You are on page 1of 8

2016 | Hau: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 6 (3): 485–492

REPRINT

Remarks on the verb


“to believe”
Jean Pouillon
 Translated from the French by John Leavitt

The French verb croire [“to believe”]1 is paradoxical in that it expresses doubt as
well as assurance. To believe [croire] is to state a conviction; it is also to add a nu-
ance to that conviction: “I believe” [je crois] often signifies “I’m not sure.” This
ambiguity involves the subjective side of belief [croyance]. As regards its object, the
situation is no less equivocal, since the complement of the verb can be produced in
two ways: direct or indirect. What is more, the indirect construction itself has two
forms: croire á . . . [“to believe in,” “to think of ”] is not the same thing as croire en
. . . [“to believe in,” in the sense of being willing to rely on], which both differ from
croire + direct object and croire que . . . [“to believe that . . .”]. Finally, the meaning of
the verb and the construction of the complement can vary depending on the nature
of the object: man, god, fact, value, statement. . . .

Editorial Note: This article is a reprint of Pouillon, Jean. 1982. “Remarks on the verb ‘to
believe.’” In Between belief and transgression: Structuralist essays in religion, history, and
myth. Edited by Michel Izard and Pierre Smith, translated by John Leavitt, 1–8. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press. The French original was published in Izard, Michel and Pierre
Smith, eds. 1979. La fonction symbolique. Paris: Gallimard. 43–51. We thank the Univer-
sity of Chicago Press for permission to publish this reprint, and we remind the reader that
we retain the style of the original translation with some minor formatting changes.
1. The author’s distinctions among different meanings of the verbs croire, croire en, croire
á, etc., bear on the semantics of the word, not directly in its morphology. For this reason
I have not followed the inflections of the French verb in my bracketed clarifications, but
have usually put the infinitive form, whatever the tense, person, etc. of the verb in the text.
For example, when the French text says il croit I have put “he believes” [croire], to make
clear the opposition with, say, il croit en, which I translate “he believes in.” —Trans.

 his work is licensed under the Creative Commons | © Jean Pouillon.


T
ISSN 2049-1115 (Online). DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.14318/hau6.3.034
This content downloaded from 200.019.190.168 on March 20, 2018 09:04:16 AM
All use subject to University of Chicago Press Terms and Conditions (http://www.journals.uchicago.edu/t-and-c).
Jean Pouillon 486

This suggests two questions (at least): is it possible to order this diversity of
usages? If so, is this order universal or does it characterize only a certain type of
culture, and in this case what is the basis for the word’s unity? In other words: how
is it that multiple meanings do not require diverse expressions?2 But since this is
apparently the case, is a translation of the verb in all its senses possible in other
languages, using a single term?
Croire á . . . is to state that something exists; croire en . . . is to have confidence;
croire que . . . is for something to be represented in a certain way. Although the
difference between the two indirect constructions may appear slight, it is undeni-
able, as the following example shows: a person believes in [croire en, “trusts in”]
God, while one believes in [croire á] the Devil, that is, one recognizes that he exists
without, by definition, putting one’s faith in him: one cannot croire en the Devil.
Croyance en [“belief in, trust in”] God does imply croyance á [“belief in”] his ex-
istence, but implication is not identity. On the other hand, this implication seems
so obvious that it often goes unformulated: a believer believes in [croire en, “trusts
in”] God, he feels no need to say that he believes in [croire á] it, one would say,
implicitly. But is this certain? In fact, the believer not only need not say that he
believes in [croire á] the existence of God, but he did not even believe in [croire á]
it; precisely because in his eyes there can be no doubt about it: the existence of God
is not believed in [crue], but perceived. On the contrary, to make God’s existence
an object of belief, to state this belief, is to open up the possibility of doubt—which
begins to clarify the ambiguity with which we started. So one could say that it is
the unbeliever who believes that the believer believes in [croire á] the existence of
God. One could call this a play upon words; but these words do lend themselves
to it, and it is precisely this possibility that must be explored, if not elucidated, in
trying to organize the field of their usages. Besides, what I have just said will appear
much simpler if we leave the religious domain. If I have confidence in a friend, if
I believe in [croire en, “have faith in”] him, will I say that I believe in [croire á] his
existence? Certainly not; that existence is, simply, undeniable. It is only if it were
not unquestionable that I would have to believe in [croire á] it, and believe in it ex-
plicitly. Again, it will probably be said that this is playing on words, this time on the
word “existence,” for the man’s existence, by definition, is not the same level as that
of the deity. By definition, yes, but by cultural definition: the distinction between
a cultural world and a natural world, or between a “this world” and a “beyond,” is
widespread, but it is not universal. It is this distinction between two modes of ex-
istence that leads to a knowledge on one side, belief [croyance] on the other. From
this kind of perspective, the existence of supernatural beings can only be an object
of belief, and this is why wherever this distinction is made the phenomenon of
belief as the affirmation of existence takes on this ambiguous aspect, between the
certain and the questionable.
This is not the only reason. Let us now consider the relations between croire á . . .
[“to believe in (a fact)] and croire que . . . [“to believe that . . .”]. To believe in [croire
á] the existence of X—“god, table, or washbasin”—can be expressed in a direct

