You are on page 1of 8

‘. . . and what they do as they’re going . . .

’:
sounding space in the work of Alvin Lucier

RANDAL DAVIS
40 Owen Street, #E7 Hartford, CT 860.233.3866, USA
E-mail: rdavis36@snet.net

This paper considers the early work of Alvin Lucier and the space ‘to sound’. Both of these interpretations –
its often problematic positioning between concert and one might more appropriately call them ‘resonances’
installation work as a means of questioning how installation – have direct meaning in Lucier’s work, and it is
might be defined. Following an introductory survey of the particular mode of Lucier’s interest that is of
Lucier’s work, a history of installation in the visual arts is concern here, specifically as it has to do with how the
traced through the debate, initiated by Michael Fried, on the
morphology and, even, the phenomenology, of sound
‘theatricality’ of minimalism. Fried’s condemnation of the
role of the viewer in what he termed ‘literalist’ art became,
installation may be understood.
contrary to his intentions, a central element in thinking about Alvin Lucier (b. 1931, Nashua, NH, USA) has, in
installation work. Fried’s position was recently engaged a body of widely recognised work beginning in 1965,
again by Hal Foster in positing a particular phenomenology with Music for a Solo Performer, consistently held
of minimalist work, which is seen to be directly relevant to a position of eminence as an innovative figure in
the example of Lucier. Having thus established the relevance live electronic music. Lucier has been no less signifi-
of this phenomenology to the consideration of sound cant in creating a body of work which both clarifies
installations, whether they are themselves minimal works or and problematises the understanding of what ‘sound
not, discussion returns to the problematic example of Lucier, installation’ might consist. This double movement,
and the conclusion that the boundary between concert and
one might say, is found throughout his work. His offi-
installation works may always be permeable, that a precise
morphology of installation will remain elusive.
cial biography, as published by Wesleyan University,
where he has taught for some years, notes that he has:

1. INTRODUCTION . . . pioneered in many areas of music composition


and performance, including the notation of per-
The title of this paper is taken from a conversation formers’ physical gestures, the use of brain waves in
between Alvin Lucier and Michael Parsons: live performance, the generation of visual imagery
But what interests me is sound moving from its by sound in vibrating media, and the evocation
source out into space, in other words what the of room acoustics for musical purposes. His recent
three-dimensional hall is. Because sound waves, works include a series of sound installations and
once they’re actually produced, they have to go works for solo instruments, chamber ensembles,
somewhere, and what they do as they’re going and orchestra in which, by means of close tunings
interests me a lot. (Parsons 1995: n.p.) with pure tones, sound waves are caused to spin
through space.
This is, in one way, an unremarkable statement of
physical fact – although, it should also be acknow- This brief statement, though, rather more confounds
ledged, one perhaps too often forgotten. The propaga- than distinguishes concert and installation works. I
tion of sound is inevitably a dynamic phenomenon, think this difficulty derives not at all from evasiveness
on the part of the composer but instead serves an
and intrinsically spatialised. This is no more evidently
accurate measure of the diffidence such distinction
the case for Lucier than, say, for Liszt.
imposes.
To make too much, however, of this seeming com-
A conversation between Lucier and Thomas Moore
monality is, finally, not helpful and may, in fact, need-
in 1983 made the differentiation, or lack of same,
lessly mystify efforts to understand sound installation.
manifest (Moore 1983: n.p.):
Thus I also refer in my title to ‘sounding space’, which
may be taken in several senses: first, in the sense of TM: You do have an installation down at the
an exploration, an essay of the characteristics of an Corcoran later this month.
acoustic space; and second, a more powerful sense, AL: Yeah, right.
that an installation project is, in some certain way, TM: Or, no, it’s next month . . .
indissociable from its environment, that is, in causing AL: Yeah, uh-huh.
Organised Sound 8(2): 205–212 © 2003 Cambridge University Press. Printed in the United Kingdom. DOI: 10.1017/00000000000000000
206 Randal Davis

TM: . . . which is the Pure Waves, Bass Drum and re-recordings by a microphone placed in the room, a
Acoustic Pendulum piece. process activating the acoustic characteristics of the
AL: Which I’m playing this evening as a concert performance space itself. As recorded by the com-
piece. poser, the text used also specifically, and reflexively,
describes the circumstance of performance (Lucier
In this case, it is evident that (to give its full title) Music
1980: 30), beginning:
for Pure Waves, Bass Drums and Acoustic Pendulums
(1980) existed for Lucier as both, though presump- I am sitting in a room, different than the one you
tively in some way different, concert and installation are in now.
works.
