You are on page 1of 10

OPTICON Citation:

De Santis, S 2012 From Psychoanalysis to Politics: Antigone as Revolutionary in Judith


MDCCCXXVI Butler and Žižek. Opticon1826, 14: 27-36, DOI: http://dx.doi.org/opt.ai

Article

From Psychoanalysis to Politics: Antigone


as Revolutionary in Judith Butler and Žižek
Sarah De Sanctis*

In this paper I will analyse two contemporary readings of Sophocle’s Antigone: the
one proposed by Judith Butler in the influential Antigone’s Claim (2000) and the re-
sponse to it by Slavoj Žižek in Interrogating the Real (2005), Welcome to the Desert
of the Real (2002) and other works of his. Both readings stem from a psychoanalyti-
cal (Lacanian) approach in order to tackle social and political issues. After providing
the reader with an investigation of Butler’s and Žižek’s interpretations, I will draw
a comparison between the two, showing that Antigone is, for both, a revolutionary
figure that challenges the established social order.

Sophocles’ Antigone has fascinated thinkers distant from Žižek’s more strictly political
and critics throughout the centuries. From one (in the original sense of the running of
Plato and Aristotle to Hegel and Kirkeg- the polis) as it might initially seem. In fact,
aard, the tragic heroine has been the object both take Lacan’s interpretation as a starting
of countless studies and interpretations. point and, while following different paths,
Recently, she has been championed by fields both end up reaching the same conclusion:
so diverse as feminism, psychoanalysis, soci- they consider Antigone as a self-conscious
ology and politics. In this article I would political figure, the revolutionary par exel-
like to focus in particular on two contem- lence. This comparison, carried out with the
porary readings which bring all these areas support of significant textual evidence, aims
together: the one proposed by Judith Butler at bringing together literary analysis and
in the influential Antigone’s Claim (2000) political readings, in the hope of shedding
and the response to it by Slavoj Žižek – who further light both on these two influential
regards Butler’s reading of Lacan as a mis- interpretations and on the text itself.
interpretation – in Interrogating the Real
(2005), Welcome to the Desert of the Real Judith Butler’s Antigone and the
(2002) and other works. Both readings, in limits of kinship
fact, stem from a psychoanalytical approach
Antigone’s Claim starts with a question:
in order to address social and political issues.
why have all the most influential readings
After providing the reader with Butler’s and
of Antigone been so apolitical? The thinker
Žižek’s interpretations, I will draw a com-
who holds major responsibility for this is, in
parison between the two, showing that But-
Butler’s opinion, Hegel, who has confined
ler’s gender-oriented reading is not quite as
Antigone to the sphere of kinship and fam-
ily, leaving politics to Creon. Lacan’s psycho-
analytical reading did not solve the problem
*
Centre for Intercultural Studies, UCL (alumni)
since, in Butler’s view, his ‘symbolic’ – which
sarahdesanctis@hotmail.com
28 De Sanctis / From Psychoanalysis to Politics

