You are on page 1of 13

The Idea of Abstraction in German Theories of the Ornament from Kant to Kandinsky

Author(s): David Morgan


Source: The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 50, No. 3 (Summer, 1992), pp. 231-
242
Published by: Wiley on behalf of The American Society for Aesthetics
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/431231 .
Accessed: 20/05/2014 14:52

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Wiley and The American Society for Aesthetics are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend
access to The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 91.105.21.1 on Tue, 20 May 2014 14:52:33 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
DAVID MORGAN

The Idea of Abstractionin GermanTheoriesof the


Ornamentfrom Kantto Kandinsky

In 1905 the art critic ArthurRoessler wrote that Writingtheir majorworkson aestheticsbetween
he had seen a numberof drawingsby the Neu- 1785 and 1793, these two Prussianscholarseach
Dachau painter Adolf Hoelzel in which the defined beauty as free of any purpose beyond
"spiritual and mental movements of the artist itself.
fromdifferentperiodsof his life were arrested."' Moritz believed that the beautiful object sig-
These drawings, Roessler continued, "formthe nified nothing beyond itself. "The truly beau-
abstractornament;abstractin the sense of non- tiful consists of the object which signifies only
objective."2Roessler'scommentsprovidea help- itself, designatesitself, encloses itself, is a whole
ful clue in pointing to ornament as a primary complete in itself."4 For Moritz, beauty was
avenue by which 'abstraction' became under- characterized by the fusion of meaning and
stood as a non-representationalimage or pic- form. "The form of a vase," he claimed, "gen-
torial procedure. By the end of the nineteenth erates itself from the naturalidea of holding."5
century, discussion of the ornamentalor deco- Idea and visual structureare seamlessly joined.
rative introduced into critical discourse about Moritz annexed this idealist view to a no less
paintingthe idea that the visual arts could oper- idealist preference for delineation or contour,
ate in a fully artistic way without employing which, like Kant, he identifiedas the essence of
representationaltechniques. Since the late eigh- representation.Contourservedto isolate or sep-
teenthcentury,however,considerationsof orna- arate, to set out form. Accordingto Moritz, the
ment have made importantcontributionsto the more a thing isolated itself within its own con-
discussion of the nature of representationand tour and contained within itself its center of
beauty. I will show how the modern notion of gravity, "the less accidental, the less subordi-
abstractionemergedfrom a theoreticaldiscourse nate to some other and mixed with it" was the
on ornamentthat focused on three of the most form.6 In the early 1790s, Moritz applied this
basic themes in nineteenth-centuryGermanart principleto ornamentand broke down the tradi-
theory: form, style, and empathy.I offer neither tional distinctionbetweenthe decorativeand the
an exhaustive treatmentof the theory of orna- fine arts. Ornament,we read, is best explained
ment nor a representativesurvey of its history, on the principleof isolation.
but a selective investigation which attempts to
understandcertain aspects of the role ornament Thebeautyof theframeandthebeautyof thepicture
playedin theoreticalreflections on art.3 proceedfromoneandthesameprinciple.Thepicture
presents[darstellen]
somethingcompletein itself;the
I. THEORIES OF FORM, frameenclosesonce againthatwhichis completein
STYLE, AND ORNAMENT itself.7

The idea thatcertain forms are inherentlypleas- The frame, Moritz wrote in his Vorbegriffezu
ant, withoutreferenceto anythingelse, is hardly einer Theorie der Ornamente, "expands exter-
a new one. But among the earliest modernwrit- nally in order that we may as it were gradually
ers to highlight this capacity of ornamentation peer into the inner sanctum which glimmers
were Karl Philipp Moritz and Immanuel Kant. throughthis enclosure."8This imageforeshadows
The Journalof Aesthetics and Art Criticism 50:3 Summer 1992

This content downloaded from 91.105.21.1 on Tue, 20 May 2014 14:52:33 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
232 The Journalof Aesthetics and Art Criticism

Philipp Otto Runge's use of the ornamented The attentiongiven by Moritzand Kantto the
framein his Tageszeitenseries of engravingsand self-containedsignificance of form in ornament
paintingsa decade later. As the revelatorychar- providedthe inspirationfor subsequentformalist
acterof his languagesuggests, Moritzheld orna- aesthetics which disregarded imitation as the
ment in high esteem, suggesting that it not only basis of art. Johann Friedrich Herbart, a later
possessed the ability to refine taste and arouse philosopherin Kdnigsberg,made Kant'sidea of
the soul, but constituteda "noble impulseof the a pure judgment of taste the exclusive basis of
soul" and an impulse which was as beneficial as aestheticexperience. Herbartarguedthatbeauty
the impulseto science or "high art."9 resided not in a particularcolor, formor tone, as
Accordingly,Moritz subsumedornamentand Kanthad suggested, but in its relationas a men-
fine art under the single category of the "im- tal representation (Vorstellung) with another
pulse toward beauty." To the objection that color, formor tone. 14 A single element is neutral
ornamentmay not possess a self-containedpur- and only becomes aestheticallysignificantwhen
pose inasmuchas it serves the purpose of deco- joined with another element. Herbart did not
rating anotherobject, Moritz would reply that deny the significance of subject matter or the
the ornamentand the 'ornamented'object serve pertinenceof a feeling with which one responds
a single purpose. The frame, for instance, is but to a work of art, but insisted that such meaning
an extension of the picture, yet anothermeans of and feeling were not the beautiful, and that the
self-isolation. Furthermore,Moritz was able to essence of aestheticjudgmentlay in one's expe-
overcome the traditionaldistinction of fine and rience of the formalrelations.
appliedart becausehe replacedthe idea of imita-
tion as the end of art with thatof the "pleasure" Whatdid the old mastersmean to express who devel-
derived from forgetting oneself in contempla- oped the possible forms of the fugue, or those still
tion of a complete aesthetic whole.'0 This al- older whose industry differentiatedthe possible or-
lowed him to fuse the aim of image and orna- ders of the column? They desired to express nothing.
ment into a single aesthetic moment of self-loss Their thoughts did not travel beyond their arts but
or self-forgetting that foreshadowed a central penetrateddeeply into theiressence. 15
featureof Schopenhauer'sthought.
The linearisolationof formin ornamentwhich Herbartdifferentiatedthe inherenteffect of aes-
Moritz prized as a fully independentaesthetic thetic relations on the viewer from what he
moment, and which he understoodto possess an called "apperception."16 By this he meantwhat-
"innerpurposiveness"[innereZweckmassigkeit], ever the viewer brings to the perception of a
anticipatedKant'sKritikder Urteilskraft(1790)."l work of art that is not found within its formal
Kant argued here that the only pure judgment effect. For instances of aesthetic pleasure with-
of taste was that which fornally exhibits "free out apperception,Herbartlooked principallyto
beauty"- 'free' because the form is independent music, architecture, and poetry-all of which
not only of any interestwe might have for it, but possess a fundamentally non-representational
also of any definite concept which might deter- dimension in their formal structure.What mat-
mine what the thing ought to be.'2 Kant men- tered in aestheticjudgment was not the subject,
tionedpure, unmixedcolors, flowers, sea shells, butthe pleasurecreatedby the mentalconfigura-
exotic birds, linearornaments'a la grecque, and tion of elementsor formspresentedto the viewer
music without words as instances of such free by the work of art. Herbartscorned the use of
beauty, "beauties in themselves." Judgmentof catalogues in the paintinggallery or librettosat
such objectsproceedssolely on the basis of their the opera and praisedHadyn'smusic for the fact
form, for they "meannothingin themselves;they that it requiredno text: "for his music is music
represent nothing-no object under a definite and to be beautiful need mean nothing."'7 And
concept."'3 Subjects such as the human figure, because the work of art carries its significance
on the otherhand,of which we possess a definite within itself, so to speak, and because its asso-
concept, exhibitKantian"dependentbeauty"be- ciation with anything beyond itself should not
cause theirperfectiondependsnot on theirrepre- condition the judgment of taste, "imitationcan
sentationalone, but on how well they fulfill the neverbe set up as a principleof aesthetic."18
purposeprescribedfor themby the concept. Herbart'sformalismreceived a more system-

