You are on page 1of 22

Journal of Anthropological Archaeology 22 (2003) 389–410

www.elsevier.com/locate/jaa

Transcending the ‘‘Obnoxious Spectator’’: a case


for processual pluralism in ethnoarchaeology
Jerimy J. Cunningham*
Department of Anthropology, McGill University, 855 Sherbrooke Street West, Montreal, Que., Canada H3A 2T7
Received 18 February 2003; revised 13 May 2003

Abstract

Several commentators have argued that ethnoarchaeology will only become a productive part of archaeological
research once both archaeology and ethnoarchaeology are unified by the axioms of a single theory of behavior. Through
an examination of the different roles that ethnoarchaeological research has adopted, I demonstrate that ethnoar-
chaeology is already theoretically unified by a general concern with analogy. I argue that the problems that many
commentators have recognized with ethnoarchaeologyÕs apparent eclecticism arise from an over-reliance on ‘‘core
universals’’ by both processual and postprocessual researchers. Instead of implementing a single unified theory of
behavior, I suggest that ethnoarchaeologists should adopt a pluralistic orientation that is sensitive to the contextual
applicability of specific causal processes.
Ó 2003 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved.

Keywords: Ethnoarchaeology; Analogical reasoning; Pluralism; Causal process; Universals

Introduction terms, ethnoarchaeology is a ‘‘Rosetta Stone: a way of


ÔtranslatingÕ the static, material. . .found on an archaeo-
Perhaps more than any other branch of archaeology, logical site into the vibrant life of a group of people who
ethnoarchaeology is reaping the rewards of its own in fact left them there.’’ Yet, despite frequent historical
ambiguity. While most archaeologists know that ethn- reviews (Charlton, 1981; David and Kramer, 2001,
oarchaeologists study modern cultural life in order to Chapter 1; Dillon, 1984; Trigger, 1978) and attempts to
develop interpretive frameworks specifically designed re-conceptualize ethnoarchaeology by developing ty-
for archaeology, ethnoarchaeologyÕs methods, objectives pologies of ethnoarchaeological research (e.g., GouldÕs,
and governing theories remain generally misunderstood. 1971 ‘‘levels of ethnoarchaeology’’; see Kirch, 1978, p.
Ethnoarchaeology developed as a response to a ten- 109; and again David and Kramer, 2001, Chapter 1),
dency among ethnologists to ignore archaeological little consensus exists even among ethnoarchaeologists
questions in their research (Longacre, 1991a; Papousek, as to the place ethnoarchaeology should have within the
1984; Watson, 1980; but see Pastron, 1974). Archaeol- larger discipline (see Longacre, 1978, p. 357 for an early
ogists have thus taken to the field to make their own discussion; and then Stark, 1993).
ethnographic observations—observations that are di- In recent years, ethnoarchaeology has been forced
rected explicitly at an ‘‘archaeological purpose’’ to weather internal and external critiques and re-
(Thompson, 1991, p. 231). In BinfordÕs (1983, p. 24) evaluations. Stahl (1993), for example, has taken both
archaeologists and ethnoarchaeologists to task for rein-
troducing elements of unilinear evolutionary thought to
*
Fax: (519) 398-4758. archaeology. She argues that the preoccupation with
E-mail address: jerimy.cunningham@mail.mcgill.ca. testing that was typical of the New Archaeology resulted

0278-4165/$ - see front matter Ó 2003 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved.
doi:10.1016/S0278-4165(03)00042-4
390 J.J. Cunningham / Journal of Anthropological Archaeology 22 (2003) 389–410

in the use of boundary conditions for analogy that were would seem to be why the solution to ethnoarchaeol-
‘‘. . .historical continuities, and/or societies occupying ogyÕs problems will suddenly be found in a single high
comparable environments pursuing similar subsistence level theory. The concern with general theorizing seems
strategies, hence in comparable stages of evolutionary antithetical to ethnoarchaeologyÕs long association with
development. . .’’ (Stahl, 1993, p. 244, emphasis added). middle-range theorizing—with the attempt to develop
Other commentators have pointed to the astounding low level linking principles between archaeological data
degree of variability that exists in ethnoarchaeologyÕs and human behavior. Indeed, the independence of ethn-
current research practices. P. Arnold (2000, p. 120) notes oarchaeologyÕs middle-range propositions from general
that ‘‘. . .it is time to call attention to the uncomfortable theory has often been taken by archaeologists to mean
hodgepodge of protocol and purpose subsumed within that these middle-range propositions could be used to
the increasingly ambiguous arena of ceramic ethnoar- employ archaeological findings to test the accuracy and
chaeology.’’ Likewise, MacEachern (1996) has shown reliability of broader propositions about human activi-
that ‘‘African ethnoarchaeology’’ includes detailed eth- ties (Binford, 1978; see Raab and Goodyear, 1984;
nographic field research in a single location and com- Wylie, 1995, for discussions). For these researchers, the
parative studies, involves long term commitments to a eclecticism of ethnoarchaeology—its disinterest in broad
native population, occurs in controlled laboratory con- range problems—is perhaps its greatest contribution to
ditions removed from any ethnographic subject, focuses the discipline. The suggestion that ethnoarchaeology
explicitly on the technicalities of archaeological research, should abandon its diverse, middle-range focus and in-
and examines human activities that are all but archaeo- stead should cling tightly to the directives of a specific
logically invisible. Elsewhere, significant differences have theoretical paradigm is a significant development.
emerged in the theoretical perspectives that ethnoar- In what follows, I develop my own reanalysis of
chaeologists seem to hold regarding ethnographic anal- ethnoarchaeologyÕs eclecticism and the proposed solu-
ogy. Despite the central role often ascribed to analogy in tion that would see ethnoarchaeology unified by a single
all archaeological and ethnoarchaeological research (see theory of human behavior. There are, I would suggest,
David and Kramer, 2001, Chapter 2), a commentator has two distinct facets to the ‘‘senseless eclecticism’’ we see
made recently the bewildering claim that postprocessual in current ethnoarchaeological research. First, I suggest
researchers do not make analogical inferences (Porr, that at least some of the diversity in ethnoarchaeologyÕs
1999, pp. 7–8). Two of the most recent volumes on methodological programs is a response to the episte-
ethnoarchaeology and ethnographic analogy (David and mological requirements of analogical reasoning. To
Kramer, 2001; Owen and Porr, 1999a; see especially make this point, I first present an overview of the dif-
Biehl, 1999, p. 172; David and Kramer, 2001, pp. 43–50; ferent ‘‘roles’’ that ethnoarchaeology has adopted within
Owen and Porr, 1999b; Porr, 1999, p. 6; Roux, 1999, p. archaeology. I then review WylieÕs (1982, 1985, 1988)
154) demonstrate that processual and postprocessual treatment of analogy and focus on her suggestions that
researchers rely on formal or structural similarities in ethnoarchaeologists should (1) combine an ever-ex-
their analogical inferences rather than on the causal panding knowledge of how causal processes operate in
regularities that—20 years ago—Wylie (1982, 1985) noted ethnographic contexts with (2) explicit programs of
as the most desirable form of ethnographic analogy. testing. I argue that the diverse methodological roles
Perhaps the most memorable critique of ethnoar- that ethnoarchaeology has within archaeology reflect, at
chaeologyÕs eclecticism comes from SimmsÕ (1992) least in part, these two suggestions. However, there is a
characterization of contemporary ethnoarchaeological second facet to ethnoarchaeologyÕs eclecticism that
work as little more than an ‘‘Obnoxious Spectator’’ and crosscuts its existing methodological programs. More-
a ‘‘Trivial Pursuit.’’ Like OÕConnell (1995), Simms has over, I would suggest that this aspect of ethnoarchae-
suggested that the solution to ethnoarchaeologyÕs ills lies ologyÕs diversity is responsible for many of the problems
in a more nuanced consideration of high level theory. In and misconceptions the plague the field. Competing
order to become a productive area of research, both partisan interests in archaeology have proposed distinct
authors have argued that archaeology and ethnoar- and often mutually exclusive models of culture. As is the
chaeology must become integrated under a unified the- case with behavioral ecology and material culture stud-
oretical perspective, preferably one based in behavioral ies, most of these theories are considered by their pro-
ecology. After unification, Simms believes ethnoar- ponents to be candidates for an emerging monism—to be
chaeology can reach its true potential, becoming the key the theory that will unify ethnoarchaeology and solve
to the ‘‘Time Machine.’’ The obvious response to ethnoarchaeologyÕs eclecticism. At the heart of these
SimmsÕ and OÕConnellÕs suggestion is to ask why ethn- models are to what I refer as ‘‘core universals’’—causal
oarchaeology should be theoretically unified under be- processes that proponents of the different models in
havioral ecology, especially since Hodder (1986) would ethnoarchaeology assume have a near universal affect on
like ‘‘material culture studies’’ to unify ethnoarchaeo- behavioral, cultural and material patterning. Because of
logical research. But the far more relevant question their uniform causal affect, these processes should be the
J.J. Cunningham / Journal of Anthropological Archaeology 22 (2003) 389–410 391

foundation on which analogical inferences are based. The propositions developed by ethnoarchaeology
My point here is not—as has so often been done in the often operate as middle-range propositions in the Bin-
processual–postprocessual debates—to advocate one fordian sense: as low-level bridging principles that can
model over another, but to show how the very idea that be used by researchers following quite different theories
specific processes are immutable interferes with our of behavior. If success is to be measured in the usability
understanding of how causal processes interact and of these propositions by different theories of cultural
combine in the creation of material patterns. I suggest behavior—i.e., by widespread acceptance—then the
that rather than a single broad level theory of behavior, success of this research has been limited almost exclu-
ethnoarchaeology needs a more nuanced and pluralistic sively to ‘‘technical’’ areas like usewear, stratigraphy,
understanding of how diverse causal influences create dating, or taphonomy. Other researchers have optimis-
material variation. tically pursued similar ‘‘law-like’’ relations in a wider
spectrum of cultural behaviors (e.g., Arnold, 1985;
contributions to Carr and Neitzel, 1995; Graves, 1981,
The roles of ethnoarchaeology 1985, 1991; Rathje, 1978; Schiffer, 1978; Schiffer and
Skibo, 1997). For example, Schiffer and Skibo (1997)
Four different roles have at one time or another been seek to develop law-like relations between artifact pro-
proposed for ethnoarchaeology within the broader dis- duction systems and their use contexts. These relation-
cipline. None of these roles is discrete, in that it reflects ships create a ‘‘correlative matrix’’ in which specific
an isolated research tradition or a distinct school of performance characteristics are related to specific
thought. Indeed, elements of all four roles are almost physical attributes. However, the conclusions reached
always combined in the research programs proposed by have often been quite contentious (Cunningham, 2003;
specific individuals (Gould, 1971; Kirch, 1978; Long- David and Kramer, 2001, pp. 141–142), and many of
acre, 1978, p. 362; MacEachern, 1996, p. 248). The four the critics have questioned how rigidly patterns in ma-
are: (1) ethnoarchaeology aimed at identifying law-like terial culture can reflect discrete elements of behavior
‘‘translations’’ of the archaeological record; (2) ethn- (also see DeBoer, 1984, 1991; Sullivan, 1978). Thus,
oarchaeology that tests archaeologically derived propo- although there are active attempts to expand the list of
sitions; (3) ethnoarchaeology as a form of ‘‘interpretive ‘‘law-like translations’’ uncovered by ethnoarchaeology,
discovery’’; and (4) ethnoarchaeology aimed at ‘‘raising they appear limited to specific, technical areas of
analogical consciousness.’’ research.

Translating the archaeological record Testing archaeologically derived propositions

The first role often assigned to/adopted by ethnoar- Binford and Sabloff (1982, pp. 148–151) note that
chaeology is to research technical questions about the one major problem in trying to extend the number of
processes that resulted in the creation of the archaeo- laws linking material culture to human behavior is that
logical record. Rejecting any form of a ‘‘Pompeii pre- the proposed relations can never be tested directly by
mise,’’ Schiffer (1976) has initiated a widespread analysis the archaeological record. Archaeological analogues
of taphonomy. Likewise, Binford (1978, 1981) argued risk affirming the consequent (Binford, 1981; Wylie,
that archaeology needed to develop middle-range theory 1982, pp. 389–390) by proposing linkages between be-
that explained how archaeological patterns related to havior and patterns of material culture, and then in-
cultural life (see Trigger, 1989, pp. 359–361). These ap- terpreting the archaeological record as if the very same
proaches outline methodologies to identify law-like linkages applied. Binford (1981, 1983, Binford and
generalizations that enable archaeologists to translate Sabloff, 1982, p. 137) thus suggests that ethnoarchaeo-
human behavior from archaeological remains, taking logical research needs to evaluate deductively proposed
into account the natural processes that intervene be- linkages between dynamics and statics. Archaeology
tween the past and present (also see Binford and Sabloff, provides the context for formulating hypotheses re-
1982). Several lines of analysis have been thus con- garding human behavior, and ethnoarchaeological re-
ducted, including taphonomic studies (e.g., Gifford, search offers a separate context for the evaluation of
1978; Gorecki, 1985), analyses of sampling (e.g., Gould, those hypotheses (e.g., D. Arnold, 2000; Charlton,
1974, 1980; Skibo et al., 1989), usewear analyses (Hay- 1981, pp. 151–152; Gosselain, 2000; Kramer, 1979, pp.
den, 1977; Keeley, 1980; Odell and Odell-Vereecken, 4–5; Stanislawski, 1978; Wiessner, 1983). At times, this
1980; Tringham, 1978; Tringham et al., 1974), the ex- type of ethnoarchaeology can be narrowly defined and
amination of functional efficiency (Carneiro, 1979), and highly operationalized, with the research directed to
analyses of ceramic use-life (e.g., David and Hennig, target specific archaeological questions. Binford and
1972; Longacre, 1985, 1991a; Mayor, 1994; Tani and Sabloff (1982, p. 151), for example, state unequivocally
Longacre, 1999). that ‘‘. . .we must learn to see the dynamics from a
392 J.J. Cunningham / Journal of Anthropological Archaeology 22 (2003) 389–410