Antigone transgresses – is purely abstract Far from reasserting it, Antigone transgresses
and distinct from the social (2000: 1-3). kinship. She does so not only through her
Butler’s aim is therefore to show the limits incestuous nature and feelings, but also
of these apolitical understandings and – as through her scant affection for anybody else
befits her politically engaged writings – bring apart from Polyneices. Take, for instance, the
Antigone back into the domain of politics. famous passage that follows:
Her first critique is directed at Hegel, who
Never, had been a mother of children,
famously considered Antigone as the hero-
or if a husband had been moulder-
ine of family values, opposed to the state and
ing in death, would I have taken this
its demands. According to Butler these two
task upon me in the city’s despite.
spheres cannot be set one against the other
What law, ye ask, is my warrant for
to begin with: on the contrary, they are inter-
that word? The husband lost, another
connected. In fact, she says, there cannot
might have been found, and child
really be kinship without the mediation and
from another, to replace the first-
support of the state and vice versa. Creon
born: but, father and mother hidden
himself assumes his sovereignty only by vir-
with Hades, no brother’s life could
tue of the line of kinship that enables his suc-
ever bloom for me again.1 (Sophocles
cession (Butler 2000: 6). Moreover, to take
2004: 165)
Antigone, offspring of an incestuous love, as
the champion of kinship is certainly rather Antigone, therefore, ‘represents not kinship
odd. Here Butler insists on the fact that Anti- in its ideal form but its deformation and dis-
gone rarely calls Polyneices by his name, but placement’ (Butler 2000: 24). Not only is she
mostly refers to him as ‘brother,’ a term that, Oedipus’s daughter and sister, not only is she
in her particular case, is highly polyvalent. As cold and rather hostile towards the other
Butler points out: members of her family, her exclusive affec-
When she claims that she acts accord- tion for her brother Polyneices also seems
ing to a law that gives her most pre- to be more than sisterly love. According to
cious brother precedence, and she Butler, Antigone is in love with Polyneices –
appears to mean ‘Polyneices’ by that or maybe, considering her ambiguous nam-
description, she means more than ing practice we have mentioned above, even
she intends, for that brother could with Oedipus himself.
be Oedipus and it could be Eteocles, In support of this thesis, it might be rel-
and there is nothing in the nomencla- evant to quote here some of the many lin-
ture of kinship that can successfully guistic expressions of erotic-incestuous
restrict its scope of referentiality to desire that appear in the text: 73 phile
the single person, Polyneices. (2000: met’autou keisomai, philou meta (‘Beloved,
77) I shall lie with him, whom I love’); 75 dei
m’areskein tois kato (‘...I have to please/satisfy
Butler carries on to ask a polemic question: those below’); 898-9 phile men hexein patri,
prosphiles de soi, meter, phile de soi, kasigne-
Antigone says ‘brother’, but does she
ton kara (‘Beloved I shall come to <my>
mean ‘father’? [...] This equivocation
father, dear to you, mother, and beloved to
at the site of the kinship term signals
you, brother’). Significantly, Antigone is phile
a decidedly postoedipal dilemma,
(‘beloved’) towards her father and brother,
one in which kin positions tend to
whereas she is merely prosphiles (‘dear, kindly
slide into one another, in which Anti-
affectionate’) towards her mother [note 2] As
gone is the brother, the brother is the
Mark Griffith put it, no other play contains
father. (2000: 67)
such numerous linguistic references to the
De Sanctis / From Psychoanalysis to Politics 29

act of ‘lying with’, ‘pleasing’ and so on (2010: lows that Antigone is far from being a self-
115-6). aware political figure. She is just driven by
Butler then proceeds to an analysis of desire. As noted by Miriam Leonard in Laugh-
Lacan’s reading of the tragic heroine (Lacan ing with Medusa, by removing Antigone from
1992b), which was conceived as opposed the symbolic, and therefore political, sphere,
to Hegel’s but, in Butler’s view, fails just as Lacan automatically opposes her to Creon,
much in recognizing Antigone’s political who becomes then the (male) representative
role. For Lacan, Antigone is the embodiment of the state. Lacan seems thus to fall back
of ‘the ethics of desire’. In order to under- into the Hegelian reading, precisely the one
stand this concept, we shall refer to Lacan’s he was opposing (Leonard 2006: 131-3).
theory of the three orders that define human Moreover, in Butler’s interpretation of
existence: the imaginary, the symbolic and Lacan, Antigone loves Polyneices’ ‘Pure
the real (1992b). Being’ in the sense of his symbolic aspect.
The imaginary order emerges when the She loves the ideal brother, who belongs to
child first sees him- or herself reflected in the the symbolic order but is detached from the
mirror in what Lacan calls ‘the mirror stage’ real person. In the same way, the symbolic
(1992a). In this way the child is able to recog- laws of kinship posited by Lacan are ideal
nise the Other as something that looks like norms that are never perfectly realized in
him or her and that he or she can identify any actual society. Butler, in fact, describes
with on one hand, and compete against on Lacan’s symbolic order as being
the other. The symbolic order is the order
defined in terms of a conception of
of language and, therefore, of the social.
linguistic structures that are irreduc-
From the moment when the child learns to
ible to the social forms that language
speak, his or her relationship with the Other
takes or that, according to structural-
will be forever regulated and freighted, in
ist terms, might be said to establish
a way, by language. The symbolic order is a
the universal conditions under which
realm where signs, or rather, signifiers, are
the sociality [...] becomes possible.
constantly exchanged. The signified, in its
This move paves the way for the con-
pure individuality, is forever lost. This is what
sequential distinction between sym-
Lacan calls ‘the Real’. Excluded from the sym-
bolic and social accounts of kinship
bolic, the Real is ineffable. It is, so to speak,
[...] The Lacanian view insists that
a void around which the signifier exists or
there is an ideal and unconscious
rather a void created by the signifier itself.
demand made upon social life irre-
Lacan uses here the metaphor of the vase, in
ducible to socially legible causes and
which the void is created by the clay that sur-
effects [...] The symbolic is precisely
rounds it. To each order corresponds a differ-
what sets limits to any and all utopian
ent kind of desire. The imaginary is the pre-
efforts to reconfigure and relive kin-
linguistic realm of basic needs like food and
ship relations at some distance from
warmth. Linguistically articulated demands
the Oedipal scene. (2000: 20)
are obviously related to the symbolic. Desire
proper – what Žižek calls drive, and that The structure of kinship, the Law of the
might be related to Freud’s libido – is con- Father that prohibits incest – which for Lacan
nected to the Real. is the basis of the symbolic and thus the very
Antigone embodies the ethics of desire possibility of the social, since the mother
because ‘she doesn’t give way on her (pure) stands for the forever lost object of desire –
desire’ (Žižek 1989: 117). She is moved by a is exactly what Antigone challenges. She is
drive, a craving for Polyneices’ ‘Pure Being’, incestuous, ambiguous, and impossible to
which comes from the unconscious. It fol- pin down. What she is cannot be fit into is a
30 De Sanctis / From Psychoanalysis to Politics