This content downloaded from 91.105.21.1 on Tue, 20 May 2014 14:52:33 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Morgan Abstractionand German Theories of the Ornament 233

atic presentationby Robert Zimmermann,pro- cance of the light andcolor was furtherextended
fessor of philosophy in Vienna, who sought to where the light and color were boundto objects,
outline the "pure science of form" in his major thoughinanimateones such as in landscape.23It
work on aesthetics of 1865.19 Zimmermann was also Vischer's belief that beauty could not
stressed emphatically that it was only the par- be exhaustedby regulargeometricalforms such
ticular form of the relation between elements as the square,circle, cube or sphere. "The beau-
which pleased or displeased and that everything tiful is [an] essentially living, autonomousindi-
outside of this relation such as subject matter vidual; what lives never grows into regularity,
and the materialof the art work were "aesthet- life brings unevennesswith it."24 And color, he
ically indifferent."20Like Herbart, Zimmer- insisted, was only the means, never the end of
mann contended that, as the science of form, painting. Color belonged to the object, was the
aesthetics had its singularpurpose in determin- wherewithalfor depictingform.25
ing the kinds of formal relations which please Accordingto Vischer, by fixing on the harmo-
and displease.21 nious combinationof colors and the connections
of lines independent of depicted objects, for-
II. THE LIMITS OF ORNAMENT malism commits itself to a view which Vischer
regardedas self-evidentlywrong: "Arabesques,
Reactionto the formalistaesthetic was severe in linearand colored ornaments[wouldhave to be]
Germany, not only for the indifference it ex- explained as really and truly beautiful and the
pressed toward the subject's significance for painter of decoration [would be] a purer artist
beauty and the marginalizationof what Herbart than the painter of history."26Vischer did not
called 'apperception,'but also for the threatfor- seek to deny thatline andcolor could producean
malism posed toward underminingthe idealist effect rightly called beautiful, but allowed them
enterprise of aesthetics as the explanation of to do so only within the frameworkof empathy.
art's metaphysicalsignificance. This reactionis He looked to landscapepainting (whose beauty
importantfor this study because it was the for- he called "musical") as the genre in which "ab-
malism of Herbart and Zimmermann which stract phenomena" or formal artistic elements
provokedmid-centuryaestheticiansin Germany were infused with a spiritual mood or disposi-
to scrutinize the capacity of line and color for tion.27In orderto accountfor those forms which
expression independentof representation.But, representnothing, yet which Vischer felt exhib-
for reasons that I will examine, this scrutiny ited beauty, he developed a special theory of
workedagainst claims for the aesthetic signifi- symbol which he defined as that process in
cance of ornament. For, although such promi- which, "following an inner necessity of the
nent critics of the formalist view as Friedrich natureof our soul, we attributea mentaldisposi-
Theodor Vischer and Gustav Fechner turned tion to the abstractforms of appearance[color,
theirattentionto the non-representationalpower tone, line, surface] so that our own inner life
of line and color, they were not prepared to appearsto meet us in them."28 Vischercould not
consider the expressive potential of formal ele- allow that "abstractforms" could function aes-
ments as the basis for an aesthetic that might thetically without being rooted in the spiritual
supplant representationin art. If the positive life of feeling. By 'abstract'he meant anything
treatmentof ornamentby Kant and Moritz en- disconnected from concrete objects and there-
couraged a formalist aesthetic in Herbart and fore devoid of life.29 This, he felt, was how the
Zimmermann,Vischer and Fechner sought to formalistview wished to characterizebeauty: a
check this developmentby diminishingthe aes- mental configuration of formal elements unre-
thetic statusof ornament. lated to the material substrateof the physical
FriedrichTheodorVischer acknowledgedthe world. Accordingly, Vischer praised two large
expressive power of color which was "abstract, decorativepaintingsby the Austrianartist Hans
without object," and pointed to the "stained Makartin which "color is not abstractlyunder-
glass of Gothic churches where clearly without stood, for it is magnificentlykeyed to the object,
plastic depictionthe transparentglow of harmo- that is, to the expression of the fullness of life,
nious color works impressively on the soul."22 of complete enjoyment."30Makart's allegori-
Yet, Vischer continued, the symbolic signifi- cal, neo-rococo style of paintingin these works

This content downloaded from 91.105.21.1 on Tue, 20 May 2014 14:52:33 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
234 The Journalof Aesthetics and Art Criticism