perspective appropriate to the archaeological record. developments outside their areas of specialization.
Such a viewpoint should be (1) nonparticipating, (2) Consequently, most archaeologists now have only a
outside, and (3) partitive.’’ Thus, ‘‘mentalist’’ (Schiffer, tenuous grasp of ethnographic methodology, the sorts of
1978, pp. 234–235) and/or ‘‘fortuitous ethnoarchaeolo- data or processes in which social/cultural/postmodern
gies’’ (Longacre, 1991a, p. 6) are rejected in favour of anthropologists are interested, or the complex proce-
formal programs of research directed at solving ar- dures by which ethnographic fieldwork becomes ethno-
chaeological problems (e.g., Krause, 1985). Not infre- graphic texts. Binford (1983, p. 14), for example, notes
quently, such testing has recognized equifinality and his surprise at how few archaeologists working on
produced ‘‘cautionary tales’’ that show how many of hunter-gatherer archaeology in Europe were even aware
the material patterns in which archaeologists are inter- of the relevant ethnographic literature. Likewise, Gould
ested can be created by entirely different sets of causal (1974, p. 30) suggests that while archaeologists may
processes. rigorously assess an interpretation of archaeological
data, there is a tendency to take ethnographic interpre-
Interpretive discovery tations as given. Archaeologists risk mistakenly applying
these analogues—treating, for example, the San Bush-
As Ascher (1961) noted long ago, one of the prime men as prototypical foragers without considering their
roles of ethnoarchaeology is to develop analogies that historical contexts (MacEachern, 1996, pp. 228–229)—
can be used in archaeological interpretation (also see because they possess little ability to assess the validity of
Kleindienst and Watson, 1956). The realization that ethnographic research.
analogies are used in all stages of research has prompted Ethnoarchaeology that aims to develop archaeologyÕs
Stanislawski (1974, p. 18) to define ethnoarchaeology as analogical consciousness tends to produce cautionary
‘‘the direct-observation field study of the forms, manu- tales, the goal of which is to alert archaeologists to the
facture, distribution, meaning, and use of artifacts in complexity of ethnographic study. Gould (1978b, pp.
their institutional setting and social unit correlates 256–257) points out in an early paper that ‘‘It is the
among living, non-industrial peoples for the purpose of fundamental task of ethnoarchaeology to heighten the
constructing better explanatory models to aid archaeo- archaeologistÕs awareness of alternative human behav-
logical analogy and inference.’’ The goal of this type of iors that could have occurred in order to explain the
ethnoarchaeology is to use ethnographic research as a pattern of archaeological facts.’’ Often, cautionary tales
form of ‘‘interpretive discovery’’ (Charlton, 1981, p. simply remind archaeologists that the material culture
152); as a way of identifying cultural practices and/or they study was created by living, breathing people. As
processes that might have affected artifact variability in David (1992, p. 352, emphasis in original) notes:
the past, yet be difficult to identify from only from ar- ‘‘EthnoarchaeologyÕs primary service mission is still the
chaeological research (Longacre, 1991b, p. 95). In con- raising of the analogical consciousness of archaeologists,
trast to the above perspective, ethnoarchaeology offers many of whom prefer their culture dead, sensitizing them
the context for discovery, creating and expanding upon to dimensions of variability and the richness of the rela-
the list of analogies that can be used to interpret the past tionship between humans and their artifacts, including
(e.g., Costin, 2000; Kramer, 1992; LaViolette, 1995; their own bodies.’’ The audience for these cautionary
Lees, 1979; Muntoni, 1999; Riley, 1984). In order to tales is, as often as not, other ethnoarchaeologists, spe-
avoid affirming the consequent, these analogies are often cifically those who argue that ethnoarchaeology must be
used to ‘‘predict the past’’ (Gould, 1980, p. 35); to act as ‘‘non-participatory,’’ ‘‘outside’’ and ‘‘partitive’’:
hypotheses that are deductive tested against archaeo-
logical remains (Atherton, 1983, pp. 96–97; Watson, Often, however, [archaeological] forays into ethnogra-
1980, p. 56). phy are limited in time and controlled in focus, cluttered
with specific questions to ask and measurements to be ta-
ken. What I want to argue here is that there is something
Raising analogical consciousness
to be said for a fuller ethnographic experience that in-
cludes moments to pause and to be edified by aspects
Ethnoarchaeology as interpretive discovery has a of those ‘‘thousand kinds of life’’ we could have lived
second form that is not tightly bound to a program of (Geertz, 1973, p. 45). (Kus, 1997, p. 200).
testing. The goal of this type of ethnoarchaeology is to
raise the ‘‘analogical consciousness’’ of their archaeo- The critiques from this area of ethnoarchaeology
logical colleagues (after David, 1992). As Chang (1967, have struck both sides of the processual and postpro-
p. 227) recognized over 35 years ago, the ‘‘general an- cessual divide. Stark (1993, pp. 96–97; see also Kus,
thropologist’’ who has sufficient training in the four 1997) note that there is a paradox in postprocessual
fields of anthropology is a mythical hero. The rapid research: these investigators examine symbolism,
expansion of the four subdisiplines makes it all but meaning and power by, first, conducting relatively brief
impossible for researchers to stay abreast of major field excursions and, second, by seeking to identify
J.J. Cunningham / Journal of Anthropological Archaeology 22 (2003) 389–410 393

broad cognitive frameworks that lie behind daily Analogy


practice. As Kus notes:
No archaeologist is worth his salt, it can almost be said,
We need to wield carefully the vocabulary of ‘‘la longue unless he [sic] makes an analogy or two in every mono-
duree’’ so it does not encompass the entirety of causality graph he writes (Chang, 1967, p. 229).
or wield too cavalierly the authority of explanation. Per-
haps more importantly we also need to be careful of the At first blush, the diverse roles outlined above for
vocabulary of ‘‘la courte duree.’’ The ‘‘midrange’’ vocab-
ethnoarchaeology appear haphazard and eclectic with
ulary of ‘‘power,’’ ‘‘belief,’’ ‘‘custom,’’ and ‘‘ideology,’’
little evidence of an underlying unity. Yet they are linked
for instance, is of a ‘‘contentlessness’’ and categorical ab-
straction so uncharacteristic of the ‘‘science of the con- by a common concern with analogy. Wylie defines
crete’’ (Levi-Strauss, 1962, pp. 1–33) that it analogy as:
underestimates and potentially simplifies other cultural
the selective transposition of information from source to
realities. To approach other cultural realities in terms
subject on the basis of a comparison that, fully devel-
of ‘‘sensuous human practice’’ is evocative in a way that
oped, specifies how the ‘‘terms’’ (elements) compared
‘‘meaning’’ and ‘‘symbol’’ are not, because meaning and
are similar (positive components), different (negative
symbol reflectively distance themselves from experience
components) or of unknown likeness (neutral compo-
and from the ‘‘materiality’’ of the senses and emotions.
nents). . . An argument by analogy, proper, involves the
(Kus, 1997, p. 211).
claim that given the similarities and differences specified
KusÕ critique indicates that we should not fall into in the premises, some specific aspects of the neutral
analogy may also be assumed to be similar or, to com-
the trap of seeing postprocessualism as the ‘‘subject
prise further points of positive analogy. . . (Wylie, 1985,
friendly’’ and ‘‘people laden’’ alternative to processual- pp. 93–94).
ism—of taking HodderÕs word when he claims that ‘‘In
so far as ethnoarchaeology limits itself to non-partici- One of the reasons that analogyÕs role in ethnoar-
patory analysis Ôfrom the outsideÕ, it is simply Ôbad chaeology has remained obscured is because archaeol-
anthropologyÕ from the postprocessual viewpoint’’ ogists have been cautious about analogical forms of
(Hodder, 1986, p. 95). Indeed, Kus demonstrates that, in reasoning, and particularly fearful of speciously af-
many ways, the ethnographic research enacted by firming the consequent. Analogies were originally used
postprocessual archaeologists, offered under the rubric in accordance with unilinear evolutionary models of
of ‘‘material culture studies,’’ is as ‘‘outside’’ and as culture that treated traditional societies as relics of
‘‘nonparticipatory’’ as the ethnoarchaeology it would earlier stages of cultural evolution (Ascher, 1961;
seek to replace (see below). Transporting specific ar- Orme, 1981; Stahl, 1993; Trigger, 1989; Wylie, 1985).
chaeological questions to an ethnographic setting re- The evolutionary stage formed the uniformitarianist
moves ethnoarchaeologists from the complexities of principle that linked the present to the past, often re-
their research settings, regardless of whether their focus sulting in the unwarranted and uncritical ‘‘mapping’’
is ecology or power and ideology. These cautionary tales of modern behaviors directly onto archaeological data.
are not simply warnings about equifinality but a re- Wylie (1985) argues that the rejection of unilinear
minder to archaeologists that the causal frameworks in evolution resulted in a comparable rejection of analogy
which material culture is created and used are complex and other forms of uniformitarianism. The outcome
and often quite fleeting. was on the one hand to pursue research that avoided
While some researchers see ‘‘the ethnoarchaeology of any interpretation beyond archaeological remains
cautionary tales’’ as little more than an obnoxious spec- (cultural–historical archaeology, artifact physics) and,
tator (to borrow SimmsÕ vocabulary), other researchers on the other, an attempt to develop and employ non-
have found cautionary tales to have an important role in analogical (non-inductive) forms of inference (Wylie,
the development of analogical explanations. As an ele- 1985, 1988, p. 141). Rather than making inductively
ment of discovery, Charlton (1981, p. 150) argues that based interpretations of archaeological remains, ar-
cautionary tales increase the amount of basic, factual chaeologists were entreated to rigorously and deduc-
knowledge archaeologists can use to develop analogies. tively test hypotheses (Wylie, 1985, pp. 84–93). Under
Hole (1978, p. 129) likewise suggests that cautionary tales a program of testing, ‘‘analogy’’ was replaced by
aid in the development of general theory that can allow ‘‘model’’ or ‘‘hypothesis,’’ marking the supposed
archaeologists to develop increasingly accurate inter- shift from a pre-scientific (inductive) to a scientific
pretations of archaeological patterns. The key for eth- (deductive) study of the past (see especially Schiffer,
nography aimed at raising an analogical consciousness is 1978, pp. 233–234).
not to ‘‘do ethnography’’ with a specific archaeological The distinction between inductive and deductive
problem in mind, but to seek a better understanding forms of argument, however, has proven more rhetor-
of the diverse ways material culture operates in living ical than real, and analogical inferences—blatantly
societies. stated or veneered in scientific terms—are now generally
394 J.J. Cunningham / Journal of Anthropological Archaeology 22 (2003) 389–410

recognized as an inescapable part of archaeological in source and subject contexts, or b, to identify material
research (Gould and Watson, 1982, p. 360; Charlton, patterns that could indicate that an alternate suite of
1981; Wylie, 1982, p. 399). Rigid frameworks of testing causal processes created the pattern for which the
meant to counter an affirmation of the consequent when analogy was originally made. Once again, the key to
interpretive hypotheses (analogies) are transferred from testing the inference is to know from source-side eth-
present to past are misplaced because, being inductive, noarchaeological research the affect different causal
archaeological interpretations always affirm the conse- mechanisms have on material, cultural, and behavioral
quent (see Graves, 1981, p. 86; Wylie, 1982, pp. 390– patterns. With this sort of knowledge, it becomes pos-
391). This is not to demote archaeological inference to sible to reconfigure processes to explain behavior that
mere speculation. As Ebert (1979, p. 60) reminds us, may differ substantially from any modern situation
‘‘. . .analogy is, in itself, no more precarious or dan- (Wylie, 1985, 1988).
gerous than any other inductive procedure.’’ If the pure
certainty of the sort sought through deductive testing is Discussion
out of reach, archaeologists are still quite capable of
identifying different degrees of plausibility in their in- WylieÕs description of analogy provides us with a way
terpretations (Charlton, 1981; Ebert, 1979; Wylie, 1982, to see how the different roles adopted by ethnoarchae-
1985, 1988). Wylie (1982, 1985) has identified two ology relate to analogical reasoning. There are two
techniques archaeologists can use to assess analogies components to the program outlined above. The first
and her suggestions hint at how archaeologists can, requisite is to develop knowledge about causal processes
over time, build increasingly secure claims about the and their affects on material variability in ethnographic
past. First, while analogies can be, and have been, contexts, and the second is to enact testing procedures
based on formal relations or on constant conjunctions, that assess the validity of transferring analogical prop-
in order to escape the problem of simple analogy that ositions between source and subject side contexts. The
underwrote unilinear evolution, archaeologists and different roles that ethnoarchaeology has adopted in
ethnoarchaeologists should focus their research on the archaeology anticipate these two requirements.
causal relations behind observable patterns. As Ebert, The ethnoarchaeology focused on ‘‘interpretive dis-
1979, pp. 60–61; emphasis added) notes, analogies can coveries’’ and on the ‘‘raising of analogical conscious-
be validated ‘‘. . .if it can be argued that the process in ness’’ are most specifically tied to developing our
operation on both sides is similar or in some way bear understanding of how causal processes relate to material
upon another. . .it must be shown that certain processes and cultural patterns in ethnographic contexts. While
are in operation or determinant in the living case; these one element of this research is the quest to identify
processes are then applied to the archaeological case.’’ previously unknown causal forces, much of the work
More importantly, in order to develop greater security done by both these roles aims at developing a better
in our analogical inferences, source-side ethnoarchaeo- understanding of how previously identified processes
logical research should be expanded as fully as possible relate to their boundary conditions. Boundary condi-
to identify valid relations between material, cultural, tions are other factors in the causal environment that
and behavioral patterns and their underlying causal have a direct bearing on the causal affects of the process
mechanisms (Wylie, 1985, p. 101; 1988, p. 146). As under investigation. Typically, boundary conditions are
Wylie explains (1985, p. 101), ‘‘. . .[analogical] in- other causal processes or structural conditions created
quiry. . .must be specifically designed to determine what from the operation of past casual processes that facili-
causal connections hold between the material and cul- tate, amplify or interfere with the operation of the pro-
tural or behavioral variables of interest, and under cess being studied. BowserÕs (2000) study of decorative
what conditions these connections may or may not be variation on Conambo ceramics is perhaps the best re-
expected to hold.’’ Second, the degree of similarity and cent work that fits under the heading of ‘‘ethnoarchae-
difference between the processual frameworks operating ology as interpretive discovery.’’ Her study introduces
in the two contexts needs to be established by testing. archaeologists to an entirely new relation between ma-
In the case of an ethnographic analogue applied to an terial variation and cultural process. She demonstrates
archaeological context: ‘‘This would [a] amount to a that ceramic decoration is causally related to womenÕs
specification of what (else) ought to be in the record as political factions within the village of Conambo rather
a consequence of the postulated past processes and than to the discrete ethnic units that are present. In
conditions if they did in fact exist and operate as hy- addition to identifying this process, Bowser (2000, p.
pothesized or, [b] more powerfully, if conditions were 244) is also careful to outline its boundary conditions for
different than postulated’’ (Wylie, 1982, pp. 396–398, archaeologists: ‘‘. . .it is precisely in small-scale societies,
note 6). The goal of the testing is, in the case of a, to where politics are consensus-driven, pottery is made in
seek additional similarities in the material record that the domestic contexts for domestic use, and there is
would be expected if the same causal processes operated relatively little separation between public and domestic
J.J. Cunningham / Journal of Anthropological Archaeology 22 (2003) 389–410 395

