You are on page 1of 19

AI & SOCIETY

https://doi.org/10.1007/s00146-018-0810-3

ORIGINAL ARTICLE

Skillful coping with and through technologies

Some challenges and avenues for a Dreyfus-inspired philosophy of technology

Mark Coeckelbergh1

Received: 22 May 2017 / Accepted: 24 January 2018


© The Author(s) 2018. This article is an open access publication

Abstract
Dreyfus’s work is widely known for its critique of artificial intelligence and still stands as an example of how to do excel-
lent philosophical work that is at the same time relevant to contemporary technological and scientific developments. But for
philosophers of technology, especially for those sympathetic to using Heidegger, Merleau-Ponty, and Wittgenstein as sources
of inspiration, it has much more to offer. This paper outlines Dreyfus’s account of skillful coping and critically evaluates its
potential for thinking about technology. First, it is argued that his account of skillful coping can be developed into a general
view about handling technology which gives due attention to know-how/implicit knowledge and embodiment. Then a number
of outstanding challenges are identified that are difficult to cope with if one remains entirely within the world of Dreyfus’s
writings. They concern (1) questions regarding other conceptualizations of technology and human–technology relations,
(2) issues concerning how to conceptualize the social and the relation between skill, meaning, and practices, and (3) the
question about the ethical and political implications of his view, including how virtue and skill are related. Acknowledging
some known discussions about Dreyfus’s work, but also drawing on other material and on the author’s previous writings,
the paper suggests that to address these challenges and develop the account of skillful coping into a wider scoped, Dreyfus-
inspired philosophy of technology, it could take more distance from Heidegger’s conceptions of technology and benefit from
(more) engagement with work in postphenomenology (Ihde), pragmatism (Dewey), the later Wittgenstein, and virtue ethics.

Keywords Dreyfus · Skillful coping · Technology · The social · Virtue · Wittgenstein · Dewey

1 Introduction recreate the human brain are gaining more traction than they
deserve.
For philosophers of technology, Dreyfus’s work is an attrac- But there is more to Dreyfus’s work than thinking about
tive and outstanding example of how one can combine philo- AI, and there is much more to be gained from it for thinking
sophical thinking with a focus on specific technologies such about technology, especially for those philosophers sympa-
as artificial intelligence (AI), and indeed how one can do thetic to using Heidegger, Merleau-Ponty, and Wittgenstein.
excellent philosophy by thinking about technology. Com- This paper focuses on Dreyfus’s account of skillful coping
pared to the often shallow contemporary debates about AI, and critically evaluates its potential for thinking about tech-
robotics, or transhumanism, for example, Dreyfus’s think- nologies today. After sketching a brief working account of
ing is a relief. His philosophical arguments against the idea skillful coping and exploring what it means for thinking
that AI can give us a human-like general intelligence are about technology, a number of challenges are identified and
still highly relevant today, when absurd Platonic–Cartesian some avenues to cope with these challenges are opened up—
ideas such as mind uploading or projects trying to artificially partly by drawing on Dreyfus and partly by going against or
beyond Dreyfus.
In particular, the paper identifies problems related to
* Mark Coeckelbergh (1) Dreyfus’s selection of tool use as the only way to con-
mark.coeckelbergh@univie.ac.at ceptualize technology (and what Ihde calls the ‘embodi-
1 ment’ relation as the only relevant human–technology rela-
University of Vienna, Universitätsstraße 7, 1010 Vienna,
Austria tion), together with the unfortunate repetition of the (later)

13
Vol.:(0123456789)
AI & SOCIETY

Heidegger’s inconsistencies and bias regarding contempo- he worked out with his brother Stuart Dreyfus (1980a), and
rary technologies; (2) his underdeveloped conceptualization in subsequent papers—some of which are bundled in the
of the social and of the relations between skill, meaning, book Skillful Coping (2014)—that further elaborated this
and practice; and (3) the question regarding the ethical and account and defended it against some objections. The main
political implications of his view, including the question how idea is that in practical activity and skillful coping, we do
skill and virtue are related. In the course of the paper, there not rely on rules or mental representations, at least when
will be references to some known debates about Dreyfus’s we gain a sufficiently high degree of expertise and mastery.
approach, which are often related to its Heideggerian dimen- In Being and Time (1927), Heidegger already made a dis-
sion, such as his Heideggerian interpretation of ground and tinction between two modes of experiencing a tool: when
his conceptualization of the social in terms of ‘das Man’ we use a tool, the tool withdraws, we do not notice it. It
(translated by Dreyfus as ‘the Anyone’). But the paper will is ready-to-hand. Under other circumstances, for instance
also introduce other material to the discussion about Drey- when something goes wrong, it might become present-at-
fus’s work, such as Ihde and Dewey. hand. But the “default” mode, we may say, is ready-to-hand.
This will lead to opening up some avenues that are not For example, when I use my computer to write this paper, I
(fully) present in Dreyfus’s own writings. In response to the do not notice the computer; but when the operating system
problems identified, the paper proposes some ways in which crashes, the technology becomes present-at-hand. Moreo-
a Dreyfus-inspired phenomenology of technology use and ver, in our skillful coping, we do not usually need mental
skill can be constructed and elaborated, but also revised, to representations. In Phenomenology of Perception (1962),
address or avoid the problems previously indicated. Concep- Merleau-Ponty already emphasized embodiment and what
tual tools offered include philosophical schools and tradi- Dreyfus interprets as a critique of mental representation
tions Dreyfus sympathized with, but—focusing mainly on (Dreyfus 2002a). He explains that Merleau-Ponty’s terms
Heidegger and Merleau-Ponty—never (fully) used: postphe- ‘the intentional arc’ and ‘getting a maximal grip’ imply that
nomenology, Dewey, the later Wittgenstein, and the tradition skill, as a tight connection between the agent and the world,
of virtue ethics—the latter interpreted in a way that replaces is not stored in the form of representations in the mind, but
the Platonic and Aristotelian obsession with theory with the instead as an embodied tendency to respond (Dreyfus 2002a,
love of practical wisdom and know-how and an emphasis on 367); we are already set to respond, so to speak (373). Influ-
the exercise of skill. In the course of the paper, some of these enced by Heidegger and Merleau-Ponty, Dreyfus, in turn,
suggestions and new directions are supported by referring argued that our knowledge of handling things involves a
to the author’s own work on skill and technology, which is know-how that is not explicit. We are absorbed in what we
inspired by Dreyfus’s view but also critical of it. do, perhaps even in a state of “flow”, and we respond to the
In the conclusion, the suggestions and directions offered situation: ‘According to Merleau-Ponty, in absorbed, skill-
in the course of the paper are drawn together and presented ful coping, I don’t need a mental representation of my goal.
as elements for a Dreyfus-inspired (but perhaps not Drey- Rather, acting is experienced as a steady flow of skillful
fusian) research program in philosophy of technology. It is activity in response to one’s sense of the situation.’ (Dreyfus
also stressed that the general direction Dreyfus took in his 2002a, 378).
thinking on skill is not only important for philosophy of Against representationalism and Cartesianism in philos-
technology, but also stands as one of the conceptual building ophy of mind and action, Dreyfus argued that the phenom-
blocks all philosophers have at their disposal today to cope enology of, and knowledge involved in, practical activity
with a ghost that continues to haunt both philosophy and AI: and skill acquisition is not based on rules or mental repre-
the crazy idea that knowledge and thinking can be entirely sentations, but involves a coping that, especially when one
formalized and divorced from lived experience and active is an expert, is based on implicit know-how and intuition.
coping in the world. Our activity may be goal directed, but we do not think
about the goal. Deliberation only comes in when coping is
blocked (Dreyfus 2002a, 381), or indeed when we learn a
2 Dreyfus’s account of skillful coping new skill. We need rules when we are novices, but experts
and its implications for thinking can do without them: rules are for beginners (Dreyfus
about technology and Dreyfus 1980a). As we move through stages of skill
development, we rely on concrete experience rather than
2.1 Skillful coping abstract principles. In the paper written with his brother
Stuart they give the examples of language learning, chess
Dreyfus’s “skillful coping” view is based on his reading of playing, and flying an airplane, which entail perfor-
the early Heidegger of Being and Time (1927), and has later mances and responses without the application of rules or
found expression in the account of skill development, which principles: ‘The expert pilot, having finally reached this

13
AI & SOCIETY

non-analytical stage of performance, responds intuitively on a meaningless Given.’ (Dreyfus 2005, 49). Instead, in our
and appropriately to his current situation.’ (Dreyfus and everyday coping, the world is already meaningful for us.
Dreyfus 1980, 12). Moreover, experts can have the experi- Moreover, whereas McDowell interprets Aristotle’s
ence that they are intensely absorbed in what they do. Here account of practical wisdom (phronesis) in terms of respond-
there is no longer self-monitoring at all: ing to reasons, Dreyfus, using Heidegger, argued that prac-
tical wisdom is more like seeing what to do in a particular
‘masterful performance only takes place when the
situation; it is about being ‘responsive to the specific situa-
expert, who no longer needs principles, can cease to
tion’ (Dreyfus 2005, 51). Or more precisely: both thinkers
pay conscious attention to his performance and can let
share the interpretation of Aristotle’s concept of practical
all the mental energy previously used in monitoring his
wisdom in terms of responding to specific situations (Riet-
performance go into producing almost instantaneously
veld 2010, 189), but they have a different view of the role
the appropriate perspective and its associated action.’
of reasons and concepts in this responding. According to
(Dreyfus and Dreyfus 1980, 14).
McDowell, we respond to reasons and rationality ‘perme-
Other terms that qualify this experience are ‘holistic’ and ates’ even unreflective action (McDowell 2007, 368) and
‘integrated’. Elsewhere Dreyfus argued that bodily skills concepts are ‘operative’ in unreflective action (372); they
such as swimming requires a kind of unification and inte- show themselves in the activity. It is rationality in action (see
gration, and cannot be reduced to rules and a sequences of also Rietveld 2010, 193). According to Dreyfus, by contrast,
movements learned by beginners: reasons are ‘retroactive rationalizations’ (Dreyfus 2005,
51) and unreflective action is not about rationality. Dreyfus
‘Even though bodily skills, for example, are sometimes
repeated that when we learn a skill, we may use rules as
learned by following rules which dictate a sequence
a kind of aid first, but like the training wheels of children
of simple movements, when the performer becomes
who learn to ride a bicycle, when we become experts we
proficient the simple movements are left behind and a
can leave them out and we switch to ‘a more involved and
single unified, flexible, purposive pattern of behavior
situated way of coping.’ (52).
is all that remains. It makes no sense to attempt to
Dreyfus’s point was not that mental representation, goal
capture a skill by using a representation of the original
directedness, reasons, etc. play no role at all in human expe-
elements used by beginners, since these elements are
rience; the point was that they do not usually play a role
not integrated into the final skill.’ (Dreyfus 1980, 9).
when we decide as experts; they may play a role at earlier
In contrast to computers, which need to recognize an stages (Dreyfus 2002b, 413). He thus stressed that some cen-
object to manipulate it, Dreyfus argued, humans do it in a tral cases of intelligent behavior—indeed most of our eve-
more gestalt-like manner and instead can ‘manipulate an ryday coping—do not require mental representations (414).
object in order to recognize it’—in other words, they cope He rejected the view that we can only act if we have reasons
with the object (Dreyfus 1967, 21). to do so; reasons play no role and rather get in the way.
Against McDowell, Dreyfus argued that experience is not Instead we have to sharpen our ability to make refined dis-
inherently conceptual and that we have to overcome the myth criminations (Dreyfus 2005, 52). And of course a game has
of the mental (Dreyfus 2005). While it is plausible that, as rules, but these rules are not stored in the mind or not even
Rietveld has argued, both McDowell and Dreyfus share the followed; instead, the expert copes and in her coping she is
view that our engagements with the world are situated and sensitive to the rules of the game (53). Everyday coping is
are each in their own way committed to phenomenology— intentional, but not conceptual. We respond to what Gibson
a view McDowell reached through Wittgenstein (Rietveld called ‘affordances’, which happens without thinking at all
2010, 185); Dreyfus mainly through Heidegger—Dreyfus (56). For example, doors afford going in and out, but we do
did not share the former’s strong emphasis on the rational not have to think about them—let alone calculate. When we
and conceptual. Perception is not conceptual “all the way learned a skill, we masterfully respond to specific situations.
out”, as McDowell agued; instead, Dreyfus focused on non- This gives us a familiarity with the world and openness to
conceptual embodied coping (Dreyfus 2005, 47). Against the world, which is not a totality of objects or of states of
cognitivism and against representing things from ‘a detached affairs. Instead we know how, and our skill opens a world.
theoretical perspective’ (49), he argued that our everyday Our conceptual capacities grow ‘out of our nonconceptual
coping does not require our minds to impose meaning onto ones’ (61).
the world: ‘We need to consider the possibility that embod- In ‘The Return of the Myth of the Mental’ (Dreyfus
ied beings like us take as input energy from the physical 2007a), Dreyfus continued his arguments against McDow-
universe and process it in such a way as to open them to a ell, this time against the claim that in mature human
world organized in terms of their needs, interests, and bodily beings, embodied coping is permeated with mindedness.
capacities without their minds needing to impose a meaning Dreyfus stressed again the non-conceptual and non-mental

