You are on page 1of 17

-

What's Left of Enlightenment?

A Postmodern Question

EDITED BY KEITH MICHAEL BAKER

AND PETER HANNS REILL

STANFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS


Stanford, California zooi
70 HAN S SLU GA JOHNSON KENT WRIGHT

nitatis. To this he adds that what matters, the meaning of life, cannot
be grasped in the terms of science and logic. The solution of the
problem of life reveals itself for him in a philosophical silence that re-
mains when all scientific problems have been resolved. Later on, he "A Bright Clear Mirror'': Cassirer's
identifies such thinking as descriptive of what is always there but
never seen because it is always too close to us. And later still he speaks The Philosophy of the Enlightenment
ofit as therapeutic, as liberating us from riddles in which the mind has
been caught, and even as a destructive clearing of the ground on
which we stand.
Heidegger, Horkheimer, Adorno, and Wittgenstein belonged to
the same culture and the same generation. Living through the disas-
ters of the first halfof this century, they experienced instrumentalized
reason in its most destructive form. One might say that the terms in
which they responded are less important than the fact that they Among the classics of historical writing on eighteenth-century Eu-
searched for modes of thinking beyond the horizons of instrumental, rope, Ernst Cassirer's The Philosophy of the Enlightenment occupies a
scientific, and technological reason. What matters is their concern unique position. Has any other book had so central and so enduring an
that without such alternatives we may be caught in the endless spiral impact on the field? First published in 1932, on the eve ofits author's
of the insatiable demands ofreason, ensnared in ever more frantic pur- exile from Germany, it received a warm welcome in Cassirer's native
suits of goals that prove always illusive. Heidegger may be said to land and elsewhere in Europe, and has continued to command respect
summarize their common concern when he asks at the end of his lec- there. But it is in the United States above all that the book has en-
tures on Leibniz's principle of reason: joyed its greatest success. Koelln's and Pettegrove's lucid translation,
published by Princeton in 1951, rode the high crest of the wave of en-
Does the already given characterization of man as an animal rationale ex- thusiasm for Cassirer that began with his arrival in New York and his
haust the essence of man? Is the final word to be said about being that
turn to writing in English. Thus launched, The Philosophy of the En-
being means ground? Or does the essence of man and his belonging to
being still remain something in need of thought and this always more ur-
lightenment soon attained a canonical status within eighteenth-
gently? And if that should be so, are we permitted to abandon what is in century studies that it has never really lost. It eventually reached a
need of thought for the rage of an exclusively calculating thinking and its . mass audience via paperback, and remains vigorously in print to this
gigantic successes? ... Tb.at is the question. It is the ultimate question of day. Even such criticism as the book has received has tended to en-
30
thinking. Its answer determines what will become of the earth. hance rather than detract from its magisterial reputation. By the end
1
of the sixties, for example, The Philosophy of the Enlightenment seems
to have become the chief pole of comparison against which the emer-
gent "social history'' of the Enlightenment defined its elf. The practice
actually began with Peter Gay, who is sometimes regarded as a "dis-
ciple" of Cassirer.1 But he was soon trumped in this regard by Robert
Darnton, for whom The Philosophy of Enlightenment was the finest
achievement of a traditional history of ideas, one that confined its at-
tention to a ''High Enlightenment'' of canonical texts, merely re-
catalogued by Gay; the most urgent task for historians in the present
72 JOHNSON KENT WRIGHT "A Bright Clear Mirror' 73

was an assault on the archives, where the true social history of the En- the work of a major philosopher, not a historian. There is neither
lightenment, high and low, lay buried. 2 Today, however, it is Darn- space nor competence here to attempt a general profile ofCassirer as a
ton himself who is taxed with failing to break free from Cassirer's thinker. Not only was he the author of one of the most ambitious,
spell, in the most commanding work of the new feminist scholarship, even extravagant philosophical projects of the twentieth century, but
Dena Goodman's The R£pi1blic of Letters: A Cu./tural History of the his thought has in fact proven very difficult to categorize, eluding any
French Enlightenment. Ultimately, c'est lafaute aR.nusseau, the original easy capture. The central puzzle of Cassirer's intellectual career is that
source of the misogyny that, in Goodman's eyes, has obscured our of determining his precise relation to the Marburg "school" of neo-
understanding of the central contribution of the salonnieres to En- Kanrianism in which he was formed. Was the centerpiece of his ma-
lightenment sociability. Bur the chief advocate of Rousseau's outlook ture thought, The Philosophy of Symbolic Forms, the culmination and
in our time has indeed been Cassirer, "who didmore than anyone else fullest expression of the neo-Kantianism of his Marburg teachers,
to make the Enlightenment the subject ofserious scholarship." Hermann Cohen and Paul Natorp? Or did it amount to a mutation in
If anything, the resultofthis kind ofcritical tribute "from below" has some novel direction, and if so, which-a turn to Hegel, to phe-
been to reinforce the status o[The Philosophy ofthe Enlightenment as the nomenology, to pragmatism? The relations between Cassirer and
quintessenrialhistory ofthe Enlightenment «from above. "The essay at such key corespondents and interlocutors as Husserl and Heidegger
hand willnot try to overturn that judgment. Goodman is no doubt cor- remain to be fully documented and interpreted; the same applies to
rect in her assessment of the pivotal role played by Cassirer's text in fascinating affinities between his thought and major figures ofAmeri-
twentieth-century scholarship on the Enlightenment, indeed, in con- can pragmatism, Peirce and Dewey above all, and to his considerable
stituting the field as an object ofstudy. For precisely that reason, how- influence on later thinkers such as Merleau-Ponty. At all events, the
ever, aserious reappraisal ofThe Philosophy ofthe Enlightenment-an at- most that can be attempted here is to suggest a periodization of Cas-
tempt to examine the substance ofits argument, rather than criticize sirer's intellectual career down to the publication of The Philosophy of
the limits ofits vision-seems overdue. For Cassirer's book appears to "the Enlightenment-if only to give us a sense of where it fits into his
have enjoyed the privilege oflaunchinga very durable research program enormous and very complicated oeuvre. 4
iriitsfield, one thatmaynot yet be spenr. What accounts for the lasting Cassirerwas born in 1874, inBreslau (today Wroclaw), Silesia, to a
impact of The Phi/.osophy of the Enlightenment? Why should it have Jewish family whose wealth was drawn primarily from the manufac-
proven difficult for different kinds ofrevisionisrn to move beyond it? If ture ofindustrial chemicals. Cassirer's own generation, however, was
this is an opportune moment to pursue such questions, then our first characterized by remarkable intellectual and cultural achievement.
task must be to take a closer look at the background from which the The circle of his first cousins, with whom he maintained extremely
book emerged. Whatever elective affinity there may have been be- close relations during his young adulthood in Berlin, included the
tween Cassirer's sru.dyand the academic world ofpost-world America, composer and musicologist Fritz Cassirer; Bruno Cassirer, whose
ThePhilosophyoftheEnlightenmentwas produced in a very different cul- publishing firm played a key role in German intellectual life; the art
tural and political context-in fact, has something of the character of a dealer Paul Cassirer, famous for promoting French Impressionism
message in a bottle, from a lost intellectual world. and other schools ofmodernist painting in Germany; and the pioneer
ofgestalt psychology, Kurt Goldstein. At university, Cassirer's inter-
ests shifted from law to literature, and finally to philosophy. The
Context: Symbolic Forms and Weimar Liberalism turning-point in his intellectual life, by all accounts, was a lecture on
Above all, it is no accident that the book that did more than any Kant by Georg Simmel, in which the latter described Hermann Co-
other to restore the Enlightenment to philosophy should have been hen's interpretation of Kant as at once authoritative and incompre-
74 JO H N SO N KEN T W RIGH T "A. Bright Clear1 'Mirror" 75