2. Diverse expressions do exist, however: credit [créance], confidence, trust [confiance],


faith [foi] . . . . But while one might turn to these for the sake of precision, they are not
required by usage.

2016 | Hau: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 6 (3): 485–492


This content downloaded from 200.019.190.168 on March 20, 2018 09:04:16 AM
All use subject to University of Chicago Press Terms and Conditions (http://www.journals.uchicago.edu/t-and-c).
487 Remarks on the verb “to believe”

construction: to believe that [croire que] X exists. But this is a statement of a pecu-
liar type—the existence of a god or of a hundred thalers is not an attribute—and
is different from the statement that endows X with certain characteristics which
permit X to be represented to oneself. The representation, the content of belief, is
accompanied by an affirmation of existence but is separable from this affirmation;
the affirmation can be bracketed—the Husserlian epoché—and this is what makes
possible studies of beliefs as such: one need not believe in [croire á] what one be-
lieves in order to analyze it. The “I believe” [je crois] which precedes so many state-
ments of the most diverse kinds, is the mark of a distancing and not of an adhesion.
These two movements, which a single verb is able to express, appear radically
opposed, or else completely unrelated. Belief as representation, as statement, per-
tains to what is also called ideology; there is no isolated belief, every representation
is part of a global system which is more or less clearly, more or less consciously
articulated, a system which may be religious but may also be philosophical, politi-
cal . . . . Believe as faith [confiance] is the conviction that he to whom one has given
something will reciprocate in the form of support or protection; it calls forth a
relationship of exchange, of which the relationship between the believe and his god
is only a particular case, even if a frequently privileged one. One puts one’s faith
[confiance] to the same end, whether in an individual, in a party, in an institution.
It is significant in this regard that Benveniste, in his Indo-European Language and
Society (1969; English edition, London, 1973), discusses belief [la croyance] not
in the section on “religion” but in that on “economic obligations.” For he sees the
original meaning of belief in this credit which has been accorded and should be re-
turned. Must we then see belief-as-representation as a derivative meaning? Or else
as a meaning that has been added on, and which would turn the verb “to believe”
into a conglomerate without unity?
This derivation is certainly a possible one: to beliefe in [croire en] someone, to
give him credit, is, among other things, to believe [croire] what he says, and in this
way one goes from the trust to the statement that it allows one to take as established
fact. This is especially evident when the belief appears in the form of religious faith:
trust in [croyance en] a god is usually the basis of what we call a credo, a group
of statements which become the direct object of belief. The same is true in many
other domains. For political examples, there is an overabundance of choices. But
it is also possible (more often than is usually . . . believed!) to accept a proposition
that is said to be scientific just as one accepts a dogma or even the possibly fantas-
tic assertion of a man who is judged worthy of trust; I believe it not because I am
able to prove it, but because I have faith in those who say they have proven it, for
example, in Einstein when, following him, I write E=mc2. But we would miss the
essential part of belief-as-representation if we reduced it to this sole case in which
it is based on the argument of authority. The specific trait of a representation is to
appear obvious, to be self-evident, and the fact that it is always possible to bracket
the judgment or the feeling of obviousness changes nothing: the obvious is replaced
by the arbitrary, but both simply mean that this form of belief is based on nothing
but itself or the cultural system within which it finds its meaning.
So it seems impossible to overcome the polysemy of the word. Its religious usage
does allow us to unify the verb’s three constructions, but it does not eliminate the
other usages; over and above this, it only unites the three constructions in religions

