You are on page 1of 12

fate and fatalism

Widerker, David. “Fatalism.” Logique et analyse 119 In the late 1960s, however, as part of a general
(1987): 229–34. resurgence of feminist activism, an unprecedented
John Martin Fischer explosion of feminist ethical debate occurred, first
among the general public, soon in academic dis-course.
Actions and practices whose gendered dimen-sions
hitherto had been either unnoticed or unchal-lenged
feminist ethics now became foci of public and philosophical attention,
Feminist approaches to ethics, often known collec- as feminists subjected them to outspoken moral
tively as feminist ethics, are distinguished by an ex- critique, developed sometimes dramatic strat-egies for
plicit commitment to correcting male biases they opposing them, and proposed alternatives that
perceive in traditional ethics, biases that may be nonfeminists often perceived as dangerously radical.
manifest in rationalizations of women’s subordina- First grassroots and soon academic feminist
tion, or in disregard for, or disparagement of, women’s perspectives were articulated on topics such as
moral experience. Feminist ethics, by con-trast, begins ABORTION, equality of opportunity, domestic labor,
from the convictions that the subordi-nation of women portrayals of women in the media, and a variety of issues
is morally wrong and that the moral experience of concerning sexuality, such as RAPE and com-pulsory
women is as worthy of respect as that of men. On the heterosexuality. By the 1980s, feminists were expressing
practical level, then, the goals of feminist ethics are the ethical concern about PORNOGRA-PHY, reproductive
following: first, to articu-late moral critiques of actions technology, so-called surrogate motherhood, militarism,
and practices that per-petuate women’s subordination; the environment, and the situation of women in
second, to pre-scribe morally justifiable ways of developing nations.
resisting such actions and practices; and, third, to Despite the long history of feminist ethical de-bate,
envision morally desirable alternatives that will the term “feminist ethics” did not come into general
promote women’s emancipation. On the theoretical use until the late 1970s or early 1980s. At this time, a
level, the goal of feminist ethics is to develop number of feminists began expressing doubts about the
philosophical accounts of the nature of morality and of possibility of fruitfully addressing so-called women’s
the central moral concepts that treat women’s moral issues in terms of the conceptual apparatus supplied by
experience re-spectfully, though never uncritically. traditional ethical theory. For instance, some feminists
alleged that a rights frame-work distorted discussions
Just as feminist ethics may be identified by its ex- of abortion because it construed pregnancy and
plicit commitment to challenging perceived male bias motherhood as adversarial situations. Other feminists
in ethics, so approaches that do not express such a charged that certain as-sumptions widely accepted by
commitment may be characterized as non-feminist. traditional ethical the-ory were incompatible with what
Nonfeminist approaches to ethics are not necessarily was now beginning to be claimed as a distinctively
anti-feminist or male-biased; they may or may not be feminine moral ex-perience or sensibility. SOCIAL
so. CONTRACT theory, for instance, was criticized for
postulating a conception of human individuals as
beings who were free, equal, independent, and
The Development of mutually disinterested, a concep-tion that some
Contemporary Feminist Ethics feminists claimed reflected an expe-rience and
The history of Western philosophy includes a perspective that were characteristically masculine.
number of isolated but indisputable instances of moral Even IMPARTIALITY, usually taken as a defining feature
opposition to women’s subordination. Note-worthy of morality, became the object of feminist criticism
examples are Mary WOLLSTONECRAFT’s (1759–1797) A insofar as it was alleged to gener-ate prescriptions
Vindication of the Rights of Woman (1792), JOHN counter to many women’s moral intuitions. Some
STUART MILL’s (1806–1873) The Subjection of Women feminists began to speculate that traditional ethics was
(1869), Frederick ENGELS’ (1820–1895) The Origin of more deeply male-biased and needed more
the Family, Private Property and the State (1884), and fundamental rethinking than they had realized hitherto.
Simone DE BEAU-VOIR’S (1908–1986) The Second Sex
(1949). Such reflection was fueled by the much-publicized

528

[Type text]
feminist ethics

work of developmental psychologist Carol Gilligan, ally masculine image of moral psychology, discour-
whose 1982 book, In a Different Voice: Psycholog- age preoccupation with issues defined culturally as
ical Theory and Women’s Development, seemed to feminine, or in other ways covertly advance men’s
demonstrate empirically that the MORAL DEVELOP-MENT interests over women’s. Since feminism is essentially
of women was significantly different from that of men. a normative stance, and since its meaning is contin-
Claiming that females tend to fear separa-tion or ually contested by feminists themselves, all feminists
abandonment while males, by contrast, tend to perceive are constantly engaged in ethical reflection; in this
closeness as dangerous, Gilligan re-ported that girls and sense, feminist ethics is practiced both inside and
women often construe MORAL DILEMMAS as conflicts of outside the academy. Within the academy, its prac-
responsibilities rather than of RIGHTS and seek to resolve titioners are scholars located mainly in the disci-plines
those dilemmas in ways that will repair and strengthen of philosophy, religious studies, and jurispru-dence;
webs of rela-tionship. Furthermore, Gilligan described they represent a variety of philosophical traditions,
females as less likely than males to make or justify moral secular and religious, Anglo-American and continental
deci-sions by the application of abstract MORAL RULES; European. In challenging perceived male bias in those
instead, she claimed that girls and women were more traditions, feminist scholars often draw extensively on
likely to act on their feelings of LOVE and com-passion for feminist work in other disci-plines, such as literature,
particular individuals. Gilligan con-cluded that whereas history, and PSYCHOLOGY.
men typically adhere to a mo-rality of justice, whose Scholarly work in feminist ethics often is also re-
primary values are FAIRNESS and EQUALITY, women often sponsive to the ethical reflections of nonacademic
adhere to a morality of CARE, whose primary values are feminists as these occur, for instance, in much femi-
inclusion and pro-tection from harm. For this reason, nist fiction and poetry. In addition, a considerable
studies of moral development based exclusively on a body of nonfiction, written by nonacademics and di-
morality of jus-tice do not provide an appropriate rected towards a nonacademic audience, presents it-
standard for mea-suring female moral development and self as feminist ethics. Popular feminist books and
may be said to be male-biased. journals frequently engage in ethical consideration of
moral or PUBLIC POLICY issues and sometimes also offer
more general discussions of supposedly “mas-culine”
Many feminists seized on Gilligan’s work as of- and “feminine” value systems.
fering evidence for the existence of a characteristi- Much of the work in feminist ethics has been done
cally feminine approach to morality, an approach by white Western women, but this is slowly changing.
assumed to provide the basis for a distinctively femi- A few male philosophers are doing signifi-cant work
nist ethics. For some, indeed, feminist ethics became in feminist ethics, and people of color are making
and remained synonymous with an ethics of care. Just increasing contributions, both within and outside the
how an ethics of care should be delineated, how-ever, discipline of philosophy, although they sometimes
was far from evident; nor was it clear whether it hesitate to accept the label “feminist,” be-cause of
should supplement or supplant an ethics of justice. feminism’s racist history.
Since the 1980s, many feminists have explored such
questions, even though the empirical connection be-
tween women and care has been challenged by some Feminist Criticisms of Western Ethics
psychologists, who allege Gilligan’s samples to be Since most feminist ethics is done in a Western
nonrepresentative, her methods of interpreting her data context, it is Western ethics, particularly (though not
suspect, and her claims impossible to substan-tiate, exclusively) the European Enlightenment tradition,
especially when the studies are controlled for that has been the most frequent target of feminist
occupation and class. critique. The feminist challenges to this tradition may
Regardless of empirical findings in MORAL PSY- be grouped conveniently under five main headings.
CHOLOGY, debate continues over whether the fun- Lack of concern for women’s interests. Many of the
damental tenets of Western ethics are male biased in major theorists, such as ARISTOTLE (384–322 B.C.E.) and
some sense: if not in the sense that they express a moral ROUSSEAU (1712–1778), are accused of having given
sensibility characteristic of men rather than women, then insufficient consideration to women’s INTERESTS, a lack of
perhaps in that they promote a cultur- concern expressed theoretically