hensible. The discovery of Cohen was a revelation for the young Cas- ment of a metaphysics of "substance" by a science of "relations," ~
sirer, who soon moved to Marburg, where he completed a doctorate which "function" had now became the touchstone of the veridical.
in 1899 under Cohen's direction. His earliest work revealed all of his The war years in turn provided the opportunity for Cassirer to make
most characteristic philosophic concerns, blending epistemology and an initial excursion beyond epistemology, into the domain of culture.
history in an original fashion. Cassirer's dissertation was a study of Ineligible for combat, Cassirer was eventually drafted into the ''War
Descartes's critique ofthe philosophy of mathematics and natural sci- Press Office," where his linguistic skills were put to work surveying
ence of his time. This in turn became the introductory chapter in his the French press for the purposes of generating political propaganda.
first book, Leibniz' System in seinen wissenschaftlichen Gru1:dicttfen As his wife recounted in her memoir, Cassirer found the experience
( 1902), which not only contributed to the striking wider revival of in- deeply demoralizing.6 His response was to produce a remarkable sur-
terest in Leibniz at the turn ofthe century, but also showed Cassirer's vey of German cultural history, Freiheit und Form: Studien zur deut-
characteristic penchant for bridging the French and the German in- schen Geistesgeschichte (1916). From the Renaissance to the Enlight-
tellectual traditions. From this starting-point, he launched a major enment, Cassirer argued, German culture had been defined by a dia-
project in historical epistemology, whose production stretched over lectical tension between freedom and form; the greatest figures in the
the next two decades, Das Erkenntnisproblem in der Philosophie und national past, Goethe and Kant above all, were those who had man-
Wissenschaft der neueren Zeit. Its first two volumes, extending from aged to maintain these two principles in a creative, if precarious equi-
Nicolas ofCusa to Kant, appeared in 1906 and 1907, and established librium. As these names also suggested, German culture was at its
Cassirer's claim to be heir apparent to Cohen and Natorp within the characteristic best when it rejoined, rather than departed from, a
Marburg "school." Cassirer in fact went on to assume the editorship common European tradition. An attempt to define national identity
of the ten-volume edition of Kant's works published by Bruno Cas- in wartime, the politics of Freiheit und Form were quiet yet firm-its
sirer between 1912 and 1923; the intellectual biography he added to liberal cosmopolitanism at the opposite end of the spectrum from,
the edition, Kants Leben und Lebre ( 1918), has of course enjoyed a long say, Mann's notorious Betrachtungen Eines Unpolitischen. Assuming a
life in print on its own. 5 milder nationalist position between the two, Ernst Troeltsch in fact
There was a lag in winning academic recognition for these intellec- charged Cassirer with having ignored the medieval roots of German
tual achievements, perhaps owing not a little to the darkening shadow freedom, which indeed rendered it distinct from Anglo- French con-
that anti-Semitism cast over German academic life in these years. In ceptions. 7
1912, Cohen's and Natorp's efforts to secure the farmer's professor- The end ofthe war and the advent of the Weimar Republic consid-
ship at Marburg for Cassirer failed; he had already assumed a position erably improved Cassirer's academic fortunes, and in fact ushered in
as Privatdozent at the University of Berlin, where he remained until the most creative and productive period of his intellectual career. In
1918. Lack of preferment did not stem his intellectual energies. In June 1918 he was appointed professor in thegeisteswissenschaftliche fac-
1910, Cassirer published Substanzbegriff und Funktionsbegrijf, in ulty at the University ofHamburg, a "republican" institution brought
which for the first time he staked out an independent philosophical into existence just one month earlier. By happy accident, Hamburg
position-in this case, a defense of"logical idealism" against empiri- also possessed an institutional resource that proved to be decisive for
cist epistemology. Here, too, however, the foundation of Cassirer's Cassirer's intellectual development in these years, the Warburg Li-
argument was narrative in form. Tracing the history of concept- brary for Cultural Studies. Cassirer soon formed a close relationship
formation in mathematics and natural science from the Greeks to with Aby Warburg's successor as director of the library, Fritz Saxl,
modernity-with explicit reference to the advances of Schroeder, and it was here that he first made the acquaintance of Erwin Panofksy.
Peirce, and Russell in logic-Cassirer described the gradual replace- The library's holdings, especially in the areas of mythology and his-
76 JOHNSON KENT WRIGHT "A. Bright Clear Mirror" 77

torical philology, provided many of the primary sources that formed understanding the development of all "symbolic forms," which could
the background to the emergent philosophy of "symbolic forms." be expected to pass from "mimetic" through "analogical"· to "sym-
Older intellectual concerns were by no means abandoned. In 1920, bolic" forms of expression, in a gradual movement from the concrete
Cassirer published the third volume ofDas Erkenntnisproblem, which to the abstract. The progress of language, in particular, was traced
pursued post-Kantian epistemology, from Hegel to Schopenhauer; from its initial "sensuous" expression, in the gestural and immediately
the next year, he produced a study of Einstein's theory of relativity aural, to more "intuitive" forms, which made use of more abstract
and the problems it posed for the philosophy of science-in effect, a conceptions of space and time, to a culminating state in which it had
striking attempt to coordinate the epistemology of "critical idealism" developed concepts of"pure relation," objective and self-referential.
with the findings of the new physics. It was in fact in the latter: work For all that, however, language never entirely loses its anchorage in
that the term "symbolic form" appeared in print for the first time. The sensuous and material media of expression-a feature of "symbolic
idea, according to family legend, first occurred to Cassirer while forms" in general. From here, Cassirer in a sense moved backwards,
boardingabusinBerlinin 1917. By the time of his first years in Ham- historically and logically, in the second volume of The Philosophy of
burg, it had become the linchpin of a massive project of philosophical Symbolic Forms, which provided a similar theory of the development
totalization, which came to fruition with impressive speed. The first of "mythical thought." Rejecting all theories of myth as "primitive
volume of The Philosophy of Symbolic Forms, entitled Language, came science," Cassirer portrayed it as a radically distinct form of con-
out in 1923, the second, Mythical Consciousness, two years later, and sciousness, rooted in social ritual, more archaic, immediate, and con-
the third, apparently culminating volume, Pbenomenoloqy of Knowl- crete than language itself; it was in fact the instability and disen-
edge, appeared in 1929. chantment of "mythic consciousness" over time that paved the way
How should the "philosophy of symbolic forms" be described? Its for the emergence oflanguage as an independent symbolic form.
background seems to have lain in a gradual realization on Cassirer's Four years later, the third volume of The Philosophy of Symbolic
part-going back at least as far as Substanzbegriff und Funktionsbe- Forms integrated these analysis of myth and language into a system-
griff-that his defense of an idealist epistemology in science required atic attempt to account for the emergence and development of scien-
foundations in a deeper theory of intersubjective ·meaning itself. By tific thought proper. Phenomenology ofKnowledge offered more than a
1921, Cassirer had arrived at a stable definition of the concept that general epistemology, however. For the theory ofsymbolic forms was
would stand at the center of such a theory: ''Under a 'symbolic form' now for the first time grounded in something close to a full-scale
should be understood every energy of mind [Ene13ie des Geistes] philosophical anthropology, pointing to Cassirer's later definition of
through which amental content ofmeaning is connected to a concrete, human beings as "symbolic animals." The key theoretical innovation
sensory sign and made to adhere internally to it. ,,a The originality of this was his concept of "symbolic pregnance," designed to situate the
definition should not be exaggerated. If Cassirer always gave pride of phenomenon ofmeaning in the very process ofperception itself, prior'
place to Humboldt in tracing its genealogy, the echoes of contempo- to any intellectual or cultural moment: ''By symbolic pregnance w,e
raries such as Peirce and Saussure are evident, if unintentional. Unlike mean the way in which a perception as a 'sensory' experience contains
these thinkers, however, Cassirer then set out to try to map both the at the same time a certain nonintuitive 'meaning' which it immedi-
variety and the development of the entire world of "symbolic forms," ately and concretely represents." Here, Cassirer suggested, lay the
in an effort to establish, as he put it in the foreword to the opening solution for the oldest problem of philosophical anthropology: ''The
volume of The Philosophy of Symbolic Forms, a "morphology of the hu- relation between body and soul represents the prototype and model
man spirit." Although the first volume was devoted entirely to just for a purely symbolic relation, which cannot be converted either into a
one form, that oflanguage, it also advanced a more general schema for relationship between things or into a causal relation ... a genuine ac-
78 JOHNSON KENT WRIGHT "A Bright Clear Mirror" ' 79