13
AI & SOCIETY

content of skillful coping and performing. We can moni- consist of representations at all (Dreyfus 1980b, 9). (I will
tor our performances while performing, but this actually soon say more about this.)
degrades the performance itself, especially since it dis-
rupts the mindless absorbed coping. Of course we can step 2.2 Technology
back and reflect, but also that kind of conceptual intention-
ality is based on a ground-floor of motor intentionality, Whether or not Dreyfus’s model of skill acquisition is a
and there is still involved coping going on in the back- sound interpretation of Heidegger (for a discussion see
ground. Luckily we are only ‘part-time rational animals’ Breivik 2007), it is an attractive model for understanding
(Dreyfus 2007a, 354); we can exercise our freedom as the everyday use and handling of technologies. Technology
humans not so much by thinking rationally, but rather by can be a tool we use, or (as we can add using postphenom-
opening ourselves ‘to being bound’—entering our involved enology—see the next section) it can be a medium through
coping (355). In this coping there is no thinking subject which we handle objects. In both cases, following Dreyfus
(358); rather, the world may afford or solicit: we can say that skillful coping is involved—at least when
we are expert users. There is no need to think about the
‘According to Merleau-Ponty, at the most basic level
technology; if we are experts there is even no need to think at
of being in the world, what does the grasping is not
all. We respond skillfully to the situation. Through technol-
the mind but the body with its nonconceptual coping
ogy the world offers affordances and solicitations, without
skills, and what is grasped are not unified, proposi-
any need for representation by means of concepts. Many
tional structures that one can observe and entertain in
examples Dreyfus uses are technological, such as using a
thought, but more or less indeterminate solicitations
doorknob or driving a car: the expert driver does not need
to act.’ (Dreyfus 2007a, 359).
to think about rules on how to shift the gears; if the driver is
To use one of Dreyfus’s examples: when we take a sufficiently skilled, there is a bodily response appropriate to
doorknob to open the door, we do not think about this the situation. Thus, apart from everything else it may be (e.g.
affordance or solicitation. We respond and do all this with- a significant contribution to epistemology, philosophy of
out thinking. Again, we can step back, but only against mind, etc.), Dreyfus’s account of skillful coping is to be seen
a pervasive background (363). Yet like in his previous as a contribution to thinking about technology, to the extent
paper on the topic, Dreyfus acknowledges that there is that it enables us to say more about the kind of knowledge
still an outstanding issue: we still want to know how the and experience involved in the use of everyday technologies
conceptual world is related to, or emerges from, the non- such as hammers, cars, and doorknobs. It seems especially
conceptual world (364). (I will return to this issue.) suitable to think about the handling of tools and equipment.
Moreover, against Searle, Dreyfus argued that social Sometimes Dreyfus explicitly addressed the question
meaning and norms are not representational (Dreyfus how we use tools. Drawing on Heidegger, Merleau-Ponty,
1999) and do not require intentional action. According and Polanyi, he argued that how we use a tool differs from
to Dreyfus, our experience of our everyday involvement explicit experience and representational knowledge of an
conflicts with the logic of constitution and reconstruction object. Taking up Merleau-Ponty’s example of the blind
proposed by Searle (Dreyfus 2001a, 181). The problem man’s stick, he writes:
is not that analysts construct a rational account; we can
‘A blind man who runs his hand along the stick he uses
do that. But it is wrong to suppose that we give mean-
to grope his way will be aware of its objective charac-
ing to artefacts. According to Dreyfus, following Hei-
teristics. When he is using it, however, he is not aware
degger and other existential phenomenologists, meaning
of its objective traits nor of the pressure in the palm of
must not be brought into a meaningless universe; there
his hand. Rather, the stick has become, like his body,
is already a meaningful world (Dreyfus 2001a, 186). We
a transparent access to objects.’ (Dreyfus 1967, 27).
are ‘from the start socialized into a world in which we
cope with equipment’ (187). For example, to use money According to Dreyfus, this use has nothing to do with
(Searle’s paradigmatic example), there is no need to think making calculations or with following rules or principles.
“this piece of paper counts as money”; we just use it and It is an embodied kind of coping, a learning of skill: I first
already see it as valuable if we grew up with it (189). happen to touch something and then I repeat it, correct it,
There is already a meaningful world. There is already a and so on. I consciously intervene to improve my perfor-
cultural style, which we already pick up as a baby. There is mance. But there is not first a knowledge of rules. Whereas
already something binding on us, and we learn it without the skilled performance may be described (from the outside,
having to be conscious about the rules (195–196). Else- by science—for instance to build a robot) in terms of rules,
where Dreyfus wrote that there is a background to which ‘these rules need in no way be involved in producing the
we respond: a background of practices, which does not performance.’ (Dreyfus 1967, 29). Hence—and luckily, we

13
AI & SOCIETY

may add—we can dwell in the world without having to for- thinking about technologies today, his view has great poten-
malize everything (31). tial. It seems suitable to be connected to other approaches
Does this mean that experts use no rules at all? I propose in contemporary philosophy of technology such as postphe-
to distinguish between a ‘strong view’ and a ‘weak view’. nomenology (see the next section) that also emphasizes how
According to the strong view, experts qua experts use no technology is part of the lifeworld.
rules at all when they do what they are good at. Perhaps they However, if we want to develop his account of skilled
use rules when they learn something new, but normally they coping into a wider scoped philosophy of technology, we
do not need rules. According to the weaker view, experts use need more reflection on technology. Not all technology is
both rules and implicit knowledge, depending on the situa- ‘tool’ or ‘equipment’, or is something we handle and which
tion. Dreyfus seems to have held the strong view. For the use disappears from view in our use and handling; there are
of technologies, it means that expert users of technology use more phenomena and experiences we can associate with
it without rules and that everyday coping with and through technology. And, related: it is striking that Dreyfus’s exam-
technology happens without the use of concepts. ples of everyday artefacts—at least in his work on skilled
This strong view also implies that even the attribution of coping—are all old technologies; what does his account
situation-specific aspects (in and by thinking) is excluded. In mean for contemporary technologies and media such as
this response to McDowell (2007b), who, as we have seen, the internet and smartphones? Surprisingly, Dreyfus was
emphasizes the role of concepts and rationality even in far more pessimistic about contemporary technologies than
unreflective action, Dreyfus also uses the example of using one would expect from his account of skillful coping. To put
tools—now taking up Heidegger’s example of the hammer. it somewhat simplistically: he did not have a problem with
Dreyfus argues that we do not even need a situation-specific hammers, but he did have a problem with the internet. Can
concept: this discrimination be justified, or is it a bias—one not dis-
similar to the bias Heidegger had against modern technolo-
‘Indeed, in our everyday coping, which he (Heidegger)
gies? And can it be justified on the basis of Dreyfus’s own
calls ‘‘pressing into possibilities”, we don’t deal with
theory of skillful coping?
objects with general properties like weight, nor with
situation-specific aspects like too heavy. Rather, when
everything is going well and we are absorbed in our
3 Problems with Dreyfus’s conceptions
coping, the equipment we are using “withdraws”
of technology
(where, as we shall see, this does not mean becomes
implicit). Then there is no place for a demonstrative
If we want to make Dreyfus’s account of skill fruitful for
concept pointing out our equipment as anything. We
philosophy of technology, we encounter a number of prob-
do not attribute a general property or even a situation-
lems that are related to the limitations of Dreyfus’s Heideg-
specific aspect to it; we just cope.’ (Dreyfus 2007b,
gerian conceptions of technology.
371–372).
Like in Heidegger texts, there are roughly two ways in
Thus, according to Dreyfus, our everyday coping is not which technology appears in Dreyfus’s work. The first one is
permeated by conceptuality at all. When we look at the phe- technology as a tool, used in everyday coping. This meaning
nomenology of tool use, we usually see absorbed coping. In is based on the early Heidegger—Being and Time (1927).
absorbed coping, when performance is at its peak, there is no The second one is technology in its modern and contempo-
monitoring going on; there is ‘flow’ (Dreyfus 2007b, 373). rary forms, such as the internet. Technology is then seen as
He uses again the example of a tool: ‘I don’t see the door- a treat to meaning and skilled engagement. Here one could
knob as a doorknob when I’m absorbed in using it’ (375). see the influence of the later Heidegger, who embraced craft
There is a direct response to the situation, no concept or work but argued that modern technology is enframing and
thinking. Conceptual mindedness, Dreyfus suggests, is only constitutes a danger (Heidegger 1977). Both conceptualiza-
possible against the background of non-conceptual, absorbed tions of technology can be criticized, have been criticized
coping (376–377). (for instance in postphenomenology), and must be criticized.
These examples show that technology, in the form of The first meaning of technology (technology as tool)
tools or equipment, is important for Dreyfus; it is part of makes sense, but is limited to one human–technology rela-
our (life) world. The already-meaningful world is a world tion. Of course we often relate to technology as a tool, and
in which we cope with equipment: we are socialized into a it is the case that in our use of the tool, the tool usually
world ‘in which we cope with equipment’ (Dreyfus 2001a, becomes invisible. But as Ihde has shown (Ihde 1990), there
187). In this sense, Dreyfus already has a philosophy of are more human–technology relations. Dreyfus focuses on
technology, or rather this work, the philosophy of skilled what Ihde calls embodiment: a relation in which the technol-
coping, is entangled with the philosophy of technology. For ogy withdraws in use. But technology can also appear, for

