You are on page 1of 18

Sorensen, Roy, "Vagueness", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2018

Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL =


<https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2018/entries/vagueness/>.

Vagueness
First published Sat Feb 8, 1997; substantive revision Thu Apr 5, 2018
There is wide agreement that a term is vague to the extent that it has borderline cases.
This makes the notion of a borderline case crucial in accounts of vagueness. I shall
concentrate on an historical characterization of borderline cases that most commentators
would accept. Vagueness will then be contrasted with ambiguity and generality. This will
clarify the nature of the philosophical challenge posed by vagueness. I will then discuss
some rival theories of vagueness with an emphasis on many-valued logic,
supervaluationism and contextualism. I will conclude with the issue of whether all
vagueness is linguistic.

 1. Inquiry Resistance
 2. Comparison with Ambiguity and Generality
 3. The Philosophical Challenge Posed by Vagueness
 4. Many-valued Logic
 5. Supervaluationism
 6. Subvaluationism
 7. Contextualism
 8. Is All Vagueness Linguistic?
 Bibliography
 Academic Tools
 Other Internet Resources
 Related Entries

1. Inquiry Resistance
If you cut one head off of a two headed man, have you decapitated him? What is the
maximum height of a short man? When does a fertilized egg develop into a person?
These questions are impossible to answer because they involve absolute borderline cases.
In the vast majority of cases, the unknowability of a borderline statement is only relative
to a given means of settling the issue (Sorensen 2001, chapter 1). For instance, a boy may
count as a borderline case of ‘obese’ because people cannot tell whether he is obese just
by looking at him. A curious mother could try to settle the matter by calculating her son’s
body mass index. The formula is to divide his weight (in kilograms) by the square of his
height (in meters). If the value exceeds 30, this test counts him as obese. The calculation
will itself leave some borderline cases. The mother could then use a weight-for-height
chart. These charts are not entirely decisive because they do not reflect the ratio of fat to
muscle, whether the child has large bones, and so on. The boy will only count as an
absolute borderline case of ‘obese’ if no possible method of inquiry could settle whether
he is obese. When we reach this stage, we start to suspect that our uncertainty is due to
the concept of obesity rather than to our limited means of testing for obesity.
Absolute borderline cases are targeted by Charles Sander Peirce’s entry for ‘vague’ in the
1902 Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology:
A proposition is vague when there are possible states of things concerning which it
is intrinsically uncertain whether, had they been contemplated by the speaker, he would
have regarded them as excluded or allowed by the proposition. By intrinsically uncertain
we mean not uncertain in consequence of any ignorance of the interpreter, but because
the speaker’s habits of language were indeterminate. (Peirce 1902, 748)
In the case of relative borderline cases, the question is clear but our means for answering
it are incomplete. In the case of absolute borderline cases, there is incompleteness in the
question itself.
When a term is applied to one of its absolute borderline cases the result is a statement that
resists all attempts to settle whether it is true or false. No amount of conceptual analysis
or empirical inquiry can settle whether removing one head from a two headed man counts
as decapitating him. We could give the appearance of settling the matter by stipulating
that ‘decapitate’ means ‘remove a head’ (as opposed to ‘make headless’ or ‘remove the
head’ or ‘remove the most important head’). But that would amount to changing the topic
to an issue that merely sounds the same as decapitation.
Vagueness is standardly defined as the possession of borderline cases. For example, ‘tall’
is vague because a man who is 1.8 meters in height is neither clearly tall nor clearly non-
tall. No amount of conceptual analysis or empirical investigation can settle whether a 1.8
meter man is tall. Borderline cases are inquiry resistant.
Where does the tail of a snake begin? When posed as a rhetorical question, the speaker is
hinting that there is no definite answer. But the tail can be located by tracing down from
the snake’s rib cage. A false attribution of indeterminacy will lead to the premature
abandonment of inquiry. The risk of futile inquiry into questions that cannot be answered
must be balanced against the risk of abandoning questions that are actually answerable.
Inquiry resistance typically recurses. For in addition to the unclarity of the borderline
case, there is normally unclarity as to where the unclarity begins. Twilight governs times
that are borderline between day and night. But our uncertainty as to when twilight begins,
shows there must be borderline cases of borderline cases of ‘day’. Consequently,
‘borderline case’ has borderline cases. This higher order vagueness seems to show that
‘vague’ is vague (Hu 2017).
The vagueness of ‘vague’ would have two important consequences. First, Gottlob Frege
could no longer coherently characterize vague predicates as incoherent. For his accusation
uses ‘vague’. Frege’s ideal of precision is itself vague because ‘precise’ is the
complement of ‘vague’.
Second, the vagueness of ‘vague’ dooms efforts to avoid a sharp line between true and
false with a buffer zone that is neither true nor false. If the line is not drawn between the
true and the false, then it will be between the true and the intermediate state. Introducing
further intermediates just delays the inevitable.
This motivates second thoughts about second order vagueness. Instead of continuing to
treat higher order vagueness as an insight, several philosophers repudiate higher order
vagueness as an illusion (Wright 2010). They deny that there is an open-ended iteration
of borderline status. They find it telling that speakers do not go around talking about
borderline borderline cases and borderline borderline borderline cases and so forth
(Raffman 2005, 23).
Defenders of higher order vagueness say that ordinary speakers avoid iterating
‘borderline’ for the same reason they avoid iterating ‘million’ or ‘know’. The iterations
are confusing but perfectly meaningful. ‘Borderline’ behaves just like a vague predicate.
For instance, ‘borderline’ can be embedded in a sorites argument. Defenders of higher
order vagueness have also tried to clinch the case with particular specimens such as
borderline hermaphrodites (reasoning that these individuals are borderline borderline
males) (Sorensen 2010).
2. Comparison with Ambiguity and Generality
‘Tall’ is relative. A 1.8 meter pygmy is tall for a pygmy but a 1.8 meter Masai is not tall
for a Masai. Although relativization disambiguates, it does not eliminate borderline cases.
There are shorter pygmies who are borderline tall for a pygmy and taller Masai who are
borderline tall for a Masai. The direct bearers of vagueness are a word’s full
disambiguations such as ‘tall for an eighteenth century French man’. Words are only
vague indirectly, by virtue of having a sense that is vague. In contrast, an ambiguous word
bears its ambiguity directly—simply in virtue of having multiple meanings.