dramatizedfor Vischer how firmly the deco- ture is replaced in architecture,ornament, and
rativeeffects of formandcolor ought to be fixed the decorative arts by such abstractdevices as
withinthe frameworkof representational,albeit symmetry, the golden section, regularizedpat-
fanciful, image-making. terns, the wavy line, the volute, and by the
Gustav Fechner also acknowledged the ex- brilliance, purity,and saturationof color-all of
pressive effect of the relationsof non-represen- which lack, according to Fechner, the associa-
tationalformandcolor, but assertedthatsuch an tive ability to evoke ideas, which is the principal
effect in the visual arts, as in music, was not of determinantof beautyin the 'higher' arts.
the superioraesthetic variety "which deserves
the name beautifuilin the narrow and higher III. EMPATHY
sense."'Fechner reasonedso because such for-
mal relations lacked "meaning" or "sense."9 At the close of the century, several important
"Objectsof little or incidentalaesthetic impor- writers abandoned the subordinationof orna-
tance, such as a carpet [or] a wall can indeed ment to naturalisticart and clearedthe way for a
achieve a direct pleasantnessthrough relations very constructiveinterpretationof ornamentand
of color and form in their surfaces, angles, and abstractform. Alois Riegl is the most notewor-
patterns;yet proveeven therebythatthey cannot thy instance of an art historianwho revised the
be elevated to a higher, independentaesthetic study of ornamentin his first majorwork, Stil-
importance,[prove]how negligible and low the fragen (1893). But the writer who was to build
aesthetic achievement of these relations is."32 on and transformthe discourse on form, style,
As pleasingas the symmetryof the kaleidoscope empathy, and abstraction most significantly,
is, it has no place, Fechner contended, in the through his public lectures and many publica-
landscapeor historypaintingbecause it does not tions, was the psychologist and aesthetician,
suit the meaning (Bedeutung) of the depicted TheodorLipps. Vischer, as we have seen, origi-
objects. The color of a painting is determined nally introduceda theory of empathyin orderto
more by the demands of meaning than by "the accountfor the aestheticsignificance of abstract
rules of color harmony."33 Moreover, all rela- forms, and sought thereby to underscore the
tions amongthe formalelements of an image are distinctionbetweenfigurativeand abstractimag-
determinedby the characteristicsof the subject ery. Lipps, however,magnifiedthis special case
matter,andare beautifulinsofaras they conform of empathy into the centerpiece of his aesthetic
to the "expression of higher and pertinent and championedthe notionof apperceptionden-
ideas."34 igratedby the formalists.
But Fechner did not attempt to ignore the In a study on the aesthetics of space, Lipps
intrinsicexpressivenessof formalrelations. For arguedthat what we apprehendin a spatialform
instance, he was able to observe that a painting, is a sympatheticfeeling mediatedby the visual
characteristicsof the form such as line and sur-
alreadyfrom a distance, even before we recognize its face.37 "Not the column," Lipps claimed, "but
content or whenever we abstract from the same, the spatialformationwhich depicts itself to us in
makes an impression as enjoyable as the other. In the column, makes itself erect."38Accordingto
order to facilitate this abstraction and to judge a Lipps, the means of representationare loosened
picture no less surely in regardto its mere effect of and detachedfrom theirconcreteconnectionsto
colors, manygive the rule to view it upside down.35 reality. There are, he asserted, many levels of
detachment.
Furthermore,Fechner was prepared to allow
that the direct pleasure of formal relations in- We designate these levels as levels of stylization. To
creased in the visual arts as one "descends" stylize means to make formsof realitydetachedfrom
(herabgehen) from sculpture and painting to their concrete contexts in reality aesthetically intel-
architecture,and then to the "technicalarts and ligible. Wedo this when we successively disregardthe
ornament," since the factor of association, characteristicswhich are peculiar to [the forms in
Fechner'scherished mechanismof "meaning," theirconcrete reality] ... especially the manykindsof
was lost to the 'direct' effect of line and color.36 accidents which necessarily underlie [the forms]....
Attentionto subjectmatterin paintingandsculp- Whatremainsis a moreor less generalversionof their

This content downloaded from 91.105.21.1 on Tue, 20 May 2014 14:52:33 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Morgan Abstractionand German Theories of the Ornament 235

existence, a more or less general law of shaping or innerlife or power. This power or striving Lipps
fonnation, or a law of their becoming. To stylize, we attributedto the viewer: "[it] is my striving, but
might therefore also say, means to release from the I experience it immediatelynot as originatingin
concrete forms of reality their more or less generally me, but in the color and its peculiar quality."46
conceived law of shaping or formationand to visu- Eachcolorpossessesits own "character of mood"
alize [the law] for itself.... (Stimmungscharakter),but Lipps refused to
All types of geometrical forms can be obtained enumeratethem since each is determinedby the
throughthis successive stylization. Inversely, we are individualviewer. Each person 'feels' the Stim-
free to say that each geometrical form-the simple munginto a color.47
straight line not excluded-if not according to its By understandingstyle as a "distancingfrom
historical origin, then according to its aesthetic es- the simple reproductionof thatwhich is found in
sence,is stylizednature.39 nature," and by regardingempathy as the indi-
vidual viewer'smeans of determiningthe beauty
In seeking to understandthe dynamics of per- of even non-representationalelements such as
ception and the nature of aesthetic experience, line and color, Lipps facilitatedthe appreciation
Lippsignoredthe traditionaldistinctionbetween of ornamentas a self-sufficient aestheticform.48
subjectmatterand abstractformby eliding them Yet he was not the first to do so. In 1886 Hein-
on a single continuum of degrees of "stylized richWdlfflin had applieda theory of empathyto
nature."This implied thatgeometricalform and architecturein his doctoral dissertation.49En-
naturalisticform obeyed the same law, a law couragedby his teacherat Basel, JohannesVol-
which was bared and made visually intelligible kelt, Wdlfflin had sought to account for the
in the abstractformof lines and figures. expression of a spiritual content or mood in
This implication was further supported by purely architectonicforms. Wdlfflin arguedthat
Lipps when, in his major work on aesthetics corporeal forms are significant to us because
(1903), he investigated the experience of "ab- "we recognize in them the expression of a feel-
stract forms" such as straight and wavy lines ing soul. Instinctivelywe animateeach thing."50
which appear "filled with life."40 They appear This animation is an impulse so primordialin
so, Lipps reasoned, because we feel life into humanity,Wdlfflin believed, that were it to per-
them. This theory of empathy, for which Lipps ish, it would mean the very death of art. He
is most well known, assumedthat the ego expe- explainedthis animationof the world outside of
riences itself in the object by imaginativelypro- us as a subordinationof all appearancesto the
jecting itself there. Perception (Wahrnehmung) image of our own bodies. "Our bodily organi-
itself shows us only mere existence. On the other zation is the form under which we apprehend
hand, empathy is the imaginativeanimationof everything corporeal."951 And he proceeded to
sense perceptions,41the conferralof unity, free- attempt to show that the elements of architec-
dom, and life throughwhat Lipps called 'apper- ture, indeed, the very laws of aesthetics, were
ception.'42In a reversalof Herbart'spsychology nothingotherthanthe conditionsunderwhich an
of aesthetics, Lipps made empathy the very organic, corporealpleasuremay exist.
basis for beauty,and applied it as a fundamental
psychic operationto the perceptionof individual IV. JUGENDSTIL
lines, shapes, and colors as well as to recogniz-
able representationsof objects. The wavy line is We have tracedan ongoing theoreticaldiscourse
beautiful, we read, "becauseits progression, its that did not reflect the aims of artistic practice
quickerand slower self-bending, the tension and until aroundthe turn of the century. Then, sev-
release lying therein, is felt by me as a free eral writers, artists, and architects associated
activity and an exuberant feeling of my own with Jugendstilarchitectureand design applied
contemplatingego sunkeninto the wavy line."43 discussions of form, style, empathy, and ab-
By virtue of empatheticprojection, every geo- stractionto the ornament.In 1901,the critic Karl
metrical form possesses a determinatecharac- Scheffler wrote enthusiasticallythat the human
ter.44Color is also "lively in itself" and "dipped instinct for symmetry exhibited in ornamentis
in mood," and only thereby does it constitute a the feeling of harmony pulsating through the
"properaesthetic object."45 This gives color an architectureof the humanbody.52