13
AI & SOCIETY

example, as reality to be interpreted or “read” (hermeneutic transcendence implied affirming, not denying our bodily and
relation) or as quasi-other (alterity relation). Phenomeno- mortal nature), it is not clear why our use of the internet,
logically speaking, a thermometer is not so much a tool as or for that matter all contemporary digital or information
a feature of the world we perceive. And if we encounter a technology, would be disembodied use. Dreyfus seemed to
humanoid robot, we do not always relate to it as a tool, but have confused the Platonic and Cartesian visions of some
often the robot is interacted with as if it was a human other. net enthusiasts with the phenomenology of the lifeworld.
When it comes to his work on skill, Dreyfus unnecessar- As I have argued against Dreyfus in Human Being @ Risk
ily limits his discussion of technology to tools. It would be (Coeckelbergh 2013a), when we are online or in virtual
interesting to discuss the role of skills and embodied cop- worlds we are still embodied and our so-called “online”
ing in, for instance, the “reading” of technologies and in actions and thinking is still embodied: ‘When we are online,
our encounters with machines. Here postphenomenological we don’t leave our body at home.’ (Coeckelbergh 2013a,
analysis is more sensitive to the various ways in which we 130). Use of these technologies does not close off possi-
experience technologies, whereas Dreyfus has more to say bilities for skilled engagement (Coeckelbergh 2013a, 132).
on the skill dimension. A combination of both approaches Elsewhere, I have also argued, against Dreyfus, that when
seems promising. For example, if it is the case that many we use the internet, we are actively related to our environ-
technologies ‘mediate’ our experience and actions (Verbeek ment as embodied beings, and information technology does
2005 and subsequent work), then using Dreyfus enables us involve skills (Coeckelbergh 2011a, 152). In other words, it
to argue that they do this by re-shaping our skilled engage- is also a form of skilled coping. And, in principle, it could
ment with the world and with others. also be a site for the acquisition of new skills and the learn-
The second meaning of technology appears in Dreyfus’s ing of mastery. It is true that, as Dreyfus argued, for masters
work on the internet (Dreyfus 2001b). Here contemporary to respond immediately to present situations in a masterful
technology is seen as alienating and meaningless, in contrast way, they must have had experience of embodied successes
to craftwork (again referring to the use of tools). Accord- and failures (Dreyfus 2001a, b, 67). But use of the inter-
ing to Dreyfus, ‘distance-apprenticeship is an oxymoron’ net, including distance learning, is also a kind of embodied
(Dreyfus 2001a, 67). Moreover, Dreyfus assumes that when learning—albeit (it must be admitted) of a different kind.
we ‘enter cyberspace’ we leave behind our ‘vulnerable, Dreyfus may have contributed to dispel the myth of
embodied selves’ and avoid risk as disembodied web surf- the mental; he still seemed to have believed in what we
ers, remote from the real (6). could call the myth of the virtual (or the myth of the real
Dreyfus has rightly raised issues concerning distance, as opposed to the virtual): the belief that somehow, when
embodiment, and meaning. It is important to evaluate uses we use the internet and related contemporary information
of contemporary technologies in these terms. But there are technologies, we are in a different reality (an online, vir-
at least the following problems with this analysis. tual world), which is disconnected with the real reality. But
First, as Verbeek and others have argued, Heidegger’s Heidegger’s and Dreyfus’s own approaches try to move
conception of modern technology is biased and conserva- beyond dualist frameworks, and on the basis of Dreyfus’s
tive (Verbeek 2005). It is not clear why modern technology own account of skillful coping, one could claim that in
would be necessarily more alienating than ancient technolo- these uses of contemporary technologies, the technology
gies. Dreyfus seems to adopt this view. In my book Envi- also often withdraws, and that embodied coping is going
ronmental Skill (Coeckelbergh 2015) I have argued that the on, mediated by the new technologies. There is no outside
internet is not necessarily alienating. Technology might to being-in-the-world and existence; we remain earthly and
sometimes lead to more engagement with the world, for situated beings. There is one lifeworld (Coeckelbergh 2011a,
instance when it attends us to features of our environment we 153). If there is alienation, it cannot be defined in this way.
may not have noticed. For this purpose it is also necessary If there is alienation at all, it needs to be conceptualized as a
to describe and reflect on the phenomenology of technolo- problem of a particular use and relation, rather than as some-
gies as opposed to ‘modern technology’ as Heidegger did thing linked to the technology as such. There is a problem
(see also again Verbeek 2005). Second, to see technology with regard to distance and telepresence, but it should not
as meaningless, or as leading to less meaningful lives (or be conceptualized in terms of a total absence of embodi-
even nihilism), contrasts with Dreyfus’s (and Heidegger’s) ment. At most, it is a different kind of embodiment. There
own view that the world is always already meaningful and might be a problem with regard to meaning, but it cannot be
that we use technology as embodied beings. This leads us, the total loss of meaning, since if that use is a skillful cop-
third, to the questions regarding embodiment. While Dreyfus ing it has meaning, and in the spirit of Dreyfus, Heidegger,
is right to expose the problematic recurrence of Platonic and the later Wittgenstein, we can say that use takes place
dream of leaving the body behind (and correctly argues that against the background of a meaningful whole. It may be
Nietzsche would reject transhumanism since his vision of the case that the processing of date itself is meaningless; but

13
AI & SOCIETY

phenomenologically there is no “in itself”; our experience But driving expertise is not only about the operations as
and our engagement with computers our phones and our such; it also consists of participating in traffic. Traffic is a
coping with data never is without meaning, and makes sense social phenomenon and hence driving, in the wider sense,
against a wider background of meaning. is a social practice. To be skilled in driving means not only
This takes us to Dreyfus’s view of ‘the background’, to be able to operate the machine but also to respond to
which I shall further discuss in the next section. situations in traffic—including its morally relevant features
(Coeckelbergh 2016). But describing this requires a phe-
nomenology that is not only about how I related to “world”,
4 Problems with Dreyfus’s (under-) but also about others. It requires a more social and relational
conceptualization of the social phenomenology.
Let me first explore how this link to the social may be
A related but different outstanding problem raised by Drey- conceptualized from a Dreyfusian (that is, mainly Heideg-
fus’s account of skillful coping is how skillful coping is gerian) perspective—before suggesting some alternatives
related to meanings not limited to a particular skilled per- that go beyond Dreyfus and take inspiration from Wittgen-
formance, meanings that have to do with the relevant prac- stein and Dewey. Like Heidegger, Dreyfus does not address
tice, and more generally the social. Skillful coping does not the social as his primary focus. But, like Heidegger, that
happen in a social vacuum, but is always already linked to does not mean that he does not mention it or that we cannot
larger practices and to a wider social background. Although (re)construct some conception of the social based on this
Dreyfus acknowledges this, the account of skillful coping writings. A good place to start is Dreyfus’s references to
itself is not very helpful for conceptualizing it. If we want an practices and to the ‘background’. Then I will turn to his
approach to philosophy of technology that says more about use of the Heideggerian concept of ‘das Man’ (the Anyone).
technology than what happens at the level of individual cop-
ing, and that is still inspired by Dreyfus, then his underde-
4.1 Dreyfus on the (social?) background
veloped dimension of Dreyfus’s work needs to be exposed,
discussed, and repaired.
The question regarding the background arises from the (tran-
Partly Dreyfus’s problem here is also a problem for phe-
scendental) question about what must be presupposed for
nomenology. One recurring problem with all phenomeno-
a particular practical experience and skillful coping. For
logical approaches—including postphenomenology—is a
example, driving is only possible, and makes sense, against
tendency to limit phenomenological analysis to individual
a background of a shared practice and shared norms and
subjects and their relation to the world. This is also applica-
beliefs about what counts as good behavior. Driving is also
ble to other phenomenological approaches in philosophy of
related to other practices, such as (getting to) work and shop-
technology. For example, in Ihde (1990) and Verbeek (2005),
ping. Ultimately, driving is also part of an entire culture and
the social and the cultural is of course acknowledged, but
way of doing, which I would call, with Wittgenstein, a form
there is a focus on an “I” that relates to “world”, mediated
of life. (See below.) Yet “norms” and “beliefs” may already
by technologies. The root of this problem lies in the classic
be a bridge too far for Dreyfus, who sees background as
phenomenological tradition (Husserl and Heidegger), or at
something that cannot be made explicit at all. Why?
least in individualistic readings of it. From the perspective
According to Dreyfus, understanding must not be seen as
of other approaches in philosophy of technology such as
a merely epistemological or theoretical problem. Of course
critical theory and (I will add) pragmatism, but also from
we interpret and explicate, but the basis is practical under-
approaches in the social sciences (social studies of science
standing: everyday coping. Practical understanding must be
and technology, for instance), it must be asked if Dreyfus
viewed in a holistic way. This approach is what Dreyfus
sufficiently conceptualized the social and took it seriously.
calls practical holism. He uses one of his favorite activities
For philosophy of technology, this is an important criticism
to illustrate what this means:
to discuss, since, as social studies of science and technology
approaches have always emphasized, technology is embed- ‘Practical understanding is holistic in an entirely dif-
ded in a social context and cannot be appropriately studied ferent way from theoretical understanding. Although
without taking into consideration the social dimension. practical understanding—everyday coping with
Consider Dreyfus’s example of driving a car. The account things and people—involves explicit beliefs and
of skillful coping is very good in describing the operation hypotheses, these can only be meaningful in spe-
of the car in the sense of changing gears, braking, steer- cific contexts and against a background of shared
ing—and indeed the coordination of all these operations. practices. And just as we can learn to swim without
When one is an expert driver, the skills involved no longer consciously or unconsciously acquiring a theory of
require instruction or rules; they are embodied and intuitive. swimming, we acquire these social background prac-