contexts, that we should expect to find evidence of sig- variation. In this regard, both ‘‘interpretive discovery’’
nification of political identity in domestic pottery style.’’ ethnoarchaeology and the ethnoarchaeology aimed at
It is worthwhile noting that in outlining relations be- ‘‘raising analogical consciousness’’ elaborate source-side
tween political factions and decorative variability, research in the way that Wylie (1985, 1988) sees as
Bowser simultaneously adds to our understanding of crucial to the development of analogical inferences.
one of the boundary conditions for ethnic symbolism. The second element of the analogical program re-
She reports that pottersÕ ethnic identities were recog- quires less explanation. Analogical inferences are valid
nizable in the ceramic variation, but that political fac- when archaeologists can assume that the causal pro-
tions were identified with more accuracy by women in cesses they are investigating operate on both sides of an
the village (Bowser, 2000, p. 238). The point is not that analogical relationship—a validation that requires them
‘‘ethnic symbolism’’ fails to exert a causal affect on to demonstrate either that similar assemblages of sup-
variability, but seemingly that its effect is supplanted by porting processes (boundary conditions) also operate in
effects that engaged political factions exert on decorative source and subject contexts, or that, while the sup-
variability. In future cases where archaeologists suspect porting processes vary, there is no significant change in
that decorative variation is caused by ethnic symbolism, the causal effect of the specific processes in which they
they will need now to consider whether political factions are interested. For example, once an archaeological
are also present and act as a limiting factor. pattern is attributed to specific causal processes, the
Although it is more rarely concerned directly analogy is tested by looking for further patterning that
with causal process, an ethnoarchaeology that ‘‘raises would be expected if the causal processes were operat-
analogical consciousness’’ likewise broadens our un- ing as hypothesized. Testing of this sort is most often
derstandings of the causal influences operating in ethno- found in the daily work of normal, hypothesis-driven
graphic contexts. Rather than focusing on specific archaeology that seeks to establish independent lines of
processes, this approach to ethnoarchaeology tends to evidence, or ‘‘horizontal independence’’ (Wylie, 2000, p.
reference the general ethnographic experiences of its 232), for a given interpretation. However, the same,
practitioners and the existing critical ethnographic lit- basic procedures are followed in the ethnoarchaeologi-
erature. Here ethnoarchaeologists aim to tell their peers, cal testing of archaeological propositions. A well
especially those archaeologists who advocate perspec- known example is Polly WiessnerÕs (1983) assessment of
tives reliant on cultureÕs simplicity and uniformity, of the the archaeologically derived hypothesis that symbolic
fluidity and complexity of their own experiences in eth- information should be encoded in the ‘‘non-functional’’
nographic settings. It would be easy to dismiss these elements of San projectile points. Wiessner tested this
critiques as simply the tropes of postmodern exuberance. hypothesis by asking San Bushman to tell her about the
But, if we read process into them, we can see that they sorts of information they could identify from attributes
are warnings to archaeologists that the processual ma- on iron points. She discovered that social information
trix that creates material variation is incredibly complex was communicated through point attributes that were
and much of it remains unknown. These critiques are clearly utilitarian, nullifying the initial hypothesis.
not simply the provenance of ethnoarchaeologists. Stahl Notably, both archaeological and ethnoarchaeological
(1993), for example, has pointed out that the New Ar- testing are best considered always to be part of ongoing
chaeologyÕs focus on testing meant that many re- programs of research. In contrast to the hypothetico-
searchers ceased to ask whether the propositions they deductive models that were originally associated with
were testing in archaeological contexts had any ethno- processual testing programs, testing never ‘‘deductively
graphic validity. She echoes many ethnoarchaeological confirms’’ our propositions in a way that finalizes our
critiques that target archaeological models which define knowledge of a causal relation. More elaborate pro-
a priori structures of causal process. For example, the grams of testing and more innovative source-side
quick jump to testing in the New Archaeology was research will always be needed. As BowserÕs and
possible because BinfordÕs (1962) tri-part model of cul- WiessnerÕs works demonstrate, archaeological testing
ture was widely believed to identify the basic structure of and ethnoarchaeological source-side research continues
the causal influences on material variability. In contrast, to fine-tune our understanding of the causal relations
ethnoarchaeology that aims at ‘‘raising analogical con- that tie ethnicity to material variability (also see
sciousness’’ argues that even the basic structures of the Cunningham, 2001). At its most basic, testing assesses
casual influences on material, cultural and behavioral the validity of transferring information from one con-
patterns have yet to be defined. Hence, ‘‘fortuitous text to another. Thus, testing reflects a key methodo-
ethnoarchaeology’’ or ‘‘ethnoarchaeology for ethnoar- logical element in archaeologyÕs epistemology that,
chaeologyÕs sake’’ is not a trivial pastime, but, as when combined with source-side research conducted by
Charlton (1981), Hole (1978), and Kus (1997) note, an the roles outlined previously, creates all the elements
important step toward understanding how processes necessary to advance archaeologyÕs ongoing investiga-
articulate in ethnographic contexts and create material tion of the past.
396 J.J. Cunningham / Journal of Anthropological Archaeology 22 (2003) 389–410

I have not yet discussed one of the four roles for example, ecological/adaptive/evolutionary processes
ethnoarchaeology identified above, namely, the quest by typical of their common materialist orientation are of
Binford, Schiffer and others to identify law-like relations primary importance in most processual applications of
that translate directly the archaeological record. This analogy, while the cultural/historical processes are fore
role for ethnoarchaeology is unique. In contrast to those fronted in postprocessual analogues. The presence of
already described above, it is not tied to the general ‘‘core universals’’ at the heart of these different partisan
requirements of analogical reasoning so much as it is to interests has splintered ethnoarchaeological research
the monistic aspiration of the processual cultural model in a way that limits its ability to illuminate how causal
and a very particularistic notion of middle-range theory. processes combine in the creation of material patterns.
As a result, I will examine this role in more detail later in To make this point, in the following discussion I will
the following section. first outline how ‘‘core universals’’ have been used in
processual and postprocessual ethnoarchaeology, and
then I will examine the key problems that have been
‘‘Core universals’’ and ethnoarchaeology created by the reliance on ‘‘core universals.’’

The above roles for ethnoarchaeology can be un- Processual ethnoarchaeology


derstood as components of archaeological epistemol-
ogy. As such, the roles possess a degree of theoretical The new New Archaeology and its rival siblings,
unity and, at least in this sense, they are free from behavioral and evolutionary archaeology, are commit-
charges of eclecticism. However, ethnoarchaeology is ted to the idea that universal principles of culture exist in
painfully eclectic in another area. Furthermore, this how humans meet the material requirements of their
eclecticism has stunted significantly the potential of the existence. For the New Archaeology, similar environ-
methodological program outlined above. Much of the mental settings created similar cultural responses, thus
present work in ethnoarchaeology rests on the idea that comparable environments were identified as the most
only a limited range of processes have enough cross- important condition for the application of analogy.
cultural uniformity to be used in analogy. I refer to AscherÕs original definition of the ‘‘New Analogy,’’
these processes as ‘‘core universals’’ because they are which predates but became an important element of the
generally assumed to have a universal or quasi-uni- ‘‘New Archaeology’’ (Binford, 1967), states quite ex-
versal causal influence over material variability. ‘‘Core plicitly that ‘‘In summary, then, the canon is: seek
universals’’ are used in analogy in two related forms: analogies in cultures which manipulate similar environ-
sometimes they are the foundation of complete models ments in similar ways’’ (Ascher, 1961, p. 319; also see
of culture that define a priori a structure of processes Atherton, 1983).2
and, at other times, they are low-level bridging princi- The ethnoarchaeological work of Gould (1971, 1974,
ples that often rest on certain methodological ‘‘givens.’’ 1978a, 1978b, 1980; Gould and Watson, 1982) is the
Different partisan interests in archaeology, specifically most explicit and fully developed attempt to outline how
those found in the processual–postprocessual opposi- uniformities in meeting material requirements can be
tion, have championed entirely different processes as used to develop analogical inferences. When compared
‘‘core universals.’’ Admittedly, significant variation to other processualists, Gould is also quite moderate—if
does exist within the processual and postprocessual inconsistent—in his commitment to materialism. In
schools, yet each school shares the belief that specific keeping with the scientism of the New Archaeology,
families of process primarily ‘‘drive’’ culture.1 For Gould explicitly avoids referring to analogy except to
dismiss it as a useful methodology. Instead, he suggests
1
I have elsewhere (Cunningham, n.d.) used Gross and
LevittÕs (1994) ‘‘driven’’ versus ‘‘influenced’’ distinction to talk
2
about the processual–postprocessual debate. For example, most AscherÕs suggestion seems to emphasize relationships
processualists and postprocessualists would recognise that between human behavior and ecology. In a footnote, for
culture exhibits traits typical of both ‘‘materialist’’ and ‘‘ideal- example, Ascher (1961, p. 318) identifies a third category of
ist’’ cultural ontologies (see Cunningham, 2003 on this point). analogy based on ‘‘properties common to all men’’ which seem
The key difference lies in the relative importance assigned to to refer to biophysical continuities held across the entire species
each—whether cultural behavior is ‘‘driven’’ by adaptive strives regardless of their ecological context. He finds this, however,
or evolutionary requirements and ‘‘influenced’’ by ideology or generally uninteresting because they do not factor in ‘‘the
whether it is ‘‘driven’’ by ideological process (negotiation of particular patterns of a prehistoric people in carrying out. . .ac-
power, constitution of meaning) and ‘‘influenced’’ by material tivities.’’ Interestingly, both biological and ecological of conti-
constraints/opportunities. Despite the diversity within proces- nuities are used by Binford to justify the paradigmatic
sual and postprocessual schools of thought, they each share a independence of middle-range theory (Wylie, 1995, p. 23; e.g.,
common understanding of what processes ‘‘drive’’ behavior. see Wallaert-P^etreÕs, 1999 work on handedness among potters).
J.J. Cunningham / Journal of Anthropological Archaeology 22 (2003) 389–410 397

that certain behaviors are analogous in the past and . . .there emerges a clear and convincing alternative to the
present because they are determined by uniform opera- argument by analogy—namely, the argument by anom-
tion of covering laws (see Gould, 1978b, 1980, pp. 37– aly. . . Only by looking for and recognizing anomalies
38). These covering laws are not general, but are found to general patterns of conformity to utilitarian expecta-
tions in human behavior can we reliably infer when
in ‘‘low-level eco-utilitarian kinds of explanations’’
and under what conditions symbolic and ideational fac-
(Gould and Watson, 1982, p. 367; see also Gould, tors make a difference in the ways people actually behave
1978a,b, 1980). As he explains: (Gould, 1980, p. xi; emphasis in original).
. . .many principles developed in evolutionary biology
and ecology can safely be assumed to have operated uni-
GouldÕs critics have pointed out that the argument
formly in the past as they do in the present, and they can by anomaly is as analogical as any other form of
usefully be applied to the study of the human species ethnoarchaeology (Gould and Watson, 1982; Watson,
providing one accepts the notion that human traditions 1980, p. 57; 1982, p. 446; Wylie, 1982, 1985; Charlton,
may expand the total ecosystem to include social and 1981, p. 151). However, it is not GouldÕs analogy/
symbolic components. So those aspects of human behav- anomaly distinction that is most interesting. Rather, it is
ior that are most closely related to the physical and bio- how Gould uses the distinction between analogy/
logical processes are also those that most reliably lend anomaly to assign differing degrees of ‘‘security’’ to
themselves to the uniformitarianist assumption (Gould, different analogical inferences according to which cul-
1980, p. 50).
tural processes they reference. With an important ca-
. . .one must look first at the eco-utilitarian relationships veat, the result is largely a rewording of the new
that occur in the situation one observes and see to what archaeologyÕs existing model of culture (Binford, 1962,
extent variation in the observed behavior can be ac- 1965). Gould and Binford both share the assumptions
counted for by these immediate circumstances. If one that (1) ecological processes are the foundation upon
has exhausted this level of explanation without totally which all cultural behavior rests and (2) that cultural–
satisfactory results, then one is entitled to go on to the
historical processes (GouldÕs ideational factors) hold a
next higher level of explanation, namely the ideational
realm of shared traditions (Gould and Watson, 1982,
secondary (epiphenomenal) position in culture.
p. 367). Eco-utilitarian processes—responding directly to the
ecological constraints/opportunities of the environ-
While these quotes may be read as a belief that all ment—operate as ‘‘core universals’’ that should be
‘‘culture’’ is adaptive, Gould (1980, p. 43) is careful to unaffected by changes in non-ecological processes.
distance himself from this position, which he associates Cultural–historical processes are thus largely emergent
with BinfordÕs statement that culture is ‘‘manÕs extra- from eco-utilitarian processes. The implication in terms
somatic means of adaptation’’ (Binford, 1962, p. 218).3 of analogy is that law-like relations between ecological
Instead, he argues that some behaviors may be largely contexts and eco-utilitarian behavior validate uniform-
independent of eco-utilitarian concerns and that these itarianist assumptions and facilitate archaeological in-
behaviors may also have an affect on archaeological vestigation. In the terminology of analogy, the similar
variability. The problem of identifying these non-utili- causal influences emanating from similar ecological
tarian, non-uniform residues is solved by first identi- contexts are the only boundary conditions necessary for
fying ethnographically the covering laws that analogical inference.
determine eco-utilitarian regularities and then, when However, GouldÕs preoccupation with anomaly
the archaeological findings deviate from these laws, to suggests an interesting addition to the Binfordian model
move on to more normative and particularistic expla- of culture. Under the Binfordian model, cultural/his-
nations. He deems this approach the ‘‘argument by torical processes are not boundary conditions for eco-
anomaly’’: utilitarian processes. While cultural/historical processes
may exist in the form of style, they have no influence
over adaptive processes, which are a direct and unme-
diated response to environmental potentials. However,
3
Gould uses ‘‘culture’’ in a very restricted fashion. Culture Gould insists that ‘‘anomalies’’ can occur when ‘‘idea-
refers specifically to norms which he distinguishes from the tional factors’’ (cultural–historical processes) interfere
animal-like eco-utilitarian concerns that generate uniformities. with a societyÕs direct response to an environmental
It is also worth noting that the differences between Binford and situation. The implication is that, under certain condi-
Gould are not nearly as marked as Gould would believe.
tions, a societyÕs response to an environment is not
Binford likewise makes room for non-adaptive behaviors under
the definition of stylistic variation (see Cunningham, 2003). The
unmediated (not at all law-like), but instead is depen-
key difference between them is that Gould argues cultural– dent on specific contextual factors; notably, the opera-
historical factors do not simply emerge from ecological tion of other processes, including those typically
constraints/opportunities, but in rare cases may actually influ- assigned to the realm of ideology. This is a significant
ence the final character of ecological adaptation. revision of the a priori structure of processes typically
398 J.J. Cunningham / Journal of Anthropological Archaeology 22 (2003) 389–410