529

[Type text]
feminist ethics

by their prescribing for women allegedly feminine culine,” insofar as they are culturally associated with
virtues such as obedience, silence, and faithfulness. men. Such associations may be empirical, norma-tive,
Some feminists charge that many contemporary eth- or symbolic. For instance, Western ethics is al-leged to
ical discussions continue the tendency to regard prioritize the supposedly masculine values of
women as instrumental to male-dominated INSTI- independence, autonomy, intellect, will, wariness,
TUTIONS, such as the FAMILY or the state; in debates on hierarchy, domination, culture, transcendence, prod-
abortion, for instance, the pregnant woman may be uct, asceticism, war, and death over the supposedly
portrayed as little more than a container or en-vironment feminine values of interdependence, community,
for the fetus, while much discussion of reproductive connection, sharing, EMOTION, body, TRUST, absence of
technology has assumed that infertility is a problem only hierarchy, nature, immanence, process, joy, peace, and
for heterosexual married women, i.e., women defined in life. Claims like this are common in both pop-ular and
relationship to men.
academic feminist writings on ethics.
Neglect of “women’s issues.” Issues of special
Devaluation of women’s moral experience. Fi-nally,
concern to women are said to have been ignored by
some feminists also charge that prevailing Western
modern moral philosophers, who have tended to
conceptualizations of the nature of moral-ity, moral
portray the domestic realm as an arena outside the
problems, and MORAL REASONING are masculine insofar
economy and beyond justice, private in the sense of
being beyond the scope of legitimate political regu- as they too are associated with men, rather than
lation. Within the modern liberal tradition, the pub-lic women, in associations that again may be empirical,
domain is conceived as properly regulated by uni- symbolic, or normative. For in-stance, feminists have
versal principles of right whereas the private is a accused modern moral theory of being excessively
domain in which varying goods may properly be pur- preoccupied with rules, ob-sessed with impartiality,
sued. Even philosophers like Aristotle or HEGEL (1770– and exclusively focussed on discrete deeds. In
1831), who give some ethical importance to the addition, feminists have charged modern moral theory
domestic realm, have tended to portray the home as an with taking the contract as the paradigmatic moral
arena in which the most fully human excel-lences relation and construing moral rationality so narrowly
cannot be realized. Feminist philosophers be-gan early as to exclude emotions of as-sessment, sometimes
to criticize this conceptual bifurcation of social life. called moral emotions. All these characteristics have
They pointed out that the home was pre-cisely that been asserted to be mas-culine in some sense. A
realm to which women had been confined historically, feminine (not feminist) ap-proach to ethics, by
and that it had become symbolically as-sociated with contrast, has been supposed to avoid assuming that
the feminine, despite the fact that heads of households individuals ordinarily are free, equal, and independent;
were paradigmatically male. They argued that the to take more account of the specificities of particular
philosophical devaluation of the domestic realm made contexts; and to be more likely to resolve moral
it impossible to raise ques-tions about the justice of the dilemmas by relying on em-pathic feeling rather than
domestic division of labor, because it obscured the far- by appealing to rules.
reaching social sig-nificance and creativity of women’s
Not all feminists endorse all of the above clusters of
work in the home, and concealed, even legitimated, the
criticisms—and even where they agree with the
domestic abuse of women and girls.
general statement, they may well disagree over its
applicability in the case of specific philosophers or
Denial of women’s moral agency. Women’s moral
debates. Despite differences of relative detail, femi-
agency is said to have often been denied, not simply by
excluding women from moral debate or ignoring their nists tend generally to agree on the first three clus-ters
contributions, but through philosoph-ical claims to the of criticisms, whose correction seems not only
effect that women lack moral rea-son. Such claims attainable in principle within the framework of En-
were made originally by Aristotle, but they have been lightenment moral theory but even to be required by
elaborated and refined by mod-ern theorists such as that framework. However, they disagree sharply on the
Rousseau, KANT (1724–1804), Hegel, and Freud last two clusters of criticisms, especially the fifth,
(1856–1939). which obviously contains clear parallels with a num-
Depreciation of “feminine” values. Western moral ber of nonfeminist criticisms of Enlightenment ethics
theory is said to embody values that are “mas- made by proponents of, for example, SITUATION