This content downloaded from 91.105.21.1 on Tue, 20 May 2014 14:52:33 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
236 The Journalof Aesthetics and Art Criticism

If we ask a good artisthow he designs ornamentsor if andrecallnothing,[and]excite oursoul as deeply


we watch him: he experiences them! Immersed in as ever music was able [to do] with tones."59
himself, he sits before the page and deliberates over Endell insistedthat "one mustlearnto see andto
each line with compensatingmovementsas one listen- steep oneself in forms."60In orderto appreciate
ing to his instinct. He suggests to his fantasy the "formalbeauty,"he claimed it was necessary to
feeling of supporting or carrying-and instantly he learn to see in an "isolated" fashion. Endell
drawsthe line which releaseshis feeling; he exercises describeda way of seeing which informedSchef-
with his anns as if dancing on a wire-and immedi- fler's passage quotedabove:
ately he has found the symmetricalcomplementof a
curve. This is the way that good and original orna- Wemustdirectourview to details,to the fonn of a
mentscome into being.53 treeroot,to thearrangementof a leafona stem,to the
structureof treebark,to the lines whichthickfoam
Ornamentaldesign is a directexpressionof feel- fonnson theseashore.Normaywe glanceoverfonns
ing and originates in the dynamics of human withoutattention,but must follow them with our
anatomy. Scheffler believed that because the eyes-every bend, every crook, every extension,
human body and everything organic share the everyjuncture,in short,we mustsharein theexperi-
same structurallaws of formation, "our orga- ence of everychangein fonn. Forwe see precisely
nism is a sort of instrumentwhose stringsare set only one pointin ourvisualfield andonly whatwe
in sympatheticvibration." This meant, he fur- haveseen clearlycan becomeeffectivefor ourfeel-
therconjectured,thatornaments-the direct ex- ing.Butif we see inthisway,therewillemergebefore
pressions of this sympathy-are to be found us a new, previouslyunknownworldof immense
everywhere: "A drop of ink squirted in a glass riches. A thousandmoods are wakenedin us ...
of water, cigar smoke in motionless air, the Natureappearsto live andwe graspnow thatthere
wave, the plant, a waving flag, the photograph reallyaresadtrees,evilandmaliciousboughs,chaste
of glacial drift, bone formations, and muscle grasses,andfearsome,horribleflowers.6'
fibers-in short, ornamentsare everywhere!"54
In an essay entitled "Line," published in the But Endell proceededto point out that these are
following year,the architectand designerHenry only appearances, and that we do not actually
van de Velde, echoed Scheffler's idea of direct "animate" (beseelen) a natural phenomenon.
expression by proclaimingthat "only few crea- Feelings are only aroused in us by objects. Nor
tions standin so direct, so close a relationshipto is it a matterof association since we may recall
their creator as line. "55 Van de Velde charac- any numberof meaningsor feelings in the pres-
terized lines as "transcribedgestures-public ence of an object. Instead,Endell suggestedthat
psychic expressions."56 Both Scheffler and Van there is a parallelism between essence and ap-
de Velde evince a significant debt to contempo- pearance, inner and outer-that we attributethe
rary theories of empathyand to the traditionof feeling aroused in us to the "innerbeing of the
physiognomyin formulatinga model of expres- object." He noted that we also listen to music
sion in which an inner force or content is visu- and are moved without knowing why. In the
alized in externalform. second installment of the article, Endell ob-
The young Munich architect, August Endell, served how lines of various size and thickness
brought both of these elements together in an producedifferentsensationsin the observerand,
importantessay of 1897, which influenced both on the premise that all feeling is a function of
Schefflerand Vande Velde.57It is in Endell that tempoandtensionrangingfromsmallerto greater
we find intense theoreticalconcerns applied to intensity, suggested that the effects of line and
architecturalpractice in a way that anticipated visual directioncould be tabulated.62
both the art and theory of Wassily Kandinsky.58 Endell'sarticleis fascinatingon severalcounts.
Endelldiscerneda rift betweenpast andpresent: First of all, in stressingthe singularfocus of the
whereas architectureand crafts of the past ex- "visual field," Endell recalls and then redefines
hibited their own historical stylistic features, an earlier attemptto characterizeabstractionin
work of the present constitutes an entirely new termsof a determinatefocus. In 1845, Johannes
period of style, indeed the beginning of an art AndreasRomberg,a prominentHamburgarchi-
whose forms "mean nothing, depict nothing, tect and prolific writer on the arts, included in

This content downloaded from 91.105.21.1 on Tue, 20 May 2014 14:52:33 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Morgan Abstractionand German Theories of the Ornament 237

the first edition of his Conversationslexiconfar pomorphism'with a theory of expression prem-