asserted in processual orientations, and it would seem to Likewise, Ebert (1979) and Krause (1985) have ex-
undermine the tight causal relationship between plicitly argued that causal processes should be the uni-
environment and culture that Gould relies upon for form cultural elements behind analogical inferences; but
archaeological inferences. Indeed, rather than environ- at least for Krause (1985), processes are narrowly
mental similarities, it would seem that other contextual identified with the material influences in ceramic pro-
factors, including the operation of cultural–historical duction. The causal regularities that are appropriate to
processes, would need to be considered to validate any archaeological and ethnoarchaeological research are
eco-utilitarian analogy. thus restricted to only those that are thought to have a
GouldÕs advocacy for nomological, eco-utilitarian widespread cross-cultural application because they are
universals—and his reluctance to give them true uni- unaffected by the causal forces affecting other areas of
versal status—brings into focus an important distinc- culture. Gould himself seems to follow this general ad-
tion. Although ‘‘process’’ has always been present in vocacy for eco-utilitarian universals. His concept of
the literature, archaeologists concerned with spuriously anomaly, however, would seem to argue for a more
affirming the consequent have argued quite strenuously nuanced and process-based understanding of causal
that archaeological inferences must be based on uni- regularities.
versal causal forces rather than watered down causal
regularities like process (e.g., Schiffer, 1978). Both Postprocessual ethnoarchaeology
Schiffer (1978, p. 240) and Gould (1978b, p. 251), for
example, recognize processes as the temporal and In contrast to processual research, postprocessual
spatial manifestations of causal laws, and then state researchers have selected an entirely different set of
that it is more important to identify the underlying uniformities that they believe to hold in the past and
law-like operations.4 For them, process is always present contexts. Postprocessualists have diligently
identified through reference to laws, which are found worked to challenge claims that the causal relation-
in a small number of ecological givens. As Schiffer ships between material circumstances and human be-
explains (1978, p. 240, emphasis in original), the laws havior can generate secure propositions useful for
he seeks are a better basis for unifomitarianism than archaeological interpretations. DeBoer (1984), for ex-
are processes: ample, undermines the use of least effort principle in
ceramic studies by suggesting that ‘‘the ultimate least
A statement of this doctrine which seems particularly
useful is that the laws of nature are constant. Thus, when-
effort strategy. . .would be to make no pottery at all!’’
ever or wherever the same process is operating, it is sub- (p. 540). Similarly, Gosselain (1994, p. 106) has also
ject to the same law or laws. This approach differs from noted the flexibility of the material constraints acting
the view that ‘‘the process found operating today also on artifact production systems, and concluded that
operated in the past’’ in ways that make it better suited ‘‘technological systems are completely embedded in
for anthropological research. Quite clearly, the process culture in much the same way as decorative motifs,
of urbanization and state formation observable today religious beliefs or kinship systems.’’ At the heart of
were not in operation 10,000 years ago; whenever and the postprocessual models is the assumed universality
wherever they are found, however, some laws will apply of a hermeneutic involvement in the world, under
(laws that specify in their boundary conditions that cer-
which power, hegemony and resistance replace
tain processes, like urbanization, must be present). Our
notions of uniformitarianism must take into account
the processual reliance on adaptationist and Darwin-
the fact that not all processes are distributed uniformly ian approaches (Hodder, 1982a,b, 1985). Indeed,
among all sociocultural systems. postprocessual researchers have largely inverted the
model proposed by processual archaeology, placing
processes related to ideology and symbolism in the
foundational role in culture as ‘‘core universals,’’ and
relegating ecological concerns to a secondary and
4
Gould is on record as stating that process should also be a non-deterministic position (see Cunningham, 2003 for
focus in research: ‘‘. . .the archaeologist is faced not only with a discussion; e.g., Shanks and Tilley, 1982, 1987,
discovering laws that determine certain aspects of human 1992).
behavior. . . but, more importantly, with discovering the This shift is often described as the move from
processes of manipulation that allow people to adapt laws to ethnoarchaeology, which is usually defined as a
their purposes’’ (Gould, 1978b, p. 251). Elsewhere (Gould,
commitment to materialism, toward ‘‘material culture
1980, p. 42) he has advocated that we focus on ‘‘propositions’’
rather than laws, with propositions closely resembling other studies,’’ which focus on the investigation of how
definitions of process. However, a close reading of his work people construct their material worlds (Appadurai,
shows that process is defined according to his overall model of 1986; Conkey, 1989; Hodder, 1986; Miller, 1983, 1985).
anomaly, which maintains the law-like influence of ecological Rather than an adaptive response, culture and
stimuli (see text). material culture are understood in relation to meaning.
J.J. Cunningham / Journal of Anthropological Archaeology 22 (2003) 389–410 399

In ConkeyÕs terms (Conkey, 1989, p. 20; 1990), that the wish to dissolve ethnoarchaeology into
culture is primarily a ‘‘constitutive process.’’ Hodder material culture studies is largely rhetorical. Closer
explains: readings of Bourdieu (see contributions to Jarker et
al., 1990) suggest at least implicitly that much of his
Ethnoarchaeology, characteristically confined to the Ôar- work does not so much synthesize materialism and
chaeologicalÕ, material dimension, has little to offer those idealism as it alternates between the two depending on
who wish to explore the relationships between culture the specific cultural practice being analyzed (as is
and material practices, between structured belief and ac- found, for example, in BourdieuÕs [1984] opposition
tion. Even though. . .discussion of the material necessar-
between the necessity driven existence of the French
ily employs assumptions about cultural meanings, the
lower classes and ‘‘aesthetic life’’ of the elites; see
latter are not brought to the surface and critically exam-
ined within a narrow ethnoarchaeology (Hodder, 1986, Gelbert, 1999 for an archaeological parallel). Collage-
p. 97). building of this sort does little to solve the nuances of
the materialist–idealist and structure-agency dichoto-
Ultimately a reformulated ethnoarchaeology will con- mies in modern social theory (see Stern, 2003 for an
tribute to material culture studies since. . .the meanings overview of the divisions in contemporary practice
of material items can only be adequately understood theory). Moreover, despite several claims to the effect
by placing them more and more fully into a cultural that both ecological and cultural–historical processes
and historical context (Hodder, 1986, p. 97). affect material culture (see Gosselain, 1994; Hodder,
1982a; but see David and Kramer, 2001), most post-
Two main tendencies have emerged in material processual approaches that use practice theory remain
culture studies. As mentioned above, the first is an uninterested in exploring relations between ecological
adherence to a form of idealism that forefronts his- processes and behavioral patterns (Ortner, 1984 notes
torically based cognitive processes. This often appears a similar tendency in how practice theory in used
in a concern with meaning (Conkey, 1989; Hodder, cultural anthropology). Advocates of practice theory
1982a, 1986), information flows/decision making (van like Hodder (e.g., 1982b, 1985) have tended to restrict
der Leeuw, 1984), symbolic messaging (Biehl, 1999), their analyses to the symbolic structures lying behind
and the flexibility in technological choices (van der experience and the reconstitution of these structures in
Leeuw and Papousek, 1992). The second element is a daily discourses of social power. Ethnoarchaeologi-
focus on cultural processes that influence behavior in cally, these structures are found in analyses of ‘‘style
the short term. Long-term culture change, such as grammars’’ (e.g., Greenberg, 1975; for sources and an
longue duree shifts in subsistence or social organization, overview, see Hardin, 1979, 1983, 1984). Hodder
are far less important to most postprocessualists than (1991) notes that among the Ilchamus, calabashes in-
understanding how individuals negotiate their place stead of grain pots are decorated because cattle pas-
within daily contexts. One of the important implica- toralism and milk have more symbolic import than
tions to follow from this line of reasoning is that ma- does grain and agriculture. While the calabashes are
terial culture—as a part of the constitutive process—is decorated according to notions of identity and beauty
not necessarily a direct reflection of social realities. (1991, pp. 80–82), he argues that these decorations
Instead, material culture can be used actively in the also reflect a mental structure that oppose male to
assertion of political and social power, and/or personal female, red to white, and blood to milk. These op-
identity (Shanks and Tilley, 1982, 1992). The active positions are then played out in daily practice and
role of material culture in these political strategies mobilized in discourses about modernization and what
suggests that archaeological patterns may indicate it means to be ‘‘a good wife.’’ Other studies, such as
imagined or even inverted versions of social reality van der Leeuw and PapousekÕs work in northern
(Hodder, 1982a,b). The two elements together have Mexico (1992; also see Miller, 1985), use similar
drawn material culture studies to BourdieuÕs (1977; also techniques to look at morphological attributes on
see 1998) notion of practice. Practice theory is often ceramics.
put forward as a solution to the major problems Postprocessualism, then, is a substantial inversion of
in ethnoarchaeology, material culture studies and— the material assumptions that govern most processual
indeed—social theory. Both Conkey (1989, p. 22) and analyses. However, the two camps are remarkably
Porr (1999, pp. 8–10), for example, have suggested similar in their tendency to rely upon a limited number
that BourdieuÕs notion of practice solves the material- of ‘‘secure’’ causal processes that they believe can be
ist–idealist dichotomy, allowing for the eventual used to develop analogical inferences that will hold
dissolution of ethnoarchaeology within material culture across cultural contexts. Despite postprocessualist re-
studies. luctance to frame their analysis in terms of causes,
While the potential for rapprochement may exist Wylie (1995, p. 22) has noted that the normative ori-
within practice theory, recent applications indicate entation advocated by postprocessualism can be as
400 J.J. Cunningham / Journal of Anthropological Archaeology 22 (2003) 389–410

explanatory as the processual model ‘‘if, in fact, human contributions to van der Leeuw and Pritchard, 1984;
behavior is structured by conformity norms.’’ HodderÕs see especially Krause, 1985; Pritchard and van der
consistency in referencing structural oppositions in his Leeuw, 1984, p. 10; Schiffer and Skibo, 1997; Vidale et
analyses of stylistic behavior (e.g., 1982a, 1990a,b, al., 1992). Roux (1999, p. 155) for example, attempts
1991) indicates that he does seem to believe these to identify ‘‘universals of processes’’ which: ‘‘relate to
structures to have a causal effect on behavior and mechanisms or laws that explain physical, cultural or
material variation. When combined with other state- biological regularities. They relate to principles that
ments claiming that all culture is ‘‘stylistic’’ (e.g., ‘‘the have been established by higher level explanations in
economy is as much stylistic as the decoration on a other disciplines.’’ As she explains: ‘‘Searching for
potsherd’’ [Hodder, 1985, p. 10]), the binary mental transcultural regularities presupposes uniformitarian
structure and its reconstitution in daily life through principles. These are more specifically congruent with
negotiations of power becomes both the primary causal a technological approach where both the constraints
mechanism that impacts behavior and the cultural and resources of the raw material and technical
continuity that enables inferences about the archaeo- practices are analyzed. . .’’ (Roux, 1999, p. 157). These
logical record (e.g., Hodder, 1991). In much the same low-level technological factors include production se-
way that Gould relied upon eco-utilitarian universals, quences and the use of natural resources, which Roux
Hodder and other postprocessualists rely on causal believes allows her to ‘‘. . .assess the technical part,
regularities located in ideology to act as ‘‘core which does not vary between the past and the present’’
universals.’’ (p. 165).
As Raab and Goodyear (1984) have pointed out,
Middle-range theory and low-level givens however, the preoccupation in archaeology with
middle-range theory as a methodological problem re-
In addition to differences in their respective foun- lated to the translation of statics to dynamics is different
dational processes, processual and postprocessual ar- from the more hermeneutical way middle-range theory
chaeologies are occasionally thought to adhere to was first defined in sociology (Raab and Goodyear,
entirely different epistemologies. Processual ethnoar- 1984, p. 262):
chaeology has long been identified with middle-range
theory, whereas postprocessual research has been de- [Social science] theorists advanced the [middle range]
fined in terms of a hermeneutic approach (Kosso, concept, not as a substantive theory of any particular
1991; Raab and Goodyear, 1984). Under processual- phenomenon, but rather as middle-range theorizing.
The essential point was to develop a strategy for inte-
ism, middle-range theory was aimed at developing
grating research problems and data into cumulative bo-
low-level, inductively based nomological propositions—
dies of scientific knowledge in which theories of limited
often about site formation processes—that translated scope, arrayed at different levels of generality, could be
statics to dynamics (Binford, 1978, 1983; see Stark, subsumed under domains of increasingly general princi-
1993, pp. 94–95; Schiffer, 1976, 1978). Because this ples (Raab and Goodyear, 1984, p. 225, emphasis in ori-
theory was built up from ethnographic observations, it ginal).
was considered to be independent of governing ar-
chaeological theory, and thus could be used to test In this sense, middle-range theory is not independent
broad range premises about cultural behavior (Wylie, of high-level theory, but is intrinsically involved in
1995). making vertical linkages between non-testable, high-le-
Processual archaeology has thus initiated a number vel propositions about culture and low-level empirical
of studies that are explicitly ‘‘middle-range’’ in the investigations. The movement up and down the theo-
sense that they attempt to identify low-level universals retical ladder is both inductive (from data to middle-
that can be used to test broad range theory (after range theory to high-level theory), and deductive (from
Wylie, 1988, p. 143). Artifacts are treated as ‘‘con- high-level theory to middle-range theory to data) (Raab
gealed behavior’’ (Conkey, 1989, p. 19; following and Goodyear, 1984, p. 257; Trigger, 1989, Chapter 1).
Fenton, 1974, pp. 23–24) in a way that allows for the The notion that middle-range theorizing is both circular
investigation of law-like regularities in the production, and bidirectional (from data to theory and theory to
use, discard and postdepositional alterations of arti- data), is shared by the hermeneutic orientations found in
facts. The methodological basis of such studies has postprocessual archaeology. As a result, postprocessu-
meant that they remain generally unconcerned with alists like Hodder (1986, p. 95) and others (Raab and
overarching questions about total cultural systems and Goodyear, 1984, p. 262 following Price, 1982 and
instead focus on ‘‘low-level’’ regularities. Uniformities Goodyear, 1977) have rejected the supposed indepen-
operating as law-like regularities below the level dence postulated by BinfordÕs version of middle-range
‘‘cultural’’ have been sought in a number of more theory despite the fact that some ethnoarchaeologists
recent studies of artifact production systems (e.g., continue to reference BinfordÕs original definition
J.J. Cunningham / Journal of Anthropological Archaeology 22 (2003) 389–410 401

