You are on page 1of 12

Jahrbuch fiir

Religionsphilosophie Vittono .Hiisle

The Idea of a Rationalistic Philosophy of Religon


Band 6 and Its Challenges'
2007
The essay defends a rationalistic phdosophy of religion, whose main founders I consider to be
Plato, Leibniz, Hegel, but also many authors of the medeval tradition. It deals with four prob-
Herausgegeben von Markus Enders lems that ttus approach has faced: 1. Does conceiving God as Reason not deprive him of free will
and subject hun to necessity? Does the rational self not become identical with God? 2. What is
the function of grace in such a system? Is there a reasonable concept of miracles? 3. How can the
authority of the Church be defended? 4. Is the unicity of Christ compatible with a rationahst ap-
proach? In d four realms, a rationalistic r e d e h t i o n of the traditional concepts is proposed.

One of the most important intellectual changes that has occurred within the
Catholic Church in the last decades is the shlft away from fideism towards ra-
tionalism - or, to be more precise, and to use comparative rather than ciassi-
ficatory concepts, a move from a more fideistic to a more rationalistic stance.
For there is no sharp demarcation, but rather a continuum between the two
positions, and certainly not even John PauI's I1 encyclica Fih~et ratio em-
braced rationalism tout court, even if it recognized its partial right in a quite
surprising form. Also Benedict XVI's Regensburg speech of September 2006
came astonishmgly close to professing reason as the justifying criterion of re-
ligion (although this central point was neglected due to the fuss made over
Benedict's perhaps unfortunate quote from Manuel I1 Paleologus). I use the
words "surprising" and "astonishingly" because most strands of neoscholas-
ticism from the 19th century onward had been quite inimical to rationalism.
They b d d on Thomas Aquinas' distinction betweenpraeambukz ad artiMlosjfidei
and artimlijfidei2and insist that the latter could not, and should not, be justified
by reason. C e r t d y , Aquinas thought that the existence of God was rationally

-
I thank Jay Mdler for correcting my English. As common in the Anglo-American
world, I use the term "philosophy of religon" to refe; to what should be better c d e d "phl-
losophcal theology." For "philosophy of religion" would better fit the discipline deahng with
the human phenomenon of religion, a subdiscipline of the philosophy of humankind intersec-
ting with, among others, social philosophy, philosophy of his to^, and aesthetics. Also the study
of the patboloaes of human r e k o n , as superstition, fanaticism, and sendmenrdty, belongs to
this d s c i p h e . I deal here only with metaphysical and epistemologcal questions related to God.
Vittorio Klostermann Frankfurt am Main
Cf. SK??I??IOtheologim I 1,2; I 2, 2, 11-11 1, 5.
The Idea oja Rationalistic Philo~opbofReL&ion and Its Challenges 161

demonstrable (and thus not an artictllusfidez), and stiU in the 19h century, Gre-
ate position, according to which there were rational (partly historical) argu-
gory XVI condemned the doctrine, orignally defended by Louis EugGne Bau-
ments for believing in a revelation whose contents could not be accepted on
tain, that God's existence had to be accepted only on the basis of faith.3 But
the basis of reason alone. A rationalist position was particularly tempting in
it is fair enough to say that many theologians of the 20thcentury were fideists
times in which there was a clear awareness that a legitimate interpretation of
even with regard to th~smost basic principle, although this attitude dramati-
"revelation" - of Scripture and tradition - was itself a work of reason. If the
cally jeopardized the chances that theology might be taken seriously as a sci-
last meaning of Scripture was allegorical, tropological, and anagogical, then
ence: After all, why should one respect an alleged revelation from a being this meaning had to be based on rational arguments, which alone could have
whose existence is dubious at best? Without philosophical propaedeutics, the power to transcend literal meaning. Even acknowledgmg the rules of pi-
dogmatic theology lacks any rational foundation, and the crisis of fundamen- ety, the Church or Scripture, as in the main work by Origen, the founding fa-
tal theolog~7,with its core disciphe of a philosophical theology, cannot leave
ther of Christian theology: did not mean much if the interpretation of this
the rest of theology unchallenged. Radical fideism was particularly held by the
rule by intellectuals was regarded as superior to that by non-intellectual, or-
theologans influenced by IGerkegaard and the movement of so-called dialec-
dained priests. There can be little doubt that the young (not the later)
tical theology, but also by Catholic theologans, especially those under the
Aug~stine,~ Eriugena, A n ~ e l mAbelard
,~ (to a limited degree), the Victorines,
spell of Martin Heidegger and his postmodernist successors.4
Ramon Llull, and Nicholas of Cusa are rationalists in the sense that they ac-
What brought about the aforementioned change? On the one hand, there
knowledge the authority of reason as the last tribunal of justification regardmg
is the old argument that the appeal to subjective faith does not warrant truth.
the truths of religion. In this respect, they are not too distant from the decisive
This situation is not significantly altered by the appeal to a religous tradition
principle of Enlightenment, and this shows that Christian intellectuals from
shared by d o n s , for there are several such religious traditions whose truth
late Antiquity and the Middle Ages were intellectually far more vivacious and
claims are not logcally compatible with each other. Besides, within the same
diverse than the often submissive and unorigmal Catholic theologians after
tradition there are radically varying interpretations. On the basis of a univer-
the Counter-Reformation. It is hardly accidental that Abelard, Llull, and
salist ethics there is even something insulting and immoral in the conviction
Nicholas of Cusa are all authors of important interreligious dialogues (the
that my religous tradition is superior to others for the simple reason that it
genre being somehow prepared by Anselm's Cur deus homo), since whoever
happens to be my tradition; for other traditions may just as well use the same
tries to engage with persons from a different religious background can hardly
words against me. On the other hand, the more seriously the Christian tradi-
appeal to his own faith, but must rely on rational arguments. Globalization,
tion was studied, the more obvious it became that the Thomist position was
with its rnixing of people from diverse religous traditions, is probably an im-
not the only one. (And the older neoscholasticism, which focused only on
portant social cause for the resurrection of rationalism in the late 20thcentury.
Thomas, often enough did not even render justice to Aquinas.) In Christian
In closed communities, the challenge of the other religions may be ignored; in
(as in Islamic) theology, there had always been a rationalistic alongside the
a world in which various traditions interpenetrate each other, however, this is
more or less fideistic ~ t r a n dand
, ~ some of the greatest Christian theologians
no longer feasible.
clearly had defended the position that the concrete contents of religious truth
An important cause for the fideistic approach to religion was a deflated
should be based on reason alone. They were not satisfied with the intermedi-
concept of rationality that identified reason with scient$c reason, i.e., with sys-
tematized experience, plus logic and mathematic. Since knowledge of God can-
Cf. Henricus Denzinger/Adolfus Schbnmetzer, E~chikdonSyvmbo/om, deefiitonum et de-
not be achieved by means of science, it was thought to be beyond the reach of
chrotionam de rehusjdei et m o ~Barcino
, 321963, n. 2751-2756 and n. 2765-2769. reason. But even if some scientists try to monopolize the term "reason" for their
This intellectual misalliance is regrettable, given the &stic tendencies of Heidegger's p h - own activities, it is not difficult to see that it is far from rational to submit to
losophy, so well elaborated by IHans Jonas, "Gnosis, Existenziahsmus und Nihihsmus," in: Hans
Jonas, Zulischen Nichts und bikei it, Gottingen 1963, 5-25.
See DepTinaPiiJ I Praef. 2; I 5,4; 111 3,4; I11 5,3; lV 2,2; l
V 3,14.
The rationalistic strand is not limited to the heterodox movement of gnosticism. Thus it
can be misleading to see modern rationalists as Hegel and Schelling mainly as heirs of gnosti- See Contra ocodenicos I 3, 9 and De ordi~~e I1 9, 26: Authority is important only at the start
cism. There are, however, other common traits. See Peter Koslowski's impressive study Phi- of the intellectual process. See my interpretation of these and other dialogues dealing with the
losophien der Ofinbonmg. Antiker ~nosti@smns,. F m Z von Boorier, Sche/(ing,Paderborn 2001. relation of reason and authority in: Derphilosophische Dio/o& Miinchen 1996,312ff.
See Bernd Goebel, Reditxh. Wohrheit xnd Frkheif bei Anselm von Cotrtthwy, Munster 2001.
162 Vittorio Hiirle The Idea ofa Rationalistic Phifosoph_yofRelgion and Its Challenges 163