bildende Kunst an unprecedentedentry entitled ised on physiognomy. The power of form over
"Abstraction."Rombergdefined the termas the soul, he wrote, was "a direct, immediate
influence without any intermediatemember,by
thementalactivityby meansof whichone acceptsin no means the result of an anthropomorphismor
the formationof art worksonly that which corre- humanization[Vermenschlichung]."67 The con-
spondsto the detenninateartisticaim andleavesthe cepts of animationand anthropomorphismwere
restunconsidered. Abstraction inthisaimis therefore employed by such proponents of empathy as
necessaryforeveryartistif he does notwantto miss Volkelt, Wdfflin, and Lipps, and it has been said
his aim throughthe superfluous,excessiveor idle. thatEndell heardLipps lecture at the University
Theartistwhodesiresto achievehis endwouldlearn in Munich.68Endell'sclarificationof how things
to separateall parts,all featureswhichdo notbelong "appear"to exhibit the feelings we experience
essentiallyto theaim, whichhindertheeffect,which suggests a firsthandknowledge of very contem-
detain in an unusefulmanner,which give neither porary debates over the nature of empathy. In
emphasisnor new light, which do not accent the 1898 Paul Stern published a study on the psy-
subject from the side that should interestus. ... for if chological analysis of aesthetic perception en-
wedo notwishto see everysideof thesubjectatonce, titled EinfiihlungundAssociation in der neueren
we will be contentto take notice of that which is Aesthetik.69 In it he criticizedthe use of the term
accented,whichshouldcaptivateourattention.63 "empathy"as metaphoricaland therefore mis-
leading, and argued for association as the psy-
Romberg's use of the term "attention" (Auf- chological basis for aesthetic experience.70By
merksamkeit)introducedcontemporaryphysio- explicitly stating that 'animation' is limited to
logical discourse into a discussion which had appearances (a fact which seems sufficiently
formerly depended more on metaphysics and obvious), Endell may have been attemptingto
epistemology. In contrastto the traditionalphil- avoid the metaphysicalexcesses for which Stern
osophicaldistinctionbetween"essence"and "ac- criticized such proponentsof empathy as Vis-
cident," "attention"was a psychological opera- cher and Volkelt, who had linked empathy to
tion studied in nineteenth-centuryphysiology. pantheism.71
In the most importantcontemporarystudy, the The first years of the twentieth century saw
professor of anatomy and physiology Johannes the critique of empathy intensified and the rec-
Mullerdescribedattentionas the effort of taking ognition of ornamentfirst rise and then decline.
cognizanceof "only one object at a time. "64The A few years after Endell's essay appeared, Ar-
mind, Muller stated, is unable to direct "an thur Roessler invoked physiognomy as an anal-
equally accurateattentionto every part" of the ogy to the expressive power of line, perhaps
object it surveys. "If we endeavouredto direct as an alternative to the anthropomorphismof
our attentionto the whole field of vision at the empathy:
same time, we should see nothing distinctly."65
In his discussion of the "visual field," Endell As mentalprocessesexpressthemselvesin certain
narrowed the focus of Romberg's concept of bodilygestures,artisticsensationscanalso be made
attentionin orderthe more completely to isolate visibleas innermovement by meansof line.Climbing
or abstract detailed structures in nature.66He andfalling,stiff andpliant,continuousandbroken,
encouraged the viewer to learn to restrict his wide-reaching as wellas narrowly-restricted
linesare
visual field to specific motifs which could evoke able in the same manneras brightor dim colors ... to
feelings withoutreferenceto or association with awakenin us the basic mood of their creator....
other objects or dimensions of experience. The Formsarenotonlyimportant as aestheticmeans,they
pursuitof abstractingcontours from nature led are in factsignificantas the symboliccoverings,the
Endell to make these forms the sole basis of sensuouslyperceptibleexpressionsof movementsof
architectureand design, as his facade for the the mind or soul.72
HofatelierElvira in Munichdemonstrates.
Endell's discussion is also noteworthyfor the Roessler could thus appreciateAdolf Hoelzel's
way in which he replacedcontemporarynotions completely abstractornamentaldrawings- "ab-
of empathydescribed as 'animation'or 'anthro- stractin the sense of non-objective,"as he said-

This content downloaded from 91.105.21.1 on Tue, 20 May 2014 14:52:33 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
238 The Journalof Aesthetics and Art Criticism

as works in which "the spiritual and mental posed, opposite poles of a psychology of style
movements of the artist ... were arrested." With which even found expression in a bipolar divi-
this non-representationalview of abstractionin sion of Europeinto northand south. Abstraction
mind, Roessler believed that the "new modern was the characteristicKunstwollenof northern
movementin art" was not a questionof stylized Europe. Empathy,on the other hand, appliedto
forms, but, "as Scheffler says, pure form, line, the naturalisticart of classicism and the Italian
ornament."7 In fact, Roessler insisted that the Renaissance. Yet scholarly discussions of Wor-
only genuine ornamentwas the "abstract"one. ringer'sthesis rarelypoint out thathis use of the
By abstracthe meantthe ornamentwhich "organ- term 'abstract' by no means intended exclu-
ically creates its form from matterin essential sively 'non-representational'form. Abstraction
lawfulness."74The naturalphenomenon "styl- meant for Worringerany linear treatment of
ized into an ornament" will never be capable, form, representationalor otherwise, whose geo-
Roesslercontended,of creating "the impression metrical, inorganiccharacterrepudiatesany as-
of an organicallyproducedthing, of a necessity sociationwith our vital sensationsas organically
which reposes in itself."75Instead, the stylized designed beings. Abstractform constitutedany
ornament will always remind us of the thing alienationfromthe body anda correlativeyearn-
from which it has borrowed its form. Such an ing for the transcendent.Although he is often
ornamentwill neverescape the status of "deco- regardedas some sort of ideologue for German
ration." With this assertion Roessler ruptured Expressionistexperiments in abstractpainting,
any idea of a continuum between naturalistic Worringer'snotion of abstractionis not consis-
depiction and abstract style, thereby placing tent with what Wassily Kandinsky envisioned
abstractionoutside the orbit of representation. for painting.76
Roessler held that the necessary antecedentfor Kandinsky, who had been in Munich since
non-representationalart was a theory of artistic 1896 as an art studentand artist, and was there-
expression which allowed form to emerge "or- fore no doubt familiarwith much of the critical
ganically," that is, as a direct expression of discourse on abstraction, eventually went be-
feeling, as an external correspondence to an yond Worringer'sdefinitionof abstraction.Kan-
inner sensation. Any reference to the world of dinsky showed no interestcirca 1912 in restrict-
objects-whether through imitation, stylization ing the artist's pictorial vocabularyto the rigid
or association-would mediate this expression geometrical patterns of ancient ornament, in
by placing it within the realmof representation. which Worringerdiscerned an abstract'urge to
Whatmatteredin the new art was the immediacy form.' By the time he published Ueber das
of the gesture, the directlinkagebetweenfeeling Geistige in der Kunst (1912), Kandinsky had
and form which 'abstract' ornament was priv- come to understandabstractionnot in terms of
ileged to provide. ornamentalgirds or flat, hard-edged'geometric
While empathyhad assisted in the emergence regularity'(to use Worringer'sexpression), but
of a theory of abstract form in the work of as a form of imagemaking aimed at complete
Vischer and Lipps, the tendency to distinguish non-objectivity.He followed Roessler in insist-
empathyandabstractionpersisted.Indeed,shortly ing on a careful distinctionbetweenornamentin
afterthe turnof the century,empathywas starkly the past and the place for a new visual form
opposed to abstractionin what has become ar- which owed nothing to visual appearances.77
guably the most discussed doctoraldissertation Yet, even as late as 1912, Kandinskywas cau-
in German art history. In his Abstraktionund tious in announcing the break with represen-
Einfiihlung(1908), Wilhelm Worringerexam- tation:
ined the linear ornament and architecture of
ancient, middle eastern, and medieval cultures If we beginat onceto breakthebondswhichbindus
andclaimedto find in theman artisticsensibility to nature,anddevoteourselvespurelyto combination
which employed abstract linear forms for the of purecolourand abstractform,we shallproduce
purposeof transcendingnature.Empathycorre- workswhicharemeredecoration,whicharesuitedto
spondedto the aestheticimpulsethatfound itself necktiesorcarpets.Beautyof FormandColouris no
at home in the world and its organic forms. sufficientaimby itself,despitetheassertionsof pure
Abstractionandempathywere diametricallyop- whoareobsessedwith
aesthetesorevenof naturalists,

This content downloaded from 91.105.21.1 on Tue, 20 May 2014 14:52:33 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Morgan Abstractionand German Theories of the Ornament 239

the idea of "beauty."It is because of the elementary altogether clearly characterizedas the inner or
stage reachedby our paintingthatwe are so little able spiritualworkingsof the creativemind.
to grasp the inner harmony of true colour and form
composition.78 V. CONCLUSION