This contrast between vagueness and ambiguity is obscured by the fact that most words
are both vague and ambiguous. ‘Child’ is ambiguous between ‘offspring’ and ‘immature
offspring’. The latter reading of ‘child’ is vague because there are borderline cases of
immature offspring. The contrast is further complicated by the fact that most words are
also general. For instance, ‘child’ covers both boys and girls.
Ambiguity and vagueness also contrast with respect to the speaker’s discretion. If a word
is ambiguous, the speaker can resolve the ambiguity without departing from literal usage.
For instance, he can declare that he meant ‘child’ to express the concept of an immature
offspring. If a word is vague, the speaker cannot resolve the borderline case. For instance,
the speaker cannot make ‘child’ literally mean anyone under eighteen just by intending
it. That concept is not, as it were, on the menu corresponding to ‘child’. He would be
understood as taking a special liberty with the term to suit a special purpose.
Acknowledging departure from ordinary usage would relieve him of the obligation to
defend the sharp cut-off.
When the movie director Alfred Hitchcock mused ‘All actors are children’ he was taking
liberties with clear negative cases of ‘child’ rather than its borderline cases. The aptness
of his generalization is not judged by its literal truth-value (because it is obviously untrue).
Likewise, we do not judge precisifications of borderline cases by their truth-values
(because they are obviously not ascertainable as true or false). We instead judge
precisifications by their simplicity, conservativeness, and fruitfulness. A precisification
that draws the line across the borderline cases conserves more paradigm usage than one
that draws the line across clear cases. But conservatism is just one desideratum among
many. Sometimes the best balance is achieved at the cost of turning former positive cases
into negative cases.
Once we shift from literal to figurative usage, we gain fictive control over our entire
vocabulary—not just vague words. When a travel agent says ‘France is a hexagon’, we
do not infer that she has committed the geometrical error of classifying France as a six
sided polygon. We instead interpret the travel agent as speaking figuratively, as meaning
that France is shaped like a hexagon. Similarly, when the travel agent says ‘Reno is the
biggest little city’, we do not interpret her as overlooking the vagueness of ‘little city’.
Just as she uses the obvious falsehood of ‘France is a hexagon’ to signal a metaphor, she
uses the obvious indeterminacy of ‘Reno is the biggest little city’ to signal hyperbole.
Given that speakers lack any literal discretion over vague terms, we ought not to chide
them for indecisiveness. Where there is no decision to be made, there is no scope for vice.
Speakers would have literal discretion if statements applying a predicate to its borderline
cases were just permissible variations in linguistic usage. For instance, Crispin Wright
and Stewart Shapiro say a competent speaker can faultlessly classify the borderline case
as a positive instance while another competent speaker can faultlessly classify the case as
a negative instance.
For the sake of comparison, consider discretion between alternative spellings. Professor
Letterman uses ‘judgment’ instead of ‘judgement’ because he wants to promote the
principle that a silent E signals a long vowel. He still has fond memories of Tom Lehrer’s
1971 children’s song “Silent E”:
Who can turn a can into a cane?
Who can turn a pan into a pane?
It’s not too hard to see,
It’s Silent E.

Who can turn a cub into a cube?


Who can turn a tub into a tube?
It’s elementary
For Silent E.
Professor Letterman disapproves of those who add the misleading E but concedes that
‘judgement’ is a permissible spelling; he does not penalize his students for misspelling
when they make their hard-hearted choice of ‘judgement’. Indeed, like other professors,
he scolds students if they fail to stick with the same spelling throughout the composition.
Choose but stick to your choice!
Professor Letterman’s assertion ‘The word for my favorite mental act is spelled j-u-d-g-
m-e-n-t’ is robust with respect to the news that it is also spelled j-u-d-g-e-m-e-n-t. He
would continue to assert it. He can conjoin the original assertion with information about
the alternative: ‘The word for my favorite mental act is spelled j-u-d-g-m-e-n-t and is also
spelled j-u-d-g-e-m-e-n-t’. In contrast, Professor Letterman’s assertion that ‘Martha is a
woman’ is not robust with respect to the news that Martha is a borderline case of ‘woman’
(say, Letterman learns Martha is younger than she looks). The new information would
lead Letterman to retract his assertion in favor of a hedged remark such as ‘Martha might
be a woman and Martha might not be a woman’. Professor Letterman’s loss of confidence
is hard to explain if the information about her borderline status were simply news of a
different but permissible way of describing her. Discoveries of notational variants do not
warrant changes in former beliefs.
News of borderline status has an evidential character. Loss of clarity brings loss of
warrant. If you do not lower your confidence, you are open to the charge of dogmatism.
To concede that Martha is a borderline case of ‘woman’ is to concede that you do not
know that she is a woman. That is why debates can be dissolved by showing that the
dispute is over a borderline case. The debaters should be agnostic if they are dealing with
a borderline case. They do not have a license to form beliefs beyond their evidence.
News of an alternative sense is like news of an alternative spelling; there is no evidential
impact (except for meta-linguistic beliefs about the nature of words). Your assertion that
‘All bachelors are men’ is robust with respect to the news that ‘bachelor’ has an
alternative sense in which it means a male seal. Assertions are not robust with respect to
news of hidden generality. If a South African girl says ‘No elephant can be domesticated’
but is then taught that there is another species of elephant indigenous to Asia, then she
will lose some confidence; maybe Asian elephants can be domesticated. News of hidden
generality has evidential impact. When it comes to robustness, vagueness resembles
generality more than vagueness resembles ambiguity.
Mathematical terms such as ‘prime number’ show that a term can be general without
being vague. A term can also be vague without being general. Borderline cases of
analytically empty predicates illustrate this possibility.
Generality is obviously useful. Often, lessons about a particular F can be projected to
other Fs in virtue of their common F-ness. When a girl learns that her cat has a nictating
membrane that protects its eyes, she rightly expects her neighbor’s cat also has a nictating
membrane. Generality saves labor. When the girl says that she wants a toy rather than
clothes, she narrows the range of acceptable gifts without going through the trouble of
specifying a particular gift. The girl also balances values: a gift should be intrinsically
desired and yet also be a surprise. If uncertain about which channel is the weather channel,
she can hedge by describing the channel as ‘forty-something’. There is an inverse
relationship between the contentfulness of a proposition and its probability: the more
specific a claim, the less likely it is to be true. By gauging generality, we can make
sensible trade-offs between truth and detail.