cess to the body-soul problem is possible only if we recognize as a an unfinished project: in later works, the "forms" analyzed by Cassirer
general principle that all thing connections and all causal connections included philosophy (in his essays in intellectual history), technology
are ultimately based upon such relations of meaning. The latter do not ( a striking anticipation of certain Frankfurt School themes), morality
form a special class within the thing and causal relations; rather they (his study ofAxel Hagerstrorn), and art ( a famous chapter inAn Essay
are the constitutive presuppositions, the condition sine qua non, on on Man). Not surprisingly, Cassirer's system also tends to lack any
which the thing and causal relations themselves are based.'?" strong conception of an end-state, to match Hegel's notion of the
With this theory of the anthropological priority of meaning, Cas- domination of"absolute" philosophic knowledge. Indeed, for all of
sirer seems to have left any narrow form of neo-Kantianism well be- Cassirer's appeals to Hegel, it does not seem difficult to glimpse in his
hind him. Where should The Philosophy of Symbolic Forms be located philosophic vision the inspiration of another figure standing behind
on the wider philosophic map? Cassirer himself was in fact quite can- both Hegel and Kant-that of Leibniz, whose thought had been the
did about the general inspiration for his philosophical program. In the starting-point in Cassirer's own intellectual itinerary. It may not be
''Introduction and Presentation of the Problem" in the first volume, entirely inaccurate to see in The Philosophy ofSymbolic Forms the out-
he paid tribute to Kant as a pioneer, each of the Critiques having line of a kind of cultural monadology, projecting a plurality of auton-
opened up a new terrain for exploring the work of spirit, in science, omous spheres of "meaning," traversed by a pre-established harmony
ethics, and art. Yet the real model for his project was to be found and unity.
elsewhere, in Hegel's attempt at a systematic, totalizing narrative in Neo-Kantian, Neo-Hegelian, or Neo-Leibnizian-in any case,
the Phenomenology of Spirit: "More sharply than any thinker before Cassirer's mature thought involved a creative recovery and develop-
him, Hegel stated that we must think of the human spirit as a concrete ment of the central themes of classical German Idealism. As such, he
whole, that we must not stop at the simple concept but develop it in had long since begun to contrast his own thought with an alternative
the totality of its manifestations.'?' The gesture of assimilation to tradition of continental philosophy, descending from Kierkegaard to
Hegel was repeated in the second volume of The Philosophy ofSymbolic Nietzsche, Bergson, and Scheler, whom he tended to group under
Forms-''That myth stands in an inner and necessary relation to the the dismissive label of"Lebensphilosophie." By the mid-twenties, how-
universal task of this phenomenology follows directly from Hegel's ever, this tradition had produced a major new figure, capable of doing
own formulation and definition of the concept?" - and then finalized battle on the most sophisticated terrain of academic philosophy. Cas-
in the third: ''In speaking of a phenomenology of knowledge I am sirer and Heidegger seem to have met as early as 1923, in Hamburg; a
using the word 'phenomenology' not in its modern sense but with its series of critical exchanges, marked by a combination of respect for
fundamental signification as established an systematically grounded and dissent from one another's philosophical positions, followed
by Hegel. ,m In point of fact, however, the differences from any con- down to 1931. In 1928, Heidegger published a generous review of the
ventional form ofHegelianism are bound to leap out at the reader. second volume of The Philosophy of Symbolic Forms, to which he also
Above all, Cassirer's presentation of the development of "symbolic alluded in a significant footnote in Being and Time.15 Cassirer recog-
forms" across time turns out to be both less linear and more plural than nized the originality and importance of Heidegger's masterpiece; his
the model of The Phenomenology ofSpirit would suggest. As Krois puts most extended comment, however, was a long and insightful review
it in his study of Cassirer's thought, the real shape of his conception of of Heidegger's Kant and the Problem ofMetaphysics in 1931. Between
development is centrifugal-a plurality of relatively autonomous these dates, the two participated in a series of public lectures and dis-
"symbolic forms" exfoliating from the common matrix of mythical cussions in Davos, Switzerland, during March and April 1929-
thought, itself a rather different starting-point from Hegel's.14 It is encounters that have, in retrospect, taken on an almost legendary
worth stressing that The Philosophy of Symbolic Forms was very much status as marking a profound parting of the ways in modern German
80 JOHNSON KENT W RIGHT ':A. Bright Clear Mirror' 81

thought. The exact terms of the "debate" between Cassirer and Hei- 1919; in the same month, he joined the center-left protest against the
degger have had to be reconstructed from onlookers' notes.16 The ter- trial and execution of Eugen Levine for his role in the Bavarian So-
rain was the interpretation of Kant, whom Heidegger sought to res- viet. Cassirer seems to have voted with the DDP consistently
cue from the extreme cognitivism of the "neo-Kantians" by restoring throughout the twenties. Nevertheless, it was not until 1928 that he
what he saw as Kant's supreme emphasis on human finitude-the produced a major political statement of his own. The occasion was
ground for his own understanding ofDasein. Cassirer's response was Hamburg's celebration ofthe ninth anniversary ofthe Weimar consti-
to concede the moment of finitude in Kant-thus rejecting the stark tution in August. Cassirer's speech, Die Idee der Republikanischen
antithesis drawn by Heidegger-while also insisting on a transcen- Verfa.ssung, published the following year, made a passionate defense
dental moment as well, the opening onto a world of"objective spirit'' ofthe Republic, by tracing its founding ideas to an interlocking set of
rooted in intersubjective language. Lacking this anchor, Heidegger's German, English, and French thinkers- Leibniz, Wolff, Blackstone,
interpretation ran the risk of endorsing a romantic irrationalism and Rousseau, and Kant, whose sober defense of the French Revolution
relativism. Two years later, Cassirer contrasted the thought of Kant Cassirer echoed and endorsed. To the spring of 1929, he reached the
and Heidegger in these pregnant terms: "Heidegger's fundamental apex of his academic career, being elected Rector at Hamburg, for
ontology, which is grounded in the interpretation of care as the being 1929-30-the first Jew to head a University in Germany. By this
of the existent and which sees a primary revelation of the existent in point, of course, the centrist liberalism for which Cassirer stood had
the fundamental mode of fear, must put all of Kant's concepts from begun to expire as a political force in Germany. Nevertheless, his
the very beginning-however much Heidegger attempted to do jus- public interventions on behalf of the Republic continued, as if in in-
tice to their purely logical mode-into a changed atmosphere and creasingly anxious compensation. Cassirer's last major political state-
thus, as it were, cover them up. Kant was and remained a thinker of ment before his exile from Germany was the speech, ''Vom Wesen
the Enlightenment, in the most noble and beautiful sense of this und Werden des Naturrechts," delivered in February 1932-a survey
word. He strove for illumination even as he thought about the deep- of the history of the modern natural rights tradition from Grotius
est and hidden grounds of being. »17 onwards, with special emphasis on the eighteenth-century elabora-
At all events, much of the drama attached retrospectively to the tion ofthe concept ofinalienable rights. Cassirer ended his remarks by
Davos "disputation" has to do with the ultimate political fates of the calling for a revival of the notion in the contemporary world. Hitler's
two thinkers. What in fact were Cassirer's own politics? As the legal assumption of the Chancellorship a year later brought his career at
liberalism ofJ ellinek and Kelsen and the ethical socialism of Hermann Hamburg to an end. In May 1933, the same month that Heidegger
Cohen suggest, the neo-Kantianism in which he was formed was ca- delivered his own inaugural address as Rector at Freiburg, Cassirer
pable of inspiring strong and original programs. There is no doubt led his family into exile in Vienna, and reached Oxford in the fall,
that Cassirer's chief inclination from the outset was toward a moder- never to return to Germany.
ate version of the former. The most overt political statement of the
early part of his intellectual career was Freiheit und Form, which pro-
jected a cosmopolitan liberalism onto the screen of German cultural
Text: Totalization and Nostalgia
history. The advent ofthe Weimar Republic naturally brought oppor- Such were the circumstances in which The Philosophy of the Enlight-
tunities for more forward kinds of political expression. Cassirer ob- enment was produced. As it happened, the book formed the last part of
served the Revolution coolly, from a distance, but actively identified an unintentional trilogy of studies in European intellectual history,
with the Republic from the start. We have seen that he accepted a having been preceded by Individual and Cosmos in the Renaissance in
professorship at the "republican" University of Hamburg in June 1927, and The Platonic Renaissance in England, published earlier in
82 JO H N SON KEN T W RIGH T ''A. Bright Clear Mirror» 83