normative structure. Furthermore, not only will spend the remainder of your life in want
is she a transgression of the Law of Kinship of him’ (Oedipus at Colonus, 1617-1619)3.
by nature, she also consciously chooses her Oedipus wants Antigone to love nobody
brother above her husband, refusing in this else than him, thus linking her love to the
way heterosexual marriage and generational realm of the dead. His curse will in fact strike
continuity as such. Antigone, shown by the conspicuous num-
Hence Butler’s wish for the re-articulation ber of references to her relation with death
of the Law of Kinship, of whose foreclos- (thanatos): 71-72 keinon d’ego thapso: kalon
ing power Antigone is the victim par excel- moi touto poiouse thanein (‘but I will bury
lence. Lacan’s concept of being ‘between two him, well for me to die in doing that’); 461-
deaths’ is reinterpreted by Butler as the state 462 ei de tou chronou prosthen thanoumai,
of living an emotionally unfulfilled life. Anti- kerdos aut’ego lego (‘But if I am to die before
gone is between two deaths in the sense that my time, I count that a gain’); 524-525 kato
love is forbidden to her: ‘she claims that she nun elthous’, ei phileteon, philei keinous (‘Pass,
has not lived, that she has not loved, and that then, to the world of the dead, and, if thou
she has not borne children [...] thus death must needs love, love them’); 555 su men gar
signifies the unlived life’ (Butler 2000: 23). eilou zen, ego de katthanein (‘Thy choice was
It is her ‘impossible’ love for Polyneices, her to live, mine, to die’); 559-560 e d’eme psuche
ineffable desire, that makes her life a living palai tethneken, oste tois thanousin ophelein
death. (‘But my life hath long been given to death,
In Butler’s view, Antigone speaks in the that so I might serve the dead’).
name of all the non-traditional families that What Antigone does, though, is to accept
have now began to spread: blended fami- the curse and repeat it, yet in an aberrant
lies, families with adopted children, homo- form. Her only love is a dead man, true: but it
sexual relationships, single parents, and so is not Oedipus or, at least, not only. As I have
forth. How can all these new forms of kin- shown, Antigone is in love with Polyneices,
ship relate to the symbolic – ideal normative and possibly Eteocles as well. Therefore,
– order? Will there always be the spectre of Antigone’s is what Butler calls ‘promiscuous
unfilled positions or places? Will those fami- obedience’ (2000: 60). From a Lacanian per-
lies have to surrender to the fact that they are spective it could be argued that, in this way,
not quite as they should be? Even if we argue she betrays and obeys Oedipus at the same
that the structure that regulates kinship is time. She willingly accepts what has been
purely formal and can be therefore inhabited bestowed on her, thus freeing herself from
by anyone, this very formalism prevents the the curse. The order becomes a choice. This
structure from being reformulated. Never- is what Slavoj Žižek refers to as an ‘Act’ (1992:
theless, for Butler, in the final analysis there 44). I shall return to this point later.
is nothing beyond social practice and its poli- What Butler argues is that we, like Anti-
tics, there is no ideal symbolic, and we have gone, expose the contingency of the Law of
to face the fact that society is changing or, Kinship by repeating it in an aberrant form.
rather, has already changed. It is time for the It is particularly important to note that, as
Law of the Father – to use Freudian-Lacanian a perversion of the law herself, Antigone
terms – to cease haunting us (Butler 2000: makes her claim precisely within the sphere
71). of the law, by using its very language (Butler
What is particularly interesting is the way 2000: 68).
in which Antigone responds to the symbolic Here Butler refers to the passage where
Law, which, in her case, is the curse laid by Creon accuses her of having violated his edict
Oedipus upon her: ‘There is no greater love and in response she refuses to deny it, namely
than the one you had from this man, and you the verses 442-443: Cr: Phes, e katarnei me
De Sanctis / From Psychoanalysis to Politics 31