‘Vague’ has a sense which is synonymous with abnormal generality. This precipitates
many equivocal explanations of vagueness. For instance, many commentators say that
vagueness exists because broad categories ease the task of classification. If I can describe
your sweater as red, then I do not need to ascertain whether it is scarlet. This freedom to
use wide intervals obviously helps us to learn, teach, communicate, and remember. But
so what? The problem is to explain the existence of borderline cases. Are they present
because vagueness serves a function? Or are borderline cases side-effects of ordinary
conversation—like echoes?
Every natural language is both vague and ambiguous. However, both features seem
eliminable. Indeed, both are eliminated in miniature languages such as checkers notation,
computer programming languages, and mathematical descriptions. Moreover, it seems
that both vagueness and ambiguity ought to be minimized. ‘Vague’ and ‘ambiguous’ are
pejorative terms. And they deserve their bad reputations. Think of all the automotive
misery that has been prefaced by
Driver: Do I turn left?
Passenger: Right.
English can be lethal. Philosophers have long motivated appeals for an ideal language by
pointing out how ambiguity creates the menace of equivocation:
No child should work.
Every person is a child of someone.
Therefore, no one should work.
Happily, we know how to criticize and correct all equivocations. Indeed, every natural
language is self-disambiguating in the sense that each has all the resources needed to
uniquely specify any reading one desires. Ambiguity is often the cause but rarely the
object of philosophical rumination.
3. The Philosophical Challenge Posed by Vagueness
Vagueness, in contrast, precipitates a profound problem: the sorites paradox. For instance,
Base step: A one day old human being is a child.
Induction step: If an n day old human being is a child, then that human being is also a
child when it is n + 1 days old.
Conclusion: Therefore, a 36,500 day old human being is a child.
The conclusion is false because a 100 year old man is clearly a non-child. Since the base
step of the argument is also plainly true and the argument is valid by mathematical
induction, we seem to have no choice but to reject the second premise.
George Boolos (1991) observes that we have an autonomous case against the induction
step. In addition to implying plausible conditionals such as ‘If a 1 day old human being
is a child, then that human being is also a child when it is 2 days old’, the induction step
also implies ludicrous conditionals such as ‘If a 1 day old human being is a child, then
that human being is also a child when it is 36,500 days old’.
Boolos is puzzled why we overlook these clear counterexamples. One explanation is that
we tend to treat the induction step as a generic generalization such as ‘ People have ten
toes’(Sorensen 2012). Whereas the formal generalization ‘All people have ten toes’ is
refuted by people with eleven toes, the generic generalization tolerates exceptions.
This hypothesis is plausible for newcomers to the sorites paradox. But it is less plausible
for those being tutored by Professor Boolos. He guides logic students to the correct
interpretation of the induction step. When students drift to a generic reading, Boolos
reminds them that induction step is a formal generalization.
Guided by Boolos’ firm hand, logic students drive a second stake into the heart of the
sorites paradox. Yet the paradox seems far from dead. The negation of the second premise
classically implies a sharp threshold for childhood. For it implies the existential
generalization that there is a number n such that an n day old human being is a child but
is no longer a child one day later.
Epistemicists accept this astonishing consequence. They think vagueness is a form of
ignorance. Timothy Williamson (1994) traces the ignorance of the threshold for
childhood to “margin for error” principles. If one knows that an n day old human being
is a child, then that human being must also be a child when n + 1 days old. Otherwise,
one is right by luck. Given that there is a threshold, we would be ignorant of its location.
Debate over the margin for error principle draws us deep into epistemology and modality
(Yli-Vakkuri 2016). Some commentators switch focus to attitudes weaker than
knowledge. According to Nicholas Smith (2008, 182) we cannot even guess that the
threshold for baldness is the 400th hair. Hartry Field (2010, 203) denies that a rational
man can fear that he has just passed the threshold into being old. Hope, speculation, and
wonder do not require evidence but they do require understanding. So it is revealing that
these attitudes have trouble getting a purchase on the threshold of oldness (or any other
vague predicate). A simple explanation is that bare linguistic competence gives us
knowledge that are no such thresholds. This accounts for the comical air of the
epistemicist. Just as there is no conceptual room to worry that there is a natural number
between sixty and sixty one, there is no conceptual room to worry that one has passed the
threshold of oldness between one’s sixtieth and sixty first birthday.
An old epistemicist might reply: My piecemeal confidence that a given number is not the
threshold for oldness does not agglomerate into collective confidence that there is no such
number. If I bet against each number being the threshold, then I must have placed a losing
bet somewhere. For if I won each bet then there was no opportunity for me to make the
transition to oldness. My bookie could have made a “Dutch book” against me. He would
have been entitled to payment without having to identify which bet I lost. Since
probabilities may be extracted from hypothetical betting behavior, I must actually assign
some small (normally negligible) probability to hypotheses identifying particular
thresholds. So must you.
Stephen Schiffer (2003, 204) denies that classical probability calculations apply in vague
contexts. Suppose Donald is borderline old and borderline bald. According to Schiffer we
should be just as confident in the conjunction ‘Donald is old and bald’ as in either
conjunct. Adding conjuncts does not reduce confidence because we have a “vague partial
belief” rather than the standard belief assumed by mathematicians developing probability
theory. Schiffer offers a calculus for this vagueness-related propositional attitude. He
crafts the rules for vague partial belief to provide apsychological solution to the sorites
paradox.
The project is complicated by the fact that vague partial beliefs interact with precise
beliefs (MacFarlane 2010). Consider a statement that has a mixture of vague and precise
conjuncts: ‘Donald is old and bald and has an even number of hairs’. Adding the extra
precise conjunct should diminish confidence. Schiffer also needs to accommodate the fact
that some speakers are undecided about whether the nature of the uncertainty involves
vagueness. Even an idealized speaker may be unsure because there is vagueness about
the borders between vagueness related uncertainty and other sorts of uncertainty.
Other commentators grant that it is logically possible that vague predicates have
thresholds. They just think it would be a miracle: “It is logically possible that the words
on this page will come to life and sort my socks. But I know enough about words to
dismiss this as a serious possibility. So I am right to boggle at the possibility that our
rough and ready terms such as ‘red’ could so sensitively classify objects.” Epistemicists
counter that this bafflement rests on an over-estimate of the role of stipulation in meaning.
Epistemicists say much meaning is acquired passively by default rather than actively by
decision. If some boundaries are more eligible for reference than others, then the
environment does the work.