1932. Cassirer spent much of the summer of 1931, just after stepping serve life and to portray it in terms of reflective thought ... Thought
down from the Rectorship at Hamburg, reading in the Bibliotheque consists not only in analyzing and dissecting, but in actually bringing
Nationale in Paris. The research trip also produced the two overlap- about that order of things which it conceives as necessary, so that by
ping studies of Rousseau that might well be seen as extended appen- this act of fulfillment it may demonstrate its own reality and truth.?"
dices to The Philosophy ofthe Enlightenment-Das ProblemJean-]acques It was this novel fusion of cognition and agency that lay at the core of
Roussea«, which has of course become a classic in its own right, and the philosophical outlook of the Enlightenment and thus provided
"L'unite dans l'oeuvre de Jean-Jacques Rousseau," first delivered ( in the chief focus of Cassirer's study. Only at the end of the Preface did
French, a matter ofsome pride to Cassirer) at a conference in Paris in he make any allusion to the intellectual and political context in which
February 1932. As for The Philosophy of the Enlightenment itself, it he wrote, expressing two larger hopes for the book. One was that it
reached print at the very end of that year, and proved to be Cassirer's might succeed in overturning "the verdict of the Romantic Move-
last publication in Germany before his exile. ment'' on eighteenth-century thought, silencing once and for all the
At first glance, the text hardly seems to register the turbulence and slogan of"the shallow Enlightenment." Beyond this, the unavoidably
drama of this background. In the Preface, Cassirer explicitly disa- critical character of reflection on the history of philosophy suggested
vowed any "polemical intentions" in writing The Philosophy of the En- that contemporary conceptions of"progress" might appear differently
lightenment. Nor did he aim at an exhaustive treatment of the subject. when glimpsed in "that bright clear mirror fashioned by the Enlight-
On the one band, limitations of space constrained him to approach enment'': ''Instead of assuming a derogatory air, we must take cour-
the Enlightenment "in its characteristic depth rather than its breadth age and measure our powers against those of the age of the Enlight-
... in light of the unity of its conceptual origin and of its underlying enment, and find a proper adjustment. The age which venerated rea-
principle rather than of the totality ofhis historical manifestations and son and science as man's highest faculty cannot and must not be lost
resulrs.?" On the other, the Enlightenment was itself only one epi- even for us. We must find a way not only to see that age in its own
sode in a larger. drama, the process "through which modern philo- shape but to release again those original forces which brought forth
sophic thoughr gained its characteristic self-confidence and self- and molded this shape.?" As a political gesture in 1932, this was char-
consciousness," which could only be gestured at in this book. Here acteristically modest, even oblique-but unmistakable nonetheless.
Cassirer referred the reader to his two earlier works of intellectual his- What shapes appeared to Cassirer in the ''bright clear mirror'' of
tory: like The Philosophy ofthe Enlightenment, these were only "prelim- eighteenth-century thought? The Philosophy of the Enlightenment is
inary studies" for a more comprehensive "phenomenology of the phil- made up of seven chapters. The first of these, "The Mind of the En-
osophic spirit," which Cassirer doubted he would ever complete. As lightenment," serves as a kind of general introduction, elaborating the
for the work at hand, his chief purpose was to emphasize the origina/,- portrait ofthe new philosophical reason of the epoch already sketched
ity of eighteenth-century philosophy within this larger story. Its key- in the Preface. In point of fact, it seems that the Enlightenment, at
note was the restoration of philosophical reason to its "classical" voca- least at the outset, may have been of two "minds," since the chapter is
tion as both unifying medium of all intellectual endeavor and active divided into two unequal parts. Cassirer began by recalling
shaper of the world. No less a thinker than Hegel had, on occasion, D'Alembert's own portrait of the French Enlightenment, at the mo-
dismissed the Enlightenment as a passive "philosophy of reflection" - ment ofits self-discovery, in his ''Elements of Philosophy'': the eight-
, even though.his own Phenomenology shows that Hegel the metaphysi- eenth century was the century ofphilosophypar excellence, and its cen-
. cian knew better. For the Enlightenment set out not merely to inter- terpiece was indeed a novel conception of reason. But there have been
pret but to change the world: "[T]he fundamental. tendency and the many"ages of reason"-what was the differentia specifica of Enlight-
main endeavor ofthe philosophy of the Enlightenment are not co ob- enment rationalism? Cassirer's answer was to construct its genealogy,
84 JOHNSON KENT WRIGHT "A Bright Clear Mirror" 85

tracing its roots to the first philosophical system ofthe modem world, approaches from different angles in its theory of knowledge and in its
·Cartesianism, and the subsequent impact on it of the emergence of philosophy of nature, in its psychology and in its theory of the state
Newtonian natural science. For the result of the success of Newton's and society, in its philosophyofreligion and in its aesthetics.?"
"analytic" method, with its emphasis on empirical induction, was to The rest of The Philosophy of the Enlightenment was devoted to sur-
modify rather than destroy Cartesian rationalism, by effecting an al- veying those topics, in precisely that order. In the second chapter, on
teration and relaxation in its guiding ideals. Here Cassirer invoked- "Nature and NaturalScience," Cassirer turned first to a more detailed
'to lasting effect-the contrast drawn by D'Alembert and echoed by account of the emergence and triumph of Newtonianism, which,
Condillac, between the "esprit de systeme" of Cartesianism and the among other things, completed the long process, begun two centu-
"esprit syste-mati,que'' of the French Enlightenment, the modulation . ries earlier, of permanently separating cosmology from religion. In
from noun to adjective suggesting the more expansive conception of physics proper, the result of the turn to empiricism was to open the
reason of the latter, now set free from any strictly mathematical or door to a new kind ofskepticism, which found its ultimate expression
logical basis. Paradoxically, what "reason" thus lost in rigor and cer- in the philosophy ofHume; the seventeenth-century concept of"sub-
taintywas more than made up for by a dramatic extension ofits pow- stance" was a major casualty ofthis line of thought. The biological sci-
ers, now reaching beyond abstract shape and number to govern the ences, on the other hand, which found their major popular represen-
physical and moral worlds as well. The result was the discovery of the tation in Diderot and made their greatest advance with Buffon'sNat-
formative powers of philosophical reason that constituted the unique ural History-the biological counterpart to Newton-were far less
contribution ofthe Enlightenment. Having thus returned to the cen- affected by epistemological doubt, since this field of knowledge re-
tral theme of the Preface, instead of ending the chapter, Cassirer mained subject to the continued dominance of Cartesianism. Cassirer
made an abrupt change of scene, devoting a short second section en- then concluded the chapter in the same way that he did the first, by
tirely to Leibniz. Despite appearances, the rationalism of the latter looking beyond French borders. In England, the Cambridge neo-
was in fact utterly distinct from that of Descartes-pluralist rather du- Platonists kept alive a Renaissance conception of the "dynamism" of
alist or monist, with a specific accent on the continu#y of monads, in- nature. Natural science in Germany, on the other hand, was domi-
stead of a more properly Cartesian obsession with identity and differ- nated by the similar heritage ofLeibniz, and it was in this domain that
ence. The result was two-fold. On one hand, the concept of totality or his impact was first felt in France, above all through the efforts of
the whole had for Leibniz a far greater significance than for any Maupertuis, who happened to be the major native exponent ofN ew-
French thinker. On the other hand, since the monad, in contrast to tonianism as well. The ultimate fate of science in the eighteenth cen-
the material atom, was conceived in terms of a unique "force," Leib- tury was in any case inseparable from psychology, the subject of the
niz's system also enshrined a certain kind of individualism-in his sys- third chapter of The Phoosophy of the Enlightenment. Here, the destruc-
tem, "an inalienable prerogative is first gained for the individual en- tion ofthe rationalist conception of''innate ideas" by the English em-
tity." What was the upshot of Leibniz's philosophy for the "mind of piricists was the counterpart to the dethronement of metaphysical
the Enlightenment"? Cassirer ended the chapter reminding his read- "substance." This left, however, a "core problem," that of the relation
ers that, according to legend, Leibniz tended to be either ignored or between the various fields of sensation, whose solution was necessary
ridiculed in France. But the example of Candide was misleading. In to ward off the threat of Berkeley's "subjective idealism." Hints of a
fact, in "this fundamental opposition" - between the "classical Carte- way out of this impasse could be found in Condillac's novel emphasis
sian form of analysis and that new form of philosophical synthesis on will in his own philosophical psychology, echoed by Rousseau. Not
which originates in Leibniz" - "lay the great intellectual tasks which suprisingly, another possible solution was implied in Leibniz's mo-
eighteenth century thought had to accomplish, and which the century nadology, which dominated the German scene. But the ultimate
I
86 JOHNSON KENT WRIGHT "A. Bright Clear Mirror" 87