13
AI & SOCIETY

tices by being brought up in them, not by forming involved in the learning of skill and in coping—is also
beliefs and learning rules.’ (Dreyfus 1980b, 7). a seat of meaning and a concrete incorporation of the
background.
Here Dreyfus seems to acknowledge the social and the
Dreyfus is right to point to the background as a seat of
cultural. Based on Dreyfus, we could see the social in
meaning that is already there, and which usually does not
terms of (the totality of) shared practices, which form the
need to be made explicit to function. But based on this analy-
background of everyday coping and beliefs, and which
sis of background, it is not so clear how the social comes in,
‘make us who we are’ (Dreyfus 1980b, 10). The social
and if the social as background must always remain entirely
and the culture are thus embodied in our practices. This
inexplicit. Does Dreyfus really mean that the background
is also the case for scientific practices, which are only
cannot even partly be made explicit in terms of rules or
possible against background practices (16). However,
norms? Is the idea of a social science, which arguably has
Dreyfus refuses to define those background practices in
this project of explicitation at its very core, entirely mis-
terms of rules. In contrast to what Quine and Davidson
taken? Is it senseless to speak of social rules or norms, for
supposed, for Dreyfus this cultural background cannot be
example, as social scientists do? And are philosophers who
made explicit and is not “in our minds” in the form of
do so entirely misguided? It is not clear why Dreyfus takes
beliefs or background assumptions which could, in theory,
on board Wittgenstein’s anti-mentalist epistemology and
be made explicit:
philosophy of mind, but does not seriously engage with
‘Heidegger, Merleau-Ponty, and Wittgenstein sug- Wittgenstein’s ideas about games and rules—ideas which
gest that this inherited background of practices can- influenced social scientists. (I will say more about a Witt-
not be spelled out in a theory because (1) the back- gensteinian route below.) Dreyfus seems to miss an oppor-
ground is so pervasive that we cannot make it an tunity here to bring in these aspects of the social. For think-
object of analysis, and (2) the practices involve skill.’ ing about technology, we seem to be stuck with an account
(Dreyfus 1980b, 7). of skillful coping that is holistic and related to ‘the back-
ground’, but that background cannot be further made explicit
What makes up the background is not beliefs, but
at all and is bound to remain mysterious.
‘habits and customs, embodied in the sort of subtle skills
An interesting exception occurs when Dreyfus does speak
which we exhibit in our everyday interaction with things
of norms in his comment on style in his response to Searle,
and people.’ (Dreyfus 1980b, 8). These cannot be reduced
already mentioned before. He suggests that there are already
to propositional knowledge or rules. We respond to what
social norms, there is already something binding on us, and
situations require.
we learn that from early ages on—without having to rely on
Increasingly, Dreyfus speaks of ‘the background’ rather
explicit rules. This makes sense and opens up the possibility
than a background of shared practices. This use of the term
of a kind of middle position, which recognizes that there are
as a noun in subject position is influenced by Searle, who
rules, norms, etc. that have some normative power over us,
speaks of ‘Background’ (Andler 2000). But, considered
but at the same time acknowledges that we do not (always?)
together with his position saying we cannot spell it out,
learn them in an explicit way and that we do not need them
this renders the background somewhat mysterious. Drey-
in an explicit and formalized form in order to cope. But this
fus argues that the background is ‘hidden and holistic’
thought is not made explicit, let alone elaborated. Other-
(Dreyfus 2012). For Dreyfus, influenced by Heidegger
wise, we must conclude that Dreyfus simply held on to the
and Merleau-Ponty, we cannot describe the background,
more extreme position that the background cannot be made
since when the world functions as background it ‘has’ to
explicit at all.
withdraw to do its job. It enables other things to show
To conclude: the social and cultural can be connected to
up (Dreyfus 2012). This is, according to Dreyfus, how
Dreyfus’s thinking about background, but this connection
the phenomenology of skilled coping works. Whereas for
is not further theorized or developed. There is, however,
Searle the background is a set of mental capacities that
one way in which he theorized the social explicitly: a very
makes possible representation, for Dreyfus meaning is
Heideggerian way, to which we now turn.
already there. As said, in his view there is no need to bring
it in via intentional acts. The world is already meaningful
4.2 Dreyfus on ‘das Man’ (the ‘Anyone’)
and the body also confers meaning. Following Heidegger,
Dreyfus holds that—as Andler put it—‘the background
Dreyfus does say something about the social in his analysis
is the condition of possibility for there to be anything at
of the early Heidegger. In a very interesting article on “the”
all of any significance to a being.’ (Andler 2000). In this
world versus “my” world (Dreyfus 1975), Dreyfus argued
sense, it is like Wittgenstein’s ‘form of life’. (I will say
that Heidegger’s analytic of Dasein was meant to overcome
more below.) And following Merleau-Ponty, the body—as
the dilemma of having to choose between prioritizing a

13
AI & SOCIETY

transcendental subject and prioritizing a social world. The itself remains one undifferentiated “block” or “box”. Drey-
everyday world is already public; there are already goals fus’s thoughts here are too vulnerable to the objection that
and equipment available in society, there are already ‘roles’ in this view there is one ‘Anyone’, which seems not up to
(Dreyfus 1975, 121–122). This thought makes a promising change or remains black boxed. Again, this is unhelpful if
opening to a more social analysis. But then it turns out that we want an approach to thinking about technology that takes
Dreyfus restricts the social to a very specific conceptualiza- seriously the social embeddedness of technology.
tion of it in the early Heidegger: he points to Heidegger’s To remedy this, one could resort to Marx or Hegel, who
“das Man” (he translates it as the ‘Anyone’). We do what analyzed the social in terms of struggle; this may help to
“one” (Dreyfus: “anyone”) does. This threatens authentic- open the black box, so to speak. Or one could go directly
ity. But it is not just negative. Explaining a hammer means to contemporary social sciences, which have more to say
to show what “one” does with it (124). In Wittgensteinian on style and the social, and which have also a lot to say on
terms, there is already agreement in form of life (125). Hei- technology and the social [social studies of science and tech-
degger, however, stressed the contrast the ‘Anyone’ with nology (STS), see below]. But as already suggested, there is
authenticity. We lose ourselves. Dreyfus is maybe more a thinker closer to Dreyfus who also may be of help to say
optimistic and argues that we can still give individual style more about the social: Wittgenstein.
to the modes provided by the ‘Anyone’ (129). But, neverthe-
less, we are constituted by the ‘Anyone’:
4.3 Wittgenstein
‘Dasein, which as Being-in-the-world is always a way
of acting, can and must give its individual style to
Wittgenstein’s post-Cartesian, anti-mentalist view in On
the modes of behavior provided by the Anyone. Thus
Certainty (1969) and his rejection of his earlier Tractatus
Dasein is both constituted by the Anyone in that all
view that the world is a collection of fact, is in line with
significance is a social achievement, and yet self-con-
Dreyfus’s view, and supports his arguments against classic
stituting by taking over significances from the Anyone
AI and his focus on how we cope with everyday problems.
to define itself or give itself meaning. With this analy-
The later Wittgenstein understood knowledge not in terms
sis of the parasitical relation of the individual to the
of static and inner mental states or objective facts, but sug-
social world, Heidegger gives an account of the rela-
gested a more practical, pragmatic, process-oriented, tacit,
tion of the personal to the public which (dis)solves the
and embodied conception of knowledge. Whether in scien-
Husserlian problems arising from the priority of my
tific research or in everyday life, our doubts rest on a basis
world to the world.’ (Dreyfus 1975, 129).
of things that are not doubted, things that are accepted and
This could be seen as pointing to a kind of (Heideg- presupposed. This approach is interesting for philosophers
gerian) social philosophy. Heidegger can be interpreted as of technology as it may help us to discuss the issue of trust
arguing that we already find ourselves in a social world, and in technology, and supports a view of technology as a skilled
that we are always socially constituted. And it is interest- and embodied practice and technique that crucially involves
ing that Dreyfus says something about the relation between implicit knowledge (Coeckelbergh and Funk 2018). But we
Dasein and Anyone, which could be seen as asking a cen- can also use Wittgenstein for the purpose of developing a
tral problem of social philosophy, but then formulated in a view of the relation between a specific practical activity (or
Heideggerian way. However, first, even within a Heideg- coping) and the wider, perhaps implicit social background.
gerian framework it can and has been objected that Dreyfus Dreyfus has not done this. Although he sometimes referred
leaves out what Heidegger calls Mitsein. Olafson has argued, to Wittgenstein, he did not really use him to further elabo-
against Dreyfus, that he gives a far too large role to ‘Das rate the holistic relation between everyday coping and the
Man’, which is only a deformation of our social being (Mit- background. But we can. Let me explore some possibilities.
sein) (Olafson 2008). Carman, in turn, has accused Olafson One way to start such a project is to draw on scholarship
of an over-individuated notion of Dasein (Carman 2008). about Dreyfus that makes connections to Wittgenstein. For
Whatever the best interpretation of Heidegger may be, it instance, Rietveld’s work on the differences between Drey-
turns out that Dreyfus (like Heidegger) has again said too fus and McDowell (Rietveld 2010) at least suggests that it
little about the social, and has left too much room for inter- can be useful to discuss interpretations of Wittgenstein in
pretation. His suggestion that human beings depend on the order to further elaborate a Dreyfusian approach. The same
social world is important but underdeveloped. Second, the can be said about McManus’s comparison of Wittgenstein-
social is mainly seen as a given, and as one monolithic kind ian and Heideggerian ideas when discussing the concept of
of thing. The rules or the antagonistic tendencies and vari- “background” in Dreyfus (McManus 2007). These critical
ations within the social are not visible, except in the form discussions could be used as a starting point to bring more
of style. But this thought is not elaborated, and the Anyone Wittgenstein into Dreyfus.

13
AI & SOCIETY

Another way is to draw directly on Wittgenstein, as I have etc. not as things that are “out there” in the world (as
done in my recent work on technology inspired by Witt- McDowell and Dreyfus seem to assume) but as something
genstein (Coeckelbergh 2017a, b; Coeckelbergh and Funk that only “lives” embodied in performance and a use, that
2018) and in line with some suggestions in Winner (1986). only exists in our engagement with the world—in particu-
Based on the Philosophical Investigations (Wittgenstein lar, our use of words and a performance with words, which
1953/2009), I have argued for a holistic and transcenden- itself is, like all performances, related and made possible
tal approach to technology which sees technological arti- by an implicit background of practices—then that seems
fact, in their use and in our performances, as embedded to me at least a preliminary answer to Dreyfus’s question.
in what Wittgenstein calls ‘games’ and ‘form of life’. The The conceptual does not have an existence outside our uses
meanings in and of the particular use and performance are and performances, and the use of concepts itself depends on
related to our activities, games, and form of life, which are embodiment and on an often inexplicit background: back-
also social and cultural, and which must be presupposed ground knowledge, experience, and practices, that are always
for the particular use and activity to make sense. This is a already social. This answer is in the spirit of Dreyfus, but—
“background”, if you wish, but one that is more practical influenced by Wittgenstein—gives more importance to the
and less mysterious than Dreyfus’s. It is transcendental in concept of use, acknowledges a role for the conceptual, and
the sense that it is a condition of possibility for technol- attends to use of language, which is often neglected in con-
ogy uses and performances, but it is not transcendental in temporary philosophy of technology (Coeckelbergh 2017c)
a Kantian (abstract categories) or Heideggerian (a mysteri- and indeed in Dreyfus’s account of skilled coping.
ous ontology of being) way. Instead, the view I proposed Another route, which is also not necessarily distant from
connects a particular use and performance (and hence the Wittgenstein, is STS and, earlier, sociology of knowledge,
skill and know-how related to it) to a wider background which usually sees knowledge as socially constructed. In the
of games and forms of life which already contain practi- 1990s, Harry Collins already criticized Dreyfus for not tak-
cal know-how. Moreover, this know-how is not necessarily ing on board Wittgenstein’s notion of form of life and, more
implicit. It contains a lot of implicit knowledge, for sure, but generally, for not seeing that the structure of knowledge is to
at least part of it can be made explicit in terms of rules. This be found in the social collectivity (Collins 1992). He writes:
understanding of the social renders it possible for the social
‘For sociologists of scientific knowledge, most of
sciences to say something meaningful about the social and
whom think of themselves as jumping off from Witt-
our social practices. But more importantly for the purpose
genstein’s later philosophy, it is surprising that a phi-
of using Dreyfus’s account of skillful coping: it presents a
losopher who leans so heavily on Wittgenstein should
more elaborated and arguably more balanced theory of the
even have a concept of a knowledge domain apart from
relation between skillful coping and its social background,
a form-of-life.’ (Collins 1992, 727).
which can at least partly be made explicit. Usually we do
not think about the rules of our social games. Usually we do There is domain knowledge, but this knowledge has a
not make explicit our form of life. And maybe we can never history—a social history in which things could have been
make it fully explicit. Maybe not everything can be captured different. This form of life shapes my usage. For instance,
in rules. But surely it makes sense to sometimes formalize the English language or arithmetic can be seen as domains
for practical purposes, that is, as a tool. (See also my use of of knowledge, but they also kind of compel me to speak in
Dewey below.) Furthermore, this view also acknowledges certain ways. But at the same time that language is made
the normative dimension of the background—even if these in society. Collins thinks that we have more control over
norms may not always be visible or even if they can only be it than Dreyfus suggests. According to him, Dreyfus failed
partly explicitated. Finally, with the concept of games we to distinguish between individual knowledge and collective
could also add that the background is not entirely given: we knowledge and focused only on individual understanding
can also change it. We can change our games, and partly that (Collins 2013). Taking up the example of car driving again:
can happen by changing the rules. But it can also happen Dreyfus talks about how we learn to drive in the sense of
differently. Technology, for instance, can be a game changer. operating the car, but this leaves out the knowledge we need
It can disrupt and transform our background understand- about traffic. This is Collins’ take:
ings and practices. However, I share Dreyfus’s Heideggerian
‘Dreyfus has no concept of collective understand-
intuitions in so far as I believe that such changes are small
ing that is separate from the concept of individual
and slow, similar to the changes in river beds—to use a Witt-
understanding; this is why he makes no clear distinc-
gensteinian metaphor (Coeckelbergh 2017b).
tion between expert car driving (gear changing etc.
Maybe this approach also helps us to relate the concep-
which requires only the context of the machine and
tual to the non-conceptual, the challenge Dreyfus formulated
its relation- ship to the road to be internalised) and
(Dreyfus 2007a): if we see the conceptual, logic, reasons,