I am recording the sound of my speaking voice, and
Much later, in a talk at the Zeitgleich symposium
I am going to play it back into the room again and
(1994), Lucier referred to Music on a Long Thin Wire
again until the resonant frequencies of the room
(1977) as ‘my first sound installation’. This would, on
reinforce themselves so that any semblance of my
the face of it, appear to establish a primacy trumping
speech, with perhaps the exception of rhythm, is
at least some of the ambiguities in his earlier discussion
destroyed.
with Moore of Music for Pure Waves, Bass Drums
and Acoustic Pendulums. However, interestingly, the What you will hear, then, are the natural resonant
published score of Music on a Long Thin Wire refers frequencies of the room articulated by speech.
explicitly throughout to its ‘performance’, no less the
I am sitting in a room appears, in this preliminary
conversation with Douglas Simon which accompanied
view, a concert work, its performance practice quite
the first publication of the score, in consistently refer-
perfectly embodying the qualities of Steve Reich’s
ring to ‘playing’ the work in what are explicitly ‘con-
Music as a Gradual Process, from 1968:
certs’ and ‘performances’ – no mention is made of it
as an installation project (Lucier 1980: 160–70). The distinctive thing about musical processes is
Again, the uncertainties here are no measure of that they determine all the note-to-note (sound-
ingenuousness on the part of Lucier. At the same time, to-sound) details and the overall form simulta-
they cannot but occasion a thorough review of the neously . . . I am interested in perceptible processes.
body of work with specific respect to these questions. I want to be able to hear the process happening
The differentiation of ‘concert’ and ‘installation’ throughout the sounding music. To facilitate
seems, in these cases, at the very least, permeable. closely detailed listening a musical process should
happen extremely gradually. (Reich 1974: 9)
2. EARLY WORKS Yet, what do we mean here by ‘performance’? If
‘performance’ is understood as what results when a
Music for Solo Performer is undoubtedly one of
performer follows the instructions of the score, then
Lucier’s signature works, and surely deserved of sus-
I am sitting in a room is clearly a ‘concert’ work, as
tained attention – this exposition, however, substan- the activities by the notional ‘performer’ to achieve
tially omits it from consideration. Its performance a ‘performance’ are clearly specified and essentially
makes, beyond doubt, an extraordinary spectacle, as invariant from circumstance to circumstance.
the performer activates, by means of hugely amplified This would be consistent with the general example
brain waves, sympathetic resonances in an ensemble offered by the mathematician Spencer-Brown, in sug-
of percussion instruments. Despite its significance on gesting a certain equivalence between cookery and
any number of levels of critical and musicological composition – the taste, to restate his argument, of a
inquiry, for the purposes of this discussion, Music for cake may be indescribable, but the steps to achieve the
Solo Performer remains a decidedly concert piece. One result are readily demarcable, called the ‘recipe’, and
might, for example, consider it a large-scale instan- so, he suggests, with composition, where the replica-
tiation of Cage’s view of the prepared piano as a tion of the composer’s gestures (i.e. notation) then
percussion ensemble under the control of a single per- replicates an experience (Spencer-Brown 1972: 77).
former, to paraphrase the suggestion of his 1948 career This is fine on the face of it, and even of perhaps
precis, A Composer’s Confessions (Cage 1993: 36). Or, broad relevance, but is nonetheless presumptive.
more broadly, pace Ravel, a concerto for left brain. Indeed, I am sitting in a room appears to offer a strik-
Lucier’s other early, no less signature work, I am ing, perhaps definitive, counter-example. It is intrinsic
sitting in a room (1969), poses a very different set of to this composition that the result of arbitrarily con-
questions. Imminently suggestive of what the com- sidered identical actions in different spaces cannot
poser himself has called his abiding interest ‘in the but produce radically different results due to the dif-
poetry of what we used to think of as science’ (Lucier fering acoustic properties of the spaces. If, therefore,
1980: 169), I am sitting in a room subjects a short ‘performance’ is understood to refer to the listener’s
fragment of spoken text to repeated playbacks and experience, the ‘taste of the cake’, as Spencer-Brown
‘. . . and what they do as they’re going . . .’ 207

would have it, I am sitting in a room appears much sing or whistle, or play any . . . instrument through the
more like, within the still general framework of our system’ (Lucier 1980: 56).