resolution of the problem was to be found in Kant, building on the narrative historians, only Hume resisted this spirit-though he, too,
work of Lambert and Tetens: "When these two separate streams of lacked the ''buried treasure" of Leibniz's thought, which alone pos-
thought of the German Enlightenment joined in Kant, their relative sessed the means of assignirig individuality its true philosophic
goal was achieved, and with achievement the goal vanished to be sup- weight in historical explanation. It was in Germany that the "trea-
planted byanew principle andnew problerns.?" sure" of Leibniz's conception of substance was finally released into
From here, Cassirer turned in his fourth chapter to religion, in re- circulation by Herder, whose philosophy of history thus broke the
gard to which the Enlightenment could lay claim to three major spell of analytical thinking once and for all. Indeed, Herder had in one
achievements. One was to complete the destruction of the dogma of sense simply surpassed the Enlightenment altogether. However, Cas-
original sin, bringing the process of secularization begun with the sirer insisted, his break with the immediate past was not total,: "The
Reformation to its climax. This move left a "problem" in its wake as conquest ofthe Enlightenment by Herder is therefore a genuine self-
well, thatoftheodicy, or the explanation of evil, whose challenge was conquest. Ir is one of those defears which really denote a victory, and
to be seen in Voltaire's tormented life-long struggle with the ghost of Herder's achievement is in fact one of the grearest intellectual tri-
Pascal. The solution was only finally reached with Kant's ethics, which umphs of the philosophy ofthe Enlightenment.?"
stripped pleasure and pain of all moral significance-though Kant was In the sixth chapter ofThePhilosophy of the Enlightenment, on ''Law,
anticipated in this respect by both the aesthetics of Shaftesbury and State, and Society," Cassirer reproduced the themes of his contempo-
the social thought of Rousseau . Kant also gave full expression to a sec- rary writings on natural law and Rousseau. An opening section ex-
ond major achievement of Enlightened thinking on religion-the amined the doctrine of inalienable rights as it emerged in the eight-
erection of toleration as a central ethical demand of religious thought eenth-century-Cassirer admitted that the notion rested on insecure
itself Another German thinker, finally, was responsible for a third foundations, in evident tension with the consensual rejection of"in-
major advance in theology: it was Lessing's Education of Humanivy nate ideas." From here he turned to the adjacent field of contract the-
that first suggested the means for overcoming the potential contra- ory in political thought, where Rousseau turned out to play a role
diction, introduced by Spinoza, between religion and history. In fact, analogous to that of Herder in the philosophy of history, anchoring
Lessing's achievement pointed beyond theology to the wider domain his own conception of inalienable rights in the communal terrain of
of historical understanding, the subject of the fifth chapter of The the state: ''Rousseau did not overthrow the world of the Enlighten-
Philosophy of the Enlightenment. Here Cassirer set out specifically to ment; he only transferred its center of gravity to another position. By
overturn the Romantic verdict that the Enlightenment was somehow this intellectual accomplishment he prepared the way for Kant as did
''unhistorical"; on the contrary, it was the Enlightenment that estab- no other thinker ofthe eighteenth century. Kant could find support in
lished the conditions of possibility for Romantic historicism itself. Rousseau when he came to build up his own systematic edifice-that
The true pioneer here was Bayle, whose destruction of one "fact" of edifice which overshadows the Enlightenment even while it repre-
historical dogma after another constituted a veritable "critique of his- sents its final glorification.'?" Cassirer then concluded The Philosophy of
torical reason."The terrain cleared by Bayle was then occupied, in the theEnlightenmentwith byfarthe longest chapter in the book-a.close
first instance, by the incomparable Montesquieu, whose conception analysis, extending across nearly a hundred pages of text, of the emer-
of "ideal types" and explanatory pluralism have formed the solid basis gence of aesthetics as an independent philosophical discipline. His
of all subsequent social science. Voltaire received rougher treatment starting-point here, as elsewhere, was with the disintegration of an
at Cassirer's hands: his historiography tended to be flawed by his essentially Cartesian program, in this case the classical aesthetics of
commitment to an all-too-static conception of human nature, sign of Boileau, which duly fell prey to a variety of subjectivist attacks, begin-
the dominance of the "analytic spirit'' in his writing. Among other ning with Bouhours and Dubos, and culmirtating with Hume. The
88 JOHNSON KENT WRIGHT "A. Bright Clear Mirror" 89

triumph of these psychological theories of art was all too complete: of undifferentiated unity to one of rupture and fragmentation, in or-
"In no other field was the transition from the psychological to the der to arrive at an end-state in which unity has been restored in a
transcendental approach, by which Kant finally resolved this alliance, higher, "differentiated" shape. As for the content of the form, the
so hard to realize and burdened with so many systematic difficulties as prior state is always some variety of Cartesianism, whose certainty is
in that of the fundamental problems of aesthetics. ms Cassirer then de- then shaken or destroyed by a species of "analytic" or "psychological"
scribed the gradual resolution of these "difficulties," first in English thought, most often English in inspiration, whose "problems" then
thought, with Shaftesbury's reconscrucrion of Plotinus's conception find their solution in the emergence of"synthetic" or "transcenden-
of "intelligible beauty" and Burke's recovery of the category of the tal" philosophy-the privilege, of course, of German thinkers above
"sublime," both pointing beyond the limits of classical aesthetics; all. Each of the six substantive chapters of The Philosophy of the Enlight-
then in the neo-classicism of Gottsched and the response of various of enment tells the same tale, in effect. Thus Cassirer's account of eight-
his Swiss critics; and finally, in Baumgarten himself, who used Leib- eenth-century science began with the challenge posed to Cartesian-
niz's doctrine ofthe degrees of knowledge to found the philosophical ism by Newtonian "analysis," whose empiricism turned out to lack
autonomy, perhaps even priority, of aesthetic judgment. At the start stable foundations, risking a collapse into Hume's skepticism; the so-
of the chapter, Cassirer had declared that the emergence of the new lution was to be found in Kant's "Copernican Revolution," whose
discipline of aesthetics had owed a good deal to the «pre-established origins were traced to the pluralist metaphysics of Leibniz. In psy-
harmony' between thought of the greatest philosopher and the great- chology, the reign of Descartes's "innate ideas" was cut short by
est poet ofthe age: ''Kant's philosophy and Goethe's poetry form the Locke and his successors; the resulting slide toward incoherent sub-
intellectual goal toward which this movement prophetically beck:- jectivism was stayed by the rediscovery of ''will" in Condillac and
ons.?" The Philosophy of the Enlightenment concluded, however, with Rousseau, which in turn inspired Kant's restoration of psychic objec-
neither Kantner Goethe, but with the figure ofLessing: ''It is above tivity and wholeness, in the "transcendental unity of apperception." It
all because of him that the century of the Enlightenment, to a very was the dogmatism ofPascal, rather than the rationalism of Descartes,
great extent dominated by its gift of criticism, did not fall prey to the that formed the target of Enlightened "analysis" in the domain of re-
merely negative critical function-that it was able to reconvert criti- ligion; but the solutions to the moral and intellectual "problems" thus
cism to creative activity and shape it and use it as an indispensable in- unleashed were, again, owing to the efforts of German thinkers-
strument oflife and ofthe constant renewal of the spirit.?" Kant's "practical reason" and defense of toleration, Lessing's recon-
Now what even such a stenographic summary of the book makes ciliation of religion and history. As for historiography, it was here a
clear, in the first instance, is the extent to which Cassirer made good French Protestant, Bayle, who challenged the rule of dogmatism,
his effort to present eighteenth-century thought "in the unity of its Cartesian or Catholic; but the story again ended in Germany, where
conceptual origins and of its underlying principle." Elsewhere in the Herder, reaching back once more to Leibniz, definitively ended an
Preface, he insisted that the Enlightenment, «which is still usually unstable period dominated by an "analytical" understanding· of his-
treated as an eclectic mixture ofthe most diverse thought elements, is tory. Cassirer's account of political thought traced a similar path, ,
in fact dominated by a few great fundamental ideas expressed with moving from the rationalist rights theories of the seventeenth cen-
strict consistency and in exact arrangement. "28 This is a perfect de- tury to the liberal doctrine of inalienability in the eighteenth, and
scription of the book itself, which is in fact structured around a single then from Rousseau to Kant. Aesthetics, finally, showed the same
narrative form, which is then presented at two successive levels in the trajectory: the Cartesian classicism of Boileau gave way to the "psy-
text, the first subsumed into the second. The narrative form is, of chologisms" of Dubas or Hume; Shaftesbury and Burke then paved
course, a familiar one: the dialectical development from an initial state the way for the consolidation of a fully modern aesthetic theory in
90 JOHNSON KENT W RIGHT "A Bright Clear Mirror}) 91