Most philosophers doubt whether precise analytical tools fit vague arguments. H. G.
Wells was amongst the first to suggest that we must moderate the application of logic:
Every species is vague, every term goes cloudy at its edges, and so in my way of thinking,
relentless logic is only another name for stupidity—for a sort of intellectual
pigheadedness. If you push a philosophical or metaphysical enquiry through a series of
valid syllogisms—never committing any generally recognized fallacy—you nevertheless
leave behind you at each step a certain rubbing and marginal loss of objective truth and
you get deflections that are difficult to trace, at each phase in the process. Every species
waggles about in its definition, every tool is a little loose in its handle, every scale has its
individual.—First and Last Things (1908)
Many more believe that the problem is with logic itself rather than the manner in which
it is applied. They favor solving the sorites paradox by replacing standard logic with an
earthier deviant logic.
There is a desperately wide range of opinions as to how the revision of logic should be
executed. Every form of deviant logic has been applied in the hope of resolving the sorites
paradox.
4. Many-valued Logic
An early favorite was many-valued logic. On this approach, borderline statements are
assigned truth-values that lie between full truth and full falsehood. Some logicians favor
three truth-values, others prefer four or five. The most popular approach is to use an
infinite number of truth-values represented by the real numbers between 0 (for full
falsehood) and 1 (for full truth). This infinite spectrum of truth-values might be of service
for a continuous sorites argument involving ‘small real number’ (Weber and Colyvan
2010).
Critics object that this proliferation of truth-values exacerbates the over-precision of
classical logic. Instead of having just one artificially sharp line between the true and the
false, the many-valued logician has infinitely many sharp lines such as that between
statements with a truth of .323483925 and those with a higher truth-value. In Mark
Sainsbury’s words, “… you do not improve a bad idea by iterating it.” (1996, 255)
A proponent of an infinite valued logic might reply to Sainsbury with an analogy. It is a
bad idea to model a circle with a straight line. Using two lines is not much better, nor is
there is much improvement using a three sided polygon (a triangle). But as we add more
straight lines to the polygon (square, pentagon, hexagon, and so on) we make progress—
by iterating the bad idea of modeling a circle with straight lines.
Indeed, it would be tempting to triumphantly conclude ‘The circle has been modeled as
an infinitely sided polygon’. This victory declaration would itself need clarification. Has
the circle been revealed to be an infinitely sided polygon? Have curved lines been
replaced by straight lines? Have curved lines (and hence circles) been proven to not exist?
A model can succeed without it being clear what has been achieved.
But it is premature to dwell on the simile ‘Precision is to vagueness as straightness is to
curvature’. The many-valued logician must first vindicate the analogy by providing
details about how to calculate the truth-values of vague statements from the truth-values
of their component statements.
Proponents of many-valued logic approach this obligation with great industry. Precise
new rules are introduced to calculate the truth value of compound statements that contain
statements with intermediate truth-values. For instance, the revised rule for conjunctions
is to assign the conjunction the same truth-value as the conjunct with the lowest truth-
value.
These rules are designed to yield all standard theorems when all the truth values are 1 and
0. In this sense, classical logic is a limiting case of many-valued logic. Classical logic is
agreed to work fine in the area for which it was designed—mathematics.
Most theorems of standard logic break down when intermediate truth-values are involved.
(An irregular minority, such as ‘If P, then P’, survive.) Even the classical contradiction
‘Donald is bald and it is not the case that he is bald’ receives a truth-value of .5 when
‘Donald is bald’ has a truth-value of .5. Many-valued logicians note that the error they
are imputing to classical logic is often so small that classical logic can still be fruitfully
applied. But they insist that the sorites paradox illustrates how tiny errors accumulate into
a big error.
Critics of the many-valued approach complain that it botches phenomena such as
hedging. If I regard you as a borderline case of ‘tall man’, I cannot sincerely assert that
you are tall and I cannot sincerely assert that you are of average height. But I can assert
the hedged claim ‘Either you are tall or of average height’. The many-valued rule for
disjunction is to assign the whole statement the truth-value of its highest disjunct.
Normally, the added disjunct in a hedged claim is not more plausible than the other
disjuncts. Thus it cannot increase the degree of truth. Disappointingly, the proponent of
many-valued logic cannot trace the increase of assertibility to an increase in the degree
of truth.
Epistemicists explain the rise in assertibility by the increasing probability of truth. Since
the addition of disjuncts can raise probability indefinitely, the epistemicists correctly
predict that we can hedge our way to full assertibility. However, epistemicists do not have
a monopoly on this prediction.
5. Supervaluationism
According to supervaluationists, borderline statements lack a truth-value. This neatly
explains why it is universally impossible to know the truth-value of a borderline
statement. Supervaluationists offer details about the nature of absolute borderline cases.
Simple sentences about borderline cases lack a truth-value. Compounds of these
statements can have a truth-value if they come out true regardless of how the statement is
precisified. For instance, ‘Either Mr. Stoop is tall or it is not the case that Mr. Stoop is
tall’ is true because it comes out true under all ways of sharpening ‘tall’. Thus the method
of supervaluations allows one to retain all the theorems of standard logic while admitting
“truth-value gaps”.
One may wonder whether this striking result is a genuine convergence with standard
logic. Is the supervaluationist characterizing vague statements as propositions? Or is he
merely pointing out that certain non-propositions have a structure isomorphic to logical
theorems? (Some electrical circuits are isomorphic to tautologies but this does not make
the circuits tautologies.) Kit Fine (1975, 282), and especially David Lewis (1982),
characterize vagueness as hyper-ambiguity. Instead of there being one vague concept,
there are many precise concepts that closely resemble each other. ‘Child’ can mean a
human being at most one day old or mean a human being at most two days old or mean a
human being at most three days old …. Thus the logic of vagueness is a logic for
equivocators. Lewis’ idea is that ambiguous statements are true when they come out true
under all disambiguations. But logicians normally require that a statement be
disambiguated before logic is applied. The mere fact that an ambiguous statement comes
out true under all its disambiguations does not show that the statement itself is true.
Sentences which are actually disambiguated may have truth-values. But the best that can
be said of those that merely could be disambiguated is that they would have had a truth-
value had they been disambiguated (Tye 1989).