(Stark, 1993).5 Current low-level methodological work to these ‘‘givens.’’6 In the processual stream, the absence
in archaeology is generally described in the literature as of such theoretical ties works to support claims that the
intrinsically related to propositions found in higher patterns uncovered by the low-level empirical research
levels of theory and recently the very distinction between relate to independent, and (often law-like) universal
middle-range theory and hermeneutics has been dis- phenomena. Therefore, a researcher may work on
missed as a matter of terminology rather than real methodological questions related to the style-function
substance (Kosso, 1991; Tschauner, 1996; VanPool and distinction without buying into, or even recognizing,
VanPool, 1999). that notions of style and function are dependent on
However, despite the rhetoric of hermeneutics, both overarching, broad range propositions about culture
processual and postprocessual archaeologists rely on (Cunningham, 2003). It is worth noting that, notwith-
the ‘‘methodological independence’’ of their low-level standing the overtly ‘‘hermeneutic’’ orientation, the
propositions in a way that validates ‘‘core universals.’’ disjointedness in postprocessualism serves the same
Processual and postprocessual archaeology have each purpose: structuralism and the analysis of style gram-
outlined models of culture that define a hierarchy of mars have an independent, methodological status often
process: the first emphasizing material constraints and quite similar to the original middle-range propositions
the second cognitive operations. Following from this, a offered by processual researchers. Thus, researchers may
suite of low-level, empirical investigations have tended find themselves treating style grammars as a purely
to operate as ‘‘givens’’ that are largely independent from methodological issue, without recognizing that the entire
broader theoretical concerns. In processual research, notion of style grammars is dependent on a set of sus-
one primary ‘‘given’’ is the important distinction be- pect theoretical propositions about the relationship be-
tween function and style (e.g., Dunnell, 1978; Hurt and tween language and cognition (see Hardin, 1983).7 Even
Rakita, 2001; Sackett, 1977), while for postprocessual- if the cultural models from which they are drawn appear
ists, ‘‘givens’’ are found in the ubiquitous structural to many as ‘‘idealized’’ or ‘‘more hypothetical than
oppositions imbedded in style (see Tschauner, 1996, pp. real,’’ the independent and insulated character of these
15–18). Missing in both cases are the mid-level theoret- low-level ‘‘givens’’ supports the continued belief that the
ical linkages that make plain how cultural models relate processes upon which they are based are ‘‘core univer-
sals.’’

Historical analogy

By way of contrast, it is worth perhaps considering


briefly one type of analogy that has not relied on ‘‘core
5
A number of low-level propositions about behavior have a universals.’’ Historical analogy often is thought to be a
universal-like application in archaeology, but they are best not distinct form of analogical inference because it relies
considered universals in the sense that their influence on on historical continuities between source and subject
variability is the same regardless of other contextual factors.
For example, whether culture is defined in processual (least
effort principles, adaptive strives) or postprocessual terms
6
(power, structuralism), the actual trace generated by a chert The recent rise of technological and/or la cha^ine operatoire
tool rubbing across a hide will be the same. But, changes in the approaches probably best illustrates this point. Research on
force applied, the hardness of lithic and/or worked material, the technical systems is often thought to produce ‘‘low-level
duration of use, or the amount of grit in any context can uniformities’’ that are independent of specific cultural models.
significantly change the character of a scraping residue. The However, postprocessualists have tended to draw from Lemo-
widespread acceptance of research tools like usewear analyses nnier (1986, 1992) in fore fronting the flexibility and cultural
comes from the fact that the theories central to usewear studies dependency of all technological systems (e.g., Gosselain, 1994)
are often independent from the governing propositions that while Schiffer and SkiboÕs (1997) largely parallel research
drive any one program of research. In other words, the examines the material constraints that limit exactly this sort
processes central to usewear studies are not derivatives of the of flexibility (see Schiffer, 1994 for an illuminating discussion).
processes central in the processual or postprocessual models of In both cases, the approaches taken to technological systems
culture. As Wylie (1985, 2000, pp. 231–232) and Tschauner (i.e., the causal processes that are referenced to explain
(1996) have noted, this sort of independence allows alternate technological choices) are largely consistent with the cultural
models of culture to be tested against such low-level proposi- models preferred by each analyst.
7
tions. However, identifying propositions with this ‘‘universal- Interestingly, at the very point where Hardin (1983) was
like’’ application in archaeology—that can be middle range in beginning to question whether style grammars were analogous
the Binfordian sense—requires knowledge of how specific to language and could be used to define cultural entities (in the
processes relate to their boundary conditions in both the low- cognitive sense), the postprocessualists adopted the approach to
level propositions and in the higher-level processes that are stimulate their research into prehistoric cognition, emphasizing
being tested. both its holistic character and its linguistic qualities.
402 J.J. Cunningham / Journal of Anthropological Archaeology 22 (2003) 389–410

contexts. Both Ascher (1961) and Chang (1967), for derived from anywhere else. Nevertheless, although [his-
example, draw a distinction between the folk-culture or torical analogies] may possess some higher degree of
direct historical approaches and the general comparative prior probability than general comparative analogies,
or ‘‘new analogy’’ approaches. Gould (1974, 1980, pp. the two kinds of analogy are on the same logical footing
as testable hypotheses; they are acceptable interpreta-
34–35) has identified discontinuous and continues
tions only after they have been confirmed (Gould and
analogies, while Watson (1979) emphasis a distinction Watson, 1982, p. 359, emphasis in original).
between homologies and analogies (also see Trigger,
1989, 1998). If we update WatsonÕs quote to figure in WylieÕs
Archaeological research going back into the 19th later emphasis on causal relations, we see that the
Century has relied on the use of both types of analogy number, nature, and range of formal similarities indicate
(see Charlton, 1981, pp. 133–134). However, historical the operation of a similar causal mechanism. What
analogies are now receiving increased attention in ar- historical continuity offers, then, is an increase in the
chaeology because they are assumed to allow for a closer likelihood that the same structure of causal processes
and more nuanced reading of archaeological materials bridge modern and archaeological contexts. WatsonÕs
(Agorsah, 1990; Kehoe, 1999; Trigger, 1998). In recent assertion that general and historical analogues are on
years, archaeologists have also begun to work with de- the same logical footing underscores the fact that his-
scendent communities that would like to see archaeology torical and general analogues are simply differences in
become more historically sensitive. As a result, archae- degree of similarity one can presuppose from the outset
ologists are beginning to revisit the Direct Historical in an analogical operation. However, because continu-
Approach (Baerreis, 1961; Steward, 1942) which was ity in the operation of specific processes cannot be
such an important part of the original work in archae- guaranteed—because the relevant boundary conditions
ology, but then lost prominence under the New Ar- may have changed in the interim—both historical and
chaeology and postprocessualism (Longacre, 1991a,b, p. general analogues must be validated by the same level
2; Trigger, 1989). In many cases, the use of historical of empirical testing. As Watson (Gould and Watson,
analogues is advocated as a way of rectifying the erro- 1982, p. 360) explains: ‘‘In fact, a case can be made that
neous ‘‘frames of reference’’ perpetuated by the ethno- one must be especially cautious of direct historical
archaeological use of general analogy (Gordon, 1992; analogues because the temptation is so great to accept
Wilmsen, 1989; see discussion in MacEachern, 1996, pp. the contemporary populations as living prehistoric
246–247).8 peoples. . .’’9
Watson (1980, 1982; Gould and Watson, 1982) has Notably, historical analogy escapes the dependence
noted that historical and general analogues are not re- on ‘‘core universals’’ despite the fact that it is logically
markably different. Citing Wylie, she claims that they similar to general analogy. The transfer of information
‘‘are logically the same when the materials are prior to between source and subject contexts in historical anal-
the memory of living informants’’ (Watson, 1982, p. 445; ogy is validated by a homological relationship in the
also see Watson, 1980, p. 56): causal structure. The actual configuration of specific
processes in this structure—whether ecological or cul-
Wylie. . .asserts that the strength of an analogical argu-
tural/historical processes are more or less uniform—is
ment is indeed increased the more fully it meets criteria
of number and detailed nature of similarities in form,
not an overriding concern. Historical analogy thus un-
and range of occurrences across a variety of archaeolog- dermines those perspectives that would see ‘‘core uni-
ical and ethnographic contexts. . . This means that an ar- versals’’ as a necessary condition for analogy.
chaeologist working in a geographic area where cultural
continuity is marked has an advantage in acquiring test-
able and a priori strong analogies to use in final interpre-
tations over the archaeologists who must rely solely on
general comparative analogy. This is true because de- 9
Ethnoarchaeologists have continued to apply direct his-
scription of the physical and cultural activities, institu-
torical approaches in their interpretations despite ‘‘classroom
tions, and materials of the descendents of the people
shifts’’ in archaeological theory (Kepecs, 1997, pp. 194–195;
whose remains are being excavated are more likely to
also see Tschauner, 1994). For example, in areas like Franco-
be analogous to past activities, institutions and materials
phone West Africa, ethnographic research beginning with
in multiple (often linked) ways than are analogies
Griaule and running to current logicistic orientations have
always integrated archaeological, historic and ethnographic
approaches (David, 1992; MacEachern, 1996; and Clifford,
8
StewardÕs original definition of the Direct Historical 1988, for discussions). Recent logicist approaches (e.g., Gallay,
Approach seems to have had much the same goal in mind, 1992; Gallay et al., 1992; Gallay and Huysecom, 1989;
being specifically formulated to redress a narrowly biological or Huysecom, 1992) have even combined a concern with historical
natural science view of artifact variation (see discussion in analogy with rigid (almost inflexible) testing strategies and the
Steward, 1942). highly technical analyses of production systems.
J.J. Cunningham / Journal of Anthropological Archaeology 22 (2003) 389–410 403