530

[Type text]
feminist ethics

ETHICS, VIRTUE ETHICS, COMMUNITARIANISM, and child care and abortion has significant consequences
POSTMODERNISM. for the lives of men as well as women. On the other
hand, since men and women typically are not what
lawyers call “similarly situated” relative to each other,
Common Misconstruals of Feminist Ethics
it is difficult to think of any moral or public policy
Feminist ethics has sometimes been construed, both (“human”) issue in which women do not have a special
by some of its proponents and some of its crit-ics, as a interest. For instance, such “human” issues as war,
simple inversion of the criticisms listed above. In other peace, and world hunger have special signif-icance for
words, it has sometimes been iden-tified with one or women because the world’s hungry are
more of the following: putting women’s interests first; disproportionately women (and children), because
focusing exclusively on so-called women’s issues; women are primarily those in need of the social ser-
accepting women (or femi-nists) as moral experts or vices neglected to fund military spending, and be-
authorities; substituting “female” (or feminine) for cause women suffer disproportionately from war and
“male” (or masculine) values; or extrapolating directly benefit relatively little from militarism and the
from women’s moral experience. These weapons industries. For these reasons, it would be a
characterizations of feminist ethics are sufficiently mistake to identify feminist ethics with attention to
pervasive that it is worth noting just why they cannot some explicitly gendered subset of ethical issues. On
be correct. the contrary, rather than being limited to a re-stricted
1. Putting women’s interests first occasionally has ethical domain, feminist ethics has enlarged the
been recommended as a way of achieving a “woman- traditional concerns of ethics, both through identifying
centered” ethics that transcends the covert bias of a previously unrecognized ethical issues and by
supposed HUMANISM grounded in fact on male NORMS. introducing fresh perspectives on issues al-ready
Whatever might be said for or against this acknowledged as having an ethical dimension.
recommendation, it cannot be definitive of feminist ethics 3. Feminist ethics certainly is being developed by
because the formula, as it stands, raises more questions feminists, most of whom are women, but this does not
than it answers. It fails to specify not only which imply, of course, that any woman, or even any
women’s interests should be preferred over which men’s feminist, should be regarded as a moral expert whose
(or children’s) and in what circum-stances, but also what moral AUTHORITY is beyond question. Not only are
should be done about con-flicts of interest between there deep disagreements among women and even
women and even how in-terests should be identified at among feminists such that it would be dif-ficult to
all. Most obviously, feminist ethics cannot be identified know whom to select as an expert, but many painful
with “putting women’s interests first” simply because examples of failed insight or principle on the part of
many femi-nists would refuse to accept and, indeed, be feminist leaders demonstrate only too clearly that no
morally outraged by what they would perceive as blatant woman, or feminist, is morally infallible.
PARTIALITY and immorality. 4. There are also serious difficulties with thinking
of feminist ethics as the substitution of female or
2. Feminist ethics certainly addresses issues of feminine for male or masculine values. These diffi-
special concern to women that have been neglected by culties include problems with establishing that any
modern moral theory, but it cannot be identified with values are male or female in the sense of being gen-
an exclusive focus on such issues. This is partly erally held by men or women, when both women’s and
because nonfeminists as well as feminists have ad- men’s values vary so much, both within cultures as
dressed these issues—and, indeed, are doing so in- well as across them. Similar problems confront
creasingly as feminism grows stronger and more ar- attempts to establish that certain values are mascu-line
ticulate. It is also because feminism rejects the notion or feminine in the sense of being considered so-cially
that moral issues can be divided cleanly into those that appropriate for individuals of one gender or the other.
are and those that are not of special con-cern to Again, norms of masculinity and feminin-ity vary not
women. On the one hand, since men’s and women’s only between societies but even within the same
lives are inextricably intertwined, there are no society along such axes as class and eth-nicity: some
“women’s issues” that are not also men’s issues; for social groups, for instance, value physi-cal health,
instance, the availability or nonavailability of strength, or athletic prowess in women;

531

[Type text]
feminist ethics

others value physical fragility, weakness, or incom- are situated similarly with some men in specific re-
petence. Even if certain values could be identified in spects or contexts. In addition, not only does femi-nist
some sense as male or female, masculine or femi-nine, ethics need constant vigilance to detect subtle as well
the conclusive objection to identifying feminist ethics as blatant manifestations of gender privilege, it must
with the elaboration of female or feminine val-ues is also be sensitive to the ways in which gen-dered norms
that the feminine is not necessarily the femi-nist. are different for different groups of women—or in
Indeed, since the feminine typically has been which the same norms, such as a cul-tural preference
constructed in circumstances of male domination, it is for slimness or blondness, affect dif-ferent groups of
likely to be quite opposed to the feminist. Personal women differently. Ultimately fem-inism’s concern for
charm, for example, may be valued not only in women all women means that feminist ethics must address not
but also by them; even if charm were, in these senses, a only “local” issues of racism or homophobia or class
feminine value, however, it would seem at least as privilege but also such global issues as environmental
likely to undermine feminist goals as to promote them. destruction, war, and access to world resources.

5. Similar problems apply to defining feminist 2. In order to develop guides to action that will tend
ethics as the systematic extrapolation of women’s to subvert rather than reinforce the systematic
moral experience, exclusive of men’s. While no ap- subordination of women, feminist approaches to ethics
proach to morality can be adequate if it ignores the must understand individual actions in the context of
moral experience of women, it is most unlikely that broader social practices, evaluating the symbolic and
women generally are similar enough to each other and cumulative implications of individual ACTION as well as
different enough from men that a single distinc-tively its immediately observable con-sequences. They must be
female or feminine approach to ethics can be equipped to recognize co-vert as well as overt
identified. Attempts to establish such an identifica-tion manifestations of domination, subtle as well as blatant
frequently commit the fallacy of generalizing about the forms of control, and they must develop sophisticated
experience of all or most women from the moral accounts of COERCION and CONSENT. Similarly, they must
experience of some women; this seems to have been provide the con-ceptual resources for identifying and
one flaw at least in Gilligan’s earlier work. Again, evaluating the varieties of resistance and struggle in
even if a distinctively feminine approach to morality which women, particularly, have engaged. They must
could be identified, perhaps in terms of symbolic or recognize the often unnoticed ways in which women and
normative connections with women rather than other members of the underclass have refused cooperation
empirical ones, there is no reason to sup-pose that such and opposed domination, while acknowledging the
an approach would be feminist. In-deed, given the inevitability of collusion and the impossibility of to-tally
feminist commitment to a critical rethinking of cultural clean hands. In short, feminist approaches to ethics must
constructions of both mascu-linity and femininity, be transitional and nonutopian, often extensions of, rather
there is good prima facie rea-son to suppose that it than alternatives to, feminist political theory, exercises in
would not. non-ideal rather than ideal theory.