Supervaluationism will converge with classical logic only if each word of the
supervaluated sentence is uniformly interpreted. For instance, ‘Either a carbon copy of
Teddy Roosevelt’s signature is an autograph or it is not the case that a carbon copy of
Teddy Roosevelt’s signature is an autograph’ comes out true only if ‘autograph’ is
interpreted the same way in both disjuncts. Vague sentences resist mixed interpretations.
However, mixed interpretations are permissible for ambiguous sentences. As Lewis
himself notes in a criticism of relevance logic, ‘Scrooge walked along the bank on his
way to the bank’ can receive a mixed disambiguation. When exterminators offer ‘non-
toxic ant poison’, we charitably switch relativizations within the noun phrase: the
substance is safe for human beings but deadly for ants.
Even if one agrees that supervaluationism converges with classical logic about
theoremhood, they clearly differ in other respects. Supervaluationism requires rejection
of inference rules such as contraposition, conditional proof and reductio ad
absurdum (Williamson 1994, 151–152). In the eyes of the supervaluationist, a
demonstration that a statement is not true does not guarantee that the statement is false.
The supervaluationist is also under pressure to reject semantic principles which are
intimately associated with the application of logical laws. According to Alfred Tarski’s
Convention T, a statement ‘S’ is true if and only if S. In other words, truth is
disquotational. Supervaluationists say that being supertrue (being true under all
precisifications) suffices for being true. But given Convention T, supertruth would then
be disquotational. Since the supervaluationists accept the principle of excluded middle,
they would be forced to say ‘P’ is supertrue or ‘Not P’ is supertrue (even if ‘P’ applies a
predicate to a borderline case). This would imply that either ‘P’ is true or ‘Not P’ is true.
(Williamson 1994, 162–163) And that would be a fatal loss of truth-value gaps for
supervaluationism.
There is a final concern about the “ontological honesty” of the supervaluationist’s
existential quantifier. As part of his solution to the sorites paradox, the supervaluationist
will assert ‘There is a human being who was a child when n days old but not when n + 1
days old’. For this statement comes out true under all admissible precisifications of
‘child’. However, when pressed the supervaluationist will add an unofficial clarification:
“Oh, of course I do not mean that there really is a sharp threshold for childhood.”
After the clarification, some wonder how supervaluationism differs from drastic
metaphysical skepticism. In his nihilist days, Peter Unger (1979) admitted that it is useful
to talk as if there are children. But he insisted that strictly speaking, vague terms such as
‘child’ cannot apply to anything. Unger was free to use supervaluationism as a theory to
explain our ordinary discourse about children. (Unger instead used other resources to
explain how we fruitfully apply empty predicates.) But once the dust had cleared and the
precise rubble came into focus, Unger had to conclude that there are no children.
Officially, the supervaluationist rejects the induction step of the sorites argument.
Unofficially, he seems to instead reject the base step of the sorites argument.
6. Subvaluationism
Supervaluationism is also haunted by a logical analogy. Whereas the supervaluationist
analyzes borderline cases in terms of truth-value gaps the dialetheist analyzes them in
terms of truth-value gluts. A glut is a proposition that is both true and false. The rule for
assigning gluts is the mirror image of the rule for assigning gaps: A statement is true
exactly if it comes out true on at least one precisification. The statement is false just if it
comes out false on at least one precisification. So if the statement comes out true under
one precisification and false under another precisification, the statement is both true and
false.
To avoid triviality, the dialetheist must adopt a logic that stops two contradictory
statements from jointly implying everything. The resulting “subvaluationism” is a dual
of supervaluationism.
The spiritual father of subvaluationism is Georg Hegel. For Hegel, the basic kind of
vagueness is conflict vagueness. The man at the threshold of your doorway is both inside
your room and outside your room. Degree vagueness is just a special case of the conflict
inherit in becoming. Any process requires a gradual manifestation of a contradiction
inherit in the original state. At some stage, a metamorphosizing caterpillar is not a
butterfly (by virtue of what it was) and a butterfly (by virtue of what it will be). Hegelians
believed this dialectical conception of vagueness solved the sorites and demonstrated the
inadequacy of classical logic. The Russian Marxist Georgi Plekhanov (1908 [1937])
proposed a logic of contradiction to succeed classical logic (Hyde 2008, 93–5). One of
his students, Henry Mehlberg (1958) went on to substitute gaps for gluts. The first version
of supervaluationism is thus a synthesis, reconciling the thesis of classical logic with the
anti-thesis posed by the logic of contradiction.
Viewed formally, there seems no more reason to prefer one departure from classical logic
rather than the other. Since Western philosophers abominate contradiction, parity with
dialetheism would diminish the great popularity of supervaluationism.
A Machiavellian epistemicist will welcome this battle between the gaps and the gluts. He
roots for the weaker side. Although he does not want the subvaluationist to win, the
Machiavellian epistemicist does want the subvaluationist to achieve mutual annihilation
with his supervaluationist doppelgänger. His political calculation is: Gaps + Gluts =
Bivalence.
Pablo Corberos (2011) has argued that subvaluationism provides a better treatment of
higher order vagueness than supervaluationism. But for the most part, the subvaluationists
(and their frenemies) have merely claimed subvaluationism to be at least as attractive as
supervaluationism (Hyde and Colyvan 2008). This modest ambition seems prudent. After
all, truth-value gaps have far more independent support from the history of philosophy
(at least if confined to Western philosophy). Prior to the explosive growth of vagueness
research after 1975, ordinary language philosophers amassed a panoramic battery of
analyses suggesting that gaps are involved in presupposition, reference failure, fiction,
future contingent propositions, performatives, and so on and so on. Supervaluationism
rigorously consolidated these appeals to ordinary language.
Dialetheists characterize intolerance for contradiction as a shallow phenomenon,
restricted to a twentieth Western academic milieu (maybe even now being eclipsed by the
rise of China). Experimental philosophers have challenged the old appeals to ordinary
language with empirical results suggesting that glutty talk is as readily stimulated by
borderline cases as gappy talk (Alxatib and Pelletier 2011, Ripley 2011).
7. Contextualism
Just as contextualism in epistemology runs orthogonal to the familiar divisions amongst
epistemologists (foundationalism, reliabilism, coherentism, etc.), there are contextualists
of every persuasion amongst vagueness theorists. They develop an analogy between the
sorites paradox and indexical sophistries such as:
1. Base step: The horizon is more than 1 meter away.
2. Induction step: If the horizon is more than n meters away, then it is more than n + 1
meters away.