differentiation, an installation work, i.e. one whose And, again, certain deep questions present them-
experience is inseparable from the specific physicality selves. In this circumstance, a listener, notionally iso-
of its instantiation. lated at the ‘last stage’, would have knowledge neither
This is not simply a matter of the fine parsing of of the originary sound materials nor of the acoustic
semantics. I am sitting in a room, like the later Music characteristics of the intervening environments; of
for Pure Waves, Bass Drums and Acoustic Pendulums course, by direct implication, interestingly enough, the
and Music on a Long Thin Wire, also seems to allow a performers themselves might have no knowledge of
range of realisations which would readily encompass the final sounding result of their performance. This is
installations, as the score also notes the possibility of an unusual circumstance and one, it should be noted,
‘mak[ing] versions in which one recorded statement is that would seem to defy Reich’s definition of music as
recycled through many rooms’ (Lucier 1980: 31). process.
This allowance raises still more very interesting The concluding paragraph of the score of Quasi-
questions. If, for example, one assumes the audience modo, however, bears quotation here in its entirety:
to be fixed in their [various] room[s], what we obtain
Systems may be set up in public or private places on
in this multiple realisation is the performance of
permanent or semi-permanent bases for people to
a ‘concert’ piece, provisos above notwithstanding, in
move through and use freely. Ambient events, such
which the audience[s] will hear very different results.
as footsteps, door slams, and explosions may also
If, though, the audience is mobile through these varied
be welcomed for processing. (Lucier 1980: 57)
environments, the inevitable multiplicity of this
experience would seem to move I am sitting in a This final provision is, in one sense, clearly contra-
room decisively toward being an installation work. dictory to the distinction of the score’s earlier
Lucier himself seems to have responded to some of specification of a separation between originary and
the implications of his own instruction with the sub- final stages. No less clearly, a situation in which
sequent Quasimodo the Great Lover (1970); it should a listener may ‘move through and use freely’ these
be noted here, as a point of reference, that the scores discrete environments is a specifically synchronic
thus far under discussion are all entirely verbal, and environment.
their allowances, for example, of alternative possibili- The allowance that the listener may ‘use freely’ these
ties for realisation are not, therefore, marginalia, but sounding results, which may also incorporate ‘ambient
explicit to the published score. events’ is deeply marked, of course, by the influence of
Quasimodo, ‘for any person who wishes to send Cage. Though Cage thematised this somewhat differ-
sounds over long distances . . . to capture and carry ently throughout his career, it served as something
to listeners far away the acoustic characteristics of very much like a constant; in the language of his later
the environments through which they travel’ (Lucier years, as in Music Without Horizon Soundscape That
1980: 55) is, in one sense, clearly and directly related Never Stops (1991), this was the recognition that
to I am sitting in a room. Employing the same basic ‘structure now in my work has given way to process
principle, that of the room as a resonant filter, Lucier’s just as a table would give way to the weather’ (Cage
score describes, as one example, the passage of sound 1993: 278).
through a building, in and out of rooms, corridors,
stairwells, and so on; the iterative process of the
3. THE PROBLEMATICS OF INSTALLATION
earlier work is, in Quasimodo, made, though perhaps
labyrinthine, linear. I have, to this point, used the terms ‘installation’ and
Or is it? The relation between I am sitting in a room ‘concert works’ rather loosely; this, first, to suggest
and Quasimodo might seem, at least in summary, to how permeable the boundary between the two is in
enact something like the familiar distinction of syn- Lucier’s music and, no less, to anticipate how difficult
chronic and diachronic structuration. I am sitting in a reliable differentiation may be in any case. Installation
room, at least in its restricted ‘concert’ version, would works have been, one may readily assert, a com-
appear decidedly diachronic, its process reflecting an monplace in the visual arts of at least the past three
explicitly stepwise causality. The spatial extension of decades. Deriving from the ‘post-studio’ practices of
Quasimodo, a literal chain of audio systems, quite minimalism and post-minimalism, installation works
complicates the perception of causality. were, at least initially, often defined via negativa – that
Again, the score is suggestive in this regard with its is, not painting, not sculpture, and so on, an operation
possibilities for realisation. Lucier first allows that characteristic of such otherwise distinct examples
‘performers’ and ‘listeners’ may be absolutely sepa- as the disordered order of Robert Morris’ ‘scatter’
rate, with the instruction that performers, ‘isolated pieces and the ordered disorder of Robert Smithson’s
[emphasis added] from the listeners at the last stage, ‘site/non-site’ projects.