Minimum Conditions of Adequacy


3. Since most of most women’s lives have been
for Feminist Ethics
excluded from that domain conceptualized as pub-lic, a
Even though feminist ethics is far broader and more third requirement for feminist approaches to ethics is
open than it appears in the foregoing miscon-struals, its that they should be salient to issues of so-called private
goals are sufficiently specific, especially when taken in life, such as intimate relations, sexu-ality, and child
conjunction with its criticisms of tra-ditional ethics, as rearing. Thus, they must articulate the moral
to generate certain minimum con-ditions of adequacy dimensions of issues that may not hitherto have been
for any approach to ethics that purports to be feminist. recognized as moral. In addition, we have seen that
feminist approaches to ethics must provide appropriate
1. First of all, feminist ethics can never begin by guidance for dealing with national and international
assuming that women and men are similarly situ- issues, strangers and foreigners. In de-veloping the
ated—although it may discover that some women conceptual tools for undertaking these

532

[Type text]
feminist ethics

tasks, feminist ethics cannot assume that moral con- ethics can never be identified in terms of a specific
cepts developed originally for application to the so- range of topics, methods, or orthodoxies. While
called public realm, concepts such as impartiality or feminist ethics is distinguished by its explicit com-
EXPLOITATION, are appropriate for use in the so-called mitment to developing approaches to ethics that will
private; neither can it assume that concepts such as care, respect women’s moral experience and avoid ration-
developed in intimate relationships, will necessarily be alizing women’s subordination, attempts to define it
helpful in the larger world. In-deed, the whole distinction more precisely or substantively than this are likely to
between public and pri-vate life must be examined disregard the richness and variety of feminist moral
critically by feminist ethics, with no prior assumptions as thinking and prematurely foreclose feminist moral
to whether the distinction should be retained, redrawn, or debates.
rejected.
4. Finally, feminist ethics must take the moral ex-
perience of all women seriously, though not, of course, Current Concerns in Feminist Ethics
uncritically. Although what is feminist often will turn Since the 1970s, feminists have made significant
out to be very different from what is fem-inine, a basic contributions to both practical and theoretical ethics.
respect for women’s moral experience is necessary to Because it is impossible to offer anything like a com-
acknowledging women’s capacities as moral subjects prehensive survey of this work in the space avail-able,
and to countering traditional stereo-types of women as this article will end by sketching a few illustra-tive
less than full moral agents, as childlike or close to examples of feminist work designed to counter male
nature. Furthermore, empirical claims about bias in ethics. Much of this work draws on the
differences in the moral sensibility of women and men culturally feminine as a resource for reconceiving eth-
make it impossible to assume that any approach to ical norms or standards thought to be androcentric.
ethics will be unanimously accepted if it fails to Giving equal weight to women’s interests. Eigh-
consult the moral experience of women. Additionally, teenth and nineteenth century feminist philosophers,
it seems plausible to suppose that women’s distinctive such as Mary Wollstonecraft and John Stuart Mill,
social experience may make them especially responded to the fact that Western ethics had often
perceptive regarding the implica-tions of domination, accorded less weight to women’s interests than to
especially gender domination, and especially well men’s by demanding that women receive the same
equipped to detect the male bias that feminists believe rights and privileges bestowed on men. They con-
has pervaded so much of male-authored Western ceptualized sexual equality as formal equality; that is,
moral theory. as identity of treatment for both men and women under
Most feminist, and perhaps even many nonfem- gender-blind laws. Their twentieth-century successors
inist, philosophers might well find the general state- sought to enshrine this understanding of sexual
ment of these conditions quite uncontroversial, but equality in the U.S. Constitution via an Equal Rights
they will inevitably disagree sharply over when the Amendment (passed by Congress in 1972, it was not
conditions have been met. Not only may feminists ratified by the minimum number of states) that would
disagree with nonfeminists, but they are likely even to have made any sex specific law uncon-stitutional.
differ with each other over, for instance, what are
women’s interests, what are manifestations of domi- Formal equality does not necessarily result in sub-
nation and coercion, how resistance should be ex- stantive equality, however. Feminist work in practi-cal
pressed, and which aspects of women’s moral expe- ethics is characterized by its use of gender as a
rience are worth developing and in which directions. category of ethical analysis and its employment of this
Those who practice feminist ethics thus may be category has revealed that many formally gender-blind
seen both as united by a shared project and as di- policies and practices are not gender-neutral in their
verging widely in their views as to how this project outcomes but instead have a disproportion-ately
may be accomplished. Their divergences result from a negative impact on women. Many illustrations could
variety of philosophical differences, including dif- be added to the examples of war, peace, and world
fering conceptions of feminism itself, which, as we hunger, noted above; for instance, women, es-pecially
have seen, is a constantly contested concept. The poor women, are among those hardest hit by
inevitability of such divergence means that feminist seemingly gender-blind economic policies, such