3. Conclusion: The horizon is more than a billion meters away.
The horizon is where the earth meets the sky and is certainly less than a billion meters
away. (The circumference of the earth is only forty million meters.) Yet when you travel
toward the horizon to specify the n at which the induction step fails, your trip is as futile
as the pursuit of the rainbow. You cannot reach the horizon because it shifts with your
location.
All contextualists accuse the sorites monger of equivocating. In one sense, the meaning
of ‘child’ is uniform; the context-invariant rule for using the term (its “character”) is
constant. However, the set of things to which the term applies (its “content”) shifts with
the context. In this respect, vague words resemble indexical terms such as: I, you, here,
now, today, tomorrow. When a debtor tells his creditor on Monday ‘I will pay you back
tomorrow’ and then repeats the sentence on Tuesday, there is a sense in which he has said
the same thing (the character is the same) and a sense in which he has said something
different (the content has shifted because ‘tomorrow’ now picks out Wednesday).
According to the contextualists, the rules governing the shifts prohibit us from
interpreting any instance of the induction step as having a true antecedent and a false
consequent. The very process of trying to refute the induction step changes the context so
that the instance will not come out false. Indeed, contextualists typically emphasize that
each instance is true. Assent is mandatory. Consequently, direct attacks on the induction
step must fail. One is put in mind of Seneca’s admonition to his student Nero: “However
many you put to death, you will never kill your successor.”
Hans Kamp, the founder of contextualism, maintained that the extension of vague words
orbits the speaker’s store of conversational commitments. In a more psychological vein,
Diana Raffman says changes in context trigger gestalt shifts between look-alike
categories.
Stewart Shapiro integrates Kamp’s ideas with Friedrich Waismann’s concept of open
texture. Shapiro thinks speakers have discretion over borderline cases because they are
judgment dependent. They come out true in virtue of the speaker judging them to be true.
Given that the audience does not resist, borderline cases of ‘child’ can be correctly
described as children. The audience recognizes that other competent speakers could
describe the borderline case differently. As Waismann lyricizes “Every description
stretches, as it were, into a horizon of open possibilities: However far I go, I shall always
carry this horizon with me.” (1968, 122)
American pragmaticism colors Delia Graff Fara’s contextualism. Consider dandelion
farms. Why would someone grow weeds? The answer is that ‘weed’ is relative to
interests. Dandelions are unwanted by lawn caretakers but are desired by farmers for food,
wine, and medical uses. Fara thinks this interest relativity extends to all vague words. For
instance, ‘child’ means a degree of immaturity that is significant to the speaker. Since the
interests of the speaker shift, there is an opportunity for a shift in the extension of ‘child’.
Fara is reluctant to describe herself as a contextualist because the context only has an
indirect effect on the extension via the changes it makes to the speaker’s interest.
How strictly are we to take the comparison between vague words and indexical terms?
Scott Soames (2002, 445) answers that all vague words literally are indexical.
This straightforward response is open to the objection that the sorites monger could
stabilize reference. When the sorites monger relativizes ‘horizon’ to the northeast corner
of the Empire State Building’s observation deck, he seems to generate a genuine sorites
paradox that exploits the vagueness of ‘horizon’ (not its indexicality).
All natural languages have stabilizing pronouns, ellipsis, and other anaphoric devices. For
instance, in ‘Jack is tired now and Jill is too’, the ‘too’ forces a uniform reading of ‘tired’.
Jason Stanley suggests that the sorites monger employ the premise:
If that1 is a child then that2 is too, and if that2 is too, then that3 is too, and if that3 is too,
then that4 is too, … and then thati is too.
Each ‘thatn’ refers to the nth element in a sequence of worsening examples of ‘child’. The
meaning of ‘child’ is not shifting because the first occurrence of the term governs all the
subsequent clauses (thanks to ‘too’). If vague terms were literally indexical, the sorites
monger would have a strong reply. If vague terms only resemble indexicals, then the
contextualist needs to develop the analogy in a way that circumvents Stanley’s counsel
to the sorites monger.
The contextualist would also need to address a second technique for stabilizing the
context. R. M. Sainsbury (2013) advises the sorites monger to present his premises in
apparently random order. No pair of successive cases raises an alarm that similar cases
are being treated differently. Unless the hearer has extraordinary memory, he will not feel
pressured to adjust the context.
The contextualist must find enough shiftiness to block every sorites argument. Since
vagueness seeps into every syntactic category, critics complain that contextualism
exceeds the level of ambiguity countenanced by linguistics and psycholinguists.
Another concern is that some sorites arguments involve predicates that do not give us an
opportunity to equivocate. Consider a sorites with a base step that starts from a number
too large for us to think about. Or consider an inductive predicate that is too complex for
us to reason with. One example is obtained by iterating ‘mother of’ a thousand times
(Sorensen 2001, 33). This predicate could be embedded in a mind numbing sorites that
would never generate context shifts.
Other unthinkable sorites arguments use predicates that can only be grasped by
individuals in other possible worlds or by creatures with different types of minds than
ours. More fancifully, there could be a vague predicate, such as Saul Kripke’s “killer
yellow”, that instantly kills anyone who thinks about it. The basic problem is that
contextualism is a psychologistic theory of the sorites. Arguments can exist without being
propounded.
8. Is All Vagueness Linguistic?
Supervaluationists encourage the view that all vagueness is a matter of linguistic
indecision: the reason why there are borderline cases is that we have not bothered to make
up our minds.
The method of supervaluation allows us to assign truth-values prior to any decisions.
Expressivists think this is a mistake akin to assigning truth-values to normative claims
(MacFarlane 2016). They model vagueness as practical uncertainty as to whether to treat
a borderline F as an F. The deliberator may accept the tautologies of classical logic as
constraints governing competing plans for drawing lines. I can accept ‘Either Donald is
bald or not’ without accepting either disjunct. An existentially quantified sentence can be
accepted even when no instance is. A shrug of the shoulders signals readiness to go either
way, not ignorance as to which possible world one inhabits. The supervaluationist tries
to express this insight by expanding the conditions under which truth-values can be
assigned. This the wrong medium for the message.