h s claim. Reason is more comprehensive than science, as Kant, the most the central premise that "indeed unsurpassable greatness is possibly exempli-
important modern theorist of the complex architecture of reason, has master- fied".14 Of course Planthga is aware that this premise has to be granted; and
fully shown. E h c s , for example, is a rational discipline, even if valuative indeed this seems to belong to the nature of all arguments: they start from
claims cannot be reduced to descriptive ones such as those dealt wlth by sci- premises in order to arrive at a conclusion, which one may always reject by
ence - this is Hume's lasting i n ~ i g h tAt
. ~ the same time, a dualistic theory is denying at least one of the premises. One's proof may even be the other's re-
unsatisfying if there is no connection between descriptive and normative sen- ductio ad absurdum: If someone regards the conclusion as utterly implausible,
tences, for after all, the Ought has to be implemented within the Is. But if the he WLU regard those premises as confuted that lead to it.
Oilght does not follow from the Is, and at the same time the two spheres There are, however, some assumptions that are conditions of possibdity
have to be connected, the Ought must determine at least some features of the of certain mental activities regarded by most people as legtimate. Science, for
Is. No doubt, the need to interpret the natural world as a place in which the example, presupposes the constancy of natural laws. This principle is not en-
demands of the Ought can be realized is one of the strongest arguments for a tailed by logic alone: for there is no contradiction in the assumption of sud-
moral principle behind nature.1° The argument does not show that all fea- den changes of natural laws; nor does it follow from experience. We do not
tures of Being derive from the Ought, but at least partial determining powers know from experience what will happen in the future, and the distant past,
have to be ascribed to the latter. which we did not witness, is reconstructed on the basis of this principle and
Also within the realm of theoretical reason alone there are arguments for a thus not itself an argument for it. Science therefore presupposes some meta-
spiritual principle of all being. Mental states cannot be identified with physical physical principles that are themselves not grounded in experience or logic.
ones, and while the former seem to supervene on the latter, it is at the same Perhaps, however, they can be made plausible by appealing to some attributes
time inevitable that the ensuing mental states that grasp an argument are con- of God, such as his being one and timeless,15 or/and through the use of
nected logically as much as by the fact that they are supervenient on ensuing teleological arguments - only a nature with constant laws would allow finite
electrochemical processes in a brain. There must be a correspondence be- rational beings to acquire knowledge and thus act morally responsibly. If the
tween these two properties, and if we do not accept a causal force of the project of science presupposes arguments of this sort, then scien*ic rational-
mental on the physical, such parallelism cannot be the result of evolutionary ity is not the most basic form of rationality, but is grounded in some antece-
forces driven by natural selection.ll T h s is, as is known, Leibniz7reformula- dent form of reason. This would explain the well-known historical fact that
tion of the teleologcal proof, and it seems to be immune to Hume's and the scientific revolution was due to deeply pious persons such as Descartes,
I<ant7sattacks against that proof, not to speak of Darwin's destruction of tra- Galtleo, Kepler, and Newton, who regarded their scientific project as a con-
ditional physicotheology. For the argument, as I have just used it, in fact pre- sequence of their religious convictions.
supposes its destruction through the category of natural sele~tion.'~ It would be important for the revival of a rationalist philosophy of religion
The status of the ontological proof is stdl debated, but it is far from clear that it to show that the project of science becomes far more plausible and rational
cannot be form~datedin a cogent way. Alvin Plantingaysreconstruction is the most when certain of its presuppositions are made explicit, namely those that are
plausible candidate for a cogent version. It presupposes, as already Leibniz knew,13 connected to classical assumptions of rational theology. S d , a stubborn scep-
tic could deny the validity of science and thus of its presumed basis, rational
theology. But that whch not even the sceptic can deny is the existence of
Cf. ' 4 Treatise ofHumon Notwre I11 1, 1. truth and its in-principle intelligibility, because this is the transcendental pre-
lo The argument was unfolded by Kant in the second and t h d Cnirgues. A modern vcr-
supposition of all claims. The strongest proof of God - because it would not
sion of "axiarchism," the idea that values determine being, was proposed by John Leslie, Vo/ue
ond Existence, Totowa 1979. start from a premise open to doubt - would certainly be one that showed that the
l1 See my halogue "Encephalius," in: Mindond Mutter 6 (2007), 101- 130. ideas of truth and its intelligibility make sense only if the world is an expression
l2 Needless to say, I do believe that Darwinism is compatible with an objective-idealist version
of theism. See my essay "Objective Idealism and D d s m , " in: Vittorio Hosle/Chdstian U e s
(eds.), Donnitism ondPhi/osophy,Notre Dame 2005,216-242.
l 3 N o m o m essh 11 10 § 7, in: Gottfried W. Leibniz: Die Phi/osophischen Schrifien V , ed. by Carl
l4Alvin Plantinga, The Nature ofNecessi9, Oxford 1982,216.
I. Gerhardt, Berlin 1882,419. j5 See, e.g., Renk Descartes, Pn'n@iophihsophioe I1 36ff.
The Idea ofa Rationalirtic Phihop& of Religion and Its Challenges 165