dedrakenai tade; An: kai phemi drasai kouk than her heritage. As noted by Butler, Anti-
aparnoumai to me. (‘Creon: Speak, do you gone refuses motherhood and marriage,
deny having done this? Antigone: I say that choosing death over the possibility of a
I have done it; I make no denial.’) By refus- future with Haemon. It is interesting here to
ing to be forced into denial, she appropriates refer to etymology. The name ‘Antigone’ is
the rhetoric of agency from Creon himself. made up by the prefix anti-, (‘against’, ‘in the
As Butler asserts, ‘He expects that his word place of’) and -gone, which may derive either
will govern her deeds, and she speaks back from -gon/ -gony (corner, bend) or -gen/ -gon,
to him, countering his sovereign speech by a root that is related to the idea of life, both
asserting her own sovereignty [...] her auton- in the sense of being and in that of gener-
omy is gained through the appropriation of ating. Antigone might therefore signify ‘one
the authoritative voice of the one she resists’ who cannot be bent’, or, as suggested also
(2000: 11). by Butler, ‘in place of the mother’, ‘against
It follows that Antigone’s claim does not motherhood’. Žižek connects the two mean-
take place outside the symbolic – which, for ings: by rejecting motherhood, Antigone
Butler, is not transcendental as Lacan posits, refuses to be bent, to be subordinated (2010:
and represents instead the hypostatisation of 104).
a historically and culturally particular social More importantly, however, she is utterly
order – but precisely within its terms. She apathetic towards her sister. Her stubborn
is thus shown to be strongly related to the coldness and lack of understanding for
social and the political. Antigone’s claim is a Ismene are such that Žižek comes to call her
claim for other laws, laws that are not part ‘inhuman’ (2006: 42). Whereas Ismene is the
of the established symbolic order. She makes friendly neighbour, or, in Lacanian terms,
her demand by showing the limits of the our semblable, Antigone perfectly embodies
Law – it cannot make sense of her heritage the scary Other we cannot understand: she is
or sexuality – and by doing it while using the what Lacan calls ‘das Ding’, the Thing (1992:
language of the Law itself. Whereas for Lacan 243-290).
she steps outside of the symbolic (norma- How is this possible? The Other is always
tive) order, for Butler she challenges it from both one’s semblable – one’s fellow human
within. The Law seems thus to bear within being, someone that looks like oneself, as
itself its own exception. The same conclu- is discovered in the mirror stage – and the
sion, although from a different perspective, Thing – the inhuman monster with whom
is reached by Slavoj Žižek, to whose work I no dialogue is possible (Žižek 2005: 347).
now turn. The Other is an unfathomable abyss, but
always hidden under a friendly mask. Why
Slavoj Žižek’s Antigone and the does Antigone become one with the Thing?
revolutionary power of the Act Because she has stepped outside the sym-
bolic order, the set of unwritten norms that
Žižek’s interpretation of Antigone is not an
mediate and make possible our interaction
organic one to be found in a specific book:
with the Other. It is precisely in this sense
the Slovenian philosopher refers to Sopho-
that Antigone is ‘between two deaths’. She is
cles’ heroine in almost all of his works. His
physically alive, but symbolically dead (Žižek
considerations of her stem from a Lacanian
1991: 16).
psychoanalytical basis to reach conclusions
Unlike Butler, Žižek does not refer here to
that, as I will show, have strong political
Antigone’s inability to fulfil her emotional
implications.
needs. She is symbolically dead because
Žižek agrees with Butler’s idea that Anti-
she is outside of the social order. This posi-
gone does not stand for kinship. In stating
tion is the domain of the Thing, what Lacan
this, though, he refers to her actions rather
32 De Sanctis / From Psychoanalysis to Politics