13
AI & SOCIETY

expert car driving in traffic, which requires national we trust them, and what if they assume power on the basis
driving conventions to be understood and updated of intuitions?
through immersion in the collectivity. Gear chang- The assumption made by the authors that trust necessarily
ing, like Dreyfus’s iconic example of an expertise, relies on explicit knowledge and the suggestion that Drey-
that of the chess grandmaster, does not depend on fus’s model of skill acquisition necessarily leaves out the
collective tacit knowledge, whereas driving in traffic, role of the coach are problematic. Trust does not require that
and most other expertises, does.’ (Collins 2013, 411). everything is made explicit; on the contrary, otherwise there
is no need for trust. Trust is not necessarily the outcome of
While I disagree with Collins that it is so easy to dis-
a rational process but, according to a ‘social–phenomeno-
tinguish between the two kinds of knowledge, or indeed
logical’ view, is already embedded in the social and in rela-
that one should make this distinction between individual
tions (Coeckelbergh 2011b). I also do not see why Dreyfus’s
and collective knowledge (I already mentioned Dreyfus’s
model of learning excludes the possibility of coaching. For
interpretation of Heidegger that tries to go beyond this
example, a coach can be helpful for beginners, and even for
dichotomy and with my interpretation of Wittgenstein I
experts, since a coach does not necessarily only give rules
show how use and the social are entangled), if the point is
and instructions; she might also encourage a trial and error
that driving is also about collective knowledge then this
kind of process of the kind that Dreyfus would approve of.
makes sense and helpfully brings in a social perspective.
And Selinger and Crease speak about a very specific kind of
For thinking about technology, it means that technologies
expert than the everyday expert of Dreyfus: not the expert
need to be understood not only in terms of “micro”-skill-
driver or swimmer but, for instance, an expert who is asked
ful coping; that skillful coping needs to be related to a
about health or climate change, who is socially recognized
“macro” wider social background knowledge. One could
as “expert” in the sense of a doctor or scientist, for example,
also draw on work in contemporary STS (Wiebe Bijker and
and has a specific role to inform policy as an “authority”,
others) that shows how the design of technologies is the
who has an “audience”, and so on. But their point about
outcome of a social process, to support this point.
embeddedness is important since it points again to a lacuna
More generally, on the one hand, we can learn from
with regard to the social dimension of Dreyfus’s model.
the social sciences that there is something like collective-
Focused on embodied coping, the account of skilled cop-
social knowledge, that the background can at least partly
ing and expertise seems less sensitive to social, cultural,
be made explicit and is at least partly something which we
and political context than it could be. This includes the
can influence. ‘Das Man’ is not simply given. Influenced
point suggested by the authors that experts are and should
by Heidegger, Dreyfus makes the background more myste-
be vulnerable in the sense that they can be challenged with
rious and untouchable than it is. On the other hand, we can
regard to their expertise and that they can be asked to give
learn from Dreyfus that the social cannot be made entirely
reasons—even if not everything can be explained and some-
explicit in terms of rules and beliefs, and that there are
times experts just have to say (not “admit”, this sounds too
limits to the extent to which we can control it.
negative) that they rely on their experience and intuitions.
Another relevant objection to Dreyfus, which also links
But it makes sense to say that the social and the political also
to STS and the social sciences, has been made by Selinger
includes giving reasons and deliberation. This is a lacuna in
and Crease (2003). Here the target is Dreyfus’s account of
Dreyfus’s work. And perhaps the more fundamental problem
expertise. While the authors praise Dreyfus for bringing in
is that the entire social and political playing field, in which
a first person perspective to studying expertise (rather than
experts are situated and which plays a role in what they say
a third person perspective, as the social sciences usually
and become, remains out of sight.
do), and for calling attention to the relation between exper-
How can this be conceptualized? Next to STS and Witt-
tise and the body, they complain that his account is not
genstein, pragmatism is another source which can help us to
sufficiently sensitive to the cultural embeddedness of the
conceptualize the social dimension of skillful coping, and
expert, including prejudices, ideologies, and hidden agen-
which has a lot more to say on deliberation and public dis-
das the expert may start from. Experts are not embodied
cussion than can be done within a Heideggerian framework.
and situated subjects, as Dreyfus shows us; they are also
people that are culturally and socially embedded, and since
4.4 Dewey
that gives them prejudices, agendas, and so on, we should
not naively trust them. Society might even be endangered
A thinker who is curiously absent in most discussions by and
by experts—an issue that cannot arise in Dreyfus’s account
about Dreyfus is Dewey. (An exception is a Dreyfus paper on
(Selinger and Crease 2003, 262–263). In particular, Drey-
ethical expertise—see Sect. 5.2). This is curious since there
fus’s point that experts might not be able to proposition-
are at least the following points of connection. First, like
ally justify decisions (270) seems dangerous—how can
Dreyfus and Wittgenstein, Dewey was skeptical about the

13
AI & SOCIETY

language of the “mental” and sees mind as embodied. But excluding it from a theory about the kind of knowledge and
he also understood it as emerging from the interaction in a experience involved in skilled coping.
social context. In Experience and Nature (Dewey 1929) he But there are also possibilities next to using Dewey, that
sees knowledge as ‘a mode of interaction’ (435) and argues are certainly not far away at all from the thinking of Hei-
that meaning is not a ‘psychic existence’ (179). Dreyfus, degger and Merleau-Ponty, but that are, nevertheless, more
focused on the handling of tools, ignores this more social- appreciative of the social aspect of skill than Dreyfus was.
interactive view. But if we see technology as an instrument For example, Borgmann, a philosopher of technology who
of social cooperation, as I proposed in my interpretation of in his praise of skilled activity is very close to Dreyfus,
Dewey’s view of language (Coeckelbergh 2017a, 33–37), manages to connect skilled activity to the social in a very
then this puts tool use as skillful coping in a more social straightforward, less Heideggerian or mysterious way. He
context. Moreover, whereas Dreyfus seems to put language writes:
in a separate category (the conceptual, the symbolical, etc.)
‘Physical engagement is not simply physical contact,
divorced from embodied coping, for Dewey language is
but the experience of the world through the manifold
both embodied and social. It is about organized interaction
sensibility of the body. Skill is intensive and refined
with other living creatures (258). Second, Dreyfus could
world engagement. Skill, in turn, is bound up with
have used Dewey’s conception of habit. In Human Nature
social engagement. It molds the person and gives the
and Conduct (1922), Dewey argues that we know how by
person character.’ (Borgmann 1984, p. 42).
means of our habits (Dewey 1922, 177). This idea seems to
fit Dreyfus’s account, and could help to understand our use Borgmann (1984) stresses that when we are engaged in
of technology from a more social angle. Dreyfus talks about skilled activity, we do not only engage with things but also
habit, but does not use Dewey to elaborate this social aspect with others, for example, when keeping a stove going cent-
of skillful coping. That coping and those skills can be under- ers the family. A similar view can be found in Crawford’s
stood as being part of habitual and shared ways of doing, analysis of craftsmanship, which is about working together
and our tools become tools in the context of social groups and sharing a concept of good (Crawford 2009, 181). One
(186). Third, Dewey’s work also seems particularly relevant could also argue that skilled activity helps us to shape our
when it comes to conceptualize public discussions about character. This takes us to the questions regarding virtue,
technology. In Dreyfus’s work, the public dimension is men- and more generally the ethical and political implications of
tioned but not theorized. Dewey could be used to elaborate Dreyfus’s position.
this aspect of the social in a non-Hegelian way. But Dreyfus
rejects this route. Here a significant barrier to using Dewey
is that whereas Dewey stresses deliberation to solve social 5 Problems with the ethical and political
problems, for Dreyfus a lot is going on without deliberation. implications and the question
Moreover, Dreyfus seems to divorce mind and knowledge regarding virtue
from the social. In his response to Collins (Dreyfus 1992,
724), Dreyfus argues that not all intelligence is social; this What are the ethical and political implications of Dreyfus’s
goes against the pragmatist view that intelligence is social view of skilled coping? While his account is mainly descrip-
and, again, is about solving social problems. (More below.) tive and aimed at understanding the kind of knowledge
Finally, one could ask if Dreyfus’s account of skilled cop- involved in skilled coping, it has normative implications.
ing is sufficiently appreciative of the social-linguistic and The problem is again that it is not entirely clear what these
communicative dimension of coping. In my interpretation implications are based on Dreyfus’s own writings; but these
of Dewey, language must be seen as a social tool (Coeck- implications need and deserve to be further articulated and
elbergh 2017a, 35). Perhaps language could be integrated developed, also with a view to arrive at a better thinking
in a Dreyfusian–Wittgensteinian view by saying that next about technology.
to the handling of things, there is also skillful coping with Like Reynolds (2006) I believe that if we look at his
words, and both kinds of skillful coping are always embed- account of skill acquisition, Dreyfus’s view is one in which a
ded in a social–practical context in which there is inexplicit kind of ethical comportment is more important than sophisti-
knowledge but also language and language games, consti- cated reasoning: moral maturity ‘is primarily about an ethi-
tuting a form of life which is given and shapes our concrete cal comportment to situations in the world rather than about
coping-performances. And here, too, one could add that in coming to have more sophisticated cognitions and judgments
the use of words, in coping using words, that language with- about principles and rule-following’ (Reynolds 2006, 545).
draws, is not always visible. Indeed, it is usually so invisible Ethics seems to require the development of a practical wis-
that Dreyfus managed to leave it out of his account of skill- dom which can respond intuitively and appropriately to spe-
ful coping. But this “default” invisibility does not justify cific situations. This sounds like virtue ethics. Dreyfus might