208 Randal Davis

The practice of installation art is manifestly not sin- Works, therefore, in the broadest sense, are under-
gular, but instead plural – and, I should go so far as to stood to be portable in a way which installations are
suggest, perhaps irreducibly so. To the extent that this not. On the surface, this seems clear enough, though it
is true, and I believe it so to a considerable extent, the sets aside consideration of ‘works’ which may also be
project of a unified history of installation practice will intrinsically fixed to a site – in this regard, one might
prove elusive, whether with respect to visual or audio regard Margaret Wertheim’s reading of Giotto’s
art. It might, then, follow that it would be similarly Arena Chapel as an installation work, ‘the medieval
difficult to identify a primary impulse to the practice – equivalent of virtual reality’ (Wertheim 1999: 74) to
a ‘source’, if you will. Yet, in fact, if figured in suf- be most suggestive.
ficiently broad terms, it is not so difficult to find such One could, quite reasonably, respond to this by
an impulse, this evidently consisting of the activation stipulating Giotto an installation artist, and drawing
of the entirety of the space as, if not an active element from that the conclusion that installation has far more
of the work, at least then as the site for an immersive permeated artistic practice than imagined, and our
experience. Put differently, this primary impulse is one failure to recognise this would, therefore, be histori-
which undermines the easy distinction of work and cally explicable as an artifact of reliance on implicitly,
environment. if not explicitly, formalist models. This may well be
The artist Jessica Stockholder expressed this well in true, but there is, in any case, nothing particularly
Parallel Parking, written in 1993: revelatory itself about the discovery that formalist
models of art may have been rather overvalued, nor
My work doesn’t have a frame, in the usual sense, does that recognition, as the example above indicates,
nor a pedestal. But it often relies on its status as necessarily clarify the status of installation works,
art to be a gestalt; it would otherwise not exist as as one still remains, generally, within the space of
a separate entity among everything else. Each piece negative definition.
relies on its context for definition and also on the
idea of ‘frame’ that we all carry with us . . . There
is an important contradiction here – the frame, 4. THE CRUX OF MINIMALISM
though it is only an abstraction, functions to hold One might expect that the ‘crux’ precede disclaimers,
the work apart from real time, and remove it to but it will be otherwise here, in part because of the
an elevated timelessness; but to the extent that the curious via negativa of understanding installation
viewer participates in framing the work, the frame work. I must also acknowledge that the particularly
becomes part of real time, part of life. apt phrase, ‘the crux of minimalism’, is borrowed from
Hal Foster, whose consideration of this question, it
Stockholder is doubtless correct that there is at least
shall be seen, is of vital importance.
one, if not several, problems here. Spencer-Brown has
Foremost among these disclaimers is that, by raising
reasonably argued in his logical calculus that, to make
the question of minimalism, I by no means wish to
a distinction, the contents of the field being so distin-
argue, nor even imply, that installation works are
guished must be said to differ in value, ‘in a world
somehow intrinsically or necessarily ‘minimal’ –
where, in the first place, the boundaries can be drawn whatever that association may figure. At the same
anywhere we please’ (Spencer-Brown 1972: v). time, neither is this to say that certain sound installa-
And thus we encounter, if not contradiction in its tion works, not least several of Lucier’s own works,
strict meaning, a paradox of self-reference at the very might reasonably fall within, as variously understood,
least. That is, if installation practice is properly dis- this rubric. Edward Strickland, for example, regards
tinct from other art practices, say, painting or sculp- I am sitting in a room as ‘rank[ing] with the finest
ture, it is distinct only because it fails or, perhaps achievements of Minimalist tape music’, though close
more accurately, refuses, to make certain distinctions reading of his enthusiastic appraisal of this figurative
necessary to differentiate it from, as Stockholder says, act of ‘sonic suicide’ also makes one wish, to some
‘everything else’. extent, to attempt a rescue mission (Strickland 1993:
So, again, one has not moved decisively away from 199). There are, in any case, obviously, and no less
the via negativa – a presumption of the propriety persuasive, contravening examples, as the works of, to
of site constitutes at least an implicit, if not explicit name but two, Maryanne Amacher and David Tudor
denial of the uniqueness of the art object. This is, on abundantly evidence.