Unlike Vischer and Fechner,Kandinskydid not From the late eighteenth to the early twentieth
considerpure color and form inherentlyincapa- centuriestheoriesof ornamentserveda vital role
ble of serving as the basis for a non-representa- in debate over the scope and natureof represen-
tional art, but did believe that neitherartists nor tation. Ornamentinspired both the creation of
the public were prepared for this revelation, formalistaestheticsand vigorous attacksagainst
although,as the apocalypticrhetoricof his trea- formalism, which in turn introducedthe idea of
tise constantlypromises, the day was not far off. empathy to explain the aesthetic effect of ab-
Were pure composition to be attempted, the stract forms. And ornamentalso served subse-
result would have been a decorativeart unequal quent attempts to distinguish abstraction and
to the revolutionarystatureKandinskyexpected empathy. Finally, with Kandinsky, traditional
of painting. Kandinskyacknowledgedthat pure ornamentwas rejected as an artistic alternative
decorationhad a "life of its own." Yet he main- in the search for a self-containedprinciple. In-
tainedthatornamentin the past was ungoverned fluenced perhapsby Riegl's idea of the Kunst-
by innerspiritand representedwhatamountedto wollen, Kandinskycalled this principlethe "in-
a capriciousplay of form unable to express any ner necessity," and understood it to direct the
innermotive. creation of the work of art without concern for
Along side of ornament,Kandinskyalso com- form or external appearancesand solely with
pared the literary genre of fable to non-natu- regard to inner meaning and idea.82 Whatever
ralistic art, but fable also failed to serve as the else that may have meant, Kandinskylooked for
basis for an art of pure harmony.79Both orna- an art which did not decorate or adorn a pre-
ment and fable were inadequatein the end as existing form, but one which occupied center
models for abstractionbecause both were gov- stage or even orchestrated an entire Gesamt-
erned by external motives (i.e., the purpose of kunstwerk. This transfiguredornament would
decorationand the narrationof a story), which no longer be marginalizedto the statusof 'mere
do not allow the harmonyto be determinedfrom decoration,' but could provide the locus for
within. Thus, Kandinsky concluded that the nothing less than an ontological disclosure, a
"new art" would have to avoid "two dangers": revelationof the spiritualor metaphysicalreality
that Kandinskybelieved loomed behind appear-
ances and awaited epiphany in the imminent
On the one hand is the totally arbitraryapplicationof
'epoch of the great spiritual.'
colour to geometrical form-pure patterning.On the
other hand is the more naturalisticuse of colour in
DAVID MORGAN
bodily form-pure phantasy.80
ArtDepartment
University
Valparaiso
Rather than subscribe to the elevation of the IN46383
Valparaiso,
ornamentin the work of Riegl and Worringer,
Kandinskyreturnedto Vischer's and Fechner's
notion of ornamentin order to distance the ab- 1. Arthur Roessler, Neu-Dachau: Ludwig Dill, Adolf
stractfrom the ornamental.The abstractserved Hoelzel, ArthurLanghammer(Bielefeld and Leipzig: Vel-
no other end for Kandinskythan visualizing the hagen and Klasing, 1905), pp. 123-124; Hoelzel's images
are reproducedin Roessler's text and more recently repro-
inner necessity of the artist. Yet this notion of duced and discussed in Peg Weiss's importantstudy, Kan-
autonomywas indebtedto Jugendstilart theory dinskyin Munich. TheFormativeJugenstil Years(Princeton
and practiceand ultimatelyrecalls Moritz'sthe- University Press, 1979), to which I am indebted for an
ory of the ornament.8'In the end, Roessler and insightful discussion and excellent bibliographyof critical
writings ca. 1900 in Munich.
Kandinskywere in search of the same thing: a 2. Roessler, Neu-Dachau, p. 125: "das abstrakteOrna-
way of painting whose articulationof form and ment bilden; abstraktin der Bedeutungvon ungegenstind-
use of color grew out of what both men not lich."

This content downloaded from 91.105.21.1 on Tue, 20 May 2014 14:52:33 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
240 The Journalof Aesthetics and Art Criticism