13
AI & SOCIETY

have been aware of this connection: when I had a chance to point is not that I disagree with Annas’s interpretation of
talk to him in Berkeley, years ago, he suggested to me that Aristotle: he may well have an intellectualist, theory-ori-
virtue ethics may be a good way forward when it comes to ented understanding of virtue, skill, and practical wisdom
elaborating the ethical implications of his work. But more (phronesis); this is at least also my impression when I read
work is needed on this: how, exactly, does his account of him. As McPherson puts it: ‘Aristotle himself, it is worth
skillful coping relate to virtue ethics? It seems to me that his recalling here, classified phronesis as an intellectual virtue,
account lends support to virtue ethics, albeit a virtue ethics aiming at truth, rather than as a practical virtue, aiming at
of a particular kind: one that does not necessarily involve goodness.’ (McPherson 2005, 706). But if this is right, there
reasoning and judgment, but rather a knowing-how to best is no need to follow Aristotle on this. Learning from Drey-
respond to the world and to others in particular situations. fus, we can do better and develop theory that is closer to
Let me develop this thought about a Dreyfusian virtue eth- the actual phenomena of skilled coping and their relation to
ics by engaging with some of the literature on virtue and virtue and good.
skill. I will end by raising the question regarding political Indeed, as becomes clear on the basis of my summary
implications. of Dreyfus’s account, and as Stichter also shows (2007,
192), Annas’s view goes against a Dreyfusian way of think-
5.1 Virtue and skill ing about skill: for Dreyfus, skillful coping does not at all
require reflection. Hence, if we use skill as a model for vir-
What does it mean to say that virtue is about skill? Annas tue and use Dreyfus’s view of skill, then virtue would also
famously argued that virtue is like skill (Annas 1995). The be virtue without an intellectual component. It suffices that
point is that there is an analogy in structure between the two. we know how to do good in the sense that we know how to
Now, whether or not this is a sound interpretation of Aristo- do good in practice. Theoretical knowledge or reflection,
tle (for a discussion see Stichter 2007), this is an interesting then, are neither necessary nor sufficient for virtue, and can
view in the light of Dreyfus’s emphasis on skill. Annas’s even get in the way of this virtue-as-skilled-engagement and
claim concerns intellectual virtue; her project was to under- virtue-as-performance. A standing back, so it seems, is then
stand intellectual virtue. But what if virtue tout court is like not required. For Annas, this would not be genuine skill.
skill? And what if virtue is not so much about intellect at According to her, virtue is about having a disposition to act
all? Indeed, perhaps there is more than an analogy: in the for reasons (Annas 2007). But, from a Dreyfusian point of
spirit of Dreyfus one could argue that this is still a far too view, there is no good reason why we have to follow her
intellectualist conception of virtue. For Annas, virtue as skill conception of virtue. Thus, let us go further than Annas, and
requires reflection (Annas 1993) and the development of an argue that virtue is not only analogous to skill but entirely
intellectual component (Annas 1995). For her, the stress is a matter of skill, but then understood as embodied coping,
on reflection and decision: ‘The skill analogy requires that and as not needing anything else than know-how: knowing
the agent reflect and achieve by reflection a unified grasp how to do good (in practice).
of the general principles underlying her patterns of action This is a conception of virtue I defended in my own think-
and decision.’ (Annas 1993, 67–68). But is this reflection ing about technology, skill, and virtue. If we think about
and decision necessary and sufficient for virtue? Stichter ethics of technology as a virtue ethics, if we define virtue in
convincingly argues they are not necessary: terms of skill, and indeed if we define technology in terms
of skill (Coeckelbergh 2012), then we get the following con-
‘A person’s ability to explain herself can be less than
ception of virtue: virtue is a matter of practical wisdom,
the person’s ability to know how to act in the situation.
which implies a knowing-how and skill. Being “wise” is
The intellectual requirements that Annas discusses are
etymologically related to a “way” (Coeckelbergh 2015, 118
relevant to any social discourse we have about moral-
footnote 2). (Here one could also consider Eastern concep-
ity, but they are not necessary for achieving expertise.’
tions of virtue, for instance in Daoism and Confucianism.)
(Stichter 2007, 194).
Influenced by Dreyfus and Dewey, I have argued that virtue
Annas admits that many skills are not like the skills she is about knowing how to do things. Virtue is not about hav-
describes, but then still endorses her intellectualist concep- ing particular properties, but about practicing virtue. There
tion of skill, going against our intuitions and experience: is not first a ‘logos’ which then needs to be applied to the
indeed she defends an account of skill that ‘does not fit real world. Rather, virtue is about having ‘ethical know-how’
numerous examples of actual skills’ (Stichter 2007, 187). and doing it, practicing it (Coeckelbergh 2011a, 162). And
She thus perpetuates an intellectualist tradition of think- if we then see technology in terms of skill, we have a view
ing about skill that started at least with Plato and Aristotle. in which virtue, skill, and technology are integrated. There
It ignores recent thinking about skill including Dreyfus’s are no longer two sides—reason and intellect versus embod-
work—which was already available when Annas wrote. The ied coping and material technologies—but there is only one

13
AI & SOCIETY

skillful coping, engagement, and practice, and virtue is all sions are necessarily crude since they have not been
about the quality of that coping, engagement, and practice. refined by the experience of the results of a variety
For example, environmental virtue is not something abstract of intuitive responses to emotion-laden situations and
and external (say, a principle) that is imposed on the life- the learning that comes from subsequent satisfaction
world as it were from outside, but rather something that goes and regret. Therefore, in familiar but problematic situ-
on in the lifeworld and that transforms it. It is about how we ations, rather than standing back and applying abstract
(skillfully and technologically) relate to our environment. principles, the expert deliberates about the appropri-
Virtue is then ‘a way of doing’ and a ‘form of life’ (168). Or ateness of his intuitions.’ (Dreyfus and Dreyfus 1991,
as I said it elsewhere, in the context of thinking about health 241).
care: good health care is ‘in the how’; it is about knowing-
Against Dewey, who thinks that in difficult situations
how to deal with people and handle technologies (Coeckel-
we need deliberation and examination, Dreyfus and Drey-
bergh 2014). Of course we can reflect and deliberate. This
fus argue that of course experts should have a dialog about
may help. But if we have that kind of practical wisdom, that
their responses, but there may be no final agreement; the
kind of know-how, there is nothing in terms of virtue that is
experts have to appreciate each other’s decisions (242). And
wanted in addition or outside of that wisdom.
against Kohlberg and Habermas (and partly in agreement
with Gilligan), they argue that the highest stage of moral
5.2 Ethical expertise: Dreyfus contra Dewey
development is not about detached and abstract reasoning,
but intuitive response to the situation. They write: ‘if being
This interpretation of virtue in terms of know-how is in line
good means being able to learn from experience and use
with Dreyfus’s own phenomenology of ethical expertise, but
what one has learned so as to respond more appropriately
he takes distance from Dewey. In a paper with his brother
to the demands of others in the concrete situation, the high-
(Dreyfus and Dreyfus 1991) he repeats the account of skill
est form of ethical comportment consists in being able to
acquisition, but then draws out the implications for ethi-
stay involved and to refine one’s intuitions.’ (247). Detached
cal expertise. In so far as ethical comportment is a form of
reflection is resorted to in case of a kind of breakdown, it
expertise, the brothers Dreyfus argue, it has the same devel-
is not the rule. One could conclude that, according to the
opmental structure (236). As a child we learn moral rules,
Dreyfus brothers, skillful coping without deliberation is the
but rules and maxims are for beginners in moral develop-
‘default’, at least for experts.
ment. Ethical experts do it differently: ‘with enough expe-
Dreyfus and Dewey may actually be closer than presented
rience, the ethical expert would learn to tell the truth or
here. Both agree that the main challenge is to appropriately
lie, depending upon the situation, without appeal to rules
respond to situations. Both may also agree that emotions
and maxims’ (237). Interestingly, here the Dreyfus broth-
and intuitions play a role. Dewey also criticized abstract
ers do use Dewey to develop their account. They endorse
principles and detached reasoning. Principles are tools to
Dewey for saying that ethical comportment is spontaneous,
cope with a situation. Dreyfus could have arrived at a less
involving an immediate reaction. But then they argue that
extreme view if he recognized that, like other tools, princi-
Dewey was wrongly focused on problem solving and ignored
ples and reasoning can help us to skillfully and expertly cope
‘ongoing coping’, which is not only simple but also complex.
with ethically challenging situations, especially in a social
According to Dreyfus, as experts we can respond to complex
context. These tools may not be sufficient. And it may well
situations without deliberation (238). Against Aristotle’s
be that before, during, and after the decision, the expert can-
intellectualism (or, in Dreyfus’s view: against intellectualist
not entirely render her decision process and the knowledge
interpretations of Aristotle), the Dreyfus brothers argue that
basis of this decision process transparent. But talking with
people should not only be praised for what they intend to do
others and the use of principles may help, like other tools
but also and especially for their ‘brilliant intuitive responses’
may help. If Dreyfus would have recognized that language,
as experts (239). Virtue, then, is spontaneous: ‘We can only
concepts, etc. are also a kind of tools, he could have held the
tell if a person is courageous, for example, by seeing his
view that deliberation is perhaps not necessary, but helpful
spontaneous response in many different situations.’ (239)
as one of the tools we have. He could have arrived at the
For Dreyfus, no practical reasoning is necessary. Principles
more moderate view that moral experts at a higher stage of
can even hinder good ethical responses:
development, when faced with a problem in a social context,
‘an ethical expert when confronted with cases of “life- often masterly know how to combine various tools and types
boat morality” may have to fall back on ethical princi- of knowledge, including intuition, emotions, principles, dis-
ples. But since principles are unable to produce expert course, etc.—without being able to fully explain themselves
behavior, it should be no surprise if falling back on afterwards but with being able to have a meaningful conver-
them produces inferior responses. The resulting deci- sation with others about their decision. However, perhaps the