2016 | Hau: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 6 (3): 485–492


This content downloaded from 200.019.190.168 on March 20, 2018 09:04:16 AM
All use subject to University of Chicago Press Terms and Conditions (http://www.journals.uchicago.edu/t-and-c).
Jean Pouillon 488

of a certain type. This observation leaves us to question its anthropological usage,


now well established and apparently unproblematic.3 What anthropologist would
deny that he seeks to uncover the beliefs of those of whom he studies, to compare
them with our own beliefs or those of other peoples, as if this object of study and its
designation presented no a priori problem, as if it were obvious that every human
being “believes” [croire]—this being one of our beliefs—in the same way, if not,
of course, in the same things? The danger in this situation is not simply the well-
known if not always foreseen one of inappropriately applying a category that may
have meaning only in our own culture; it has to do with the fact that this category
may not be a single, unified one at all, even for us, or at the least that is a shattered
category, whose fragmentation is, precisely, a singular cultural phenomenon. What
is more, anthropological usage reduplicates the paradox I emphasized above when
I said that it is the unbeliever who believes that the believer believes. If for example
I say that the Dangaleat4 believe in [croire á] it in the same way that I imagine I
could, if I did. But how can one tell whether they believe [croire] and in what way?
What question can one ask them, using what word of their language, in what con-
text? Or, inversely, how is it possible to translate into French the word or words they
use to talk about what is to our eyes an object of belief?
In J. Fédry’s Dictionnaire dangaleat,5 we find the verb àbidé “to perform the
rites faithfully.” It comes from the local Arabic abada, “to adore God,” adoration
being understood as a ritualized activity. It is a matter of worship [du culte], of faith
in action, and not of the representation of a being whose existence must also be
affirmed. This verb is used with a direct-object complement: this being, God for
converts to Christianity or Islam, or the margaï for others. The best way to translate
it is thus “to serve,” in the biblical sense of the trm: to worship [rendere un culte à]. No
abday margaï, “I serve the margaï.” Another verb, amniye, signifies “to bestow one’s
trust on,” “to rest on,” “to believe in” [croire en]. It is constructed with an indirect-
object complement, introduced by the preposition ku: no amnay ku marigo, “I have
faith in the margaï,” “I give my faith to the margaï”; this is the verb that Christian
use to say “I believe in [croire en] God,” no amnay ku bungir. In contrast to the fore-
going, this verb is not used exclusively in religious contexts: one can evidently, as
in French, put one’s faith in another person. The first sense given by the dictionary,
besides this, is “to be used to, familiar with . . . ,” and one will say, for example: no
amniy-iy-g pisò, “I am used to horses.” This too is a word of Arabic origin whose
Semitic root has given us the “amen” of Christian liturgy which, as Fédry points
out, marks adhesion to a person more than to a conceptual “truth.” As this author
notes, “one may wonder about the fact that both of these verbs come from Arabic,

3. Rodney Needham has done this (Belief, Language, and Experience), in a perspective
different from my own. The two do overlap, however: the themes are necessarily the
same, but they are put together in different ways.
4. The Dangaleat are one of the groups called Hadjeraï, who live in the central region of
the Republic of Chad, Department of Guera. They worship [rendent un culte á] what
one could summarily call local spirits: the margaï.
5. Thése du troisième cycle, mimeographed (1971). I thank the author for having added to
the information included in his thesis with a personal communication.