calls ‘Ate’: a term that recurs twenty times in the limit of the symbolic community
the text and that literally means ‘ruin, reck- to which I belong. (1992: 44)
less impulse, madness, fixation’. For Lacan,
it is the limit that Antigone crosses with The reason for Antigone’s striving for
her transgression and, at the same time, the self-annihilation is therefore explained: to
transgression itself. The domain of Ate is become a subject, to act, she has to exit the
unbearable for more than a little time. This symbolic order and, by means of this trans-
is why Antigone goes through her second gression, enter the domain of Ate. It is impor-
(physical) death. The only other option would tant to underline here that to act means to
be to step back into the symbolic order, but ‘freely assume what is imposed on us [...]
this is something Antigone would never do. subjectification is thus strictly correlative
She does not accept compromise, she ‘does to experiencing oneself as an object’ (Žižek
not give way on her desire’ and this is what 1991: 42), in a way that reminds of Kierkeg-
makes her an ethical figure. aard’s view on suffering.
It is easy to link Antigone’s connection And does not Antigone do exactly this?
with the dead mentioned in the previous sec- She is inhuman in the sense that she is – and
tion to what Žižek, following Lacan, defines sees herself as – an object. This admission
as her ‘death drive’. Antigone’s desire makes of passivity brings us back to what we have
her inhuman, by taking her away from the mentioned above, namely that to act means
symbolic order. Such a gesture is suicidal: to freely assume what has been imposed
hence Antigone’s striving to rejoin the dead upon us. In Antigone’s case, what has been
in Hades. It is tempting here to suggest bestowed on her is the Law of the Father,
another interpretation of the name ‘Anti- the incest taboo, which, according to Lacan,
gone’, by referring to the root -gen/ -gon not founds the symbolic order. As noted by But-
in the sense of ‘to generate’ but in that of ler, Antigone repeats the Law, and she does
‘being’: Antigone would thus come to signify it in its same language, thus freeing herself
‘against life’, ‘against being’. from it. In Butler’s view this repetition of
Far from seeing death as the legitimate the Law in its very language is the proof of
punishment for her immoral behaviour, the fact that Antigone never leaves the sym-
Žižek – following Lacan – believes Antigone bolic but challenges it from within. In Žižek’s
to be the ethical figure par excellence. She is interpretation, however, this means precisely
not opposed to Creon in the usual political- that Antigone, by accepting her fate as if it
apolitical antithesis. She is a revolutionary was the result of her own decision, sees her-
figure, because she acts. It is opportune to self as an object and so acts – that is to say,
introduce here Žižek’s conception of ‘Act’ as enters the domain of Ate. Ate is, in this sense,
opposed to ‘action’. The latter is an ordinary ‘transgression’, it is Sade’s ‘crime’: ‘that which
accomplishment, something we do that has doesn’t respect the natural order’. This kind
no particular relevance to our lives. An Act, of crime forces nature to start ex nihilo, and
on the other hand, is something that makes therefore possesses a revolutionary power
us subjects. This is possible, paradoxically, (Lacan 1992: 260).
only by annihilating our very subjectivity. As It is interesting that, immediately after
Žižek explains: Antigone’s deed is revealed to Creon, the
chorus utters the well-known sentence: 332
The act involves a kind of temporary polla ta deina kouden anthrôpou deinoteron
eclipse, aphanisis, of the subject [...] pelei (‘Wonders are many, and none is more
by means of it, I put at stake every- wonderful than man’). The Greek word for
thing, including myself, my symbolic ‘wonder’ is deinos, which means both ‘ter-
identity; the act is therefore always rible’, ‘monstrous’ and ‘wonderful’, ‘mar-
a ‘crime’, a ‘transgression’, namely of vellous’. Whatever the connotation, deinos
De Sanctis / From Psychoanalysis to Politics 33