533

[Type text]
feminist ethics

as structural adjustment measures; similarly, envi- normative individual who is taken as the standard
ronmental degradation often has more serious con- against which others’ equality is measured. These
sequences for women, especially for mothers, than it feminists argue that equal concern for women’s in-
does for men. Such systematically gendered out-comes terests requires reassessing major social institutions on
suggest that construing sexual equality in purely the presumption that their users are likely to be
formal terms may be inadequate for reaching women—including women who are not otherwise
substantive sexual equality. Because norms of gen-der privileged. The revised institutions would still be
situate women differently from men in most so-cial formally gender-blind but they would not be de-signed
contexts across the world, substantive equality may primarily for people who were able-bodied and fully
require establishing policies and practices that are employed, people unlikely to be subjected to sexual
gender-sensitive or gender-responsive rather than assault or harassment, people without re-sponsibilities
gender-blind. for the primary care of dependents such as children or
Formulating policies and practices that respond elders. For instance, they might offer workers paid
appropriately to gender differences is controversial and leaves to enable them to care for family members or
complicated. For instance, providing women with they might provide child care on the same basis as
special legal protections such as pregnancy and public schooling. If social policies and practices were
maternity leaves may promote a public perception that revised according to a principle of what Christine A.
women are less reliable workers than men. At-tempts Littleton calls “equality of ac-ceptance,” sex
to protect women’s sexuality by restricting differences could become socially “costless.”
pornography or excluding women from employment in
male institutions such as prisons may have the Broadening the domain of ethics. In response to
unintended consequence of perpetuating the cultural their recognition that mainstream, especially mod-ern,
myth that women are by nature the sexual prey of men; Western ethics has defined the moral domain in such a
by suggesting that sexual harassment and as-sault are way as to exclude many issues of special con-cern to
in some sense natural, this myth implicitly legitimates women, contemporary feminists have sought to expand
these practices. Thus, gender-responsive the ethical arena. In some cases, their questions have
interpretations of sexual equality may not only pro- generated whole new bodies of re-search, such as
voke an anti-feminist backlash, they may even un- feminist environmentalism and femi-nist BIOETHICS.
dermine the prospects of long-term sexual equality by Issues that feminists have identified as morally
stigmatizing women’s competences. In addition, problematic include: abortion; sexuality, including
although gender-responsive conceptions of equality are compulsory heterosexuality, sexual harass-ment, and
intended to reflect sensitivity to differences in the rape; representations of masculinity and femininity,
circumstances of men and women in general, they are including those produced by the MASS MEDIA and
sometimes insensitive to differences in the social pornography; the domestic division of labor; self-
situations of different women. They may fail to no-tice presentation, including body image and fashion; and the
that broad social groups, like men and women, are role of language in reinforcing as well as reflecting
characterized by internal differences that are sys- women’s subordination. Although these issues received
tematic as well as individual, following the fault lines little attention from mainstream ethics until recent years,
of other social divisions such as race and class. Thus, all have significant impli-cations for women’s lives, to the
these conceptions are sometimes responsive to gen- extent that they sometimes involve matters of life and
dered differences in need that are characteristic of only death for women. As noted earlier, feminists resist
some men and women but not of all; often those taken character-izing such issues as exclusively women’s
as paradigms are men and women from more issues; in-stead, by presenting them as hitherto neglected
privileged classes; for instance, a feminist demand that hu-man issues, they broaden previous conceptions of
child care be provided for mothers in paid em- normative human experience.
ployment may be used to discredit other mothers’
claims to welfare support. Rethinking the moral subject. Feminists’ first re-
Some contemporary feminists seek to avoid the sponse to Western philosophy’s disparagement of
horns of the so-called equality/difference dilemma by women’s moral subjectivity was to insist on women’s
questioning its underlying assumptions about the capacity for moral autonomy and rationality, soon,

534

[Type text]
feminist ethics

however, they began to question prevailing under- and sexual capacities, and that it is expressed in
standings of autonomy, rationality, and even subjec- women’s traditional assignments for biological re-
tivity. With respect to autonomy, for instance, femi- production and bodily maintenance. They see West-ern
nist concern about women’s collaborations with male philosophy’s symbolic association of women with the
dominance and consequent interest in the so-cial body as not only reflecting but also rationalizing and
construction of gendered character structures provided reinforcing these unjust social arrangements.
insight into many ways in which choice can be Attention to human embodiment has implica-tions
socialized and consent manipulated. Some femi-nists for moral psychology. The identity of embodied moral
have faulted much modern moral philosophy for subjects is constituted in part by specific so-cial
failing to recognize that autonomy cannot be as-sumed relations, and these, in turn, are partially deter-mined
but instead is an achievement with complex material by the social meanings attached to bodily
and social preconditions. characteristics such as parentage, age, or sex. Rec-
Conceptions of moral subjectivity that privilege ognizing human embodiment explains why moral
autonomy are especially characteristic of the Euro- subjects are often motivated more by considerations of
pean Enlightenment; they derive from the Cartesian particular attachment than by abstract concern for duty,
model of the self as disembodied, asocial, unified, more by care than by respect, and more by
rational, and essentially similar to all other selves. In responsibility than by right. Some feminists have ar-
developing alternatives to this conception, some gued that devaluing the body in comparison with the
feminists have drawn on traditions such as M ARX-ISM, mind has turned moral theorists’ attention away from
PSYCHOANALYSIS, communitarianism and post- bodily related differences among individuals, such as
modernism; others have been influenced by the work of age, sex, and ability, and encouraged them to regard
Carol Gilligan, who postulated that girls and women were people as indistinguishable and inter-changeable. They
more likely than boys and men to con-ceive themselves in further contend that disparaging the body has
relational terms. Viewing one-self as integrally related to encouraged ethical theory to ignore many fundamental
others is said to promote systematically different moral aspects of human life and to posit ideals unattainable
preoccupations from those that have characterized much by human beings.
mainstream Western ethics, particularly modern ethics; Philosophical reflection that begins from the body
for in-stance, such a view of the self encourages women tends to give prominence to aspects of human nature
to construe moral dilemmas as conflicts of responsi- that are very different from those emphasized by
bilities rather than rights. Many feminist philoso-phers Cartesianism; for instance, it highlights temporality
argue that a relational conception of moral subjectivity is and situatedness rather than timelessness and non-
not only more adequate empirically than an atomistic locatedness, growth and decay rather than change-
model but that it also generates moral values and a lessness, particularity rather than universality, soci-
conception of moral rationality that are superior to those ality rather than isolation. Reflection on these features
characteristic of the En-lightenment. For instance, it reveals that INEQUALITY, dependence and
encourages women to seek resolutions to conflicts by interdependence, specificity, social embeddedness, and
means that promise to repair and strengthen relationships, historical community must be recognized as per-
to practice positive caretaking rather than respectful manent features of human social life. They generate
noninter-vention, and to prioritize the personal values of ethical problems that cannot be adequately ad-dressed
care, trust, attentiveness, and love for particular others by developing highly idealized conceptions of
above impersonal principles of equality, respect, and equality, LIBERTY, autonomy, and impartiality or that
rights. posit isolated individuals, ideal communities, or some
supposedly universal human condition.
The features of human subjectivity emphasized by
Feminist dissatisfaction with the Enlightenment many feminist philosophers are precisely those that
conception of moral subjectivity springs partly from an Western culture associates with women and the
interest in the body, which many feminists regard as feminine; they are features that tend to preoccupy
key to women’s subordination. Some argue that this women in virtue of their social situation, they are
subordination is maintained by male control of culturally defined as appropriate to women, or they are
women’s bodies, especially women’s procreative associated symbolically with women. However,