2016 | Hau: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 6 (3): 485–492


This content downloaded from 200.019.190.168 on March 20, 2018 09:04:16 AM
All use subject to University of Chicago Press Terms and Conditions (http://www.journals.uchicago.edu/t-and-c).
489 Remarks on the verb “to believe”

whose linguistic influence is very strong Dangaleat have taken what fits their own
way of “believing” [croire]: the terms that designate a specific behavior and mental
attitude—worshipping [rendre un culte] and trusting in the addressee of the wor-
ship—and not terms that are based on definite representations or propositions.
One may thus translate our “believe in” [croire en] into Dangaleat, and the fact
that the Hadjeraï took the word from Arabic suggests that for them it expresses the
essential aspect of belief (and of religious faith in general, says Fédry, who belongs
to the Society of Jesus and should know whereof he speaks): faith [la confiance].
But in this case, how can we translate “to believe [that]” [croire que]? To find out,
to know, to know about something, is ibiné; pakkine serves to render: think, sup-
pose, figure out, foresee. These two verbs are pure Dangaleat. The first will be used
to mark certainty and so translates “to believe” [croire] in cases where the French
verb is more or less equivalent with “to know,” when for instance Don Juan says to
Sganarelle, who is questioning him about belief, “I believe that two and two make
four.” The second verb covers the doubtful usages of our verb, all those in which the
speaker takes a certain distance with regard to what he is talking about.
In sum, we can translate all aspects of the verb “to believe” . . . except the verb
itself. What we have been able to translate has been the French equivalent of “to
believe” in each of its particular usages, but in Dangaleat there is no single term that
serves at the basis of their unification. In other words, we can translate everything
except the ambiguity. We must therefore return to the reasons for this ambiguity.
Ambiguity is not simply polysemy, the fact that a verb sometimes has one mean-
ing and sometimes another, each of them unequivocal; it is, rather, that all of these
meanings, even the contradictory ones, are intrinsically liked; that, above all, there
is always doubt at the heart of the conviction, and that the affirmation itself indi-
cated that it could always be suspended. But why condense this paradoxical liason
into a single word instead of sorting out its elements, as the Hadjeraï do? The an-
swer, “I believe,” lies in the comparison between a religion like Christianity and a
religion like that of the Dangaleat.
It is not so much the believer, I would say, who affirms his belief as such, it is
rather the unbeliever who reduces to mere believing what, for the believer, is more
like knowing. Nevertheless, the Christian cannot avoid expressing his faith not only
as trust in God [confiance en], but also as belief in [croyance à] his existence and
belief that [croyance que] God possesses such and such attributes, that the world
was created, and so forth. He states this as a belief, even though he knows it—but
also because he knows that by this very fact it is contestable and contested. Above
all he knows that there are other beliefs, on the one hand, because his religion has
a history and was constituted against the “false” gods, on the other because this
history is not over yet and there are still idols to be eliminated; and there can be
other beliefs only because his own belief is one among others. Next, he knows—it is
even an essential point in his credo—that the object of his belief is in a “reality” of
a different order than the realities of the world of creation, which are the object of
a permanently revisable scientific knowledge, or of calculations, of predictions that
can be proven wrong; and he also knows that this possibility of revision lies in the
demonstrable or verifiable character of the knowledge or the hypothesis, a char-
acter whose legitimacy he challenges in the case of his belief, but which, inversely,
challenges the legitimacy of his belief. Thus he must simultaneously assume both