Discussion understood through reference to the structure inherent


in systems of meaning. The causal affect of these struc-
The reliance on ‘‘core universals’’ creates a number of tures cannot be altered by ecological forces emanating
problems for ethnoarchaeology. Wylie (1982, 1985) has from the environment. By elevating specific processes to
cautioned for two reasons against making strong dis- the status of ‘‘core universals,’’ researchers shield the
tinctions between secure analogues—like those based on essential character of these causal regularities from
‘‘core universals’’—and other seemingly tenuous ana- critical evaluation and significant revision. Defining
logical propositions. First, even so-called secure propo- some processes as a priori more secure than others ren-
sitions are analogous, inductive, and include a degree of ders nonsensical investigations of how those secure
uncertainty.10 Hence, the assumption that specific pro- processes are modified by more ‘‘contextually sensitive’’
cesses are ‘‘universal’’ may prematurely restrict source- causal forces, even those that may be included in the
side investigation of the scope and those processes have same cultural model. At a broader scale, the shielding of
on material variability. Furthermore, during testing the ‘‘core universals’’ in this way leaves competing cultural
same assumption may leave researchers in a poor posi- models in a state of theoretically incommensurability.
tion to recognize when the variation in the causal Despite the commonalities identified in their epistemo-
frameworks between source and subject contexts nullifies logical stances (see Wylie, 2000, p. 228), processual and
the analogy (Wylie, 1982, pp. 393, 399; e.g., HoleÕs, 1978 postprocessual archaeologies remain diametrically op-
discussion of pastoralism). Second, the identification of posed in the causal regularities that they find to be se-
secure propositions directs research toward only those cure.11 These core processes becomes further insulated
hypotheses that appear amenable to a high degree of as competing theoretically perspectives move from sim-
certainty. In the processual case, research is directed to- ple differences in opinion to full-fledged theoretically
ward processes that seemingly involve natural laws, while schools mired in disciplinary politics. The net result is an
in postprocessualism, research is directed toward pro- unhealthy eclecticism that allows for little critical eval-
cesses that draw upon the assumed inherent structure of uation of these core processes.12
meaning. Such restrictions in the goals of research re- One only needs to look at the analytical cul-de-sac in
move other processes (and other analogies) from con- which ethnoarchaeology has been trapped to see the
sideration simply because they do not meet a priori consequences. Consider, for example, the cautionary
criteria. Recent calls for an expansion of middle-range tales that often derive from testing programs. Proposi-
theory by archaeologists like Saitta (1992) and Trigger tions have often been tested in order to elaborate upon
(1995) indicates that the preoccupation with ‘‘core uni- the existence of the ‘‘core universals’’ advocated by a
versals’’ has taken a toll in exactly this way.
The predicament of ‘‘core universals’’ in cultural
ontology is primarily a problem related to how specific 11
The one exception lies in the ongoing discussions by
processes are insulated from critical analysis. In defining processualists and postprocessualists over the processes respon-
‘‘core universals,’’ theorists establish limits on what the sible for stylistic variation. Style represents an interesting
processes or structural factors that can act as boundary element of variability because, even under strongly ecologically
conditions for those universals. Thus, by treating eco- driven conceptions of material variability like that we see with
utilitarian processes as ‘‘core universals,’’ processual processual archaeology, style is an area of variation that is
theorists have fixed the boundary conditions for these considered to be caused by the cultural/historical processes
processes in environmental variables alone. The causal central to the postprocessual critique (see Cunningham, 2003).
As a result, ‘‘stylistic analysis’’ is one area where processualists
relationship between environment and culture is thought
and postprocessualists have found common ground. Note that
to be so fundamental that non-eco-utilitarian processes this small zone of commensurability is created by effectively
cannot significantly modify the causal effect of the en- partitioning material variability into areas of ‘‘style’’ and
vironment. The same holds for the ‘‘core universals’’ ‘‘function’’ which in turn further insulates ‘‘core universals’’
outlined by postprocessualism. The meaningfulness of from significant critical evaluation. See Hegmon, 2003 for a
the human endeavor means that all action must be recent discussion of other postprocessual insights that have
been grafted onto the processual model.
12
Although I have dealt with processual and postprocessual
archaeology to this point, it should be noted that the eclecticism
10
As Wylie notes, fully secure relations occur only when the is made worse by the different camps that are encapsulated by
inference is based on an exclusive causal relation of the form ‘‘if these two broad perspectives. For example, although behav-
and only if x obtains, then y.’’ All archaeological inferences are ioral, processual and Darwinian archaeologies are equally
based on less secure causal relationships ‘‘because of the committed to materialism, and thus can be opposed to
possibility—especially present where human behavior is con- postprocessual archaeology, there are significant differences in
cerned—that the same concatenation of environmental causes the core universals they each propose. The nested character of
might be capable of yielding a range of different behavioral these core universals further exacerbates the eclectic state of
responses’’ (1982, p. 391). ethnoarchaeology.
404 J.J. Cunningham / Journal of Anthropological Archaeology 22 (2003) 389–410

given cultural model. In these testing programs, the cross-contextual uniformity of the causal structures in
immutability of these ‘‘core universals’’ is never to be in which they are found—may be warranted, but this needs
question—the low level givens and cultural models that to be built up by reflexive empirical research. These two
define the structure of causal processes should be con- adjustments will do much to moderate the walls that
firmed through testing. The results, however, have rarely create ethnoarchaeologyÕs eclecticism. I should under-
been so accommodating. Testing programs have often score that I am not naively suggesting here that current
returned a cautionary tale that indicate that the core differences in archaeological theory should be squeezed
universal was not nearly as universal as was originally into one large, genial and theoretically unified research
proposed and, instead, was subject to a wider range of venture. Disciplinary unity will always remain a fantasy
boundary conditions. Rephrased, the effect of the pro- in archaeology. On the other hand, there are ways we
cess being investigated on behavioral, material and cul- can make more productive use of our existing hetero-
tural patterning is shown through testing to be modified doxy. Wylie has already shown how archaeologists ex-
or even nullified by other causal forces in the local ploit the disunities in science to build better
context—including causal forces considered ‘‘epiphe- understandings of the past (Wylie, 1992, 2000; see
nomenal’’ under the governing cultural model. Ironi- Dupre, 1993; Longino, 2002, Chapter 8 for broader
cally, rather than allowing this new knowledge to discussions). Tempered versions of our existing cultural
contribute to our understandings of the causal deter- models and research emphases can provide a compara-
minants of variability, many researchers dismiss such bly robust foundation for crosscutting and competing
‘‘cautionary tales’’ as proof of ethnoarchaeologyÕs inef- analyses of variability. But in order for our choking
fectiveness. However, such testing programs are fulfill- eclecticism to be transformed into a theoretically in-
ing precisely the role they are supposed to play. formed pluralism, we need to find at least some path-
Archaeologists and ethnoarchaeologists have assumed ways toward commensurability that can allow us to take
that ‘‘core universals’’ and their associated cultural better advantage of these disunities. Once ‘‘core uni-
models have a universal presence and effect on material versals’’ are recognized as processes, theoretically op-
variability, and testing programs have prevented them posed conceptions of processes can be recast as
from spuriously affirming the consequent. The problem pluralistic standpoints that have relevance for the dis-
has less to do with ethnoarchaeological testing than it cipline as a whole in a way that is presently lacking.
does with the politically charged preconceptions implicit Gould (1980, p. 34; also see Watson, 1980, p. 55) per-
in the analyses. Simply put, when a cautionary result haps says it best: ‘‘Instead of assuming that uniformities
emerges from testing, many researchers find fault with always exist, why not develop ways of finding out when
the testing program instead of revisiting the original and under what conditions different kinds of human
proposition. Testing programs may be poorly conceived behavior can be expected to occur?’’
and this can produce spurious results, but the consis- Once devoid of universalist assumptions, ethnoar-
tency with which ethnoarchaeological testing is blamed chaeology can gain the ability to look more closely at
for cautionary tales is far out of hand. If ethnoarchae- how a mutable and fluid sets of cultural processes relate
ologyÕs overriding goal is to develop knowledge of the to behavioral, cultural and material variability. Rather
processes that cause material variability, so that than perpetuating ‘‘negative’’ cautionary tales, ethn-
knowledge can be extended via analogy into the past, oarchaeology can produce positive knowledge of causal
then knowing how any causal processes is modified by relationships. And freed from partisan political interests,
other processes should be an essential element of eth- ethnoarchaeology can also investigate the enormous
noarchaeological work. Cautionary tales are a principle number of causal processes that affect artifact patterning
aim of ethnoarchaeological testing, not its greatest (see Carr and Neitzel, 1995; Schiffer and Skibo, 1997 for
quandary. lists), not as placeholders in mutually exclusive cultural
The problem, I would suggest, lies ultimately in a ontologies, but as part of a complex causal milieu. Of
fundamental misunderstanding of how the causal forces course, none of these processes need to be truly wide-
that determine material variation should be character- spread in effect; indeed, they may operate only under
ized. I would propose two related conceptual adjust- very specific circumstances (similar to urbanization or
ments. First, ‘‘core universals,’’ like those outlined state formation as discussed by Schiffer above). But their
above, should be exposed consistently to wider critical fleeting nature should not reduce their importance as
analyses. Rather than insulated as ‘‘core universals,’’ all potential analogues.
causal regularities should be understood as processes
that may vary according to context. Second, the existing
structures of process that make up archaeologyÕs oper- Conclusion
ating cultural models should be thought of heuristically
rather than fixed as competing eternal truths. In time, How, then, are archaeologists to understand the
the primary causal role of specific processes—and the claims by Simms and OÕConnell that archaeology and
J.J. Cunningham / Journal of Anthropological Archaeology 22 (2003) 389–410 405

ethnoarchaeology should be unified by a universal ‘‘Ethnographic Analogy and Processual Pluralism: West
model of culture based on behavioral ecology, or Hod- African Examples’’ in a session titled Global Advances in
derÕs desire to see ethnoarchaeology metamorphose into Ethnoarchaeology at the 2003 Society for American
material culture studies and become focused on an Archaeology Meetings in Milwaukee.
analysis of meaning? At its most general, these claims
reflect the na€ıve assumption that ethnoarchaeology
should be unified by something specific, that it is a single
area of research rather than a tool that has been used by References cited
different and quite distinct partisan interests in archae-
Agorsah, E.K., 1990. Ethnoarchaeology: the search for a self-
ology (David and Kramer, 2001, pp. 411–412). The
corrective approach to the study of past human behaviour.
suggestions that we find unity through a specific cultural
African Archaeological Review 8, 189–208.
model would be easy, therefore, to dismiss as simply Appadurai, A. (Ed.), 1986. The Social Life of Things:
another attempt by different partisan interests to gain an Commodities in Cultural Perspective. Cambridge University
upper hand. But, I suspect that this reading would miss Press, Cambridge, MA.
the very important problem that motivates their claim. Arnold, D.E., 1985. Ceramic Theory and Cultural Process.
To date, the research done even by partisan interests in Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, MA.
ethnoarchaeology has rarely developed synthetic un- Arnold, D.E., 2000. Does the standardization of ceramic pastes
derstandings of the causal processes behind material really mean specialization? Journal of Archaeological
variability. By seeking to refocus research through a Method and Theory 7 (4), 333–375.
Arnold III, P.J., 2000. Working without a net: recent trends in
unified model, these commentators would seem to hope
ceramic ethnoarchaeology? Journal of Archaeological Re-
to moderate ethnoarchaeologyÕs eclecticism while si-
search 8 (2), 105–133.
multaneously developing the critical mass of research Ascher, R., 1961. Analogy in archaeological interpretation.
necessary to advance such synthetic understandings. Southwestern Journal of Anthropology 17, 317–325.
Nevertheless, reintroducing ‘‘core universals’’ embedded Atherton, J.H., 1983. Ethnoarchaeology in Africa. African
in one-size-fits-all cultural models will neither ‘‘correct’’ Archaeological Review 1, 75–104.
ethnoarchaeologyÕs diversity nor provide the needed Baerreis, D.A., 1961. The ethnohistoric approach and archae-
critical gaze on causal regularities. Transcending ethn- ology. Ethnohistory 8, 49–77.
oarchaeologyÕs depiction as an obnoxious spectator thus Biehl, P.F., 1999. Analogy and context—a re-construction of
requires ethnoarchaeology to find ways of working the missing link. In: Owen, L.R., Porr, M. (Eds.), Ethno-
Analogy and the Reconstruction of Prehistoric Artifact Use
with—rather than against—its diversity. Ethnoarchaeol-
and Production. Urgeschichtliche Materialhefte 14, Mo
ogy may need to disassemble the more extreme positions
Vince Verlag, T€ ubingen, pp. 171–184.
in archaeology, but the result will be a frank and pro- Binford, L.R., 1962. Archaeology as anthropology. American
ductive analysis of how processes affect each another Antiquity 28 (2), 217–225.
and articulate in the creation of behavioral, cultural and Binford, L.R., 1965. Archaeological systematics and the study
material patterns. of culture process. American Antiquity 31 (2), 203–210.
Binford, L.R., 1967. Smudge pits and hide smoking: the use of
analogy in archaeological reasoning. American Antiquity
Acknowledgments 32, 1–12.
Binford, L.R., 1978. Nunamiut Ethnoarchaeology. Academic
Press, New York.
I would like to thank Aubrey Cannon, Neal Ferris,
Binford, L.R., 1981. Bones: ancient men and modern myths.
Scott MacEachern, Farid Rahemtulla, and Michael
Academic Press, New York.
Spence for reading drafts of this paper. Bruce Trigger Binford, L.R., 1983. In pursuit of the past: decoding the
commented extensively on the ideas outlined herein, archaeological record. Academic Press, New York.
provided essential advice when I needed it and encour- Binford, L.R., Sabloff, J.A., 1982. Paradigms, systematics, and
aged me to seek publication for the paper. Two anon- archaeology. Journal of Anthropological Research 38 (2),
ymous reviewers for JAA provided insightful 137–153.
commentaries that greatly helped me reconfigure the Bourdieu, P., 1977. Outline of a Theory of Practice. Cambridge
argument to its current form. Farid Rahemtulla and University Press, Cambridge, MA.
Scott MacEachern also provided last minute and sub- Bourdieu, P., 1984. Distinction: A Social Critique of the
Judgment of Taste, translated by R. Nice. Harvard
stantive commentaries on the final version of my dis-
University Press, Cambridge, MA.
cussion. Gerry and Terri Cunningham lent me the
Bourdieu, P., 1998. Practical Reason: On the Theory of Action.
basement space in which I wrote this paper in December Stanford University Press, Stanford.
of 2001, and I thank them and other members of my Bowser, B., 2000. From pottery to politics: an ethnoarchaeo-
family for understanding my preoccupation with this logical study of political factionalism, ethnicity and domes-
project during our Christmas holiday. An abstracted tic pottery style in the Ecuadorian Amazon. Journal of
version of this argument was presented under the title of Archaeological Method and Theory 7 (3), 219–248.
406 J.J. Cunningham / Journal of Anthropological Archaeology 22 (2003) 389–410