3. For a broad historical treatmentof ornamentin nine- 28. Vischer,KritischeGange 6 (Stuttgart:VerlagderJ.G.


teenth-centuryGermanart theory, see Frank-LotharKroll, Cotta, 1873), p. 4: the "Begriff der Symbolik" is: "das
Das Ornamentin der Kunsttheoriedes 19. Jahrhunderts dunkle, aber innige, unwillkirliche und doch nicht religids
(Hildesheim:Olms, 1987); a helpful and importantstudy is gebundene,sondernaesthetischefreie Leihen, wodurchwir,
E.H. Gombrich'sThe Sense of Order:A Study in the Psy- einer innern Nothwendigkeitder Natur unserer Seele fol-
chology of DecorativeArt (Cornell UniversityPress, 1979). gend, abstractenErscheinungsformen eine Seelen-stimmung
4. Karl Philipp Moritz, Vorbegriffezu einer Theorieder unterlegen, so dass unser eigenes inneres Leben uns aus
Ornamente(Berlin:KarlMassdorff, 1793), p. 42. ihnen entgegenzukommenscheint." For a discussion of the
5. Ibid., p. 39. 'abstract'elements, see p. 36 of the same text.
6. Karl Philipp Moritz, Schriften zur Aesthetik und 29. For a related view that perceptionof lines, surfaces,
Poetik, ed. Hans Joachim Schrimpf (Tibingen: Max Nie- forms, etc. are incapable on their own right of evoking a
meyer, 1962), p. 116. fully aestheticexperience, see JohannesVolkelt, "ZurPsy-
7. Ibid., p. 210. chologie der aesthetischenBeseelung," Zeitschriftfur Philo-
8. Moritz, Vorbegriffe,p. 6. sophie und philosophische KritikNF 113 (1899), pp. 172-
9. Ibid., p. 5. 173, where Volkeltfollowed Vischer by invokingthe neces-
10. Moritz, Schriften,pp. 3, 5. sity of a corporealempathyin aestheticexperience.
11. Ibid., p. 6; the article, entitled "Versucheiner Ver- 30. Vischer, Kritische Gdnge 6: p. 100. Makartpainted
einigung aller schbnen Kinste und Wissenschaften unter the two large, densely-composed, and highly coloristic alle-
dem Begriff des in sich selbst Vollendeten,"was originally gories (entitled Abundantia:Die Gaben der Erde and Die
publishedin 1785 in the BerlinischenMonatsschriften. Gaben des Meeres) depicting the gifts of the earth and sea
12. The role of ornamentin Kant'sthirdcritiquehas been for the dining-hall of a Hungarianmagnate in 1870-see
recently discussed by Serge Trottein, "Ornement et es- reproductionsanddiscussion in GerbertFrodl, Hans Makart
thetique chez Kant," in WorldArt, Acts of the XXVIth (Salzburg:Residenz, 1974), pp. 312-313. Both images are
InternationalCongress of the History of Art, ed. Irving now located in the Louvre. Although the pictures were
Lavin (PennsylvaniaState UniversityPress, 1986), pp. 255- intendedfor a residence in Vienna, they were not installed,
259. buttraveledto Berlinfor exhibition, whereVischer mayhave
13. ImmanuelKant, Critiqueof Judgment, tr. J.H. Ber- seen them.
nard(New York:Hafner, 1951), p. 66. 31. GustavFechner, Vorschuleder Aesthetik,volume one
14. Michael Podro has discussed the ambiguity which (Leipzig: Breitkopfand Hartel, 1876), pp. 177-178.
Herbart failed to resolve between the Vorstellungas the 32. Ibid., p. 178.
mentalrepresentationof an object or the aspect of an object, 33. Ibid.
The Manifold in Perception (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 34. Ibid., pp. 178-179.
1972), p. 66. 35. Ibid., p. 182. It is worth noting that Kandinsky re-
15. Quoted in Philosophies of Beauty, ed. E.F. Carritt called that an importantbreakthroughin his work was wit-
(Oxford University Press, 1931), p. 156, translationem- nessing a painting transfigured into non-representational
mended; Herbart, Kurze Encyklopaedie der Philosophie formsby sunlight, "Ruckblicke,"in Kandinsky.Die Gesam-
(Halle: C.A. Schwetschke und Sohn, 1831), pp. 124-125. melten Schriften, volume one, ed. Hans K. Roethel and
Emphasisin original. JelenaHahl-Koch(Bern:Benteli, 1980), p. 38.
16. Herbart, Encyklopaedie der Philosophie, pp. 121- 36. Fechner, Vorschule der Aesthetik, volume one,
123. p. 183. For Fechner'sdiscussion of the mechanismof asso-
17. Philosophiesof Beauty,p. 156, translationemmended; ciation which appearsto be precisely what Herbarthad in-
Encyklopaedieder Philosophie, p. 124. tended by 'apperception,' see Fechner, "Das Association-
18. Ibid., p. 155. Emphasisin original. sprincip in der Aesthetik," Zeitschriftfar bildende Kunst 1
19. RobertZimmermann,AllgemeineAesthetikals Form- (1866): pp. 179-191.
wissenschaft(Vienna: Wilhelm Braumriller,1865). 37. Theodor Lipps, Raumaesthetik und geometrisch-
20. Ibid., I, p. 21. optische Tauschungen.Schriften der Gesellschaft fur psy-
21. Ibid., I, p. 31; cf. Herbart,Encyklopaedieder Philo- chologische Forschung,IX-X (Leipzig: JohannAmbrosius
sophie, pp. 127-128. Barth, 1897).
22. Vischerhadasked "canlines andcolors, which depict 38. Ibid., pp. 14-15.
nothing, neverthelessproducean impression, which is more 39. Ibid., pp. 25-26. Emphasisin original.
than sensuously pleasant?"(Kritische Gdnge N.F. 5 [Stutt- 40. Theodor Lipps, Aesthetik. Pyschologie des Schonen
gart: Verlag der J.G. Cotta, 1866], p. 62), and answered und der Kunst, part one, Grundlegungder Aesthetik(Ham-
affirmatively with the proviso that such lines or colors, burg and Leipzig: Leopold Voss, 1903), p. 225. All quota-
"indeed abstract,without object," be experienced "as part tions are from the first volume.
of a concrete whole, as in the painted windows of Gothic 41. Ibid., p. 163.
churches, where certainly also without pictorial depiction 42. Ibid., p. 11: "Apperzeption."
the transparentglow of harmoniouscolors works compel- 43. Ibid., p. 248.
lingly on the soul" (p. 76). 44. Ibid., p. 251.
23. Ibid., pp. 76-77. 45. Ibid., p. 441
24. Ibid., pp. 67-68. 46. Ibid., p. 442.
25. Ibid., p. 61. 47. Ibid., p. 445.
26. Ibid., p. 62. 48. Ibid., p. 261.
27. Ibid., pp. 76-77, 141-142, 104-105. 49. Heinrich Wolfflin, "Prolegomenazu einer Psychol-

This content downloaded from 91.105.21.1 on Tue, 20 May 2014 14:52:33 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Morgan Abstractionand German Theories of the Ornament 241