The expressivist is poised to explain how supervaluationism developed into the most
respected theory of vagueness. Frege portrayed vagueness as a side-effect of laziness. But
supervaluationists countered that indecision is functional. Instead of committing
ourselves prematurely, we can fill in meanings as we go along in light of new information
and interests. This conjecture is promising for the highly stipulative enterprise of
promulgating and enforcing laws (Endicott 2000). Judges frequently seem to exercise and
control discretion by means of vague language. Uncertainties about the scope of
discretion may arise from higher order vagueness (Schauer 2016).
Discretion through gap-filling pleases those who regard adjudication as a creative
process. It alarms those who think we should be judged by laws rather than men. The
doctrine of discretion through indeterminacy has also been questioned on grounds that
the source of the discretion is the generality of the legal terms rather than their vagueness
(Poscher 2012).
Supervaluationists emphasize the distinction between words and objects. Objects
themselves do not seem to be the sort of thing that can be general, ambiguous, or vague
(Eklund 2011). From this perspective, Georg Hegel appears to commit a category mistake
when he characterizes clouds as vague. Although we sometimes speak of clouds being
ambiguous or even being general to a region, this does not entitle us to infer that there is
metaphysical ambiguity or metaphysical generality.
Supervaluationists are here incorporating an orthodoxy dating back to Bertrand Russell’s
seminal article “Vagueness” (1923). This consensus was re-affirmed by Michael
Dummett (1975) and ritualistically re-avowed by subsequent commentators.
In 1978 Gareth Evans focused opposition to vague objects with a short proof modeled
after Saul Kripke’s attack on contingent identity. If there is a vague object, then some
statement of the form ‘a= b’ must be vague (where each of the flanking singular terms
precisely designates that object). For the vagueness is allegedly due to the object rather
than its representation. But any statement of form ‘a = a’ is definitely true.
Consequently, a has the property of being definitely identical to a. Since a= b,
then b must also have the property of being definitely identical to a. Therefore ‘a = b’
must be definitely true!
Evans agrees that there are vague identity statements in which one of the flanking terms
is vague (just as Kripke agrees that there are contingent identity statements when one of
the flanking terms is a flaccid designator). But then the vagueness is due to language, not
the world.
Despite Evans’ impressive assault, there was a renewal of interest in vague objects in the
1980s. As a precedent for this revival, Peter van Inwagen (1990, 283) recalls that in the
1960s, there was a consensus that all necessity is linguistic. Most philosophers now take
the possibility of essential properties seriously.
Some of the reasons are technical. Problems with Kripke’s refutation of contingent
identity have structural parallels that affect Evans’ proof. Evans also relies on inferences
that deviant logicians challenge (Parsons 2000).
In the absence of a decisive reductio ad absurdum, many logicians feel their role to be
the liberal one of articulating the logical space for vague objects. There should be “Vague
objects for those who want them” (Cowles and White 1991). Logic should be
ontologically neutral.
Since epistemicists try to solve the sorites with little more than a resolute application of
classical logic, they are methodologically committed to a partisan role for logic. Instead
of looking for loopholes, we should accept the consequence (Williamson 2015).
Some non-enemies of vague objects also have an ambition to consolidate various species
of indeterminacy (Barnes and Williams 2011). Talk of indeterminacy is found in quantum
mechanics, analyses of the open future, fictional incompleteness, and the continuum
hypothesis. Perhaps vagueness is just one face of indeterminacy.
This panoramic vision contrasts with the continuing resolution of many to tether
vagueness to the sorites paradox (Eklund 2011). They fear that the clarity achieved by
semantic ascent will be muddied by metaphysics.
But maybe the mud is already on the mountain top. Trenton Merricks (2001) claims that
standard characterizations of linguistic vagueness rely on metaphysical vagueness. If
‘Donald is bald’ lacks a truth-value because there is no fact to make the statement true,
then the shortage appears to be ontological.
The view that vagueness is always linguistic has been attacked from other directions.
Consider the vagueness of maps (Varzi 2001). The vagueness is pictorial rather than
discursive. So one cannot conclude that vagueness is linguistic merely from the premise
that vagueness is representational.
Or consider vague instrumental music such as Claude Debussy’s “The Clouds”. Music
has syntax but too little semantics to qualify as language. There is a little diffuse reference
through devices such as musical quotation, leitmotifs, and homages. These referential
devices are not precise. Therefore, some music is vague (Sorensen 2010). The strength
and significance of this argument depends on the relationship between music and
language. Under the musilanguage hypothesis, language and music branched off from a
common “musilanguage” with language specializing in semantics and music specializing
in the expression of emotion. This scenario makes it plausible that purely instrumental
music could have remnants of semantic meaning.
Mental imagery also seems vague. When rising suddenly after a prolonged crouch, I “see
stars before my eyes”. I can tell there are more than ten of these hallucinated lights but I
cannot tell how many. Is this indeterminacy in thought to be reduced to indeterminacy in
language? Why not vice versa? Language is an outgrowth of human psychology. Thus it
seems natural to view language as merely an accessible intermediate bearer of vagueness.
Bibliography

 Alxatib, Sam and Jeffry Pelletier, 2011, “The psychology of vagueness: Borderline cases
and contradictions”, Mind and Language, 26(3): 287–326.
 Barnes, E. J. and J. R. G. Williams, 2011, “A Theory of Metaphysical
Indeterminacy”, Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, vol. 6.
 Boolos, George, 1991, “Zooming Down the Slippery Slope”, Nous, 25: 695–706.
 Corberos, Pablo, 2011 “Paraconsistent Vagueness: A Positive
Argument”, Synthese 183(2): 211–227
 Cowles, David W. and Michael J. White, 1991, “Vague Objects for Those Who Want
Them”, Philosophical Studies, 63(2): 203–216.
 Dietz, Richard and Sebastiano Moruzzi (eds.), 2010, Cuts and Clouds: Vagueness, Its
Nature and its Logic, New York: Oxford University Press.
 Dummett, Michael, 1975, “Wang’s Paradox”, Synthese, 30: 301–24.
 Endicott, Timothy, 2000, Vagueness in the Law, New York: Oxford University Press.
 Eklund, Matti, 2011, “Being Metaphysically Unsettled: Barnes and Williams on
Metaphysical Indeterminacy and Vagueness”, Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, vol. 6.
 Evans, Gareth, 1978, “Can there be Vague Objects?”, Analysis, 38: 208.
 Fine, Kit, 1975, “Vagueness, truth and logic”, Synthese, 54: 235–59. Reprinted in Keefe
and Smith (eds.) 1996, 119–150.