the one hand, simple enough. We might well, for Second, the following discussion makes reference to
example, see a painting or sculpture in a particular several conspicuous ‘landmarks’ of art historical and
exhibition, and subsequently encounter it in some theoretical discourse of the preceding decades, and it
other circumstance; that change of context may well need be understood that those treatments were, in
carry profound consequences for our apperception, all probability, undertaken without anticipation of
but is unlikely to compel the conclusion that the work the particular use to which they are here applied. This
itself was somehow different. is, in other words, a syncretic reading, one whose value
‘. . . and what they do as they’re going . . .’ 209

is understood to consist less in its conformity to passage, which draws upon Robert Morris’ Notes on
originary context than to its utility to the matter Sculpture, bears quotation at length:
at hand: in that sense, referentially though broadly
. . . literalist works of art must somehow confront
figured, this discourse claims its identity as an
the beholder – they must, one might almost say, be
installation, not a concert piece.
placed not just in his space but in his way. None of
Those reservations aside, we begin with a critical
this, Morris maintains,
thunderclap, or as much of one as recent art history
and criticism has produced, that being Michael Fried’s indicates a lack of interest in the object itself. But
Art and Objecthood. In this argument, first appearing the concerns are now for more control . . . of the
in 1967, Fried was at considerable pains to elucidate entire situation. Control is necssary if the vari-
the manifestly deleterious effects of what he charac- ables of object, light, space, body, are to func-
terised as ‘literalist art’. Specifically, to cite a now- tion. The object has not become less important.
familiar passage in which he distances himself from the It has merely become less self-important.
practice of artists such as Donald Judd, Robert Morris
It is, I think, worth remarking that the ‘entire situa-
and Carl Andre:
tion’ means exactly that: all of it, including it seems,
. . . the literalist espousal of objecthood amounts to the beholder’s body . . .
nothing other than a plea for a new genre of theatre;
Everything counts – not as part of the object, but
and theatre is now the negation of art. (Fried 1968:
as part of the situation in which its objecthood is
125)
established and on which that objecthood at least
The first segment of his assessment is, at least in prac- partly depends [emphasis in the original]. (Fried
tice, unobjectionable, since the milieu was indisput- 1968: 127)
ably rife with calls for ‘new genres of theatre’. It is the
Morris’ texts are themselves deeply imbricated, not
second term, though, that demands attention here.
without their inconsistencies and contradictions, and
In what sense is this ‘theatre’, new or otherwise, the
also the subject of a sustained body of critical inquiry.
‘negation of art’? Fried, to his credit, is not evasive on
In this passage, at least, Fried serves the opposition
this question, unhesitating though perhaps less than
well, perhaps better than his own position. Relative
satisfying:
to his apparent indignation at having an object placed
The experience of literalist art is of an object in a ‘in his way’, and the odd emphasis on the corporeality
situation – one that, virtually by definition, includes of the viewer, which would, in any case, seem unavoid-
the beholder [emphasis in the original]. (Fried 1968: able, Morris’ claim that the object simply lost in
125) ‘self-import[ance]’ seems finally rather modest. For
this discussion, however, we need only note Fried’s
For Fried, this is simply to say that he proposes ‘a
final castigation, that ‘everything counts’, an observa-
crucial distinction . . . between work that is fundamen-
tion entirely consistent with, for example, Stock-
tally theatrical and work that is not’ (Fried 1968: 130).
holder’s observation, yet one plainly drawn to a very
The distinction is, indeed, crucial, and even a cursory
different conclusion. Fried’s position was, of course,
survey of the critical literature which has grown
controversial at the time and, as noted, remains so.
around his essay is far beyond the scope of this
Indeed, as comparison with the observations of
inquiry; the depth, no less the continuing acrimony, of
Morris and Stockholder make clear, the terms of
same is nowhere more in evidence than in Theories
engagement were/are not so dissimilar; the sense that
of Art After Minimalism, a roundtable between Fried,
is made of them is what is incommensurate. It is
Rosalind Krauss, Benjamin H. D. Buchloh, and
against the backdrop of this debate that one might
others, a discussion also of considerable relevance to
read Foster’s The Crux of Minimalism, in which he is
what was referred to above as the relative overvaluing
primarily concerned with a rereading premised upon
of formalist models (Krauss et al. 1987: 71–87).