indicates something that goes beyond the nor a prescriptive norm distinct from social
human. In this way the chorus is signalling practice. It is the name given to the whole of
Antigone’s stepping out of the symbolic and the contingent configurations that we find
her consequent entrance into Ate, the inhu- in society. Žižek in fact agrees with Butler:
man. there is nothing outside of those, there is no
Only by becoming inhuman can Antigone ideal Law (2005: 35). In this way, the Laca-
follow a ‘drive’, a concept that Žižek opposes nian symbolic order becomes, in Žižek, one
to that of ‘demand’. A demand is a striving thing with the social. Thus, Antigone’s Act
for something that is not our real object rises above the sphere of kinship (Hegel) and
of desire: we want something but what we that of language (Lacan in Butler’s reading)
are truly aiming for is something else (this and regains its political value.
is the logic of the symbolic). A drive, on the By becoming The Thing, Antigone is in
other hand, is somehow mechanic, auto- fact opposed to eunomia, literally ‘the good
matic. It is a blind, insistent desire that has set of norms, the harmonious order’, which
no ‘logic’ to it. It is a desire one cannot give was the principle at the basis of Ancient
way to, no matter what. It is easy to see how Greek democracy. Antigone is therefore anti-
a drive so conceived is, so to speak, inhuman. thetical to the polis and the community, but
A drive belongs not to the realm of the big not in the way posited by Hegel. By break-
Other, but to that of the Thing, the domain ing with the symbolic, Antigone acts, and in
of Ate. And here is where Antigone goes. By this way opens up the possibility for a new
stepping outside the symbolic, she accepts, social order. In fact, as Žižek puts it, ‘an Act is
wants and finally becomes the Thing (Žižek not only a gesture that does the impossible
1991: 15). It is following this view that Žižek but an intervention into social reality that
rejects Butler’s interpretation of Lacan: changes the very coordinates of what is per-
ceived to be possible; it is not simply beyond
The Thing is Pure Being, but not in
the good, it redefines what counts as good’
the sense that Butler attributes to it.
(2000: 672).
Antigone does not long for the ‘ideal
According to Žižek, Antigone’s is the only
brother’. What the Thing stands for
way. No negotiation is possible. No compro-
is the individual, the irreplaceable,
mise will work. To create a new social order,
the value of Being as such, regard-
one needs to act, to challenge the symbolic,
less of its content: something that,
to stick to one’s desire no matter what. This
because of its very uniqueness, can-
explains Antigone›s scarce predisposition
not be exchanged in the symbolic
to dialogue, something that has been con-
order. ‘In the case of Polyneices, it
sidered rather undemocratic. Consider, for
designates his absolute individuality
instance, Derek Barker’s remarks:
that remains the same beyond the
changing properties that characterize Antigone is one-sided and headstrong
his person (his good or evil deeds).’ [...] she tends to speak in passion-
(1992: 92) ate outbursts rather than reasoned
deliberation [...] she engages in all
In fact, according to Žižek, Butler’s interpre- manner of hyperbole and insults her
tation of the symbolic is an idealistic one. interlocutors (469-70) [...] Antigone
Butler sees it as an ideal prescriptive norm to demonstrates that she lacks the quali-
which nothing can truly conform – hence her ties [which are] essential to political
accusation of structuralism against Lacan. life: sensitivity to others, openness to
For Žižek though, her reading is a misinter- deliberation, and the ability to yield.
pretation. The Law of the Father – the sym- (2009: 30)
bolic order – is not an aprioristic structure,
34 De Sanctis / From Psychoanalysis to Politics