 Field, Hartry, 2010, “The Magic Moment” in Dietz, Richard and Sebastiano Moruzzi
(eds.), 2010, Cuts and Clouds: Vagueness, Its Nature and its Logic, New York: Oxford
University Press, 200–08.
 Graff, Delia, 2000, “Shifting sands: an interest-relative theory of
vagueness”, Philosophical Topics, 28: 45–81.
 Graff, Delia and Timothy Williamson (eds.), 2002, Vagueness, Aldershot: Ashgate
Publishing.
 Hu, Ivan, 2017, “Vague at Higher Orders”, Mind, 126.
 Hyde, Dominic and Mark Colyvan, 2008, “Paraconsistent Vagueness: Why
Not?”, Australasian Journal of Logic, 6: 107–121.
 Hyde, Dominic, 2008, Vagueness, Logic and Ontology, Aldershot: Ashgate Publishing
 Kamp, Hans, 1981 “The Paradox of the Heap”, in Uwe Münnich (ed.), 1996, Aspects of
Philosophical Logic, Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 225–77.
 Keefe, Rosanna, 2000, Theories of Vagueness, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
 Keefe, Rosanna, and Peter Smith (eds.), 1996, Vagueness: A Reader, Cambridge: MIT
Press, 119–150.
 Keil, Geert and Ralf Poscher (eds.), 2016, Vaguenes and Law, Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
 Keil, Geert, Lara Keuck and Rico Hauswald (eds.), 2017, Vagueness in Psychiatry,
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
 Lewis, David, 1982, “Logic for Equivocators”, Noûs, 16: 431–441.
 –––, 1988, “Vague Identity: Evans Misunderstood”, Analysis, 48: 128–30.
 –––, 1993, “Many, but almost one”, in Ontology, Causality, and Mind: Essays on the
Philosophy of D.M. Armstrong, Keith Campbell, John Bacon, and Lloyd Reinhardt (eds.),
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
 MacFarlane, John, 2010, “Fuzzy Epistemicism”, in Dietz and Moruzzi (eds.) 2010, 438–
463.
 –––, 2016, “Vagueness as Indecision”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 90: 255–
283.
 Merricks, Trenton, 2001, “Varieties of Vagueness”, Philosophy and Phenomenological
Research, 63: 145–157.
 Parsons, Terence, 2000, Indeterminate Identity: Metaphysics and Semantics,Oxford
University Press.
 Peirce, C.S., 1902, “Vague”, in Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology, J.M. Baldwin
(ed.), New York: MacMillan, 748.
 Plekhanov, Georgi, 1908 [1937], Fundamental Problems of Marxism, E. Paul and C. Paul
(trans.), London: Lawrence and Wishart.
 Poscher, Ralf, 2012, “Ambiguity and Vagueness in Legal Interpretation”, in Lawrence
Solan and Peter Tiersma (eds.), 2012, Oxford Handbook on Language and Law, Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
 Raffman, D., 1996, “Vagueness and context-sensitivity”, Philosophical Studies, 81: 175–
92.
 –––, 2005, “Borderline cases and Bivalence”, Philosophical Review, 114: 1–31.
 Ripley, David, 2011, “Contradiction at the Borders”, Vagueness in Communication, Rick
Nouwen, Robert van Rooij, Uli Sauerland, Hans-Christian Schmitz (eds.), Dordrecht:
Springer: 169–188.
 Russell, Bertrand, 1923, “Vagueness”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy and
Psychology, 1: 84–92.
 Sainsbury, R. M., 1996, “Concepts without boundaries”, Vagueness: A Reader, in Keefe
and Smith (eds.) 1996, 251–264.
 –––, 2013, “Lessons for Vagueness from Scrambled Sorites”, Metaphysica, 14: 225–237.
 Schauer, Frederick, 2016, “Second–Order Vagueness in the Law”, Vagueness and the
Law, in Geert Keil and Ralf Poscher (eds.) Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016, 177–
188.
 Schiffer, Stephen, 2003, The Things we Mean, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
 Shapiro, Stewart, 2006, Vagueness in Context, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
 Smith, Nicholas J. J., 2008, Vagueness and Degrees of Truth, New York: Oxford
University Press.
 Soames, Scott, 1999, Understanding Truth, New York: Oxford University Press.
 –––, 2002, “Precis of Understanding Truth and replies”, Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research, 65: 429–452.
 Sorensen, Roy, 2001, Vagueness and Contradiction, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
 –––, 2010, “Borderline Hermphrodites: Higher Order Vagueness by Example”, Mind,
119: 393–408.
 –––, 2011, “Vague Music”, Philosophy, 86: 231–248.
 –––, 2012, “The Sorites and the Generic Overgeneralization Effect”, Analysis, 201: 42–
47.
 Stanley, Jason, 2003, “Context, interest-relativity, and the sorites”, Analysis, 63: 269–80.
 Sutton, Peter, 2017, “Probabilistic Approaches to Vagueness”, Erkenntnis, 82: 269–80.
 Tye, Michael, 1989, “Supervaluationism and the Law of Excluded Middle”, Analysis,
49(3): 141–143.
 Unger, Peter, 1979, “There are no ordinary things”, Synthese, 4: 117–54.
 van Deemter, Kees, 2010, Not Exactly: In Praise of Vagueness, New York: Oxford
University Press.
 Van Inwagen, Peter, 1990, Material Beings, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
 Varzi, Achille, 2001, “Vagueness in Geography”, Philosophy and Geography, 4: 49–65.
 Waismann, Friedrich, 1968, “Verifiability”, in Logic and Language, Anthony Flex (ed.),
Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
 Weber, Zach and Mark Colyvan, 2010, “A Topological Sorites”, Journal of Philosophy,
107(6): 311–325.
 Williams, J. R. G., 2016, “Vagueness as Indecision”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian
Society, 90: 285–309.
 Williamson, Timothy, 1994, Vagueness, London: Routledge.
 –––, 2015, “Logic and Neutrality”, in Peter Catapano and Simon Critchley (eds.), The
Stone Reader, New York: W. W. Norton, 162–165.
 Wright, Crispin, 2001, “On Being in a Quandary”, Mind, 110: 45–98.
 –––, 2010, “The Illusion of Higher-Order Vagueness”, in Dietz and Moruzzi (eds.) 2010,
523–549.
 Yli-Vakkuri, Juhani, 2016, “Epistemicism and modality”, Canadian Journal of
Philosophy, 46: 803–835.

You might also like