precisely the engagement Fried decried:
To advance this exposition, it is simply necessary to
note that Fried’s own emphasis makes apparent that In short, with minimalism sculpture no longer
the notional inclusiveness of ‘literalist art’ marks, quite stands apart, on a pedestal or as pure art, but is
literally, as we will see below, an impediment to art. repositioned among objects and redefined in terms
A thorough derivation of his position from the neo- of place. In this transformation the viewer, refused
Kantian formalist criticism of Clement Greenberg, the safe, sovereign space of formal art, is cast back
and its implicitly Cartesian reductivism, is, again, on the here and now; and rather than scan the sur-
beyond the present scope, but may also be readily face of a work for a topographical mapping of the
inferred, as will also be seen. properties of its medium, he or she is prompted to
Fried, again to his considerable credit, was far explore the perceptual consequences of a particular
from unwilling to cite his adversaries. The following intervention in a given site. (Foster 1996: 38)
210 Randal Davis

This, for Foster, marks ‘a fundamental reorientation’, Thus, of course, might one readily understand I am
one in which, clearly enough, the ‘refusal of safe sitting in a room, the conception of which, in its
[and] sovereign space’ mirrors Fried’s abhorrence of theoretical sense, lies in readily demonstrable physics.
the theatrical. In Foster’s view, though, two ‘great The score is also, setting aside for the moment some
misreadings’ of minimalism persist: the first that of the allowances for other possible realisations, quite
it is reductive, the second that it is idealist. His explicit in, as Spencer-Brown would have it, many
commentary on the latter is incisive: aspects of its ‘recipe’ – at the same time, some ingredi-
ents remain, in a certain sense, unspecified, those being
For it is precisely such metaphysical dualisms of the properties of the acoustic space which are, as
subject and object that minimalism seeks to over- Lucier aptly indicates in his own performance text,
come in phenomenological experience. Thus, far ‘articulated’ only as a result of the process. What is
from idealist, minimalist work complicates the this, of course, but the contingency of perception? I am
purity of conception with the contingency of per- sitting in a room enacts, in its very contingency, that
ception, of the body in a particular space and time. ‘sounding space’ in that sense of exploration and
(Foster 1996: 40) discovery.
Music on a Long Thin Wire offers an even more
With necessary respect to the subtlety and breadth of complex view of this contingency. A coil of wire is
Foster’s argument, it need be noted here that he finds extended to great length, passing through a powerful
this ‘announce[ment] of a new interest in the body’ magnetic field and connected to an amplifier being
itself problematic, not least as it may lead to a regard driven by a sine wave oscillator. A hybrid dis-
of perception ‘somehow before or outside history, assembled loudspeaker (Lucier 1980: 165) and mono-
language, sexuality and power’ (Foster 1996: 43). chord, the resonating wire, whose vibrations are
Yet, in this case, the power of his reading consists transduced and themselves amplified to audibility,
precisely in its generality; the critique of the idealist is an extraordinarily unstable system, as one might
reading of minimalism demonstrates, as noted above readily imagine, due in large part to its (relative to a
in the first disclaimer, toward an understanding of loudspeaker) lack of damping; ‘the ecology of the
installation work independent of stylistic filiation. wire’, Lucier has noted, ‘is very fragile’ (Lucier 1994:
Despite, or perhaps because of, its widespread cur- n.p.).
rency, the term has always been somewhat suspect in As Lucier specifies in his score, the wire may be
music. Strickland’s ambitious cross-disciplinary sur- ‘played’ in concert with, given sufficient preparation,
vey, for example, abounds in provocative illustrations more or less predictable results. In an installation
from painting, sculpture and music, ‘not only recogni- environment, however, the results are significantly
sable but visible on all fronts’, yet this ubiquity obtains different. Left alone, so to speak, a particular tuning
at the cost of a very broad definition, premised upon of oscillator[s] may, and is in fact likely to, produce, at
‘severity of means, clarity of form, and simplicity of various times, clear and specific pitches, dense clouds
structure and texture’ (Strickland 1993: 2, 4). Keith of harmonics, and extended periods of silence. One’s
Potter, however, takes a rather different methodolo- experience of Music on a Long Thin Wire in an installa-
gical tack in his study of LaMonte Young, Terry tion context is, therefore, explicitly conditioned by the
Riley, Philip Glass and Steve Reich in regarding the duration of listening (Lucier 1994: n.p. has an amusing
anecdote about the particular experience of these
matter rather more settled in the visual arts, which are
extended silences).