This blind perseverance, however, is related tion and the Law cannot exist one without
to the drive as such, as we mentioned above. the other4.
To act means to leave the sphere of the sym- With her statement ‘523 outoi sunechthein,
bolic and to become, so to speak, inhuman. alla sumphilein ephûn’ (‘It is not my nature
Moreover, Antigone’s attitude is deeply to join in hating, but in loving’), Antigone
negative. To refer again to Barker, ‘Antigone’s refuses the friend/foe policy that sustains
negativity is a political end in itself [...] Anti- (Creon’s) power. To use another Benjamin-
gone does not point to anything beyond her- ian expression, Antigone is a ‘great crimi-
self’ (2009: 133). Similarly, Žižek posits that nal’: someone who, despite their violent and
she does not offer an alternative to Creon, often immoral deeds, is admired for resisting
she just opposes him. Her Act is to say: ‘No!’ power and exposing its inherent contradic-
This negativity, however, is a constitutive tion. Benjamin writes also that ‘[h]owever
part of the Act as such. As Žižek points out, repellent Creon’s ends may have been, [he]
in fact, ‘[a]n Act always involves a radical risk has aroused the secret admiration of the
[...] it is a step into the open, with no guaran- public’ (1999: 59). It is easy to see how, in
tee about the final outcome – why? Because fact, the chorus’ secret admiration for Anti-
an Act retroactively changes the very coordi- gone persists throughout the text: 504-505
nates into which it intervenes’ (Žižek 2002: ‘All here would own that they thought it
152). well, were not their lips sealed by fear’; 800-
The Act is therefore a violent rupture, but 805 ‘But now at this sight I also am carried
only violence can be a founding gesture. As beyond the bounds of loyalty, and can no
posited by Benjamin, the foundation of the more keep back the streaming tears, when
law coincides with its transgression. Every I see Antigone thus passing to the bridal
rule springs out of its own exception. Both chamber’; 817-818 ‘Glorious, therefore, and
the foundation and the preservation of the with praise, thou departest to that deep
law are, furthermore, violent acts. Whereas place of the dead’.
Creon stands for the principle of ‘law-pre- It has been shown that Antigone is inhu-
serving’ violence – he stands above the law man, that she goes beyond the limits of the
in order to protect it – Antigone’s Act is ‘law- symbolic and that, by breaking with the big
making’ – to create a new order there has to Other, she opens up the possibility for a new
be a break with the present one (Benjamin social order. Žižek’s psychoanalytical read-
1999). As a Creator, Antigone has therefore ing is in fact very much politically freighted,
to be hupsipolis apolis (370): both inside and fulfilling Butler’s wish to have Antigone
outside the polis and its norms. Only in this returned to the sphere of politics.
way is a new order made possible.
Thus, another point of similarity between Conclusion
Butler’s and Žižek’s readings emerges: they
It is not hard to see that Antigone comes to
both seem to lead back to Benjamin, and
have the same function in both Butler and
his idea that the revolutionary excess (in
Žižek. For Butler she exposes the contingent
this case, Antigone) emerges precisely out of
character of the Law both by her heritage
eunomia. It was Benjamin’s belief that ‘The
and by her actions, showing the need for
good cannot reign over all without an excess
a re-articulation of the Law. For Žižek, she
emerging’ (Lacan 1992: 259). Antigone does
acts, defying the Law and showing its inher-
exactly the same: she brings Creon’s sover-
ent contradiction – Creon’s violence, which
eign power to an extreme, revealing in this
is an exception to the very law he stands
way its repressive nature. As stated by But-
for – opening up, in this way, the possibil-
ler, Antigone shows the limits of the Law by
ity of a new social order. Both thinkers not
speaking precisely in its language: the excep-
only bring Antigone back into the domain of
De Sanctis / From Psychoanalysis to Politics 35