of an absolute mind.16 I myself have argued that our capacity of having a pri-
ontology is rooted in axiology. Plato, however, does not yet have a theory of
ori knowledge, which at the same time cannot be consistently understood as
mentality; the only dualism he knows is that between the ideas and the physi-
being a merely subjective knowledge, shows that the world is necessarily
cal world. Leibniz, on the contrary, has an elaborate theory of subjectivity,
structured in a way that corresponds to the conceptual demands of a mind.
which is integrated into an axiological worldview. As a good Lutheran, how-
Since th~sis a property of the world that our f d t e minds cannot bestow on
ever, he does not have an ontology of universals; and this is a serious threat
it, it must come from a Mu7d antecedent to the world, i.e. from a divine
to axiology, which seems to presuppose that values actually exist. The other
Mind.I7 It is not the purpose of this essay to elaborate the basic arguments great step in Leibniz' unfolding of the idea of rational theology is his use of a
and ideas of rational theology. What should already be clear, however, is that metaphysics of possible worlds, which is indispensable if we want to ascribe
any attempt to make sense of religious traditions would be well advised to choice to God.
study carefully the aforementioned arguments. Certainly some disagreements There are three reasons why Hegel's philosophy is of enormous impor-
on the divine attributes and God's relations to the world are inevitable, since tance to every person interested in rational theology, and particularly in a phi-
the divine radically transcends human nature, particularly its temporality, which
losophical justification of basic Christian tenets." The first is that Hegel's
permeates all our cognitive efforts. Two famous issues concern whether God is
complex metaphysics acknowledges three strata of being - ideal, natural, and
omnipotent, and whether divine omnipotence entails human freedom in the
mental being. This is itself not accepted as mere fact, but connected to a the-
compatibibst form or allows for a libertarian form. But it would be intellec-
ory of concept formation that is both epistemologcal and ontologcal and
tual suicide to radicalize this insight to some form of negative theology that
tries to be a rational transformation of the Christian belief in a Trinitarian
denies any intelligbllity to God. For such an unintelligible God might well be
God who creates the world according to a triadic pattern. Second, Hegel is
evil or perhaps identical with matter. The basic properties of God that alone
the first great philosopher who offers an elaborate metaphysics of history,
warrant awe for Him are His rationahty and morality - indeed, He is the
still alien to both Plato and Leibniz. He is able to make philosophical sense of
standard of all our claims to morality and reason.
the historical development of Christianity, which can easily disturb traditional
The philosophers who have contributed most to the development of ra-
Christians, when they become aware of it. Third, Hegel insists that God is
tional theology (as distinguished from a theology that takes tradition and
Reason. By doing so, he continues a tradition that begins already with the
revelation into account) are certainly Plato, Leibniz, and Hegel. We owe to
Gospel of John, but there is little doubt that he alters it profoundly. God is
Plato the insights that our knowledge is not reducible to empirical knowledge
no longer a being external to finite humans; he is grasped through reflection
(even if he may well'err in denying a y empirical knowledge) and that we have
on one's own true self, one's reason. Fundamentally, Hegel ident;f;e~the transcen-
a knowledge of the Idea of the Good, which transcends the factual world and
dental with the transcendent: what is a conltion of possibility of our own thought
cannot be identified with our mental acts either.18The Timaem (29 e ff) offers
- the system of basic categories - is something absolute because it cannot be
a picture of the world as a place in which the Idea of the Good realizes itself
negated. God cannot be different from it. Of course, Hegel recognizes that
- the basic structures of the world are as they are because they realize value;
his reconstruction of our basic categories is not identical with the true set of
basic categories, but he rests convinced that the ideal set of categories would
See Josef Schmidt, Phihsophirche Theologie, Stuttgart 2003, 79-105: "Der alethologische be the core of any rational concept of God.2n
Gottesbeweis." An important recent book that uses transcendental hrpments for the founda-
It is this claim that provoked the revolt against Hegel. A further reason
tion of a metaphysical view recognizing in spirit the ultimate reality is the latest work by Bila
Weissmahr, Die Wirklichkeit des Geistes, Stuttgart 2006. A remarkable defence of a spiritualist
was that Hegel's theism is non-eschatological and does not have place for an
and theistic metaphysics can be found in the last work of Germany's best analytical philoso-
pher: Franz von Kutschera, Die Wege des I&alismus, I'aderborn 2006, 252ff. It starts from the
assumption (presumed to be a simple hypothesis) of the intelligibility of being.
I immortality of the soul. It speaks, incidentally, for Hegel's dialectic recon-
struction of the history of pMosophy that his utmost rationalism in religous

l7 See my essay "Foundational issues of objective idealism," in: Vittorio Hiisle, Obective
Ideahim, Ethics, and Politics, Notre Dame 1998,l-40 and 201 -209 (German version 1986).
l8 See my preface to Vittorio Hiisle, Platon inteptetiemn, Paderborn 2004, 19ff. O n Plato's
1 l9 I am aware of the fact that there are irreligious interpretations of Hegel. I defend a dif-
ferent one in my book Hgelr Qstem, Hamburg 1987.
20 Analogously, from a Kandan point of view, God seems to become identical with practical r a -
natural theology as continuation of the presocratic doctrines see Markus Enders, NatIrkche The-
ologie iim Denken der Griechen, Frankfurt a. M . 2000. ~ it/ nofis. Die Ikntitit van Gon utrd reitref
son. See the impressive book by Gerhard Schwarz, E s Deus
praktischer Vernun) in ImmanuelKants 'Kritik lrpraktischen Vernut$", Berlin 2004.
166 Vittotio Hosle The Idea of a Rationalistic Philosophy ofRel&ion and Its Challenges 167