accorded the capitalised Minimalism, than in music,
One of Lucier’s most extraordinary essays in
for which he retains the lower case; his introduction
‘sounding space’ is ‘Still and moving lines of silence in
is, in any case, the single most useful treatment of the
families of hyperbolas’ (1973–4). In this composition,
history of the sobriquet in music theory and criticism which again can function explicitly as installation or
(Potter 2000: 1–20) and bears reading parallel to performance, sine wave oscillators drive pairs of loud-
Foster as an account of the varied, often conflicting, speakers, typically placed in the corners of rooms.
meanings in purely formal and concretely historical When the same frequency is present in both speakers
terms. (of a pair), an invisible topography of sound is created
between them (the titular lines of sound and silence
5. ‘. . . AND WHAT THEY DO AS THEY’RE of the physical wavelength of the frequencies in use).
GOING . . .’ If one oscillator is slightly detuned, this pattern of
troughs and crests will move through the space, rotat-
That said, I would restate the power, understood in ing on the axis of their hyperbolic distribution between
broad terms, of Foster’s reading, and suggest that the loudspeakers.
Lucier’s interest, noted above, ‘in the poetry of what As one would expect, the score indicates several pos-
we used to think of as science’ can be read as a gloss sibilities for realisation; dancers may use the ‘families
on Foster’s ‘complication’ of ideality by contingency. of hyperbolas’ as guides for movement, musicians
‘. . . and what they do as they’re going . . .’ 211

may, by playing pitches microtonally distinct from the In Lucier’s Vespers (1969) this phenomenon, and
oscillators, themselves cause the patterns to move, phenomenology, is even more explicit. Performers
passive resonators (‘unattended percussion’, he says, use Sondols (small devices emitting an intense, highly
such as snare drums – an interesting reference back to directional clicking sound, originally developed to
Music for Solo Performer’s ensemble) may be placed assist blind persons in navigating spaces by means of
throughout the space, articulating the movement of echolocation) to map the performance space. In his
patterns by their response or, of course, an audience notes to a recent release of a recording of the work,
may simply explore the environment freely (Lucier Robert Ashley observes:
1980: 128–9). In Vespers the musical experience comes from the
One’s exploration of this subtly defined space is special ‘meaning’ that the sounds give to the space
almost by definition hesitant, tentative – one has, in in which they are performed. This meaning of space
very literal terms, been deprived, as Foster says, of is something that we have not been invited to appre-
the ‘safe and sovereign’ space, and to navigate the ciate before. Also in the equation, and equally
troughs and crests of Still and Moving Lines of Silence important, the sounds, as what we have come to the
in Families of Hyperbolas is to stimulate a very particu- concert to hear, do not have any musical meaning
larly heightened sense of one’s own corporeality and apart from their relationship to the space. In Ves-
orientation to space. pers the music is not heard even in imagination
This has hardly been a thorough review of Lucier’s except in the performance. (Ashley 2002: 2)
work, and has omitted, for example, his work with The argument that the sounds are devoid of musical
‘portable environments’, a line of development begin- meaning is, in this case, derived from Lucier’s specific
ning with Chambers (1968) and continuing through admonition in the score that ‘any situations that arise
such recent manifestations as Theme (1994) and from personal preferences based on ideas of texture,
Empty Vessels (1997). The latter is particularly inter- density, improvisation or composition that do not
esting, as evidenced by this note for the presentation of directly serve to articulate the sound personality of the
the work in P.S. 1’s Volume: Bed of Sound (2000): environment should be considered deviations from
. . . eight green glass flasks, vases and melon jars are the task of echolocation’ (Lucier 1980: 17).