Baumgarten and Kant, which emerged in "pre-established harmony'' scientific and epistemological terrain of the first to the religious and
with the artistic practice ofLessing and Goethe. moral topics of the second, and then conclude at the doorstep ·of the
At the same time, these are not simply discrete case-studies of Critique ofJudgment itself. Moreover, there was a precedent for the
topics in eighteenth-century thought, nor is the orde~ oftheir presen- emphasis placed upon the aesthetic in this design. For Cassirer em-
tation an accidental one. For taken together, the separate chapters of phatically belonged to the camp of those interpreters of Kant who see
The Philosophy ofthe Enlightenment reproduce precisely the same narra- his aesthetic theory as the capstone of the critical system as a whole-
tive at a higher level of generality. Here the first chapter, depicting the chapter on the Critique ofJudgment in Kants Leben und Lebre oc-
the "Mind of the Enlightenment," plays a crucial enabling role. For as cupies roughly the same position and weight as the chapter on aes-
we have seen, far from attributing a single, stable outlook to the En- thetics in The Philosophy ofthe Enlightenment. At the same time, there
lightenment, Cassirer instead produced an elaborate description of is an evident problem for any attempt to read the book as a "Kantian"
what was essentially the French version of it, caught in a long moment account of eighteenth-century thought tout court. This is the fact that
of disequilibrium -in transition, that is, from the reign of the "esprit Cassirer quite clearly excluded Immanuel Kant himself from the En-
de systeme" to that of the "esprit syste?nati que." The chapter then con- lightenment. The plan of The Philosophy of the Enlightenment echoes
cluded by shifting abruptly to a snapshot of Leibniz, sitting offstage. that of Kant's critical philosophy; and Kant is referred to continually
It was the essential "task'' of the Enlightenment as a whole, Cassirer in its pages-the place he occupies in its index puts him in the same
insisted, to bridge the gap between the "analytic'' outlook of the one rank as Diderot and Voltaire. Yet there is no extended discussion of a
and the "synthetic" project of the other-to combine, as it were, a major work of Kant's anywhere in the book, even where it is most to
French melody and a German counterpoint. As the succeeding six be expected. Over and over Cassirer's chapters lead the reader in a di-
chapters pursue this project, the center of gravity of the narrative rection for which one work or another ofKant's would seem to be the
gradually shifts from the French to the German scene, with English logical end-point, only to stop short, concluding with discussions of
thinkers, again, serving as mediators-of the "vanishing'' variety, one what come to seem to be so many substitutes or "precursors" -
is tempted to add-between the two. Thus the chapters devoted to Lessing, Herder, Rousseau, Baumgarten. Behind these, there is the
science and psychology are still dominated by accounts of French figure of one other German thinker, whose works do receive ex-
thought, ending with mere gestures in the direction of Leibniz or tended discussion in The Philosophy of the Enlightenment, and who in
Kant. The gap begins to close in the next three chapters, each of fact looms as a far larger presence in the book than Kant-Leibniz,
which concludes with descriptions of German resolutions to French surprisingly enough. The paradox here looks acute: the one major
"problems," in Kant, Lessing, and Herder. The story then reaches its German thinker of the epoch to align himself self-consciously and
climax in the last chapter, with its astonishingly detailed account of unequivocally with the Enlightenment appears to have been excluded
the emergence of German aesthetics; indeed, the weight ofthis chap- from Cassirer's study, in favor of a philosopher who died a half-
ter in The Philosophy of the Enlightenment, which lacks any conclusion century before the movement can plausibly be said to have arrived in
proper, lies in its presentation of Baumgarten's aesthetic theory as in Germany. What is the explanation for this?
some sense the climax and end-point of the European Enlightenment In a fascinating political reading of Cassirer's intellectual career
as a whole. down to the moment of his exile, David Lipton has suggested that
In point of fact, this is unlikely to surprise any reader who knows Cassirer's treatment of Kant, or lack thereof, in The Philosophy of the
that Cassirer was in some sense a "neo-Kantian" philosopher. For the Enlightenment was in effect an "evasion" in the face of wrenching
basic shape ofthe narrative at this level faithfully reproduces the order philosophical and political pressure. Both the implosion of Weimar
of topics of Kant's three Critiques: Cassirer's chapters move from the liberalism and the intellectual challenge posed by Heidegger ought to
92 JOHNSON KENT WRIGHT "A Bright Clear Mirror" 93

have led Cassirer to a new, more profound engagement with Kant. diminish the Enlightenment, turning it into a mere preamble to
His study of the Enlightenment brought him to the threshold ofjust Critical Philosophy. Instead, Cassirer chose to reduce Kant to some-
such a project; but in the end, he nervously swerved away: ''Under thing like a gestural presence in the text, with his place, and that of
these circumstances Cassirer undoubtedly felt that to re-examine the classical Idealism as a whole, "held" by the series of transitional figures
nature of reason would only further undermine the cause of human who occupy center stage in the book. Moreover, there was a specific
freedom.'?" Lipton's suggestion is to be respected; we will return in a logic in granting Leibniz a certain pride ofplace among these, in addi-
moment to the character of The Philosophy ofthe Enlightenment as a po- tion to Cassirer's own evident affection for him: rather than being a
litical statement. But it may explain too much. For Cassirer's handling central figure in the Enlightenment proper, Leibniz serves as the in-
of Kant in the text is not only a good deal more coherent and nuanced dispensable bridge linking its immediate predecessor, the philosophic
than it appears at first glance; but it in fact becomes still more intelli- culture of rationalism, to its immediate successor, that of classical
gible when the book is restored to the context of his mature philo- German Idealism.
sophical thought as a whole. As we have seen, the Preface alerted the It is perhaps not surprising to discover that the Enlightenment was
reader to the fact that the text was to be regarded as one more "pre- in some sense subordinated to classical Idealism in Cassirer's book,
liminary study'' for a much larger project, that ofa "phenomenology of given the depth of his own philosophic commitments to the great
the philosophic spirit." Philosophy, in other words, was here under- themes ofthe latter tradition. ''Needless to say," he wrote in the Pref-
stood as another "symbolic form," in Cassirer's technical sense of the ace, "following Kant's achievement and the intellectual revolution ac-
term, in whose history the Enlightenment was only one specific mo- complished by Kant's Critique of Pure Reason, i~ is no longer possible
ment. Indeed, it is one of the great rhetorical achievements of The to return to the questions and answers of the philosophy of the En-
Philosophy of the Enlightenment that Cassirer was able to present the lightenment. "30 But neither was there any need for such a "return,"
"dramatic action" of eighteenth-century thought as a coherent, self- since the most original contribution of the Enlightenment to moder-
enclosed narrative, while also continually conjuring up the shape of a nity survived the movement itself, finding a still more secure home at
wider philosophical drama extending before and after the story at the heart of classical Idealism. This was its "activist'' conception of
hand. At one end, this is what explains the close attention that Cas- philosophic reason, which "attributes to thought not merely an imita-
sirer devoted in the book to seventeenth-century rationalism, Des- tive function but the power and the task of shaping life itself." The
cartes above all, which, strictly speaking, might be thought to fall out- philosophy of the Enlightenment set out not merely to understand
side his purview. At the other, there is Kant, whose thought is consis- the world, but to use that understanding freely to remake it, according
tently presented as marking both the "culmination" of the Enlighten- to its lights. This is indeed the central, enduring theme of The Philoso-
ment and its cancellation, for the launching of an entirely new phase in phy of the Enlightenment, and no reader is likely to forget the vividness
the development of philosophy. Cassirer's description of Kant's phi- with which Cassirer presents the idea in the Preface and first chapter
losophy as an "edifice which overshadows the Enlightenment even of the book. To make such a claim, however, is to point to another
while it represents its final glorification" was perfectly loyal to Kant's paradox, which will return us to the question of Cassirer's politics.
own understanding of his relation to the Enlightenment-though it For if we ask ourselves what examples Cassirer cites of this kind of
is hardly necessary to add that the guiding spirit behind this narrative philosophic reason in action-what institutions and practices were
was not Kant but Hegel, the original model for this and the rest of actually shaped by Enlightened thought-the answer appears to be
Cassirer's "phenomenologies" of form. Given this understanding of virtually none. The idea ofphilosophy as sovereign maker ofthe world
Kant, the result of a full-scale presentation of his thought in The Pm- largely remains just that, an idea-it is never brought to earth in con-
losophy ofthe Enlightenment, logically enough, could only have been to crete instances. It is noticeable that the chapter devoted to politics in
94 JOHNSON KENT WRIGHT "A Bright Clear Mirror" 95