13
AI & SOCIETY

final aim and the highest stage is moral wisdom and virtue reveals. (.. .) Indeed, in an important sense this expe-
understood as knowing-how to do good, which may also be rience turns you into an automated device the GPS
reached without deliberation and conversation; they are nei- can use to arrive at its destination.’ (Dreyfus and Kelly
ther sufficient nor necessary. Moreover, with Dewey we can 2011, 215).
add that when we seek consensus, it is impossible to reach
While I agree with the authors on the value of skilled
a final agreement, with “final” meaning: an agreement for
activity, and even on the potentially alienating aspect of tech-
once and for all. Dreyfus could have agreed with this view.
nologies such as GPS, alienation and nihilism are certainly
But with Dewey we must appreciate, more than Dreyfus did,
not the only possibilities when it comes to contemporary
the social and collective dimension of coping and indeed of
technologies. First, the world is a lot less disenchanted than
the problems we face. There is often the practical–social
Dreyfus and Kelly suppose. Consider for instance how much
need for collective coping to reach a temporary consensus
wonder there is in contemporary science and technology,
among experts. Language and other tools may help with this.
and how romanticism and technologies are still entangled
(Coeckelbergh 2017d). More generally, it is highly doubtful
5.3 If skilled engagement and craft work are
if we find ourselves in the nihilistic situation Dreyfus and
good, what does that imply for contemporary
Kelly describe. We always find and create meaning, also in
technologies?
our daily coping with and through technologies. Second,
even if there is still alienation due to technologies, new tech-
Next to implications for a conception of virtue and moral
nologies are not only a problem; they may also be part of
development, Dreyfus’s work also contains a particular
the solution. Different technologies and uses are possible.
view of the good life—especially the good life in the con-
As postphenomenology reminds us (Ihde 1990), and as I
text of modernity. Dreyfus does not only make a descrip-
have argued using Wittgenstein (Coeckelbergh 2017a, b),
tive claim about knowledge and skill; we can also discern
technologies are ambiguous and ‘multistable’ in the sense
in this work the normative claim that skilled engagement
that they are always technologies-in-use: the same artifact
itself is something good, that particular technological prac-
has different meanings depending on use and context. This
tices—craft work especially—are ethically good in several
has implications for thinking about technology and virtue.
ways, are conducive to the good life. In line with work by
In my work on skill, technology, and virtue (Coeckelbergh
Pirsig, Sennett, Crawford, and in philosophy of technol-
2011a, 2012, 2015), I have proposed a more constructive
ogy Borgmann (see my discussion in Coeckelbergh 2015),
approach than Heidegger and Dreyfus: one which does not
Dreyfus thought that there is something special about skilled
a priori exclude the possibility that new technologies may
engagement that makes it good in itself, and that helps us
contribute to skilled activity, virtue, and good. For example,
to cope with the nihilist tendencies in modern culture. Now
when it comes to wayfinding it is true that GPS may divert
this claim—which, by itself, has a lot to say for it—is not
our attention from our surroundings, but perhaps some apps
necessarily right in its evaluation of modernity and can lead
can help us to see features of the environment that we did
to a conservative and pessimistic position with regard to
not notice (yet). There may be more modes and possibili-
new technologies. This seems the direction Dreyfus took, for
ties (Coeckelbergh 2015, 149) and more creative uses of the
example, in his book with Kelly (Dreyfus and Kelly 2011).
same device to explore different ways of wayfinding and
According to Dreyfus and Kelly, our modern (self-)under-
walking (152).
standing has left us with a meaningless world. In response
More generally, I have argued that contemporary informa-
to this nihilist condition, they argue that we must re-enchant
tion and communication technologies could, in principle,
the world by seeing that the gods are there (polytheism), that
also help us to overcome alienation and find a better relation
there is the sacred, and that there are still Greek-style heroes,
to our environment and to others. In ‘Technology as skill and
for example in sport (Dreyfus and Kelly 2011, 201). But they
activity’ (2012), I have argued that we can take seriously the
also propose craftwork and its skilled activity as a response
problem of alienation but at the same time have a Dreyfus-
to alienation and nihilism. According to the authors, we can
inspired (but also more social and Dewey-inspired) ethics
come to discern meanings that are already there (209) and
of skill that is open to the possibility that new technologies
may feel that there is a force outside our self (8). The crafts-
can also help us to overcome alienation. We can use the
man achieves ‘intimacy’ with the material (2010), whereas
concept of skill to evaluate new technologies, asking if they
modern technology such as GPS alienates us from our envi-
contribute to more or less skilled engagement. But there is
ronment. They write:
no a priori answer as to which technologies are more ‘focal’
‘to lose the sensitivities—to the landmarks, street (to use Borgmann’s term; Borgmann 1984) or more engag-
signs, wind direction, the height of the sun, the stars— ing and more conducive to skilled activity and craftsman-
all the meaningful distinctions that navigation skill ship—activities and modes of knowledge and interaction

13
AI & SOCIETY

which Dreyfus rightly valued. What matters then is not what individual or personal level. This is also the case in Drey-
technology “is” (as is sometimes suggested in Dreyfus’s late fus’s account of skillful coping. As I proposed, the social
Heideggerian approach to new technologies), but rather what dimension could be developed by bringing in a pragmatist
kind of skills–activities are promoted and supported by spe- (or other) conception of habit and other concepts that help
cific technologies, by a particular technology-in-use. What us to understand the social and public dimension of skilled
matters is whether or not the skills–activities lead to more engagement and virtue. Individual or personal experience
engagement and less alienation. (Coeckelbergh 2012). and wisdom are always linked to collective knowledge—
Thus, new technologies are far more ambiguous with explicitly and implicitly. If virtue and the highest stage of
regard to skilled engagement than Dreyfus suggests. Con- moral development are a matter of skillful coping, as Drey-
sider also the work of Shannon Vallor, who has argued that fus argued, then this skillful coping should not only be con-
while contemporary ICTs can lead to ‘moral deskilling’ ceptualized in terms of individual knowledge. Dewey’s prag-
there may be also potential for ‘upskilling’ (Vallor 2015). matism or the social sciences could help Dreyfus-inspired
Recently, she has called for a technomoral virtue ethic (Val- philosophers to further work on this problem. Another inter-
lor 2016). These interpretations of the relation(s) between esting source may be MacIntyre, who is acknowledged by
technology, skill, and virtue suggest that it is possible to talk Dreyfus but not fully used. His conception of practice as
about virtue and skill in a way that is critical of contempo- a social and historically situated activity that enables par-
rary technologies, but also takes a more constructive and ticipants to attain goods internal to the practice and achieve
hopeful approach: perhaps there often is, but there does not excellence and virtue (MacIntyre 1984) might have enabled
need to be, an opposition between the cultivation of virtue Dreyfus to say more about the social dimension of skillful
and the development of advanced technologies. coping and virtue, in particular about the links between skill-
Consider again the use of electronic technologies in ful coping, virtue, and practice. It may certainly provide a
health care. In ‘E-care as craftsmanship’ (2013b) I have source of inspiration to those philosophers working on virtue
argued that while under modern conditions and with the use and technology who are interested in developing the social
of tele-care there are real dangers with regard to the erosion dimension of their work. (Note also that MacIntyre, Dewey,
of craftsmanship, the use of new technology is not neces- and the later Wittgenstein are in agreement when it comes
sarily jeopardizing skillful and careful engagement with to rejecting the fact/value distinction, which may also help
patients and quality care. Whether such an engagement is to conceptualize a view of virtue that links it firmly to its
possible depends on whether in a specific practice and given social and practical contexts. However, I will not further
a specific technology e-care workers can develop the know- elaborate this point here.)
how and skill to engage more intensely with those under Moreover, given the often-lacking attention for the social
their care, and to cooperate with their co-workers. What dimension of virtue in modern theories of virtue, virtue
matters is how care workers work and care, when using approaches are in danger of ignoring the political dimen-
and working with new technology—and with each another. sion—including potential political problems that are often
Hence, craftsmanship in “e-care” is possible, for example, ascribed to thinking in terms of skill, craft, and virtue. Since
when tele-care technologies are used as a complement rather modern virtue ethicists tend to be focused on individual
than a replacement of care workers, and when criteria and moral development or (more local) practices, they are often
conditions for craftsmanship are fulfilled (Coeckelbergh blind to the wider and often antagonistic social playing field,
2013b). Another way of putting this is, again, to say that within which individual cultivation of character is set. Or far
good health care is not about the technologies as such; good worse, they do not ask the political question at all.
health care is in the “how” (Coeckelbergh 2014). The chal- This is also a problem for a Dreyfus-inspired thinking
lenge is to design and use technologies in such a way that about technology, to the extent that it comes in the shape of
more engaged and care-full ways of doing and knowing-how a virtue ethics focused on individual skillful coping. Such
are promoted. a focus leaves too much room for interpretation concerning
the political implications. Reynolds (2006) has argued that
5.4 The social and political dimension of virtue there is a danger that Dreyfus’s phenomenology devolves
and craftsmanship: Dewey and MacIntyre into a conservative communitarianism that does not recog-
nize ‘the inevitability and vitality of social conflict.’ (555).
As I already suggested, craftsmanship also has a social Whether or not this is true, it raises the issue of the political
dimension (Coeckelbergh 2012). It is not only a kind of implications of Dreyfus’s phenomenology. Dreyfus seems
technical skill; it is also about doing things together, shar- to have inherited Heidegger’s positive valuation of the kind
ing good, and indeed the skill to work and relate to others. of knowledge that is involved in craft work. But did he also
But this social dimension is not always presents in views of inherit Heidegger’s conservatism or worse, his Nazism?
craftsmanship, skill, and virtue. Often the emphasis is on the Does a positive valuation of craft work or a tendency

13
AI & SOCIETY

towards virtue ethics necessarily lead to conservatism? Is conceptions of the social dimension of skillful coping, and
it communitarian, and then what kind of communitarian- uncertainty with regard to the ethical and political implica-
ism? Is communitarianism necessarily conservative? Or are tions of this view, including questions regarding the relation
there other possibilities? And is there an unbridgeable gap between virtue and skill. I have indicated some potential
between phenomenology and critical theory, or could Drey- avenues for addressing these problems. In general, my rec-
fus’s phenomenology be combined with some concerns and ommendation to those inspired by Dreyfus in philosophy
methods from critical theory? of technology is to take more distance from the later Hei-
Reading Dreyfus’s work I do not see indications in the degger’s conception of technology and to do more with
direction of conservatism, let alone Nazism, and I do not see Wittgenstein and Dewey than Dreyfus did to deal with these
why his thinking would necessarily lead into that direction. challenges. I have indicated that there is also a lot of room
There is conservatism regarding technology, perhaps, but for further development in the direction of virtue theory, for
this does not necessarily imply social or political conserva- example by combining Dreyfus and Dewey or by engaging
tivism. However, these questions deserve further discussion, with the work of MacIntyre. Finally, so far authors working
also in the light of contemporary debates about Heidegger’s in the field of postphenomenology have not been very inter-
political sympathies. Since, as I have argued, Dreyfus’s ested in Dreyfus’s work (and vice versa); perhaps since the
thinking has insufficiently engaged with the problem of the former rejects the latter as too Heideggerian. This neglect is
social, and since it has never been fully developed in terms to be regretted since Dreyfus’s work, in particular its account
of its social and political implications, it remains somewhat of skillful coping, has a lot to offer to anyone interested
vulnerable to typical anti-Heideggerian criticisms. There- in the phenomenology of technology use. By shifting the
fore, if philosophers of technology want to use Dreyfus’s emphasis from the material artifact as such to its use and
thinking, they need to say more about the relations between the skills and knowledge involved in that use, contempo-
skill and the social, and explicitly reflect on the normative rary philosophers of technology in postphenomenology and
and political directions this may take them. In the previous related approaches could work towards a more relational and
pages I have proposed some ways in which this can be done non-dualistic thinking about the relations between humans
by staying relatively close to Dreyfus’s own sources (rather and technology—an aim Ihde may sympathize with.
than resorting to critical theory, for instance). In particular, More generally, Dreyfus’s work constitutes a rich poten-
I have suggested that using and combining Wittgenstein and tial source of inspiration for philosophers of technology
Dewey (and maybe also MacIntyre) has a lot of potential to today, not only in the area of philosophy of AI but—with the
say more about the social in relation to the phenomenology account of skillful coping—also in other areas of thinking
of skillful coping. about technology. It is especially of interest to philosophers
More generally, more work is needed to develop these who aim to be sensitive to the phenomenology of living with
thoughts about how Wittgenstein, Dewey, and Dreyfus can technologies, to human experience with technologies. This
be combined to (re)conceptualize and discuss virtue and attention to technology in the lifeworld also requires us to
its social dimension. This project requires, among other adopt, in contrast to Dreyfus and Heidegger, a view of new
things, further engagement with Wittgenstein’s work and technologies that is more open and constructive and that
its interpreters and a more elaborate discussion of both con- goes beyond embodied tool use, without, however, dismiss-
vergences and tensions between these thinkers. Here I have ing the concerns about skill, alienation and virtue Dreyfus
limited myself to offering some signposts in this direction, and others rightly raised. This could help philosophy of
and to exploring some potential implications for philosophy technology to further develop thinking about the phenom-
of technology. enological and ethical implications of AI: not in the abstract,
but in use, as it is becoming part of our lifeworld and indeed
of our skilled practices and our coping.
6 Conclusion But Dreyfus’s work also remains relevant to contempo-
rary philosophy in general. Its main message is especially
For thinking about technology, Dreyfus’s account of skilled relevant and urgent when, and to the extent that, this philoso-
coping is and remains a valuable source, especially for phy is too mesmerized by formal and theoretical knowledge
those who are, like Dreyfus, interested in using Heidegger, and by abstract arguments and principles, to the neglect of
Merleau-Ponty, and the later Wittgenstein to better under- other, less explicit types of knowledge involved our everyday
stand the knowledge and experience involved in the use of living and coping. Together with other key twentieth-century
tools, in skillful coping with and through technologies. How- philosophers (and indeed contemporary cognitive science),
ever, I have also outlined and discussed some challenges Dreyfus successfully criticized the idea that we can sepa-
that come with Dreyfus’s approach: problems with regard rate mind and thinking from bodies and living people. If
to his assumptions about technology, his underdeveloped that were possible, we would not miss Dreyfus’s voice here