placed on pedestals positioned in specific locations The situation in Vespers seems, therefore, to satisfy
the conditions of the installation work, yet it is also no
in the room. Microphones are inserted into the
less clearly, as Ashley’s notes indicate, a concert work,
mouths and necks of the vessels and routed to eight
albeit a very unusual one. A similar observation might
loudspeakers similarly deployed throughout the
be made for Bird and Person Dyning (1975) in which
space. The volume levels of the amplifiers are set to
the performer, using a binaural headset/microphone
just below the threshold of feedback. As visitors system, maps the acoustic space using the twitterings
walk through the installation the motions of their of an electronic ‘bird’ as source material. Signals
bodies will alter the delicate balances of the system picked up by the microphones are amplified to the
and cause unexpected resonances, acoustic ringing very edge of feedback so, as with the later Empty
and soft feedback sounds to occur. (Lucier 2000: Vessels, miniscule movements by the performer may
n.p.) produce complex ringings, difference tones and other
Empty Vessels, unlike, for example, I am sitting in resonances.
a room, is not particularly dependent upon the acous- It is a peculiarity, however, of binaural recording
and playback that, properly configured, each listener
tic properties of the space in which it is realised.
in the space will hear the movement of sounds as if
It is, though, another example of a ‘fragile ecology’ – a
surrounding them, and them alone. Bird and Person
silent and motionless viewer would, presumably
Dyning is thus another instance of a work that seems
hear nothing, as there would be no disruption from to satisfy much of what we would expect from an
equilibrium. installation work, yet to do so while remaining within
Of course, the fact that the viewer will almost inevi- the context of the concert presentation.
tably fracture that stasis is a condition of their material Thus does the distinction between concert and
being, and Empty Vessels is, therefore, a precise installation works remain, in the case of Lucier, some-
instantiation of the Friedian situation which ‘virtually what permeable, and as I strongly suspect, is finally, in
by definition, includes the beholder’. It is also a quite this and most other cases, almost inevitable. Bird and
beautiful realisation of an observation made, though Person Dyning is, however, a particularly apt con-
in a very different context, by Victor Burgin, that clusion here, as its engagement of the listener in its
‘perceptual fields are not experienced as objects in process, through the properties of the binaural system,
themselves. Perception is a continuum, a precipitation and their unusual application in the composition,
of event fragments decaying in time, above all a results in something very much like the creation of
process’ (Burgin 1969: 119). a virtual space.
212 Randal Davis

In the most general terms, the process discussed here Krauss, R. et al. 1987. Theories of art after minimalism.
by which, as Foster says, ‘the body in a particular In H. Foster (ed.r) Discussions in Contemporary Culture
space and time’ is situated, is always the creation of a 1: Dia Art Foundation. Seattle: Bay Press.
Lucier, A. 1980. Chambers. Wesleyan: Wesleyan University
virtual space, one dependent upon what Stockholder
Press.
calls ‘the idea of “frame” that we all carry with us’. A Lucier, A. 1994. Thoughts on installations. http://www.
particular space and time is never, of course, fully kunstradio.at/ ZEITGLEICH/CATALOG/ENGLISH/
delimitable; those ‘virtual worlds’, or, in phenomeno- lucier-e.html
logical terms, enframings, as a system, will never Lucier, A. 2000. Volume: bed of sound. http://www.ps1.org/
achieve complete consistency, which may finally sug- cut/volume/lucier.html
gest the simplest answer to why an absolute distinction Moore, T. 1983. Interview with Alvin Lucier. http:
of installation work, whether in sound or visual art, //research.umbc.edu/~tmoore/interview_frame.html?
will remain elusive. /~tmoore/lucier.html
Parsons, M. 1995. Beats that can push sugar. http://www.
l-m-c.org.uk/ texts/lucier.html
REFERENCES Potter, K. 2000. Four Musical Minimalists. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Ashley, R. 2002. Alvin Lucier: Vespers and Other Early Reich, S. 1974. Writings about Music. Halifax: Press of the
Works. New York: New World Records 80604. Nova Scotia College of Art and Design.
Burgin, V. 1969. Situational aesthetics. Studio International Spencer-Brown, G. 1972. The Laws of Form. New York:
178(915) (October 1969): 118–21. Julian Press.
Cage, J. 1993. John Cage: Writer. New York: Limelight Stockholder, J. et al. 1995. Jessica Stockholder. London:
Editions. Phaidon.
Foster, H. 1996. The Return of the Real. Cambridge, MA: Strickland, E. 1993. Minimalism: Origins. Bloomington:
MIT Press. Indiana University Press.
Fried, M. 1968. Art and objecthood. In G. Battcock (ed.) Wertheim, M. 1999. The Pearly Gates of Cyberspace. New
Minimal Art. New York: E. P. Dutton. York: W.W. Norton & Company.

You might also like