535

[Type text]
feminist ethics

to point to these features of human subjectivity is not but also by the working classes, especially, in most of
to imply that the paradigm moral subject should be a the West, by people of colour. This analysis of the
woman rather than a man, or even culturally feminine social genesis of care thinking fits well with Law-rence
rather than culturally masculine. Instead, it is to Blum’s argument that justice ethics expresses a
suggest that previous conceptions of human juridical-administrative perspective that is indeed
subjectivity have often provided understandings and masculine but reflects the concerns specifically of men
ideals of both women and men that are partial and from the professional and administrative classes.
distorted. Together, these arguments suggest that both the ethics
Revaluing the feminine. Feminists have fre-quently of justice and the ethics of care express moral
responded to Western philosophy’s dispar-agement of perspectives that are not only gendered but simulta-
what it has constructed as feminine by insisting that the neously characteristic of different races and classes.
feminine should be revalued. We have observed Feminist philosophers are divided about the po-
already that feminist ethics cannot be identified with tential of care ethics. One concern is that it may be
feminine ethics but we have also seen that ways of insufficiently sensitive to the characteristically fem-
thinking that are culturally feminine may point toward inine moral failing of self-sacrifice; another is that its
less biased and more adequate ap-proaches to ethics. emphasis on meeting the immediately perceived needs
Some feminists regard the ethics of care as a case in of particular individuals may lead agents to show
point. unfair partiality to those closest to them. There also
The first articulations of the ethics of care repre- exist concerns about whether care’s character-istic
sented it as an expression of women’s characteristic focus on the details of small-scale situations can
experience of nurturing or mothering particular oth-ers, address problems that are rooted in social struc-tures;
but later studies had difficulty confirming a clear such a focus may encourage what are some-times
empirical link between women and caring. When called band aid or social work approaches to moral
subjects were matched for education and occupa-tion, problems rather than attempts to address them through
women often achieved almost identical scores with institutional changes. For these and other reasons,
men on justice-oriented tests of moral devel-opment, some feminists doubt that care ethics provides
leaving women who worked in the home as the main resources capable of adequately critiquing male
representatives of the care perspective; moreover, dominance in both public and private life.
some men as well as women were found to employ Despite these problems, many philosophers are
care thinking. Recent advocates of an ethics of care continuing to draw on care’s “feminine” insights and
acknowledge not only that some women think in terms values to develop alternative and more feminist ap-
of justice and some men in terms of care, but also that proaches to democratic theory, to social and eco-nomic
most people of each sex are able to adopt either policy, and to international relations. Rather than
perspective. Nevertheless, they still view care as dismissing the claims of justice, such ap-proaches
feminine on the grounds that it emerges from forms of typically seek to reinterpret them within a framework
socialization and practice that, in contemporary of care. Their goal is to reconceptualize social and
Western society, are culturally feminine; these include even global institutions so that they will enable and
nursing, maintaining a home, raising children, and reinforce caring relations among people.
tending to the elderly. Caring is also feminine in the Building on women’s moral experience. The ethics
symbolic or normative sense of expressing cultural of care is often represented as an approach to ethics
expectations that women be more empathic, altruistic, that is based on women’s moral experience; however,
nurturant, and sensitive than men. it has been presented here as an ethical revaluation of
the culturally feminine. To illustrate ethical initiatives
Some feminists have associated the ethics of care that are based on women’s moral experience, let us
not only with gender but also with race and class. Joan consider instead some recent femi-nist reinterpretations
Tronto links the moral perspective of care with the of HUMAN RIGHTS.
work of cleaning up after body functions, tasks that in The concept of rights was central to the emer-gence
Western history have been relegated primar-ily to of Western feminism but, because rights are central in
women but not to all women or to women exclusively; most modern versions of the so-called jus-tice
caring work is done not only by women tradition, some contemporary feminists have

536

[Type text]
feminist ethics

dismissed them as reflections of a moral perspective in the currently burgeoning global feminist move-
that is characteristically masculine. These feminists ment, which is united by the slogan, “Women’s rights
regard rights as expressing an inherently adversarial are human rights.” This movement calls not simply for
morality that disparages the more basic and impor-tant enforcing women’s human rights but for radically
human values of interdependence, cooperation, and rethinking how human rights have been conceived.
trust. Some contend that appeals to rights may Many feminist proposals for reinterpret-ing rights
rationalize male POWER over women; for example, the begin by recognizing that violations of women’s rights
right to freedom of expression may justify mi-sogynist are more often carried out by non-state than by state
pornography. Others observe that legal equality of actors—often by male family members—and that they
rights may obscure inequalities of power to exercise occur in the private as well as the public sphere. This
them, noting that the procedures asso-ciated with recognition requires ex-panding the definition of state
claiming and redressing rights are often degrading, sanctioned repression to include acceptance of family
intimidating, and humiliating for women, especially in
forms in which brides are sold and in which fathers
trials for rape and sexual harassment. Still other
and husbands exert strict control over women’s
feminists argue that focusing on rights ignores the
sexuality, dress, speech, and movement; it also
ways in which women may be compelled by their
requires redefining SLAVERY to include forced domestic
social situations to exercise their rights in a manner
labour and prostitution. Because some violations of
that is harmful to them, for instance, by “choosing”
human rights take gender-specific forms, the definition of
prostitution or cosmetic surgery. In short, some
war crimes must be expanded to include systematic rape
feminists charge that rights talk may often be not only and sexual TORTURE. Similarly, the definition of GENOCIDE
unhelpful to women but even rationalize their must be expanded to include female IN-FANTICIDE; the
inequality. systematic withholding of food, medi-cal care, and
It is certainly true that appeals to rights have had education from girls; and the battery, starvation,
only limited success in promoting women’s equality. mutilation, and even murder of adult women. Feminists
The United Nations identifies three categories or have also noted that women’s rights are often indivisible
“generations” of rights, including civil, political, eco- from each other; for in-stance, many violations of
nomic, social, and cultural rights and, in each of these women’s civic and politi-cal rights are made possible by
categories, abuses to women are often still ne-glected women’s economic vulnerability. Fully protecting
or excused. Either women are seen as iden-tical to women’s human rights requires changing not only laws
men, so that substantive equality is equated with but also ECONOMIC SYSTEMS and cultural practices.
formal equality, ignoring salient differences be-tween
the social situations of men and women; or women are
seen as “other,” inherently different from men, so that In the above examples, women’s gender-specific
abuses of their rights have been rep-resented as experiences have served as a resource for identifying
“normal,” “natural,” or “inevitable.” covert male biases lurking in existing definitions of
Despite continuing systematic abuse and subor- human rights and as a model for revising those def-
dination of women, some feminists still believe that initions. However, to imagine the normative bearer of
the rights tradition constitutes a valuable resource for rights as a woman rather than a man is not to replace
women’s liberation. For instance, rights may be male with female bias. Because women are vastly
interpreted to take account of morally salient differ- overrepresented among the poor and illiterate of the
ences among rights holders and they may be as-signed world and among those most vulnerable to oppressive
to groups as well as individuals. They may include systems of power, this image instead ex-poses the false
“positive” as well as “negative” rights, which are humanism of older conceptions of human rights; it
“ENTITLEMENTS“ rather than liberties and carry claims also points toward new understand-ings of rights that
not only to noninterference but also to cor-relative are more inclusive and fully human.
duties on the part of others. Such rights may be
thought of as embodying the supposedly feminine The global movement for women’s human rights
values of interdependence, social co-operation, and provides a final illustration of the trajectory followed
care. by much feminist ethics; beginning by criticizing the
Faith in the concept of rights is certainly evident exclusion of women and DISCRIMINATION against