Carneiro, R.L., 1979. Tree felling with the stone ax: an Dillon, B., 1984. Ethnoarchaeology in middle America: an
experiment carried out among the Yanomam€ o Indians of introduction. Journal of New World Archaeology 6 (2), 1–3.
Southern Venezuala. In: Kramer, C. (Ed.), Ethnoarchaeol- Dunnell, R., 1978. Style and function: a fundamental dichot-
ogy: Implications of Ethnography for Archaeology. Co- omy. American Antiquity 43, 192–202.
lumbia University Press, New York, pp. 21–58. Dupre, J., 1993. The Disorder of Things: Metaphysical Foun-
Carr, C., Neitzel, J.E. (Eds.), 1995. Style, Society and Person: dations of the Disunity of Science. Harvard University
Archaeological and Ethnological Perspectives. Plenum Press, Cambridge, MA.
Press, New York. Ebert, J.I., 1979. An ethnoarchaeological approach to reassess-
Chang, K.C., 1967. Major aspects of the interrelationship of ing the meaning of variability in stone tool assemblages. In:
archaeology and ethnology. Current Anthropology 8, 227– Kramer, C. (Ed.), Ethnoarchaeology: Implications of eth-
243. nography for archaeology. Columbia University Press, New
Charlton, T.H., 1981. Archaeology, ethnohistory and ethnol- York, pp. 59–74.
ogy: interpretive interfaces. In: Schiffer, M.B. (Ed.), Ad- Fenton, W.H., 1974. The advancement of material culture
vances in Archaeological Method and Theory, vol. 4. studies in modern anthropological research. In: Richardson,
Academic Press, New York, pp. 129–176. M. (Ed.), The Human Mirror: Material and Spatial Images
Clifford, J., 1988. The predicament of culture: twentieth-century of Man. Louisiana State University Press, Baton Rouge, pp.
ethnography, literature, and art. Harvard University Press, 15–36.
Cambridge, MA. Gallay, A., 1992. A Propos de la ceramique actuelle du delta
Conkey, M.W., 1989. The place of material culture in contem- interieur du Niger (Mali), approach ethnoarcheologique et
porary anthropology. In: Hedlund, A.L. (Ed.), Perspectives regles transculturelles. In: Audouze, F. (Ed.), Ethnoarcheol-
on Anthropological Collections from the American South- ogie: Justification, Problemes, Limites. Internationales
west: Proceedings of a Symposium. Anthropological Re- dÕArcheologie et dÕHistoire dÕAntibe 12. Editions APDCA,
search Papers, No. 40. Arizona State University Press, Juan-les-Pines, pp. 67–89.
Tucson, pp. 13–31. Gallay, A., Audouze, F., Roux, V., 1992. Questions pour un
Conkey, M.W., 1990. Experimenting with style in archaeology: colloque. In: Audouze, F. (Ed.), Ethnoarcheologie: Justifi-
some historical and theoretical issues. In: Conkey, M.W., cation, Problemes, Limites. Internationales dÕArcheologie et
Hastorf, C.A. (Eds.), The Uses of Style in Archaeology. dÕHistoire dÕAntibe 12. Editions APDCA, Juan-les-Pines,
Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, MA, pp. 5–17. pp. 13–14.
Costin, C.L., 2000. The use of ethnoarchaeology for the Gallay, A., Huysecom, E., 1989. Ethnoarcheologie africaine:
archaeological study of ceramic production. Journal of Un programme dÕetude de la ceramique recente du
Archaeological Method and Theory 7 (4), 377–403. Delta Interieur du Niger. Document du Departement
Cunningham, J.J., 2001. Ceramic variation and ethnic holism: a dÕAnthropologie et dÕEcologie 14, Universite de Geneva,
case from the ‘‘Younge-early Ontario Iroquoian Border’’ in Geneva.
Southwestern Ontario. Canadian Journal of Archaeology Geertz, C., 1973. The Interpretation of Culture: Selected
25, 1–27. Essays. Basic Books, New York.
Cunningham, J.J., 2003. Rethinking style in archaeology. In: Gelbert, A., 1999. Technological and stylistic borrowings
VanPool, T.L., VanPool, C.S. (Eds.), Essential Tensions in between ceramic traditions: a case study from Northeastern
Archaeological Method and Theory. University of Utah Senegal. In: Owen, L.R., Porr, M. (Eds.), Ethno-Analogy
Press, Salt Lake City (in press). and the Reconstruction of Prehistoric Artifact Use and
Cunningham, J.J., n.d. Essentializing culture: conceptual hur- Production. Urgeschichtliche Materialhefte 14, Mo Vince
dles to pluralism in archaeology. In: Indigenous Peoples and Verlag, T€ ubingen, pp. 207–224.
Archaeology. Proceedings of the 32nd Annual Chacmool Gifford, D.P., 1978. Ethnoarchaeological observations of nat-
Conference. The University of Calgary Press, Calgary (in ural processes affecting cultural materials. In: Gould, R.A.
press). (Ed.), Explorations in Ethnoarchaeology. University of
David, N., 1992. Integrating ethnoarchaeology: a subtle realist New Mexico Press, Albuquerque, pp. 77–102.
perspective. Journal of Anthropological Archaeology 11, Goodyear, A.C., 1977. Review of Behavioral Archaeology.
330–359. American Antiquity 42, 668–671.
David, N., Hennig, H., 1972. The ethnography of pottery: a Gordon, R., 1992. The Bushman Myth: The Making of a
Fulani case seen in archaeological perspective. Addison- Namibian Underclass. Westview Press, Boulder.
Wesley Module, Reading, MA, vol. 21. Gorecki, P., 1985. Ethnoarchaeology: the need for a post-
David, N., Kramer, C., 2001. Ethnoarchaeology in Action. mortem enquiry. World Archaeology 17 (2), 175–191.
Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, MA. Gosselain, O.P., 1994. Skimming through pottersÕ agendas: an
DeBoer, W.R., 1984. The last pottery show: system and sense in ethnoarchaeological study of clay selection strategies in
ceramic studies. In: van der Leeuw, S., Pritchard, A.C. Cameroon. In: Childs, S.T. (Ed.), Society, Culture, and
(Eds.), The Many Dimensions of Pottery: Ceramics in Technology in Africa, MASCA Research Papers in Science
Archaeology and Anthropology. University of Amsterdam, and Archaeology, Supplement to vol. 11. University of
Amsterdam, pp. 527–568. Pennsylvania Museum of Archaeology and Anthropology,
DeBoer, W.R., 1991. The decorative burden: design, Philadelphia, pp. 99–107.
medium, and change. In: Longacre, W.A. (Ed.), Ceramic Gosselain, O.P., 2000. Materializing identities: an African
Ethnoarchaeology. University of Arizona Press, Tucson, perspective. Journal of Archaeological Method and Theory
pp. 144–161. 7 (3), 187–217.
J.J. Cunningham / Journal of Anthropological Archaeology 22 (2003) 389–410 407

Gould, R.A., 1971. The archaeologist as ethnographer: a case Hodder, I., 1985. Postprocessual archaeology. In: Schiffer, M.B.
from the Western Desert of Australia. World Archaeology (Ed.), Advances in Archaeological Method and Theory, vol.
2, 143–177. 8. Academic Press, New York, pp. 1–26.
Gould, R.A., 1974. Some current problems in ethnoarchaeol- Hodder, I., 1986. From ethnoarchaeology to material culture
ogy. In: Donnan, C.B.Clewlow Jr., C.W. (Eds.), Ethnoar- studies. Dialoghi Di Archeologia 3 (1), 93–97.
chaeology. Monograph IV, Archaeological Survey, Institute Hodder, I., 1990a. The Domestication of Europe. Blackwell,
of Archaeology. University of California, Los Angeles, pp. Oxford.
29–48. Hodder, I., 1990b. Style as historic quality. In: Conkey, M.W.,
Gould, R.A., 1978a. From Tasmania to Tuscon: new directions Hastorf, C.A. (Eds.), The Uses of Style in Archaeology.
in ethnoarchaeology. In: Gould, R.A. (Ed.), Explorations in Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, MA, pp. 44–51.
Ethnoarchaeology. University of New Mexico Press, Albu- Hodder, I., 1991. The decoration of containers: an ethno-
querque, pp. 1–10. graphic and historical study. In: Longacre, W.A. (Ed.),
Gould, R.A., 1978b. Beyond analogy in ethnoarchaeology. In: Ceramic Ethnoarchaeology. University of Arizona Press,
Gould, R.A. (Ed.), Explorations in Ethnoarchaeology. Tucson, pp. 71–94.
University of New Mexico Press, Albuquerque, pp. 249– Hole, F., 1978. Pastoral nomadism in Western Iran. In: Gould,
293. R.A. (Ed.), Explorations in Ethnoarchaeology. University
Gould, R.A., 1980. Living Archaeology. Cambridge University of New Mexico Press, Albuquerque, pp. 127–167.
Press, Cambridge, MA. Hurt, T.D., Rakita, G.F.M. (Eds.), 2001. Style and Function:
Gould, R.A., Watson, P.J., 1982. A dialogue on the meaning Conceptual Issues in Evolutionary Archaeology. Bergin &
and use of analogy in ethnoarchaeological reasoning. Garvey, Westport.
Journal of Anthropological Archaeology 1, 355–381. Huysecom, E., 1992. Vers un Ethnoarcheologie Appliquee:
Graves, M.W., 1981. Ethnoarchaeology of Kalinga ceramic Examples Africains. In: Audouze, F. (Ed.), Ethnoarcheol-
design. Unpublished Ph.D. Dissertation, Department of ogie: Justification, Problemes, Limites. Internationales
Anthropology, The University of Arizona, Tuscon. dÕArcheologie et dÕHistoire dÕAntibe 12. Editions APDCA,
Graves, M.W., 1985. Ceramic design variation within a Kalinga Juan-les-Pines, pp. 91–102.
village: temporal and spatial process. In: Nelson, B. (Ed.), Jarker, R., Mahar, C., Wilkes, C. (Eds.), 1990. An Introduction
Decoding Prehistoric Ceramics. Southern Illinois University to the Work of Pierre Bourdieu: The Practice of Theory. St.
Press, Carbondale, pp. 9–34. MartinÕs Press, New York.
Graves, M.W., 1991. Pottery production and distribution Keeley, L., 1980. Experimental Determination of Stone Tool
among the Kalinga: a study of household and regional Uses: A Microwear Analysis. University of Chicago Press,
organization and differentiation. In: Longacre, W.A. (Ed.), Chicago.
Ceramic Ethnoarchaeology. University of Arizona Press, Kehoe, T.F., 1999. The development of the direct ethnological
Tucson, pp. 112–143. approach studies of archaeology in the northwestern plains
Greenberg, L.J., 1975. Art as a structural system: a study of of North America: the case of medicine wheels, tipi rings
Hopi pottery designs. Studies in the Anthropology of Visual and boulder effigies. In: Owen, L.R., Porr, M. (Eds.),
Communication 2, 33–50. Ethno-Analogy and the Reconstruction of Prehistoric
Gross, P.R., Levitt, N., 1994. Higher Superstition: The Artifact Use and Production. Urgeschichtliche Material-
Academic Left and its Quarrels with Science. Johns Hop- hefte 14, Mo Vince Verlag, T€ ubingen, pp. 255–273.
kins University Press, Baltimore, MD. Kepecs, S., 1997. Introduction to New Approaches to Com-
Hardin, M.A., 1979. The cognitive basis of productivity in a bining the Archaeological and Historical Records. Journal
decorative art style: implications of an ethnographic study for of Archaeological Method and Theory 4 (3/4), 193–198.
archaeologistsÕ taxonomies. In: Kramer, C. (Ed.), Ethnoar- Kirch, P.V., 1978. Ethnoarchaeology and the study of agricul-
chaeology: Implications of Ethnography for Archaeology. tural adaptation in the humid tropics. In: Gould, R.A.
Columbia University Press, New York, pp. 75–101. (Ed.), Explorations in Ethnoarchaeology. University of
Hardin, M.A., 1983. Applying linguistic models to the decora- New Mexico Press, Albuquerque, pp. 103–126.
tive arts: a preliminary consideration of the limits of Kleindienst, M.R., Watson, P.J., 1956. ÔAction archaeologyÕ:
analogy. Semiotica 46, 309–322. the archaeological inventory of a living community. An-
Hardin, M.A., 1984. Models of decoration. In: van der Leeuw, thropology Tomorrow 5, 75–78.
S.E., Pritchard, A.C. (Eds.), The Many Dimensions of Kosso, P., 1991. Method in archaeology: middle-range theory
Pottery: Ceramics in Archaeology and Anthropology. as hermeneutics. American Antiquity 56, 621–627.
University of Amsterdam, Amsterdam, pp. 573–607. Kramer, C., 1979. Introduction. In: Kramer, C. (Ed.), Ethn-
Hayden, B. (Ed.), 1977. Lithic Use–Wear Analysis. Academic oarchaeology: implications of ethnography for archaeology.
Press, New York. Columbia University Press, New York, pp. 1–20.
Hegmon, M., 2003. Setting theoretical egos aside: issues and Kramer, C., 1992. Ceramics in Rajasthan: distribution and
theory in North American archaeology. American Antiq- scalar variation. In: Audouze, F. (Ed.), Ethnoarcheologie:
uity 68 (2), 213–243. Justification, Problemes, Limites. Internationales dÕArcheol-
Hodder, I., 1982a. Symbols in Action. Cambridge University ogie et dÕHistoire dÕAntibe 12. Editions APDCA, Juan-les-
Press, Cambridge, MA. Pines, pp. 127–133.
Hodder, I., 1982b. Theoretical archaeology: a reactionary view. Krause, R.A., 1985. The Clay Sleeps: An Ethnoarchaeological
In: Hodder, I. (Ed.), Symbolic and Structural Archaeology. Study of Three African Potters. The University of Alabama
Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, MA, pp. 1–16. Press, Tuscaloosa.
408 J.J. Cunningham / Journal of Anthropological Archaeology 22 (2003) 389–410