matters was followed by one of the most radical forms of fideism, namely makes something good will easily grant human sovereigns the same capacity.
Kierkegaard's philosophy of religion. In the following, I want to discuss some Hobbes, after all, is deeply rooted in the rehgous voluntarist traditi0n.~3If
of the objections that are voiced against theologcal rationalism;I will answer someone accepts orders by a divine tyrant, he may easily subject himself to
them from a rationalist point of view. Probably the most important criticisms human tyrants as well. The refusal of rational scrutiny is not a respectable act
are the following. First, rationalism subjects God to reason, divinizes human of faith, but a betrayal of a faculty that most intensely connects humans with
reason and does not render justice to our experience of finitude and sinful- God - this is the rationalists' viewpoint. Wlether the latter is circular or not
ness. Second, rationalism does not allow us to reconstruct the concept of depends on whether there can be an ultimate foundation of the basic princi-
grace. Third, the authority of the Church or Scripture is inevitably corroded ples of reason, a question that I cannot pursue here, even if I support an af-
by the project of rationalism. While these three objections can be used also by firmative answer.24
non-Christian theists against their own rationalist philosophies, the fourth Of course, the voluntarist is moved by the reflection that binding God by
and final one is specific to Christianity. It simply states that rationalism can- logic or morality means limting Him by something external to Him, thus de-
not render justice to the figure of Chri~t.~' priving Him of absolute omnipotence. The only answer to this objection can
be that logical truths, the moral law, and perhaps all the eide and laws of being
are not antecedent to God, but are themselves God. This seems, however, to
transform God into a set of absolute Truths. One does not see how He can
s d be somethtng like a person. As we have seen before, in the Platonic tradi-
Why is it, despite these objections, so difficult to get rid of rationalism? Be- tion true being is conceived after the pattern of ideas. The demiurge in the
fore I try to tackle the various objections, let me state that the price of giving Timaetr~is probably nothing other than the mythical symbolization of the ac-
up rationalism can be very high. This is best shown by Kierkegaard's F ~ g otg tive aspect in the Idea of the Good. I have already conceded that Plato is un-
Bmen (Fear and Trembling).22If God is not bound by reason and morality, but, able to capture the specific form of being of fintte subjectivity, and so it should
as the voluntarist tradtion teaches, it is His will that determines what is ra- not come as a surprise that he has difficulty ascribing full-fledged subjectivity
tional and good, then it may well be moral to ktll one's own innocent son, if to God, even if in the Sophist he struggles with the issue. But whoever recog-
He so orders. It i ~ n odifficult
t to see that such an attitude is detrimental to all nizes that mentality is an irreducible form of being, and that it is axiologically
normal moral convictions: jihadist terrorists can fmd in it their justification. superior to non-mental being, cannot avoid interpreting God as Mind. S d , it
Certainly, reasonable voluntarists will deny that jihadists are authorized by is clear that not only the range, but also the nature, of the divine Wnd is quite
God, but the point is that they do not have anythlng more to offer than their different from the human mind. God is not only non-spatial (and thus not a
subjective conviction against the others' subjective conviction. For a rational- body), He is, as the overwhelmng part of the tradition has recognized, non-
ist, refuting the jihadists' claim is easy. It is impossible that God may have au- temporal as well. And that is the reason why it can be an expression of pro-
thorized the jihadists, since their acts are against the moral law, and the moral found religiosity if one hesitates to ascribe personality to God. This has become
law belongs to God's essence. There are good reasons for seeing in the later particularly true in the 20h century, since the phenomenological analysis of per-
doctrine of the potentia absoltrta and in the breakdown of the essentialist tradi- sonhood by Husserl Scheler, and Heidegger has so much insisted on the
tion, to which Thomas Aquinas still belongs, one of the most dangerous temporal features of human persons that it seems difficult to attribute per-
events in the hlstory of philosophical theology - and this not only with regard sonality to an atemporal being. Nevertheless, God's being must be closer t~
to religion, but also to public life. For the whole idea of natural law presupposes mental than to physical being. He must be some form of atemporal Reason in
some form of essentialism, and whoever thinks that it is God's arbitrary will that which the various ideas are connected. For if one accepts the idea that the
starting point of ultimate foundation is the reflection on what one necessarily
See, e.g., Giovanni B. Sala, Die Chri~falogie in Kants 'Religion innerhalb cier Grenxen der blossen presupposes whde raising certain claims, then God is not simply Truth, but
Vemunj", Weilheim 2000.
22 See my criticism in my essay "Kann Abmham gerettet werden? Und: Kann Saren Kierke-
23 See Luc Foisneau, Hnbbes et la toute-puissanc~
rie Dieu, Paris 2000.
gaard gerettet werden? Eine Hcgelsche Auseinandersetzung mit Turcht und Zittern'," in: Vittorio
24 See the important studies by Dieter Wandschneider, particularly "Letztbegriindung und
Hosle, Phihophiegeschichft und alyekn'uer Irieadimu~,Miinchen 1996, 206- 239 and 274-276.
Lo&," in: Hans-Dieter Klein (ed.), Le~tbgriindungah System, Bonn 1994,84-103.
~ The Idea ofa Rationalistic Philosop& ofRel&ion and Its Chalenges 171
this consequentialist justification of the sufferings of the innocent for the
sake of the whole can hardly be the last word. If God is a Icantian and not a dom, in which case hii point is correct, but unoriginal; it has been made by
utilitarian, He will hardly be satisfied with the instrumentaltzation of the less 1 the tradition of Christian rational theology - from A n ~ e l t nto~Hegel
~
which Jiingel wants to break. O r he means something different. The only
- from
fortunate persons without any form of compensation for them.
meaningful reconstruction I can offer would be that God's creation of the
world is a supererogatory act. For indeed supererogarory norms are not easy
~ to capture in the usual triadic system of deontic logic: They are not obliga-
I tory, npr does saying that they are permissible render justice to their specific
Grace is a central concept of religion, and it is often regarded as incompatible difference. Whence this peculiar status? It has to do with the W t s of human
with a rationalist theology. For according to such an approach, there are rea- nature: Even if in a p e n situation it would be morally better to sacrifice
l
sons for God's creating the world as it is; since He is rational, He has to fol- one's life (for example, because it could save many innocent lives), an ethical
low these reasons and is not free to reject them. But when we cannot experi- doctrine usually cannot prescribe such an act, since our drive for self-
ence the good that we receive from Him as a free gift, we are less motivated preservation is too strong. But the limits of human nature do not apply to God;
to accept with h u d t y all that we are and have. The problem of this objec- thus there is no way to reconstruct Jungel's statement through the appeal to
tion is not only that it implies an enormous pride in one's own h d t y , supererogatory norms. It is true that religous persons are often characteriied
which is modestly opposed to the arrogance of reason in people like Plato by an uncommon capacity of engaging in supererogatory acts; however, it
and Leibniz. Readers of Charles Dickens' David Copperjield have probably kept would be an anthropomorplism to transfer this concept to God.
not too affectionate a memory of Uriah Heep's ostentatious h u d t y , which The concept of grace has not only the presumed function to grant God
utmost liberty; it often gves the recipient of grace the feeling of being some-
always smacks of performative contradiction. The more serious flaw is that
the objection is based on a complete misunderstanding of the rationalist posi-
1 thing special, even if at the same time the conviction of not having deserved
tion. When rationalist theology speaks of God's necessary creation of the the grace elicits profusions of h u d t y . This can be understood on the basis
world, it clearly does not mean that the world is logically necessary. Spinoza of common human experiences: When we receive the same as others or
may have thought so, but one &d not even need Leibniz' superior logical in- something that is due to us, we do not think that we are an object of special
tehgence to understand that this cannot be the case: Other worlds are logi- affection, but when we are privileged, we feel loved by the person who so
cally possible. It would be even less appropriate to think of a nomologcal ne- I treats us. And exactly this is the problem of focusing on the concept of grace:
cessity: In the creation of the world, the choice of the laws of nature is at 1 Often enough, one who does so sees in pure accidents of life somedung that
is aiming at him, and him alone, and wants to budd up a special relationship
stake; thus they cannot constrain the creator. What is meant by necessity in
God comes closest to what we experience as moral necessity: The good per- to God, even at the expense of others, who are regarded as less worthy of
son cannot really commit a murder; it is her own nature that prevents her grace. The correct concept of God's relation to humankind, however, can
from doing so. Analogously, if God is perfectly good, it follows from the only be that He aims at realizing as much value as possible; whatever share
falls to oneself must be gratefully accepted, but true gratitude must react to
goodness of His nature that He has to create a world that could not be better. 1
1 the whole world as a divine gift.
This necessity is an intrinsic necessity, and thus simultaneously a manifestation
of freedom. In his influential book Go2t als Geheiinnis der Welt,32 Eberhard Nevertheless, one cannot deny that there is a legitimate place for the ex-
Jungel has averred that God is more than necessary. But eicher he means perience of grace. Even if all persons who exist are there because they belong
what I have just said, namely, that God's necessity is compatible with free- to the best possible world (or the one of the worlds with maximal value that
God has chosen), there is stiU the undeniable fact that not all persons have
the same degree of proximity to God. If someone happens to be relatively
32 Tiibingen 51986. The polemic agatnst what Jiingel calls with Abraham Calov and Karl I close to God -let us assume she is Mother Teresa -, she can s d ask herself:
Barth "mixophilosophrcotheolo~a"(204, note 1) is misleading, for all dsdplmes are bound by
If Mother Teresa necessarily belongs to the world to be created by God, why
conceptual analysis and thus none can get rid of philosophy. It is a good idea also for theolo-
gians, if they want to speak about necessity, to render themselves familiar with the basic con-
cepts of modal logic.
i 33 curdeus horn 115.
The Idea ofa Rationalistic Phi/usoph_y o f h l i g o n and Its Challenges 173