The Philosophy ofthe Enlightenment, where the notion might have been in the German context. As we have seen, his reaction to the catastro-
expected to find its chief illustration, is by far the slenderest in the phe ofthe Great War was to seek relief in a celebratory recovery of the
book; the topic of"enlightened despotism," the zone of philosophical cultural past of the nation; yet his constant focus throughout Freiheit
activitypar excellence in the second half of the eighteenth century, is und Form was on those moments when German thought converged
never broached. Beyond this, probably the largest single lacuna in with wider European streams-the Reformation, the Enlighten-
Cassirer's study is the total disregard ofeconomic theory and practice; ment, and the rights-based ethical liberalism of the present. What
neither Smith nor physiocracy make an appearance in the pages of The seems clear is that he now repeated the gesture in The Philosophy of the
Philosophy ofthe Enlightenment. The garden later tilled by Peter Gay in Enlightenment, on a grander scale, in the face of a still more dire emer-
Voltaire's Politics, and the entire domain of Enlightened political prac- gency. For by the early thirties, the strain of European liberalism to
tice, reformist and revolutionary, magisterially cultivated by Franco which Cassirer adhered had reached the very nadir of its historical for-
Venturi, were utterly neglected by Cassirer. If it is appropriate to tunes. Before its political thought and practice could even begin to
speak ofan "evasion" in the book, it is probably here, in what appears stage a recovery from the disaster of the Great War, the inflation of
to be the near-total excision ofpolitics from an account of the Enlight- the twenties and then the Depression itself threw its economic.insti-
enment that insists on placing a conception of conscious agency at its tutions and doctrines into utter disarray. Nowhere was the crisis of
core. liberal civilization felt more acutely than in Germany, where the de-
A full explanation ofthis anomaly would point us to a larger pattern cline of Weimar constitutionalism into Nazi dictatorship proved to
of omission and occlusion in Cassirer's thought. In a thinker re- be the deepest sounding ofits depths.
nowned for the encyclopedic breadth of his vision, such gaps as there Cassirer's response to this crisis-obviously personal as well as na- ·
are come to have, in a sense, a "symptomatic'' look to them. There is a ti.onal-was to seek consolation and inspiration alike in a vivid por-
very striking contrast, for example, between Hermann Cohen's pas- trait ofEuropean civilization at the moment of its maximum intellec-
sionate, life-long engagement with both the intellectual traditions of tual and cultural unity, in the epoch when the lacerations of early- '
socialism and those of modem Jewish philosophy, and his star pupil's modem religious conflict first lay securely behind it, and the divisions
almost complete silence about them. It is unlikely to be accidental of later nationalist contention were still well in its future. Cassirer's
that psychoanalysis, too, failed to attract any attention from Cassirer. 31 recovery of the Enlightenment was all the more compelling in that
At all events, the explanations for both ofthe features of The Philosophy the unity he ascribed to it was neither simple nor facile. The cos-
of the Enlightenment highlighted here-its paradoxical treatment of mopolitanism he described by no means canceled the differences be-
Kant, simultaneously "in" and ''beyond" the Enlightenment, and its tween national intellectual traditions, which continued to feature
apparent repression of the "politics" of the movement-are no doubt prominently in his text. The distinction between Anglo-French Zivi-
to be traced to the same source. At the end of the day, what is most lisation and GermanKultur, a token not only of German conservatism
striking about Cassirer's study in its proper historical context, sur- but of a good deal of liberal thought as well, was not simply set aside
prisingly enough, is its quality as a political intervention of a unique by Cassirer, but surpassed, in something closer to a properly hard-
kind. In some ways, Cassirer's liberalism can be seen to have con- wonAufhebung. There was naturally a price to be paid for the result-
formed recognizably to a national type, reflecting a wider German ing "totalization" of the Enlightenment, which, in Cassirer's render-
concern with the free expression ofindividual personality, above all in ing, became a moment in the career of modem philosophy above all.
the various domains of culture. At the same time, however, Cassirer's The result.on the one hand, was to make it necessary to set Kant, and
consistent cosmopolitanism-the almost complete lack of any nation- German Idealism as a whole, just beyond the precincts of the Enlight-
alist tincture in this liberalism -marks him out as very unusual indeed enment itself, in order to maintain the full autonomy of the latter.
96 JOHNSON KENT WJ.lIGHT <':A_ Bright Clear Mirror" 97

Whatever else they achieved, Cassirer's efforts in this regard bear the unityofEuropean thought, was essentiallyonly a "German history."
marks of an almost superhuman rhetorical tact under the circum- Among the outrages in The Phi/.osophy ofthe Enlightenment was the fact
stances. On the other hand, the story of the "dramatic action" of the that the catalytic role that rightfully belonged to Locke had been
philosophy of the Enlightenment also required that a good deal of its usurped by Leibniz;' and, at the other end of the century, that utili-
actualpolitics, reformist or revolutionary, be set aside as well. In point tarianism had disappeared entirely, while the thought of Herder and
offact, it is not quite accurate to speak of a simple repression of a po- Kant was presented as the culmination of the Enlightenment. The
litical moment in the text. Instead, what seems to have occurred was a effect of Cassirer's narrative-obviously unintended by the author, a
displacement from the political to the aesthetic realm-as the other, "good European" -was to add "the Enlightenment to the genealogi-
less divisive domain in which the idea of reason as the active maker of cal. tree of the Nazi movement." The English and French reader,
the world could be brought to earth. The aesthetic theories of Baum- Cobban concluded, could be forgiven for declining to see "the found-
garten and Kant, the artistic achievements of Lessing and Goethe, ers of German idealism and nationalism" as having contributed very
wen; presented, in a sense, as promissory notes for a future politics. If much to the "process of man's progressive self-liberation. ms
the authority for this move can be traced back to Kant himself, there Cassirer had plainly touched a nerve-there is perhaps something
were contemporary parallels as well. In a famous essay on Walter refreshing about recalling so strong a reaction to the book, given the
Benjamin, Fredric Jameson once reminded readers that "nostalgia as a combination of veneration and condescension with which The Phi-
political motivation" - "a nostalgia conscious of itself, a lucid and re- losophy of the Enlightenment tends to be viewed today. Issues of na-
morseless dissatisfaction with the present on the grounds of some re- tional pride aside, the example ofDialectic ofEnlightenment from the
membered plenitude" -was not the privilege of Fascism alone, but Left is there to suggest that Cobban was not entirely wrong to worry,
had its counterparts on the Left. 32 In Cassirer's Philosophy of the En- from the Right, about suggestions of a filiationlinking the European
lightenment, we seem to be presented with asimilarly"lucidnostalgia" Enlightenment to European Fascism. At the same time, it also seems
of the Center, from the same epoch-as if encouraging European lib- clear that what were vices for Cobban were precisely the virtues that
eralism, at its darkest hour, to begin to reconstruct its identity by recommended The Philosophy of th.e Enlightenment to its post-War
means of a meditation on its happy youth. audience, especially in the United States. For this was the moment
when the brand of liberalism for which Cassirer stood had begun' to
Conclusions: Abstraction and Reflection make its astonishing recovery from the trough of the inter-war years,
and was showing the first fruits of this resurgence under American
It would be wrong to suggest that the character of The Phi/.osophy of sponsorship. In the epoch of the Schuman Plan and the Treaty of
the Enlightenment as a political statement-as one of the masterpieces Rome, what could be more appropriate than a portrait of the Enlight-
of Weimar liberalism, a fitting German counterpart to, say, Rug- enment as, in effect, the joint production of French and German
giero's Storia del Liberalismo Europeo- has somehow been overlooked thinkers? In fact, it might be thought that the combination ofpoliti-
until now. Twenty years after its initial publication, the book could cal will and economic design that lay behind the emergent institu-
still provoke surprisingly strong responses. One stands out in its tions of the European Community was a perfect illustration of the
harshness, coming from what may be a surprising source. Writing in new kind of historical agency-philosophic reason in action, remak-
the Spectator in the year after the book's first appearance in English, ing the world-whose origins Cassirer located in the Enlightenment.
Alfred Cobban declared without further ado that Cassirer's portrait of Above all, the intellectual reconstruction of liberalism after the War
the Enlightenment was "profoundly wrong." What the author had required the careful rehabilitation of the main traditions of German
produced, in a misguided effort to demonstrate the fundamental thought and culture. In this regard, one suspects that the lesson of The
JO H N SON KEN T W RIGH T ''.A Bright Clear Mirror"
.99
Philosophy of the Enlightenment for most of its readers in this period, yet to escape." Cassirer himself came down on the side of the Enlight-
especially those in America, was precisely the opposite of that feared enment. But the lesson ofhis book lay not so much in his political de-
by Cobban-the message that Kant, Lessing, Herder, and Goethe cision, as in the methodological model that accompanied it. For Cas-
were all "good Europeans" as well, active contributors to the· collec- sirer's return to the eighteenth century proceeded by means of a
tive, cosmopolitan effort ofthe Enlightenment. ''foundational abstraction" that, on the one hand, set aside the appeals
At the same time, there is an obvious limit to any attempt to ex- to "individual motivation" and ''biographical accident'' that made for
plain the reception of Cassirer's book in primarily political terms. In the substance of psychological explanation, and, on the other, de-
order to arrive at a fuller estimation of the achievements and qualities ferred consideration of social and economic determinations. The re-
that have made The Philosophy ofthe Enlightenment an enduring classic, sult was to uncover, for the first time, an "autonomous world of dis-
we need to turn to a review whose lavish praise is at least as surprising cursive thought," whose ordering principles and laws of motion could
as Cobban's brusque dismissal. A French translation of The Philosophy be grasped in their own terms. What Cassirer had left behind, in his
of the Enlightenment was delayed until 1966, when it was brought out flight from the Nazis, was a manifesto for a new kind of history of
as the inaugural volume in Fayard's Histoire sans frontieres series, ed- thought, still to be accomplished.
ited by Francois Furet and Denis Richet. The first major comment There is an attractive irony in the fact that Foucault could hail The
came from Michel Foucault, fresh from completing Les mots et les cho- Philosophy ofEnlightenment for showing the way to a new intellectual
ses, writing in the Quinzaine litte'raireduring its first year." What history, at precisely the moment that spokesmen for the new "social
made for the "actuality'' of Cassirer's masterpiece, thirty years after its history" of the Enlightenment-whose later practitioners have often
first publication, wrote Foucault, was that we are all in some sense looked to Foucault himself for inspiration -were first declaring its
"neo-Kantians," living with "the impossibility, for Western thought, model obsolete. In retrospect, it is not at all difficult to see the parallels
of overcoming the gash [ coupure] opened up by Kant." The supreme between Cassirer's "phenomenology" and Foucault's "archeology'' of
merit ofThePhi!.osophy ofthe Enlightenment was that it reposed the es- the human sciences, indeed between the project of The Philosophy of
sential question: ''what are the fatalities of reflection and knowledge SymbolicFormsand the whole enterprise ofFoucault's thought, at least
that made Kant possible and necessitated the constitution of modern down to TheArcheology ofKnowledge-convergences all the more strik-
thought?" Kant had sought to establish the conditions ofpossibility of ing, given the embattled "humanism" ofthe one and the strident "anti-
scientific knowledge. In a mimetic gesture that added a profoundly humanism" ofthe other. In any case, Foucault was certainly right about
important reflexive dimension, Cassirer set out to establish the condi- one aspect of the lasting appeal of The Philosophy of the Enlightenment.
tions of possibility for Kantianism itself, the "enigma" that for two We have seen that Cassirer set out to overturn the Romantic verdict on
centuries has rendered Western thought ''blind to its modernity." For the Enlightenment's "shallowness." His success in establishing its
there is nothing less at stake here, Foucault went on, than the identity philosophic depth, once and for all, depended on just the manner of
and autonomy of modernity itself. Two great currents of nostalgic "foundational abstraction" described by Foucault-his bracketing of
identification have flowed from the birth of the modern epoch at the explanations ofeither a psychological or social kind, in order to focus on
end of the eighteenth century: a ''Hellenism," extending from Hold- a description ofthe "dramatic action" of the thought of the Enlighten-
erlin to Heidegger, and an attachment to the Enlightenment, de- ment. The result was what remains to this day the most vivid and finely
scending from Marx to Levi-Strauss. ''To be Greek or Enlightened, wrought of all general surveys of eighteenth-century philosophy, a
on the side oftragedy or the Encyclopedia, that of poetry or the well- majorworkofhistoricalliterature as well as scholarship. In fact, Cassirer
made language, that of the morning of Being or the noon of Repre- achieved more than just effective description in The Philosophy of the
sentation, such is the dilemma from which modem thought ... has Enlightenment. His roots in the dialectical tradition of classical Idealism
IOO JOHNSON KENT WRIGHT ':A. Bright Clear Mirror, rot

