhere negative
and the other terms are positive. The numerator is positive if DARA
holds: therefore an increase in wealth reduces the demand for insurance
coverage.
c _Frank Cowell 2006 131
Microeconomics CHAPTER 8. UNCERTAINTY AND RISK
Exercise 8.13 Consider a competitive, price-taking rm that confronts one of
the following two situations:
uncertainty: price j is a random variable with expectation j.
certainty: price is xed at j.
It has a cost function C() where is output and it seeks to maximise the
expected utility of prot.
1. Suppose that the rm must choose the level of output before the particular
realisation of j is announced. Set up the rms optimisation problem and
derive the rst- and second-order conditions for a maximum. Show that,
if the rm is risk averse, then increasing marginal cost is not a necessary
condition for a maximum, and that it strictly prefers certainty to un-
certainty. Show that if the rm is risk neutral then the rm is indierent
as between certainty and uncertainty.
2. Now suppose that the rm can select after the realisation of j is an-
nounced, and that marginal cost is strictly increasing. Using the rms
competitive supply function write down prot as a function of j and show
that this prot function is convex. Hence show that a risk-neutral rm
would strictly prefer uncertainty to certainty.
Outline Answer:
1. Prot is given by
:= j C()
where j is a random variable. Maximising expected utility of prot cn()
by choice of requires the FOC
c(n

()j) c(n

())C
q
= 0
where n

() is the rst derivative of n(). This will represent a maximum


if
d
2
cn
d
2
< 0.
We nd that this implies
c(n

[j C
q
]
2
) c(n

)C
qq
< 0.
Notice that since the rst term is negative for a risk-averse rm then the
condition can be satised not only if C
qq
0 but also if C
qq
< 0 and [C
qq
[
is not too large. Now consider transforming j to j thus: j = (1`)j+`j
then j has the same mean as j but is less dispersed. Maximised utility for
the random variable j is
cn([(1 `)j +`j]

C(

))
where

is the output satisfying the rst-order conditions for a maximum.


Dierentiate this expected utility with respect to `
0cn

0`
= [c(n

[j j])]

+ [c(n

[ j C
q
])]
0

0`
c _Frank Cowell 2006 132
Microeconomics
where the last term vanishes because of the rst order condition. So
@Eu

@
has the sign of c(n

[j j]). But this must be positive if n

is
decreasing with and will be zero if n

is constant. Hence the rm strictly


prefers certainty if it is risk averse and is indierent between certainty and
uncertainty if it is risk neutral.
2. For any known realization j we may write = o(j) where o is the com-
petitive rm supply curve. Prots as a function of 1 may thus be written:
(j) = jo(j) C(o(j))
which implies
d(j)
dj
= [j C
q
]o
p
(j) +o(j) = o(j) (8.20)
where o
p
(j) is the slope of the supply curve at j, a positive number.
Therefore, dierentiating (8.20) we have
d
2
(j)
dj
2
= o
p
(j) 0.
Hence () is increasing and convex. So it is immediate that c(j) (j).
c _Frank Cowell 2006 133
Microeconomics CHAPTER 8. UNCERTAINTY AND RISK
Exercise 8.14 Every year Alf sells apples from his orchard. Although the mar-
ket price of apples remains constant (and equal to 1), the output of Alf s orchard
is variable yielding an amount 1
1
, 1
2
in good and poor years respectively; the
probability of good and poor years is known to be 1 and respectively. A
buyer, Bill, oers Alf a contract for his apple crop which stipulates a down pay-
ment (irrespective of whether the year is good or poor) and a bonus if the year
turns out to be good.
1. Assuming Alf is risk averse, use an Edgeworth box diagram to sketch the
set of such contracts which he would be prepared to accept. Assuming that
Bill is also risk averse, sketch his indierence curves in the same diagram.
2. Assuming that Bill knows the shape of Alf s acceptance set, illustrate the
optimum contract on the diagram. Write down the rst-order conditions
for this in terms of Alf s and Bills utility functions.
0
a
0
b
R
1
x
RED
b
x
RED
b
x
BLUE
b
x
BLUE
b
x
BLUE
a
x
BLUE
a
x
RED
a
x
RED
a

R
2
D
Figure 8.2: Acceptable contracts
Outline Answer:
1. In Figure 8.2 the contours represent Alfs indierence curves: note that
they are convex to the point 0
a
(risk aversion) and that they have the same
slope [1 ] , where they cross the 45

ray through 0
a
(consequence of
von-Neumann utility function). Point D represents the initial endowment;
Alfs endowment is (1
1
, 1
2
). Alfs indierence curve through point D
represents the boundary of the set of consumptions that Alf would regard
as being at least as good as the initial endowment: the shaded area is his
acceptance set. The buyer (Bill) has an endowment 1 that is independent
of the state of the world see Figure 8.3. Note that the indierence curves
for Bill also have the slope [1 ] , where they cross the 45

ray through
0
b
.
2. Point E in Figure ?? represents the optimum contract (from Bills point
of view) since it is a point of common tangency of two indierence curves.
c _Frank Cowell 2006 134
Microeconomics
0
a
0
b
x
RED
b
x
RED
b
x
BLUE
b
x
BLUE
b
x
BLUE
a
x
BLUE
a
x
RED
a
x
RED
a
D

K
K
Figure 8.3: Buyers situation
0
a
0
b
E
x
RED
b
x
RED
b
x
BLUE
b
x
BLUE
b
x
BLUE
a
x
BLUE
a
x
RED
a
x
RED
a

R
1
R
2
D

Figure 8.4: Optimal contract


At E we have that
n
a0
(r
a
1
)
n
a0
(r
a
2
)
=
n
b0
(r
b
1
)
n
b0
(r
b
2
)
.
c _Frank Cowell 2006 135
Microeconomics CHAPTER 8. UNCERTAINTY AND RISK
Exercise 8.15 In exercise 8.14, what would be the eect on the contract if (i)
Bill were risk neutral; (ii) Alf risk neutral?
Outline Answer:
In case (i) Bills indierence curves become lines with slope [1 ] , and
the optimum is at E in Figure 8.5. In case (ii) Alfs indierence curves become
lines with slope [1 ] , and the optimum is at the endowment point D.
0
a
0
b
E
x
RED
b
x
RED
b
x
BLUE
b
x
BLUE
b
x
BLUE
a
x
BLUE
a

R
1
R
2
D

Figure 8.5: Optimal contract: risk-neutral buyer


c _Frank Cowell 2006 136

You might also like