have 1 become Mother Teresa? Indexicality is a notoriously murky issue, and


it may be that for a divine Mind the problem does not exist. But for a fnite racle at work. If that motivates her to achieve her moral best, there is no rea-
consciousness with fust-person access to herself, it clearly does; and since son why she should refrain from thmking so. A decisive criterion in the
there can be no objective answer to it, even a rationalist can concede that re- choice of the world to be created is certainly that nature serves moral pur-
flection on t h s question trigers an experience of grace. If such an experience poses, and therefore such events may well have been one of the reasons why
transforms itself into the desire to give to others in exchange for the divine God chose such a world. But they are causally connected to many other
gift of one's core self (it is a g f t , for one has not created oneself), then we can events, and we can never exclude the possibihty that God did not choose
assume that this both corresponds to the divine W d and contributes to a them primarily for their own sake, but because they prepare, or follow from,
deepening of one's autonomy. For we become autonomous only by trans- other events with a hgher value. Wanting to exclude t h s would indeed be a
forming, as far as we can, what we have received into something of our own sign of vanity, of making oneself the center of the universe.
making. Again, autonomy and theonomy converge. It cannot come as surprise that conversions are often perceived as being
Closely connected to the issue of grace is the problem of miracles. The connected with miraculous events. But what makes Augustine's Confes~iones
concept is notoriously difficult to defie. First, the statement of facts is not the extraordinary book that it is is the fact that the hearing of the voice sing-
easy, and in the case of events long past, is almost never beyond reasonable ing "Tolle ip" and the ope&g of the Bible (VIII 12,29) are only the last trig-
doubt; second, if extraordinary facts can be proven to occur, the question in- gering events in a long story that prepares the conversion with psychological
evitably arises whether they can be explained by natural laws (including laws necessity. The Christian mother, the death of the close friend (IV 4, 7 ,the
correlating mind and body) perhaps yet unknown to us. There is the further disappointment by Manichee authorities (V 7, 12), the intellectual and per-
problem that an absolute Mmd should not need miracles in the sense of ad sonal model represented by Ambrose (V1 3, 30, the disgust with worldly am-
hoc interventions. After all, we admire a watchmaker the more, the less often bition (VI 6, 9), the appropriation of Platonism (VII 9, 14), and fially the
we have to bring our watch to hun for repair. Baden Powell has expressed conversion stories about Victorinus, Antony, and Ponticianus' colleagues
this argument with the words: "It is derogatory to the idea of Infinite power (VIII 2ff, 3ff) are all decisive steps, to which almost anything could have been
and wisdom, to suppose an order of things so imperfectly established that it added in order to kgger Augustine's own conversion. The "miracle7' is far
must be occasionally interrupted and violated when the necessity of the case less relevant than its prehstory. And in fact, the true miracle is not the myste-
compelled."34 The decisive point for a religious person is that nature mani- rious voice but the structure of the human mind that even in a time as shal-
fests a moral order. Whether such manifestations happen in accordance with low as that of Late Antiquity cannot be deprived of its desire and its capacity
known laws or through their violation should not matter. Indeed, John Henry to return to its divine principle. The hstory of Christianity with its extraordi-
Newman deliberately disconnects the concept of miracle from the idea that it nary abihty for regeneration is in this sense rmraculous, and the more miracu-
has to occur agamst laws of nature. "There wdl be no need of analyzing the lous, the less unexplainable facts have occurred in it.36
causes, whether supernatural or natural, to which they are to be referred.
They may, or they may not, in this or that case, follow or surpass the laws of
nature, and they may do so plainly or doubtfully, but the common sense of
mankind will call them miraculous; for by a miracle is popularly meant what-
ever be its formal defmition, an event which impresses upon the mind the Why does a rationalist need a church, a tradition, a Scripture? Again let me
immediate presence of the Moral Governor of the w0rld."3~ begin with a reflection on the price one has to pay if one exempts church,
In t h s sense a person whose life is saved through a surprising event or tradition, or Scripture from the tribunal of reason. In many aspects, it is even
who, on account of an important encounter, discovers what her real vocation higher than if one embraces a voluntarist concept of God. For the voluntarist
is, i.e., how she can make the best of the talents she has, may well see a mi- critic of the jlhadist terrorist can deny that the latter is f u l f ~ God's
g will (even
if he does not have a cogent argument against it) After all, a claim that God
34 .‘On the Study of the Evidences of Chnstianiry," in: Frederick Temple et. al., Essqs and speaks directly to a person, without the mediation of reasons, is unverifiable
Reviews, London 1860,94- 144,114.
35 ilpologia Pm I4ta Sua, Mineola 2005, 198f. 36 This was h e a d y sdd by some ancient Christian apologetics, but nobody has formulated
I
l it as beautifidly as Dante does in Para&so XXN 106ff.
The Idea of a Rationalistic Pbilosoph_y of Religion and Its Challenges 175