537

[Type text]
feminist ethics

them, it moves to challenging the covert male bias of ———. The Unnatural Lottery: Character and Moral
existing ethical frameworks, and finally draws on the Luck. Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1996.
culturally feminine to propose more ethically ad- ———, ed. Feminist Ethics. Lawrence: University Press of
Kansas, 1991.
equate norms and standards.
———. Feminist Ethics and Politics. Lawrence: Univer-sity
See also: ABORTION; AGENCY AND DISABILITY; AUTONOMY Press of Kansas, 1999.
OF MORAL AGENTS; BIOETHICS; CARE; CHILDREN AND ETHICAL Clements, Grace. Care, Autonomy and Justice. Boulder, CO:
THEORY; COERCION; COM-MUNITARIANISM; CONSENT; Westview, 1996.
CULTURAL STUDIES; DE BEAUVOIR; DISCRIMINATION; DUTY de Beauvoir, Simone. The Second Sex. New York: Bantam
1964 [1949].
AND OBLIGA-TION; EMOTION; ENGELS; ENTITLEMENTS;
Diquinzio, Patrice, and Iris Marion Young, eds. Feminist
ENVIRON-MENTAL ETHICS; EQUALITY; EXPLOITATION; FAMILY;
Ethics and Social Policy. Bloomington and Indianap-olis:
FIDELITY; FRIENDSHIP; GAY ETHICS; HOMOSEXUAL-ITY; HUMAN Indiana University Press, 1997.
RIGHTS; INEQUALITY; LESBIAN ETHICS; LIBERTY; LITERATURE Friedman, Marilyn. What Are Friends For? Feminist Per-
AND ETHICS; MASS MEDIA; JOHN STUART MILL; MORAL spectives on Personal Relationships and Moral Theory.
ATTENTION; MORAL DE-VELOPMENT; MORAL IMAGINATION; Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1993.
MORAL PSY-CHOLOGY; MULTICULTURALISM; NARRATIVE Gilligan, Carol. In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory
ETHICS; NURSING ETHICS; OPPRESSION; PARTIALITY; PATER-
and Women’s Development. Cambridge: Harvard Uni-
versity Press, 1982.
NALISM; PERSONAL RELATIONSHIPS; PORNOGRAPHY;
Griffiths, Morwenna. Feminisms and the Self: The Web of
POSTMODERNISM; PSYCHOANALYSIS; PUBLIC AND PRI-VATE
Identity. New York and London: Routledge, 1995.
MORALITY; PUBLIC HEALTH POLICY; PUBLIC POLICY; RACISM
Held, Virginia. Feminist Morality: Transforming Culture,
AND RELATED ISSUES; REPRODUC-TIVE TECHNOLOGIES; Society, and Politics. Chicago: University of Chicago
RESPONSIBILITY; RIGHT HOLD-ERS; SELF AND SOCIAL SELF; Press, 1993.
SELF-OWNERSHIP; SEX-UAL ABUSE AND HARASSMENT; ———, ed. Justice and Care: Essential Readings in Femi-
SEXUALITY AND nist Ethics. Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1995.
Hoagland, Sarah Lucia. Lesbian Ethics: Toward New Value.
¨ Palo Alto, CA: Institute of Lesbian Studies, 1988.
;S ;T ;
SEXUAL ETHICS TAEL HOMSON WELFARE RIGHTS AND
SOCIAL POLICY;
WOLLSTONECRAFT; WOMEN MORAL Jaggar, Alison M. “Caring as a Feminist Practice of Moral
PHILOSOPHERS; WORK.
Reason.” In Justice and Care: Essential Readings in
Feminist Ethics, edited by Virginia Held. Boulder:
Westview, 1995.
Bibliography Kabeer, Naila. Reversed Realities: Gender Hierarchies in
Development Thought. New York: Verso, 1995.
Addelson, Kathryn Pyne. Moral Passsages: Toward a Col- Kittay, Eva Feder. Love’s Labor: Essays on Women, Equal-
lectivist Moral Theory. New York: Routledge, 1994. ity, and Dependency. London and New York: Rout-ledge,
Baier, Annette C. Moral Prejudices: Essays on Ethics. 1999.
Cambridge and London: Harvard University Press, 1994. Kittay, Eva Feder, and Diana T. Meyers, eds. Women and
Moral Theory. Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield,
Bar On, Bat-Ami, and Ann Ferguson, eds. Daring to be 1987.
Good: Essays in Feminist Ethico-Politics. London and Littleton, Christine A., “Reconstructing Sexual Equality.”
New York: Routledge, 1998. California Law Review 75:4 (1987): 1279.
Benhabib, Seyla. Situating the Self: Gender, Community and Meyers, Diana Tietjens. Self, Society and Personal Choice.
Postmodernism in Contemporary Ethics. New York: New York: Columbia University Press, 1989.
Routledge, 1992. ———, ed. Feminists Rethink the Self. Boulder, CO:
Blum, Lawrence A. “Kant’s and Hegel’s Moral Rational- Westview, 1997.
ism: A Feminist Perspective.” Canadian Journal of Phi- Mies, Maria, and Vandana Shiva. Ecofeminism. London:
losophy 12:2 (1982): 287–302. Zed Press, 1993.
Bowden, Peta. Caring: Gender-Sensitive Ethics. London Mill, John Stuart, and Harriet Taylor Mill. Essays on Sex
and New York: Routledge, 1997. Equality. Edited, and with an introductory essay, by Alice
Calhoun, Cheshire. “Justice, Care, Gender Bias.” Journal of Rossi. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970 [1832,
Philosophy 85:9 (1988). 1851, 1869].
Card, Claudia. Lesbian Choices. New York: Columbia Moser, Carolyn. Gender, Planning and Development. Lon-
University Press, 1995. don: Routledge, 1993.