politics, but make her into the revolutionary reading might seem to turn Antigone into
figure par exellence, one who challenges the a victim rather than a wilful subject, but
established social order, a role model, in a we have to remember that, for Žižek, the
way, to be followed if we want to make our two aspects coincide.) Both Žižek and But-
society better. In both readings, furthermore, ler refer to Agamben’s concept in describ-
we can see a strong connection to Benjamin’s ing Antigone as on outcast.
idea of ‘law-making’ and ‘crime’.
Nonetheless, there are two major differ- References
ences. The first consists in the fact that But-
Agamben, Giorgio 1998 Homo Sacer: Sov-
ler refers specifically to the Law of Kinship,
ereign Power and Bare Life. Translated by
whereas Žižek’s reading focuses on politics in
Heller-Roazen, D. Stanford: Stanford Uni-
the specific sense of the organisation of the
versity Press.
state. The second refers to the mode in which
Barker, Derek W M 2009 Tragedy and Citi-
Antigone’s transgression should be read and
zenship: Conflict, Reconciliation, and De-
transposed into today’s political action. But-
mocracy from Haemon to Hegel Albany.
ler advocates the need for a re-articulation
NY and Bristol: SUNY Press.
from within – something that might be
Benjamin, Walter 1999 Critique of Vio-
called a reformist perspective. In the femi-
lence. In: Steger, M B and Lind, N S (eds.)
nist thinker’s view, in fact, Antigone never
Violence and its Alternatives: an Interdisci-
leaves the symbolic order but challenges it
plinary Reader. New York: Palgrave Mac-
from inside. Žižek, by positing the rejection
millan, pp. 57-63.
and stepping outside of the symbolic as the
Butler, Judith 2000 Antigone’s Claim: Kin-
very conditio sine qua non of the Act, calls,
ship Between Life and Death. New York:
in a Leninist sense, for a revolution from the
Columbia University Press.
outside: in order to build something new the
Griffith, Mark 2010 Psychoanalysing Anti-
present order has to be destroyed.
gone. In: Wilmer, S E and Zukauskaite, A
(eds.) Interrogating Antigone in Postmod-
Notes
ern Philosophy and Criticism. Oxford: Ox-
1 If not stated otherwise, all translations ford University Press, pp. 115-6.
from Antigone refer to this edition. Lacan, Jacques 1992a The Seminars of
Jacques Lacan, Book I: Freud’s Papers on
2 My translation. Technique, 1953. Miller, J-A (ed.) Translat-
ed by Porter D. New York: Norton.
3 My translation. Oedipus at Colonus was Lacan, Jacques 1992a The Seminars of
written in 406 bc. Focusing mainly on Jacques Lacan, Book VII: The Ethics of
Oedipus’ death after his tragic discovery, Psychoanalysis, 1959-60. Miller, J-A (ed.)
it narrates events that occur after Oedipus Translated by Porter D. New York: Norton.
the King and before Antigone. pp. 243-290.
Leonard, Miriam 2006 Lacan, Irigaray,
4 Creon’s excess, which is shown by Anti- and Beyond: Antigone and the Politics of
gone, leads to another interesting point. Psychoanalysis. In: Zajko, V and Leon-
When Creon condemns her to a living ard, M (eds.) Laughing with Medusa:
death, he denies her humanity. Expelled Classical Myth and Feminist Thought.
from the sphere of the law, she becomes Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp.
what Giorgio Agamben calls a homo sacer: 131-3.
someone who can be killed, being physi- Sophocles, 2004 Sophocles: Plays, Antigone.
cally alive, but not sacrificed, since their Translated by Jebb R C. Easterling P E
life has no value (Agamben 1998). (This (ed.) Bristol: Bristol Classical Press.
36 De Sanctis / From Psychoanalysis to Politics

Žižek, Slavoj 2000 Melancholy and the Act. Žižek, Slavoj 1991 Looking Awry, an Intro-
Critical Inquiry, 26(4): 657-681. duction to Jacques Lacan through Popular
Žižek, Slavoj 1992 Enjoy Your Symptom! Culture. Cambridge, Mass; London: MIT
Jacques Lacan in Hollywood and Out. New Press.
York; London: Routledge. Žižek, Slavoj 2006 The Parallax View. Cam-
Žižek, Slavoj 2005 Interrogating the Real bridge, Mass; London: MIT Press, p. 42.
Butler, R and Stephens, S (ed.). London; Žižek, Slavoj 1989 The Sublime Object of
New York: Continuum. Ideology. London: Verso.
Žižek, Slavoj 2010 Living in the End Times. Žižek, Slavoj 2002 Welcome to the Desert of
London; New York: Verso. the Real. London; New York: Verso.

You might also like