(at least from the outside), and thus even a voluntarist can deny the authority
of alleged revelations that another pretends to have received. He is not able I of thts idea. Needless to say, it would be an irresponsible optimism whlch be-
to reject them based on content - since everythg is possible $01 God. But lieves that any accretion constitutes intellectual or moral progress; after all,
neither is he bound to assume that they stem from the ultimate source of va- even the spiritual world knows forms of increasing entropy. The reification of
lidity. The situation changes, however, when the ultimate source is a church - once novel ideas for the purpose of maintaining hterocratic power often leads
or better, the persons in a certain moment in charge of a church. For what to the loss of the truth o r i p d y present in them. A periodical return to be-
gnnings is thus both wholesome and necessary. But one suffers from a pro-
they decree is usually quite clear. Now it is never the self-understanding of a
found self-deception if one believes that this attempt at reformation is a real
church that its decrees determine what is good. In the o r h essendi, God, and
even Scripture, plus tradition (in the Catholic case), come before the church. return to the past. A grown-up cannot become a child again (only clddish),
But regarding the ordo cognoscendi, churches often have claimed that they are and every sober analysis of the Christian Reformation will have to concede
that it did not delay, but rather accelerated the transformation of Christianity
the only way to access the w d of God and that reason must submit to them.
I that fmally brought forth the modern world. Despite all the dangers and vices
There is a well-known circularity in wanting to found the legitimacy of a I

church on God and at the same time found the knowledge of God on the peculiar to modernity it seems obvious to me that a religious interpretation of
church. For in this manner, any church - and for an outside perspective there
are many communities claiming to be churches - can fmd a way of justifying
1
I
it is obliged to acknowledge its function in the divine plan for human history.
A tendency that has prevailed for almost three centuries now cannot be seen
itself: It simply has to state that it has been founded by God and that one can
I
as purely negative.39 And in fact it is obvious that the positive force of mod-
understand this only by submitting to its authority. A self-justification may be
1 ernization is that it has destroyed the old hierarchical world and implemented
possible for reason, since any negation of it at the same presupposes it; but moral universalism in new legal and economic institution^.^ No doubt, a uni-
ths certainly does not hold for the various churches, whose authority can be versalism that has become completely formal and detached from a religious
denied without performative self-contradiction. But not only are there various
I interpretation of the world is not likely to be stable, and thus totalitarianism is
competing churches; each individual church itself changes in its hstory. Tra- a threat specific to modernity. S d , a church's right answer can never be the
dition is far less homogeneous that it seems at first glance, and the variations denial, but only the integration, of modernity, not only because of its effi-
in the concept of God that we find in the various books and strata of the Old ciency, but also because of the moral principle that drives and ennobles it.
Testament as well as the different christologies offered by the four Gospels, Let me return to my question: Why does a rationalist need a church? The
show us that, at least in the Christian tradition, Scripture is not a monolithic answer is relatively simple. Claims of truth are universal, and thus nobody can
bloc. Its doctrine varies, and it has evolved. And usually we can recognize be satisfied with having found truth alone. It is certainly not the consensus
moral progress - suffice it to compare the book of Joshua with the prophetic that makes a proposition true, but gven our own fallibihty, we are well-advised
books.37 to check our convictions in discourse with other people. We even arrive at ra-
Since the criteria of identity for a doctrine are even fuzzier than those for tional autonomy only after a long education during which we internahe the
personal identity, one may certainly defend the thesis that there has been only errors as well as the wisdom of the tradition. Through the appropriation of
I tradition we come to know arguments of an amazing intellectual force, which
a deveIopment of a doctrine, without danger to its core contents and its identity. 1
I
we would never have found on our own. Since it is good that a truth be
But even such a development inevitably triggers the.question: Why did a
church evolve?38And the best answer one can hope for would be that new
insights based on reason have led to a modification of the original position.
The idea that the Holy Spirit guides the church is an expression of this trust,
and no doubt Hegel's optimist philosophy of history is a legitimate unfolding
1 known to f d t e minds, we have the natural desire to spread truth when we
think we have discovered i t And in Ibs process we may develop personal
bonds with each other that go far beyond seeing each other only as tools for
the growth of our individual knowledge (which is a form of reciprocal in-