2016 | Hau: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 6 (3): 485–492


This content downloaded from 200.019.190.168 on March 20, 2018 09:04:16 AM
All use subject to University of Chicago Press Terms and Conditions (http://www.journals.uchicago.edu/t-and-c).
Jean Pouillon 490

his affirmation and the challenge to it, a challenge that belief is, nonetheless, sup-
posed to make impossible on its own level. In other words, the contradiction is
inside his faith, and that is what it is “to believe.”6
This situation is the result of the distinction made between two worlds: the
Kingdom of God and this world. In our culture such a distinction seems so char-
acteristic of religion, to those who reject it as much as to its adherents, that religion
in general and so-called “primitive” religions in particular are usually defined by
a belief in supernatural powers and by their worship. There is even a tendency to
think that the extent and importance of the supernatural world are much greater
for “primitives” than for “moderns,” that super-nature is not only the domain of
gods and spirits but also, for example, the domain in which the power of the magi-
cian and the sorcerer operates. I certainly do not mean to deny that at any latitudes
one can find people who believe in [croire à] the supernatural, but one equally finds
people for whom such an affirmation is completely meaningless—without them
being, for all that, areligious—far from it. For here we have a major misunderstand-
ing: because we have constructed the concept of natural law, we are ready to admit
the supernatural (whether as illusion or as other reality hardly matters) as a place
to put whatever contravenes, or seems to contravene, natural law; but this is our
own notion, whether we judge it well grounded or not, and not that of the people
to whom we abusively attribute it. As Evans-Pritchard remarks, “many peoples are
convinced that deaths are caused by witchcraft. To speak of witchcraft being for
these peoples a supernatural agency hardly reflects their own view of the matter,
since from their point of view nothing could be more natural.”7 For his part, Claude
Lévi-Strauss has stressed the realist, materialist character of magic, its monistic, not
dualistic, conception of the world.8
The margaï, the spirits who have such an important place in the individual and
social lives of the Hadjeraï, are invisible, nonhuman powers; they act unpredict-
ably, and are the cause of whatever disturbs the natural course of things. But they
are no less a part of the same world as human beings. The latter believe in [croire
à] the existence of the margaï like they believe in their own existence, in that of
animals, things, atmospheric phenomena . . . . Or rather they do not believe in
[croire à] it: this existence is simply a fact of experience:9 there is no more need to
believe in [croire à] the margaï than to believe that if you throw a stone it will fall.

6. It would be easy to show that today many “political believers” find themselves in an
analogous situation. But they are not always as aware of it as Saint Augustine was when,
according to Tertullian, he said: credo quia absurdum.
7. Theories of Primitive Religion (Oxford, 1965), pp. 109-10.
8. Lévi-Strauss, The Savage Mind, English translation (Chicago, 1966), pp. 221-22.
9. In the same way, among the Nuer the expression Kwoth a thin (“God is present”) “does
not mean ‘there is a God.’ That would be for the Nuer a pointless remark. God’s exis-
tence is taken for granted by everybody. Consequently, when we say, as we can do, that
all Nuer have faith in God, the word ‘faith’ must be understood in the Old Testament
sense of trust (the Nuer Ngath). . . . There is in any case, I think, no word in the Nuer
language which could stand for ‘I believe’.” Evans-Pritchard, Nuer Religion (Oxford,
1956), p. 9.

2016 | Hau: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 6 (3): 485–492


This content downloaded from 200.019.190.168 on March 20, 2018 09:04:16 AM
All use subject to University of Chicago Press Terms and Conditions (http://www.journals.uchicago.edu/t-and-c).
491 Remarks on the verb “to believe”