ogie der Architektur"(1886; reprintedin Kleine Schriften, Macht der Form uber unser Gemut, ein direkter unmit-
ed. JosephGantner[Basel: Benno-Schwabe, 1946]), pp. 13- telbarerEinfluss ohne alle Zwischenglieder,durchausnicht
47. etwa die Folge eines Anthropomorphismus,einer Vermen-
50. Ibid., p. 15. schlichung."
51. Ibid., p. 21. 68. For the notion of Vermenschlichungor Anthropo-
52. Karl Scheffler, "Meditationenuber das Ornament," morphismus,see HeinrichWoifflin, "Prolegomena,"p. 16;
DekorativeKunst8 (1901): pp. 347-414. Scheffler's article Theodor Lipps, Aesthetik, volume one, pp. 163-167; on
was published in Dekorative Kunst, a Munich- and Paris- beseelen and Beseelung, see JohannesVolkelt, Der Symbol-
basedjournalfoundedin 1897to promotethe decorativearts Begriff in der neuesten Aesthetik (Jena: Hermann Dufft,
in Germanyand France. The article has been examined by 1876), pp. 116-118; and "ZurPsychologie der aesthetischen
Weiss, Kandinskyin Munich, p. 111. Beseelung," Zeitschriftfir Philosophie undphilosophische
53. Scheffler,"Meditationenuberdas Ornament,"p. 400. Kritik NF 113 (1899), pp. 161-179; Wblfflin, "Prolego-
54. Ibid. mena," pp. 15-16; Lipps, "AesthetischeEinfifhlung,"Zeit-
55. Henry van de Velde, "Die Linie" (1902; reprintedin schriftftirPsychologie undPhysiologie der Sinnesorgane22
Essays, Leipzig: Insel, 1910), p. 43. (1900), p. 416. According to Fritz Schmalenbach,Jugend-
56. Ibid., p. 42. stil, Ein Beitrag zu Theorie und Geschichte der Flchen-
57. August Endell, "Formenschonheitund Dekorative kunst(Wurzberg:KonradTriltsch, 1935), pp. 31, 92, Endell
Kunst." part 1, "Die Freude an der Forn," Dekorative studied with Lipps in Munich, cited in Weiss, Kandinskyin
Kunst 1 (1897): pp. 75-77; part 2, "Die gerade Linie," Munich, p. 169, note 57.
Dekorative Kunst 1 (1898): pp. 119-120; part 3, "Gerad- 69. Paul Stern, Einffihlungund Association in der neu-
linige Gebilde." DekorativeKunst 1 (1898): pp. 121-125. eren Aesthetik. Beitrage zur Aesthetik, V (Hamburg and
58. Peg Weiss, Kandinskin Munich, pp. 34-40. Leipzig: Leopold Voss, 1898).
59. Endell, "Die Freudean der Forn," p. 75. 70. Ibid., pp. 23, 79-80. In 1901 ConradLange repeated
60. Ibid. this charge in his long work, Das Wesender Kunst, volume
61. Ibid., pp. 75-76. Emphasisin original. one (Berlin:G. Grote, 1901), p. 4.
62. Endell, "Die gerade Linie," pp. 119-120. 71. Stern, Einfihlung undAssociation, pp. 38-39; Wblf-
63. J.A. Romberg, founder, continued by Friedrich flin had also expressed some reservations regarding Vol-
Faber,Conversationslexiconfur bildendeKunst,volume one kelt's pantheismandthe operationof Selbstversetzungwhich
(Leipzig: Renger, 1845-1857), p. 43. Because this text has Volkeltdiscussed, "Prolegomena,"pp. 17-2 1.
not been commented on heretoforethat I am aware, I offer 72. Roessler, Neu-Dachau, pp. 119, 121.
the originalin full: 73. Ibid., p. 115.
74. Ibid., p. 123.
Abstraction,eigentl. Absonderung,als philosophischerterminustech- 75. Ibid.
nicus, die Geistesthatigkeit,verrnogewelcher man bei der Bildung 76. In contrastto the common assumptionthatKandinsky
von Begriffen das Unwesentliche und Minderwesentlichevon dem owed a great debt to Worringer'sAbstraktion und Ein-
Wesentlichenabsondert;in der schonen Kunst, die Geistesthatigkeit,
fahlung, it is in fact likely that he had not read the book
verrnogewelcher man bei Bildung von Kunstwerkennur das dem
bestimmten Kunstzwecke Entsprechendeannimmt und das andere before Ueber das Geistige was first published in 1912, see
unberiicksichtigtlIsst. Abstractionin diesem Zwecke ist daherjedem Norbert Lynton, "Expressionism,"in Conceptsof Modern
Kunstlernothig, wenn er nicht Theile, all Zilge, die nicht wesentlich Art, ed. Nikos Stangos(London:Thamesand Hudson, 1981),
zum Zweck gehoren, welche die Wirkunghindern, unnutzerWeise pp. 42-43. I have discussed Worringer'srelationto German
aufhalten,nicht Nachdruckoder neues Licht geben, den Gegenstand Expressionism in greaterdetail elsewhere, see David Mor-
nicht von der Seite herausheben,die uns jetzt interessirensoll, lerne gan, "Concepts of Abstraction in German Art Theory,
der Kuinstler,der seinen Zweck erreichen will, absondern. Nur hute 1750-1914" (Ph.D. dissertation, University of Chicago,
er sich von der dann den Fehler der Dunkelheit, Trockenheit,Kalte
1990), pp. 146-152; for an extensive review of German
und einformrigenMattigkeit vermeiden. Nicht dass abgesondert,
sondern was abgesondertwerde, ist es, worauf alles hier ankommt; historiographyon Worringer,see Evelin Priebe, Angst und
denn wollen wir gleich nichtjede Seite des Gegenstandes zugleich Abstraktion. Die Funktionder Kunst in der Kunsttheorie
sehen, so werden wir doch mit Vergnugeneben jene herausgehoben Kandinskys(Frankfurtam Main:PeterLang, 1986), pp 135-
bemerken,die eben jetzt unsereAufmerksamkeitfesseln sollte. [em- 152. For a contemporaryand unrestrainedrepudiationof
phasis in originall ornament,see the lectureby Viennese architectAdolf Loos,
"Ornamentund Verbrechen,"first presented in Munich in
64. Johannes Muller, Handbuch der Physiologie des 1908, reprintedin a collection of essays by Loos entitled
MenschenfPr Vorlesungen,volume two (Coblenz: J. Hol- Trotzdem, 1900-1930 (Innsbruck: Brenner, 1931). As
scher, 1834-40), part 1, p. 96; Elements of Physiology, Reyner Banham pointed out, Loos even singled out for
volume two, tr. William Baly (London: printed for Taylor censure such practitionersof Jugendstil design as Van de
and Walton, 1842), p. 938. Velde, Olbrich, and Eckmann, in Banham, Theory and
65. Muller,Elementsof Physiology, volume two, p. 1085. Design in the First Machine Age, 2 ed. (Massachusetts
66. Whetheror not Endell knew Romberg'sdefinition is Instituteof TechnologyPress, 1980), p. 94.
immaterial.As a studentof Lipps at the universityin Munich 77. FranzMarc, Kandinsky'scollaboratorand friend, ex-
(see note 68), Endell was certainly initiated into the scien- plicitly contrasted his artistic aim with 'stylization,' see
tific and academic discourse of perceptual psychology as Marc, Schriften, ed. Klaus Lankheit (Cologne: DuMont,
suggestedby his use of technicaltenninology such as Sehfeld 1978). On Marc'sfundamentalshift from understandingthe
and Vermenschlichung. new paintingcirca 1910as a refinementof "decorativecolor
67. Endell, "Die Freudean der Form,"p. 76: "Das ist die values" thatpromised much for the appliedarts to a "purely

This content downloaded from 91.105.21.1 on Tue, 20 May 2014 14:52:33 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
242 The Journalof Aesthetics and Art Criticism

pictorial"aim with no concern for "decorativeeffect," see works of sculpture and painting because the presence of
Claus Pese, Franz Marc. Leben und Werke (Stuttgart: content in the latter distracts the modern viewer with his
Belser, 1989), pp. 30-31, 117. preoccupationwith message, Riegl, SpatromischeKunstin-
78. Wassily Kandinsky,Concerningthe Spiritual in Art, dustrie, 2 ed (1927; reprint, Darmstadt:Wissenschaftliche
tr. M.T.H. Sadler(New York:Dover, 1977), p. 47. Buchgesellschaft, 1973), p. 19; reiterated by Worringer,
79. Ibid., pp. 49-50. Abstractionand Empathy.A Contributionto the Psychology
80. Ibid., p. 51. of Style, tr. Michael Bullock (New York:InternationalUni-
81. In a similar manner, Kant's distinction between free versities Press, 1953), p. 51.
and dependentbeauty is recalled in Riegl's contention that 82. Riegl used the term "innereNotwendigkeit"in 1901
the basic laws of a period's Kunstwollenare more clearly when defining his term Kunstwollenin SpatromischeKun-
expressed in architectureand the crafts than in figurative stindustrie,p. 22.

This content downloaded from 91.105.21.1 on Tue, 20 May 2014 14:52:33 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

You might also like