37 O n the Bible see my article "Philosophy and the Interpretation of the Bible," in:Internu-
I 39 Compare Tocqueville's reflections on the "religious terror" caused in him by the tdumph
I
tiotlub Zeitschriifir Phibsophie 8 (1 999), 181-21 0. 1 of democracy that he cannot help interpreting otherwise than as an expression of the divine w d
An impressive overview of the histo~yof Christiaiq can be found in Hans Kvng, Dus (Alexis de Tocqueville, De h &mocrutie en R-ne'rigue I , Paris 1981, 61).
Chrhentum. Weren nnd Ge~chichte,Munchen/Zurich 1994. 40 See the rnapficent reconsmction by Jonathan Israel, RadcuLEnh~btenment,Oxford 2001, and
Enlightenment Contested,Oxford 2006.
The Idea o f a Rationahtic PhiIosophy ofReligon and Its Challenges 177

strumental~ation).~~ What T have said applies to all truths - even science is


necessarily an intersubjective process. But it holds particularly for those basic
truths on which a correct understandmg of one's own place arid task in the
I fa&ar with the tradition, contribute to the further development of doctrine,
justifies the limitation of democratic structures in the inner constitution of rea-
sonable churches (as in, by the way, academic institutions). If one acknowledges
world depends, i.e., for religious truths. They must enjoy a stron,ger stability that the modern constitutional state represents a complex balance between the
than scientific opinions, the essence of which is to be challenged periodtcally. 1
two logically independent, but not incompatible, principles of liberalism and
Thus it is of utmost importance that there be a respected institution that ! democracy, one can even argue that only the presence of non-democratic or-
represents a longstanding consensus on basic metaphysical and moral issues 1 ganizational principles in non-political institutions maintains a dtversity vital
and that renders people f a d a r with the arguments in their favor. In the reli- for a liberal society.43
gious cult, it must build up emotional support in favor of t h s consensus and The desire for dtversity may lead one to value positively the fact that there is
forge a religious community. It is not at all an exaggeration to say that such a pluraLity of churches. It is much better that every religious tradttion develop
an institution has a particularly high value and is therefore especially willed by independently towards a greater standard of theoretical and practical rationality
God. Since already a child k e l y has metaphysical needs, and certainly has than achieve institutional unity without sound moral principles. On the other
moral needs, this institution has the right and the duty to communicate its hand, the argument against the splitting of a church can easily be used in favor
convictions to children, even if they cannot yet be based on arguments, as of the necessity to overcome religious divisions. The more humankmd grows
long as the end of the education process is that the adults may finally study together, the more indispensable it becomes to add a common value system to
the arguments and decide autonomously with regard to their validity. This in- a common market. Only the two together will allow the formation of effec-
cludes their right to leave their church and choose another if they find that it tive global political structures. The most promising way to move in that direc-
I
expresses more adequately the demands of reason. The more a church is able tion is by promoting dialogue between religions. At the end of this process,
i
to integrate the element of critical and intelligent reflection into its own insti- I there may be achieved one religion - as would befit one humankmd created
tutional framework, the greater - ceterirpan'bus - its chance to endure under by one God.
conditions of modernity.
Churches are, as we have seen, socially indispensable institutions, and the jI
right and duty to contribute to the further development of its doctrine must i

1
be exerted in such a way that it does not endanger the moral stabhty of the
institution and of society at large. For one of the functions of religion is the The greatest challenge that Christianity presents to reason or reason to Chris-
achievement and maintenance of moral consensus. It runs against this pur- tianity is not the doctrine of the Trinity. For trinitarian ideas are already found
pose if every person who has a new idea founds her own church. As in a state in pagan Neo-Platonism, and Hegel's peculiar version of Trinitarian thought
people must submit to the final judgment of the supreme court, even if they I shows that a more complex concept of reason that takes the failure of con-
think it a bad decision, so a certain self-disciplme is essential to the mainte- cept empiricism seriously is thoroughly compatible with the idea that our ba-
nance of the unity of the church. A radtcal rationalist such as Fichte recog- sic categories, and thus the basic structures of reality, are triadic. Even if
nizes that a scholar in theology must have the right to publish his critical tritheism must be avoided by all means, one of the most fascinating traits of
opinions, but that he does not have the right to teach them on the pulpit: "Es the doctrine of the Trinity is that it aims at a compromise between subjectiv-
ist ganz in der Ordnung, ihm zu verbieten, sie auf die Kanzel zu bringen, und ity and intersubjectivity as basic principles of reality - a compromise whose
es ist von Am selbst, wenn er nur gehorig aufgeklart ist, gewissenlos, dies zu phdosophical articulation is truly difficult, but one of the worthiest tasks of
" ~ ~necessity of maintaining a certain stability as well as the desire to
t h ~ n . The reason. In general, the seeming paradoxes of Christianity have provoked in-
have only persons of high intelligence, integrity, and who are sufficiently tellectual efforts unmatched in the Islamic and Jewish tradition. And it might
even be that the structures of the division of power built up in modern West-
41 See on this issue Vittorio HGsle, Die Knse der Gegenwart und die Verontwortung der Phifo~o-
phie, Miinchen 31997,192ff. 1
42 D m mem der Sittenfehte nach den Principien cler Wi~senschujlsfehre§ 18 V, in: Johann Gott-
fried Fichte, Werke IV,ed. by Immanuel Hermann Fichte, Berlin 1971,252. 43 See my reflections in Morals andPo(itic~.,Notre Dame 2004,721.
The Idea o f a Rationalistic Phihoph_y ofRel&ion and Its Challenges 179