One fears and/or trusts in them, one gets to know them, one gets used to them,
one performs the special sacrifices that please each margaï, and one is careful to
make no mistakes, for fear of getting sick or being affected in some unpleasant way.
If we can speak of a Dangaleat religion—another untranslatable expression—it is
not in the sense in which the faithful share a single elaborated body of beliefs about
supernatural beings, but rather in the etymological sense, according to Benveniste,
of the Latin religiō:10 that of a meticulous concern for the proper carrying out of the
cult, without, however, being able to define the necessary correctives in advance; at
every occasion, one takes aim within uncertainty. One can only estimate what each
margaï desires. The four verbs mentioned above define these behaviors equivo-
cally and without contradictions: one serves the margaï, one trusts in them (that is,
in the mutually fruitful nature of the exchange inaugurated by the sacrifice), one
knows from experience that they exist, and one tries to guess their intentions. All
this does presuppose a particular representation of the world, but one which ex-
cludes the possibility of its explanation in the form of “belief,” of an assertion that
in spite of itself is doubtful, relativized. The Dangaleat certainly know that others
think differently, and it happens that many of them convert to Islam or to Christi-
anity. But this situation cannot surprise them: one does not believe in [croire à] the
margaï; one experiences them, and this experience is first of all a local one; such
spirits do not necessarily exist everywhere. While the encounter with otherness
relativizes Christian belief in an otherworldly absolute, it confirms the Dangaleat
experience of the world, which is relative from the beginning and so cannot be
disturbed by diversity. This is why religions of the Dangaleat type are without the
proselytizing inherent in religions founded on beliefs whose vulnerability impels
their formidable dynamism.11
If the Dangaleat have no need of the verb “to believe” this is not solely because of
their monism, as opposed to Christian dualism. Equally in play is another opposi-
tion, one between the historicism of the Christian religion and the empiricism of
Dangaleat religion. This empiricism assures everyone of the presence of the margaï,
and has no need of an intercessor. Every man performs his own sacrifices and will
have recourse to the diviner only to know what animal, or what sex and what color,
he should kill and on what day. A religion like Christianity or Islam is based, on
contrary, on a revelation, testimony, a transmission whose fidelity is guaranteed by a
church or specialized experts. This revelation is, precisely, that another world exists;
the revelation is a unique historical event, its content is constituted by the words of its
protagonist, God incarnate or prophet. So everything rests on a faith, which is simul-
taneously a trust and a specific credo. All the meanings of the verb “to believe” should
then come together, but his necessity is nothing more or less than a cultural necessity.
It is only in this perspective, in my opinion, that we can speak of “religious belief,”
and it is only when it is understood that this notion does not have universal value
that we can appreciate how difficult the problem of a general definition of religion
really is; but this may also be the point from which we can try to resolve the problem.

10. Benveniste, Indo-European Language and Society.


11. I do not mean to say that some beliefs are vulnerable and others are not. Any belief, in
the fact of its communication, makes itself, and know itself to be, vulnerable.

2016 | Hau: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 6 (3): 485–492


This content downloaded from 200.019.190.168 on March 20, 2018 09:04:16 AM
All use subject to University of Chicago Press Terms and Conditions (http://www.journals.uchicago.edu/t-and-c).
Jean Pouillon 492

References
Benveniste, Emile. 1973. Indo-European Language and Society. London: Faber and Faber.
Evans-Pritchard, E.E. 1956. Nuer Religion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
———. 1965. Theories of Primitive Religion. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Fédry, Jacques. 1971. Dictionnaire dangaleat. PhD diss., Lyon.
Lévi-Strauss, Claude. 1966. The Savage Mind. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Needham, Rodney. 1973. Belief, Language, Experience. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.

Jean Pouillon (1916–2002) was a French anthropologist and was the editor of the
journal L’Homme since its foundation in 1961 to 1996. He is the author of many
works, including Temps et roman (Gallimard, 1946) and Le Cru et le su (Editions
Seuil, 1993).

2016 | Hau: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 6 (3): 485–492


This content downloaded from 200.019.190.168 on March 20, 2018 09:04:16 AM
All use subject to University of Chicago Press Terms and Conditions (http://www.journals.uchicago.edu/t-and-c).

You might also like