13
AI & SOCIETY

and now. The writings and other memory technologies we Coeckelbergh M (2017a) Using words and things: language and phi-
have would do the job of representing and preserving his losophy of technology. Routledge, New York
Coeckelbergh M (2017b) Technology games: using Wittgenstein for
thinking. But, as Dreyfus taught generations of philosophers understanding and evaluating technology. Sci Eng Ethics https://
by means of his teaching and (in my case) writings, nei- doi.org/10.1007/s11948-017-9953-8
ther thinking nor human beings can be reduced to what can Coeckelbergh M (2017c) Language and technology: maps, bridges, and
be represented. Thinking needs to be embodied and lived. pathways. AI Soc 32(2):175–189
Coeckelbergh M (2017d) New romantic cyborgs: romanticism, infor-
And, therefore—if not for other reasons—Hubert Dreyfus mation technology, and the end of the machine. MIT Press,
is greatly missed. Cambridge
Coeckelbergh M, Funk M (2018) Wittgenstein as a philosopher
Acknowledgment Open access funding provided by University of of technology: tool use, forms of life, technique, and a tran-
Vienna. scendentalargument. Hum Stud https://doi.org/10.1007/s1074
6-017-9452-6(online first)
Open Access This article is distributed under the terms of the Crea- Collins H (1992) Hubert L. Dreyfus, forms of life, and a simple test
tive Commons Attribution 4.0 International License (http://creativeco for machine intelligence. Soc Stud Sci 22:726–739. http://www.
mmons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted use, distribu- jstor.org/stable/285462
tion, and reproduction in any medium, provided you give appropriate Collins H (2013) The core of expertise. Phenomenol Cognit Sci
credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the 12:399–416. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-012-9277-8
Creative Commons license, and indicate if changes were made. Crawford MB (2009) Shop class as soulcraft: an inquiry into the
value of work. Penguin Press, New York
Dewey J (1922) Human nature and conduct. Allen & Unwin, London
Dewey J (1929) Experience and nature. George Allen & Unwin,
London
References Dreyfus HL (1967) Why computers must have bodies in order to be
intelligent. Rev Metaphys 21(1):13–32
Dreyfus HL (1972) What computers can’t do. the limits of artificial
Andler D (2000) Context and background: Dreyfus and cognitive sci- intelligence. MIT Press, New York
ence. In: Wrathall M (ed) Heidegger, coping and cognitive sci- Dreyfus HL (1975) The priority of the world to my world: Hei-
ence. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 137–159 degger’s answer to Husserl (and Sartre). Man World 8:121–130
Annas J (1993) The morality of happiness. Oxford University Press, Dreyfus HL (1980b) Holism and hermeneutics. Rev Metaphys
Oxford 34(1):3–23
Annas J (1995) Virtue as a skill. Int J Philos Stud 3(2):227–243. https Dreyfus HL (1991) Towards a phenomenology of ethical expertise.
://doi.org/10.1080/09672559508570812 Hum Stud 14:229–250
Annas J (2007) Virtue ethics. In: Copp D (ed) The Oxford handbook Dreyfus HL (1992) Response to Collins, artificial experts. Soc Stud
of ethical theory. Oxford University Press, Oxford Sci 22(4):717–726
Borgmann A (1984) Technology and the character of contemporary Dreyfus HL (1999) The primacy of phenomenology over logical
life: a philosophical inquiry. The University of Chicago Press, analysis. Philos Top 27(2):3–24
Chicago Dreyfus HL (2001a) Phenomenological description versus rational
Breivik G (2007) Skillful coping in everyday life and in sport: a critical reconstruction. Rev Int Philos 2(216):181–196
examination of the views of Heidegger and Dreyfus. J Philos Sport Dreyfus HL (2001b) On the internet (revised 2nd edition), 2009.
34(2):116–134. https://doi.org/10.1080/00948705.2007.9714716 Routledge, London
Carman T (2008) On being social: a reply to Olafson. Inquiry Dreyfus HL (2002a) Intelligence without representation—Merleau-
37(2):203–223 Ponty’s critique of mental representation. Phenomenol Cognit
Coeckelbergh M (2011a) Environmental virtue: motivation, skill, and Sci 1:367–383. https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1021351606209
(in)formation technology. J Environ Philos 8(2):141–170 Dreyfus HL (2002b) Refocusing the question: can there be skillful
Coeckelbergh M (2011b) Can we trust robots? Ethics Inf Technol coping without propositional representations or brain represen-
14:53–60 tations? Phenomenol Cognit Sci 1:413–425
Coeckelbergh M (2012) Technology as skill and activity: revisiting the Dreyfus HL (2005) Overcoming the myth of the mental: how philos-
problem of alienation. Techné 16(3):208–230 ophers can profit from the phenomenon of everyday expertise.
Coeckelbergh M (2013a) Human being@ risk: enhancement, technol- Proc Addresses Am Philos Assoc 79(2):pp 47–65
ogy, and the evaluation of vulnerability transformations. Springer, Dreyfus HL (2007a) The return of the myth of the mental. Inquiry
Dordrecht 50(4):352–365. https://doi.org/10.1080/00201740701489245
Coeckelbergh M (2013b) E-care as craftsmanship: virtuous work, Dreyfus HL (2007b) Response to McDowell. Inquiry 50(4):371–377.
skilled engagement, and information technology in health care. https://doi.org/10.1080/00201740701489401
Med Healthc Philos 16(4):807–816 Dreyfus HL (2012) Introductory essay: the mystery of the back-
Coeckelbergh M (2014) Good healthcare is in the how: the quality of ground qua background. In: Radman Z (ed) Knowing without
care, the role of machines, and the need for new skills. In: Coeck- thinking. Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke, pp 1–10
elbergh M, van Rysewyk SP, Pontier M (eds) Machine medical Dreyfus HL (2014) Skillful coping: essays on the phenomenology
ethics. Springer, Berlin, pp 33–47 of everyday perception and action. In: Wrathall M (ed) Oxford
Coeckelbergh M (2015) Environmental skill: motivation, knowledge, University Press, Oxford
and the possibility of a non-romantic environmental ethics. Rout- Dreyfus S, Dreyfus HL (1980a) A five-stage model of the mental
ledge, New York activities involved in directed skill acquisition. Operations
Coeckelbergh M (2016) Responsibility and the moral phenomenology Research Centre, University of California, Berkeley
of using self-driving cars. Appl Artif Intell 30(8):748–757 Dreyfus HL, Kelly SE (2011) All things shining. Reading theWestern
classics to find meaning in a secular age. Free Press, New York

13
AI & SOCIETY

Heidegger M (1927) Being and time: a translation of Sein und Zeit, Rietveld E (2010) McDowell and Dreyfus on unreflective action.
Stambaugh J (trans, 1996). State University of New York, Inquiry 53(2):183–207. https ://doi.org/10.1080/00201 74100
Albany 3612203
Heidegger M (1977) The question concerning technology. In: Lovitt Selinger E, Crease RP (2003) Dreyfus on expertise: the limits of phe-
W (trans) The question concerning technology and other essays. nomenological analysis. Cont Philos Rev 35:245–279
Harper & Row, New York, pp 3–35 Stichter M (2007) Ethical expertise: the skill model of virtue. Ethi-
Ihde D (1990) Technology and the lifeworld: from garden to earth. cal Theory Moral Pract 10:183–194. http://www.jstor.org/stabl
Indiana University Press, Bloomington e/40602522
MacIntyre A (1984) After virtue: a study in moral theory, 3rd edn. Vallor S (2015) Moral deskilling and upskilling in a new machine age:
2007. University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame reflections on the ambiguous future of character. Philos Technol
McDowell J (2007) Response to Dreyfus. Inquiry 50(4):366–370. https 28:107–124
://doi.org/10.1080/00201740701489351 Vallor S (2016) Technology and the virtues: a philosophical guide to a
McManus D (2007) Rules, regression and the ‘Background’: Dreyfus, future worth wanting. Oxford University Press, New York
Heidegger and McDowell. Eur J Philos 16(3):432–458. https:// Verbeek P (2005) What things do: philosophical reflections on technol-
doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0378.2007.00255.x ogy, agency, and design. The Pennsylvania State University Press,
McPherson I (2005) Reflexive learning: stages towards wisdom with University Park
Dreyfus. Educ Philos Theory 37(5):705–718. https://doi.org/10. Winner L (1986) The whale and the reactor: a search for limits in an
1111/j.1469-5812.2005.00152.x age of high technology. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago
Merleau-Ponty M (1945) Phenomenology of perception. Smith C Wittgenstein L (1969) On Certainty. In: Anscombe GEM, von Wright
(trans, 1962). Routledge, New York GH (eds) Basil Blackwell, Oxford(trans: Paul D, Anscombe
Olafson FA (2008) Heidegger à la Wittgenstein or ‘coping’ with Pro- GEM)
fessor Dreyfus. Inquiry 37(1):45–64 Wittgenstein L,. (trans: Anscombe E, Hacker PMS, Schulte J
Reynolds J (2006) Dreyfus and deleuze on, coping, and trauma in skill (1953/2009) Philosophical investigations, 4th edn. Wiley-Black-
acquisition. Int J Philos Stud 14(4):539–559 well, Malden

13

You might also like