ern states, and which avoid granting sovereignty to one single state organ, are
which he probably, and rightly, did not regard as relevant for his mission). Of
indirectly influenced by the trinitarian model.
course, one may say that for dogmatic reasons we must ascribe to bun all
Not only the doctrine of the immanent, but also that of the economic
knowledge. But then there is the problem of justifying such a claim. The his-
trinity, is rationally accessible: God must manifest himself in human history
torical facts clearly do not provide such a justification; nor does there seem to
and overcome the alienation inherent in the status of natural man. The func-
be, despite remarkable attempts by the theological tradition, a cogent meta-
tion of the church and its continuous development in this process has already
physics! argument for the existence of a God-man. (If there were, then the
been discussed; and there is no difficulty in seeing herein a manifestation of
question would still remain how we can know that the God-man is Jesus.)
the Holy Spirit. The thorny issue is the correct interpretation of the nature of
A reasonable reduction of the christological claim would be to say that Jesus'
Jesus Christ. That he belongs to the series of mediators between God and
moral doctrine is the best possible and that he himself was morally perfect,
man is obvious. But the prophets of the Old Testaments count among them
and to add that, since the moral law is the core of God, the teaching and liv-
as well, and from Justin onwards Christianity has recowzed traces of the di-
ing of it may justify the docaine of a (weak) identity of Jesus with God. This
vine even beyond its own tradition, e.g., in the Greek world. In the Enlight-
is certainly a reasonable approach, but there is no way of getting beyond mere
enment, the comparison of Socrates and Jesus became a commonplace. Few
probability with respect to Jesus' moral perfection (it is easier to come to a posi-
Christian theologians today would deny that even the founders of other reli-
tive answer with regard to later Saints, where the documentation is much am-
gions were inspired by God. What, then, is unique about Christ?
pler and historically more reliable).
There are at least three difficulties with orthodox christology, as it is for-
More important is the fact that the normativity of a certain behavior can-
mulated in the Ecumenical councils (the study of whose history is not always
not follow from the fact that Jesus has instantiated it.45 The relation is in-
morally edifying). The fist objection against the uniqueness of Christ is that
verted: Jesus is Pely to have instantiated it because it is morally perfect. This
its defenders often tend to regard those who do not share their interpretation
not only follows from our criticism of voluntarism; it is also a result of the
of Christ as excluded from the community with God. This is morally unpalat-
epistemological superiority of a priori claims, which we fiid in ethics, over a
able, and even the attempt to have Buddhists saved by declaring them
posteriori claims, whch pertain to hstorical research. As already the 18th cen-
anonymous Christians is often perceived as condescending (even if in his
tury understood: The validity of ethics must never depend on hstorical re-
time I h r l Rahner's theory was strategically smart in order to change the tradi-
search. But as long as narrative theology does not deny this point, it is based
tional understandmg of Ectra ecclesiam nulh salus) Second, there is the problem
on a valuable insight. In order to train humans in moral behavior, stories are
of consistency. It is cot at all clear whether the concept of a person who is
exceedingly important. One of the reasons why the Bible is such an extraor-
both true man and true God makes sense logically. Is such a person both
dinary book is that it offers many sublime stories about human experiences of
omniscient and non-omniscient? If he is simply omniscient, as the tradition
the divine; and the historically trained reader of the Bible may extract particu-
assumes, can he still be regarded as a real man? If one defends the doctrine of
lar pleasure from the fact that he is able to recognize a complex story at the
A e n 0 . k ~and
~ ~ denies Christ's omniscience (as he does himself Matthew 24:36
metalevel, i.e., regarding the development of the concept of the divine that
and as the disappointment of the imminent expectation suggests), then the
unfolds in the various human authors of this Book of Books.
problem arises over what common elements guarantee the identity between
In the introductory pages to his recent book on J e s ~ s , "Benedict
~ XVI has
the second person and Jesus of Nazareth.
insisted on the lunits of the historical method - fundamentally, it cannot an-
Perhaps even more intractable is, h d , the problem of the hstorical re-
swer the valuative question and thus the issue of the present appropriation of
construction of Jesus. If we accept the usual historical methods, we come to a
a past figure. This is doubtless a true and profound criticism of historicism.
figure who is both an extraordinary moral innovator and who is deeply
But the desire of appropriation, legitimate though it may be, cannot replace
rooted in the Jewish culture of his time. We hardly come to an omniscient
figure (according to the normal standards of reconstruction, Jesus does not I
even seem to have had a knowledge of contemporary Greek mathematics, 45 This holds a fortiori for later religous reformers. The cult of its founder in Lutheranism
(wisely molded by Calvinism) must either lead to frustrations, when one studies the figure in
more detail, or to absurd imitations (brilliantly caricatured in the XI1 chapter of Thomas
Mann's Doktor Fatlsttls).
44 It is expressed in Paul's Letter to the Philippians 27.
I 46 ]tw I J O I N a p e t b . Votl der Tauji im]orhn his y r Verkkiinmg, Freiburg 2007.
180 Vittotio Hlirle The Idea ofa htionalirtic Philosophy ofRelgzon and Its Challenges 181

the historical work, nor should it influence it in such a way that the experi- There is little doubt that the two major political problems of our time are the
ences of the successors are projected back into the source. History is full of inequalities on international scale and the ecologcal issue. Both are
examples of this very human tendency; and a universalist ethics cannot belittle problems that can hardly be solved by appealing to an ethics of reciprocity.
them in other traditions and condone them in one's own. This said, there is no The quality of the Christian contribution to their solution w d be a decisive
doubt that the vitahty of Christianity depends on the ever renewed attempts of indicator of its enduring vitality and the future that it will have.
imitation and succession of Jesus. The moral law shall not only be grasped
theoretically; it ought to be lived, and models are crucial for this purpose. Jesus
is not only a teacher of how to live; the story of his passion is one of the most
important sources of force in suffering and dying.47 Recognizing the divine in
this story is a far greater moral achievement than seeing it in the triumphs of
a warrior prophet like Muhammad.
Christianity has a central social message, and there is no exaggeration in
claiming that Christianity, from its beginnings to our day, has strongly con-
tributed to the solution of social problems.48 But it is of utmost importance
to see that this message flows from both a metaphysical and ethical basis. The
redistribution mechanisms of the modern welfare society may be compatible
with Christianity; but Christianity cannot be reduced to their support. The
decisive point is that Christian ethics transcends the idea of reciprocity. Who-
ever supports the welfare state only because this is in his long-term interest
does not act out of a specific Christian motive. Nor is the mere transfer of
money to the poor a sufficient compliance with the demands of Christianity.
The decisive point is the personal interest in the other and the willtngness to
be challenged in one's own habits, even if this e n t d s the h u d a t i o n of feel-
ing one's own failure in front of the demands of the moral law.49 Not all
forms of expression of this humiliation are morally or aesthetically attractive,
but the experience of h u d a t i o n as such is indispensable gven the weakness
of human nature.

47 In Goethe's last novel, Wilheh Meisters Wotrcleiohn, there is in the gallery of the Peda-
gogical Province a sharp division between the dzpiction of the Life and that of the death of Je-
sus - "denn zu jenen Priifungen ist jeder, zu diesern sind nur wenige berufen" (Goethes Werke
VIII, ed. by Erich Tmnz, Miinchen 1981, 163). Goethe may be right that a special training is
needed in order to understand and appropriate the passion, but he is wrong in wanting to ex-
clude from its contemplation most people. For even if tremendous suffering may not befall
everybody, every human has the oppormnity to witness it in others.
48 See Adolf Harnack, Dm Wesen des Christenturns, Leipzig 51901, 56-65: "Das Evangelium
und die Armut, oder die soziale Frage."
49 Probably no other modem author has been able to capture thts aspect of Christian ethics
as aesthetically perfectly as Charles Dickens. See my essay "The Lost Prodigal Son's Corporal
Works of Mercy and the Bridegroom's Wedding. The Religious Subtext of Charles Dickens'
Greot Expecrotions," appears in: AngLo 126 (2008).

You might also like