Kus, S., 1997. Archaeologists and anthropologists: much ado Orme, B., 1981. Anthropology for Archaeologists: an intro-
about something after all? Journal of Archaeological duction. Cornell University Press, Ithica.
Method and Theory 4 (3/4), 199–213. Ortner, S.B., 1984. Theory in anthropology since the sixties.
LaViolette, A., 1995. Women craft specialists in Jenne: the Comparative Studies in Society and History 26, 126–166.
manipulation of Mande social categories. In: Conrad, D.C., Owen, L.R., Porr, M. (Eds.), 1999a. Ethno-Analogy and the
Frank, B.E. (Eds.), Status and Identity in West Africa: Reconstruction of Prehistoric Artifact Use and Production.
Nyamakalaw of Mande. Indiana University Press, Bloom- Urgeschichtliche Materialhefte 14. Mo Vince Verlag, T€ ubin-
ington, pp. 170–181. gen.
Lees, S.H., 1979. Ethnoarchaeology and the interpretation Owen, L.R., Porr, M., 1999b. Ethno-analogy in theory and
of community organization. In: Kramer, C. (Ed.), practice: an introduction. In: Owen, L.R., Porr, M. (Eds.),
Ethnoarchaeology: Implications of ethnography for archae- Ethno-Analogy and the Reconstruction of Prehistoric
ology. Columbia University Press, New York, pp. 265– Artifact Use and Production. Urgeschichtliche Material-
276. hefte 14, Mo Vince Verlag, T€ ubingen, pp. 1–2.
Lemonnier, P., 1986. The study of material culture today: Papousek, D.A., 1984. Pots and people in Los Pueblos: the
toward an anthropology of technical systems. Journal of social and economic organization of pottery. In: van der
Anthropological Archaeology 5, 147–186. Leeuw, S.E., Pritchard, A.C. (Eds.), The Many Dimensions
Lemonnier, P., 1992. Elements for an anthropology of tech- of Pottery: Ceramics in Archaeology and Anthropology.
nology. Anthropological Papers of the Museum of Anthro- University of Amsterdam, Amsterdam, pp. 475–520.
pology 88, University of Michigan Press, Ann Arbor. Pastron, A.G., 1974. Preliminary ethnoarchaeological investi-
Levi-Strauss, C., 1962. The Savage Mind. University of gations among the tarahumara. In: Donnan, C.B., Clewlow,
Chicago Press, Chicago. C.W. (Eds.), Ethnoarchaeology. Monograph IV, Archaeo-
Longacre, W.A., 1978. Ethnoarchaeology. Reviews in Anthro- logical Survey, Institute of Archaeology. University of
pology 5, 357–363. California, Los Angeles, pp. 93–114.
Longacre, W.A., 1985. Pottery use-life among the Kalinga, Porr, M., 1999. Archaeology, analogy, material culture, society:
Northern Luzon, the Philippines. In: Nelson, B. (Ed.), an exploration. In: Owen, L.R., Porr, M. (Eds.), Ethno-
Decoding Prehistoric Ceramics. Southern Illinois University Analogy and the Reconstruction of Prehistoric Artifact Use
Press, Carbondale, pp. 335–345. and Production. Urgeschichtliche Materialhefte 14, Mo
Longacre, W.A., 1991a. Ceramic ethnoarchaeology: an intro- Vince Verlag, T€ ubingen, pp. 3–15.
duction. In: Longacre, W.A. (Ed.), Ceramic Ethnoarchae- Price, B.J., 1982. Cultural materialism: a theoretical review.
ology. University of Arizona Press, Tucson, pp. 1–10. American Antiquity 47, 709–741.
Longacre, W.A., 1991b. Sources of ceramic variability among Pritchard, A.C., van der Leeuw, S.E., 1984. Introduction: the
the Kalinga of Northern Luzon. In: Longacre, W.A. (Ed.), many dimensions of pottery. In: van der Leeuw, S.E.,
Ceramic Ethnoarchaeology. University of Arizona Press, Pritchard, A.C. (Eds.), The Many Dimensions of Pottery:
Tucson, pp. 95–111. Ceramics in Archaeology and Anthropology. University of
Longino, H.E., 2002. The Fate of Knowledge. Princeton Amsterdam, Amsterdam, pp. 1–23.
University Press, Princeton, NJ. Raab, L.M., Goodyear, A.C., 1984. Middle-range theory in
MacEachern, S., 1996. Foreign countries: the development of archaeology: a critical analysis of origins and applications.
ethnoarchaeology in sub-Saharan Africa. Journal of World American Antiquity 49, 255–268.
Prehistory 10, 243–304. Rathje, W.L., 1978. Archaeological ethnography. . .because
Mayor, A., 1994. Duree de vie des ceramiques africaines: sometimes it is better to give than to receive. In: Gould,
facteurs responsables et implications archeologiques. In: R.A. (Ed.), Explorations in Ethnoarchaeology. University
Terre cuite et societe: la ceramique, document technique, of New Mexico Press, Albuquerque, pp. 49–78.
economique, culturel. Rencontres int. jdÕarcheol. Et dÕhist., Riley, J.A., 1984. Pottery analysis and the reconstruction of
14. Editions APDCA, Juan-les-Pines, pp. 31–44. ancient exchange systems. In: van der Leeuw, S.E., Prit-
Miller, D., 1983. Things ainÕt what they used to be. Royal chard, A.C. (Eds.), The Many Dimensions of Pottery:
Anthropological Institute Newsletter 59, 5–7. Ceramics in Archaeology and Anthropology. University of
Miller, D., 1985. Artifacts as categories: a study of ceramic Amsterdam, Amsterdam, pp. 55–73.
variability in Central India. Cambridge University Press, Roux, V., 1999. Ethnoarchaeology and the generation of
Cambridge, MA. referential models: the case of Harappan Carnelian beads.
Muntoni, I.M., 1999. From ceramic production to vessel use: a In: Owen, L.R., Porr, M. (Eds.), Ethno-Analogy and the
multi-level approach to the neolithic communities of the Reconstruction of Prehistoric Artifact Use and Production.
tavoliere Southern Italy. In: Owen, L.R., Porr, M. (Eds.), Urgeschichtliche Materialhefte 14, Mo Vince Verlag, T€ ubin-
Ethno-Analogy and the Reconstruction of Prehistoric gen, pp. 153–169.
Artifact Use and Production. Urgeschichtliche Material- Sackett, J.R., 1977. The meaning of style in archaeology: a
hefte 14, Mo Vince Verlag, T€ ubingen, pp. 237–254. general model. American Antiquity 42 (3), 369–380.
OÕConnell, J.F., 1995. Ethnoarchaeology Needs a General Saitta, D.J., 1992. Radical archaeology and middle-range
Theory of Behavior. Journal of Archaeological Research 3 methodology. Antiquity 66, 886–897.
(3), 205–255. Schiffer, M.B., 1976. Behavioral Archaeology. Academic Press,
Odell, G., Odell-Vereecken, F., 1980. Verifying the reliability of New York.
lithic use–wear assessments by Ôblind testsÕ: the low-power Schiffer, M.B., 1978. Methodological issues in ethnoarchaeol-
approach. Journal of Field Archaeology 7, 87–120. ogy. In: Gould, R.A. (Ed.), Explorations in Ethnoarchae-
J.J. Cunningham / Journal of Anthropological Archaeology 22 (2003) 389–410 409

ology. University of New Mexico Press, Albuquerque, pp. Trigger, B.G., 1989. A History of Archaeological Thought.
229–247. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, MA.
Schiffer, M.B., 1994. Review of ‘‘Elements for an Anthropology Trigger, B.G., 1995. Expanding middle-range theory. Antiquity
of Technology’’. American Anthropologist 96, 202–204. 69, 449–458.
Schiffer, M.B., Skibo, J.M., 1997. The explanation of artifact Trigger, B.G., 1998. Archaeology and epistemology: dialoguing
variability. American Antiquity 62, 27–55. across the Darwinian chasm. American Journal of Archae-
Shanks, M., Tilley, C., 1982. Ideology, symbolic power, and ology 102, 1–34.
ritual communication: a reinterpretation of Neolithic Tringham, R.E., 1978. Experimentation, ethnoarchaeology,
mortuary practices. In: Hodder, I. (Ed.), Symbolic and and the leapfrogs in archaeological methodology. In:
Structural Archaeology. Cambridge University Press, Cam- Gould, R.A. (Ed.), Explorations in Ethnoarchaeology.
bridge, MA, pp. 129–154. University of New Mexico, Albuquerque, pp. 169–200.
Shanks, M., Tilley, C., 1987. Social Theory and Archaeology. Tringham, R., Cooper, G., Odell, G., Voytek, B., Whitman, A.,
Polity Press, Cambridge, MA. 1974. Experimentation in the formation of edge damage: a
Shanks, M., Tilley, C., 1992. [1987] Re-Constructing Archae- new approach to lithic analysis. Journal of Field Archae-
ology: Theory and Practice, second ed. Routledge, London. ology 1, 171–196.
Simms, S.R., 1992. Ethnoarchaeology: obnoxious spectator, Tschauner, H., 1994. Archaeological systematics and cultural
trivial pursuit, or the keys to a time machine? In: L. evolution: retrieving the honour of culture history. Man 29,
Wandsnider (Ed.), Quandaries and Quests: Visions of 77–93.
ArchaeologyÕs Future. Center for Archaeological Investiga- Tschauner, H., 1996. Middle-range theory, behavioural archae-
tions, Occasional Paper No. 20, Southern Illinois Univer- ology, and postempiricist philosophy of science in archae-
sity, Carbondale, pp. 186–198. ology. Journal of Archaeological Method and Theory 3, 1–
Skibo, J.M., Schiffer, M.B., Kowalski, N., 1989. Ceramic style 30.
analysis in archaeology and ethnoarchaeology: bridging the van der Leeuw, S.E., 1984. Dust to dust: a transformational
analytical gap. Journal of Anthropological Archaeology 8, view of the ceramic cycle. In: van der Leeuw, S.E.,
388–409. Pritchard, A.C. (Eds.), The Many Dimensions of Pottery:
Stahl, A.B., 1993. Concepts of time and approaches to Ceramics in Archaeology and Anthropology. University of
analogical reasoning in historical perspective. American Amsterdam, Amsterdam, pp. 707–773.
Antiquity 58, 235–260. van der Leeuw, S.E., Pritchard, A.C. (Eds.), 1984. The Many
Stanislawski, M.B., 1974. The relationships of ethnoarchaeol- Dimensions of Pottery: Ceramics in Archaeology and
ogy, traditional and systems archaeology. In: Donnan, Anthropology. University of Amsterdam, Amsterdam.
C.B.Clewlow Jr., C.W. (Eds.), Ethnoarchaeology. Mono- van-der-Leeuw, S.E., Papousek, D.A., 1992. Tradition and
graph IV, Archaeological Survey, Institute of Archaeology. Innovation. In: Audouze, F. (Ed.), Ethnoarcheologie: Jus-
University of California, Los Angeles, pp. 15–26. tification, Problemes, Limites. Internationales dÕArcheologie
Stanislawski, M.B., 1978. If pots were mortal. In: Gould, R.A. et dÕHistoire dÕAntibe 12. Editions APDCA, Juan-les-Pines,
(Ed.), Explorations in Ethnoarchaeology. University of pp. 135–158.
New Mexico Press, Albuquerque, pp. 201–227. VanPool, C.S., VanPool, T.L., 1999. The scientific nature of
Stark, M.T., 1993. Refitting the ‘‘cracked and broken facßade’’: postprocessualism. American Antiquity 64 (1), 33–53.
the case for empiricism in post-processual ethnoarchaeol- Vidale, M., Kenoyer, J.M., Bhan, K.K., 1992. A discussion of
ogy. In: Yoffee, N., Sherratt, A. (Eds.), Archaeological the concept of cha^ıne operatoire in the study of
Theory: Who Sets the Agenda?. Cambridge University stratified societies: evidence from ethnoarchaeology and
Press, Cambridge, MA, pp. 93–104. archaeology. In: Audouze, F., Ethnoarcheologie: Justifica-
Stern, D.G., 2003. The practical turn. In: Turner, S.P., Roth, tion, Problemes, Limites. Internationales dÕArcheologie et
P.A. (Eds.), The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of the dÕHistoire dÕAntibe 12. Editions APDCA, Juan-les-Pines,
Social Sciences. Blackwell, Oxford, pp. 185–206. pp. 181–194.
Steward, J.H., 1942. The direct historical approach to archae- Wallaert-P^etre, H., 1999. Manual laterality apprenticiship as
ology. American Antiquity 7, 337–343. the first learning prescribed to potters. In: Owen, L.R., Porr,
Sullivan, A.P., 1978. Inference and evidence in archaeology: a M. (Eds.), Ethno-Analogy and the Reconstruction of
discussion of the conceptual problems. In: Schiffer, M.B. Prehistoric Artifact Use and Production. Urgeschichtliche
(Ed.), Advances in Archaeological Method and Theory, vol. Materialhefte 14, Mo Vince Verlag, T€ ubingen, pp. 185–
1. Academic Press, New York, pp. 183–222. 206.
Tani, M., Longacre, W.A., 1999. On methods of measuring Watson, P.J., 1979. The idea of ethnoarchaeology: notes and
ceramic uselife: a revision of the uselife estimates of cooking comments. In: Kramer, C. (Ed.), Ethnoarchaeology: Impli-
vessels among the Kalinga, Philippines. American Antiquity cations of ethnography for archaeology. Columbia Univer-
64, 299–308. sity Press, New York, pp. 277–287.
Thompson, R.H., 1991. The archaeological purpose of ethnoar- Watson, P.J., 1980. The theory and practice of ethnoarchaeol-
chaeology. In: Longacre, W.A. (Ed.), Ceramic Ethnoarchae- ogy with special reference to the Near East. Paleorient 6,
ology. University of Arizona Press, Tucson, pp. 231–245. 55–64.
Trigger, B.G., 1978. Ethnoarchaeology: some cautionary con- Watson, P.J., 1982. Review of Living Archaeology. American
siderations. In: Tooker, E. (Ed.), Ethnology By Archaeol- Antiquity 47, 445–448.
ogists. American Ethnological Society, Washington, DC, Wiessner, P., 1983. Style and social information in Kalahari
pp. 1–9. San projectile points. American Antiquity 49, 253–276.
410 J.J. Cunningham / Journal of Anthropological Archaeology 22 (2003) 389–410

Wilmsen, E., 1989. Land filled with flies: a political economy of Wylie, A., 1992. The interplay of evidential constraints and
the Kalahari. Chicago University Press, Chicago. political interests: recent archaeological research on gender.
Wylie, A., 1982. An analogy by any other name is just as American Antiquity 57 (1), 15–35.
analogical: a commentary on the Gould–Watson dialogue. Wylie, A., 1995. [1989] The interpretive dilemma. In: Pinsky, V.,
Journal of Anthropological Archaeology 1, 382–401. Wylie, A. (Eds.), Critical Traditions in Contemporary
Wylie, A., 1985. The reaction against analogy. In: Schiffer, Archaeology: Essays in the Philosophy, History, and
M.B. (Ed.), Advances in Archaeological Method and Socio-Politics of Archaeology. University of New Mexico
Theory, vol. 8. Academic Press, New York, pp. 63–111. Press, Albuquerque, pp. 18–27.
Wylie, A., 1988. ÔSimplyÕ analogy and the role of relevant Wylie, A., 2000. Questions of evidence, legitimacy, and
assumptions: implications of archaeological practice. Inter- the (dis)unity of science. American Antiquity 65 (2),
national Studies in the Philosophy of Science 2 (2), 134–150. 227–237.

You might also like