made it possible to give the book a narrative thrust that is lacking in neque detestare, sed intelligere" ("Smile not, lament not, nor condemn,
Foucault's own handling of "discursive thought," in which, notori- but understand"). Indeed, much of the power of Cassirer's text de-
ously, narrative explanation ofideas, or their dynamic over time, tends rives precisely from its serene, even Olympian "objectivity''-from
to give way to static description and categorization. This, in tum, the sense that one is gazing on the Enlightenment from the "out-
probably explains why it has never proven particularly difficult for later side," affording a view of it as a whole, as a totality, together with a
historians to restore one "missing'' dimension or another to Cassirer's fleeting glimpse ofits place within an even larger narrative of struggle
account of the Enlightenment, without dramatically altering its sub- and emancipation.
stance. Cassirer's own essay on Rousseau shows how easily the move to In the end, we are left with Cassirer's own image for grasping our
biographical evidence and explanation could be made; the different relationship to the eighteenth century from the vantage-point of the
"social histories" ofGay and Darnton reveal something ofthe same for twentieth -the notion of the Enlightenment as holding up a "bright
the restoration of Cassirer's "high Enlightenment'' texts to their social clear mirror'' to the present. The metaphor is more studied and am-
and economic context. biguous than might appear at first glance. Elsewhere in Cassirer's
But what ofthe other dimension of The Philosophy of the Enlighten- writing, reflection ofthis kind could take on a sinister aspect. In the first
ment highlighted by Foucault-not its method, but its parti pris? It is chapter of The Myth of the State he invoked the scene in the "Witch's
evident that Foucault respected Cassirer's quiet defense of the En- Kitchen" from the first part ofFaust, in which Faust, in pursuit of eter-
lightenment, even if the choice was not quite his own. In specifying nal youth, falls prey to a beautiful phantom glimpsed in an enchanted
the two great alternatives facing the modem age-the camps, rough- glass-the shadow of his own imagination, scoffs Mephistopheles."
ly, ofEnlightened rationalism and Romantic reaction - Foucault sug- The menace in question here was the Romantic retreat to mythical
gested in an aside that the "monstrosity" of Nietzsche was perhaps to thought, in whosemirrorcouldfirst be glimpsed the furies later set free
belong to both at the same time; a sentence later, he asserted that if bynationalism andfascism. Other thinkers have ofcourse seen a return
the antithesis still dominated modern thought, it was nevertheless ofrepressedelements ofmythical thought in the Enlightenment itself,
possible to sense it "shaking beneath our feet." The hope of discover- "intertwined"withits rationalism. For his part, Cassirer allowed that a
ing a third path, of eluding a choice between, as it were, Marx and gaze in the mirror ofthe Enlightenmentwaslikely to be disconcerting:
Heidegger, of course animated Foucault for much of his intellectual "Much that seems to us todaytheresult of'progress' will be sure to lose
career. Unlike many of his postmodern successors, however, it is not its luster when seen in this mirror; and much that we boast ofwill look
clear that Foucault was ever satisfied that he found such a path- nor, strange and distorted in this perspective."Nevertheless, he went on,
like other thinkers who followed, was he ever tempted by a retreat to "we should be guilty ofbastyjudgment and dangerous self-deception if
Heidegger. If anything, the itinerary ofhis later career, with its com- we were simplyto ascribe these distortions to opaque spots in the mir-
pulsive returns to the terrain of Kant, suggests that Foucault's final ror, rather than to look elsewhere for their source. The slogan: Sapere
position was rather closer to that of Cassirer than might be expected. aude, which Kant called the 'motto of the Enlightenment,' also holds
As for The Philosophy of the Enlightenment, if it is indeed the most for our own historical relation to that period.'?" More than sixty years
compelling of all twentieth-century "defenses" ofthe Enlightenment, later,itisnotclearthattheenchantedglassoftheEnlightenment, with
it is surely not by way of any straightforward identificatwn with its its dear reflections, opacities, and "distortions," has exhausted all ofits
object of study-in the style, say, of Gay's TheEnlightenment:Anin- lessons for us. For those still gazing into this mirror, friends and foes of
terpretation. At the outset, Cassirer warned his readers that he in- philosophical modernism alike, The Philosophy of the Enlightenment re-
tended neither to celebrate nor to criticize the Enlightenment; his mains an incomparable guide.
motto was instead borrowed from Spinoza- "non ridere, non lugere,

You might also like