538

[Type text]
Fe´ nelon, Franc¸ois

Narayan, Uma. Dislocating Cultures: Identities, Traditions Fe´ nelon, Franc¸ois (1651–1715)
and Third World Feminism. New York: Routledge, 1997.
Franc¸ois de Salignac de la Mothe Fe´nelon was born
Nelson, Hilde Lindemann. Feminism and Families. Lon-don into a noble but impoverished family in Perigord. He
and New York: Routledge, 1997. was ordained in 1675; named director of the New
Nicholson, Linda J. Feminism/Postmodernism. New York: Catholics (former Protestants) in 1678; appointed tutor
Routledge, 1990.
of Louis, Duc de Bourgogne (1682–1712, the
Noddings, Nel. Caring: A Feminine Approach to Ethics and
grandson of Louis XIV) in 1689; elected to the
Moral Education. Berkeley: University of Califor-nia
Press, 1984. Acade´mie Franc¸aise in 1693; and made Archbishop
Nussbaum, Martha, and Jonathan Glover, eds. Women, of Cambrai in 1697. At the center of major contro-
Culture and Development. Oxford: Clarendon Press, versies of the period, he rejected the Jansenist inter-
1995. pretation of AUGUSTINE (354–430) and opposed
Okin, Susan Moller. Women in Western Political Thought. Bossuet (1627–1704) in the Quietist debate, a de-bate
Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1979. precipitated by his refusing to condemn Mme. Guyon
———. Justice, Gender and the Family. New York: Basic (1648–1717) as a heretical mystic. He set out his
Books, 1989. position in Explication des maximes des saints sur la
Peters, Julie, and Andrea Wolper, eds. Women’s Rights, vie inte´ rieure (1697), in which he ar-gues that saintly
Human Rights: International Feminist Perspectives. New
York: Routledge, 1995.
love of God is pure, radically dis-interested LOVE.
Phelan, Shane. Identity Politics: Lesbian Feminism and the
Although his opposition to Bossuet was costly in the
Limits of Community. Philadelphia: Temple Uni-versity short term—he was banished from the court in 1697
Press, 1989. and his book was condemned by Pope Innocent XII in
———. Getting Specific: Postmodern Lesbian Politics. 1699—his views on pure love, FREE WILL, predestination
Minneapolis and London: University of Minnesota Press, and grace soon thereafter found favor both in Rome and
1994. in France. He carried out pastoral functions as
Plumwood, Val. Feminism and the Mastery of Nature. Archbishop in his war-ravaged diocese until his death.
London: Routledge, 1993.
Robinson, Fiona. Caring and International Relations. Fe´nelon’s work in philosophy was apologetic,
Boulder, CO: Westview, 1999.
though he believed that the path to the best apolo-
Ruddick, Sara. Maternal Thinking: Towards a Politics of
getics was that of reason and true philosophy. He
Peace. New York: Beacon Press, 1989.
admired the ancient philosophers—especially PLATO
Sen, Gita, and Caren Grown. Development, Crises and
Alternative Visions: Third World Women’s Perspec-tives. (c. 430–347 B.C.E.)—and sought a synthesis of Au-
New York: Monthly Review Press, 1987. gustine and DESCARTES (1596–1650). In his earliest
Sherwin, Susan. No Longer Patient: Feminist Ethics and work, he maintains that MALEBRANCHE’s (1638– 1715)
Health Care. Philadelphia: Temple University Press, metaphysics, contrary to good theology and sound
1992. reason, restricts the possible to the necessary and
Spelman, Elizabeth V. Inessential Woman: Problems of deprives God of free choice. On the contrary, he
Exclusion in Feminist Thought. Boston: Beacon Press, argues, owing to God’s infinite perfection and power,
1989.
God is free to create or not to create any possible
Tronto, Joan C. Moral Boundaries: A Political Argument
world entirely at his pleasure and does not, accord-
for an Ethic of Care. New York: Routledge, 1993.
ingly, choose a world because it is good, but makes the
Walker, Margaret. Moral Understandings: A Feminist
Study in Ethics. New York: Routledge, 1998. world good by choosing it.
Wendell, Susan. The Rejected Body: Feminist Philosoph-ical And similarly by gratuitous choice does God make
Reflections on Disability. New York: Routledge, 1996. the chosen few good and worthy of salvation. To the
objection that this is at once unfair to those who are
Wing, Adrien Katherine, ed. Critical Race Feminism: A not chosen and contrary to the scripture that says that
Reader. New York: New York University Press, 1997. God wills that all be saved, Fe´nelon replies as
Young, Iris Marion. Intersecting Voices: Dilemmas of follows: First, it is evident that we have free will, the
Gender, Political Philosophy, and Policy. Princeton:
power to do or not to do A, even when A appears to us
Princeton University Press, 1997.
to be what we ought to do. Second— this is what it
Alison M. Jaggar means to say that God wills that all

539

[Type text]

You might also like