You are on page 1of 7

© Copyrighted Material

m
Introduction

co
te.
ga
sh
w.a
Angus J.L. Menuge

ww
m
co
te.
ga
sh
w.a
ww
m
co
Human Rights are All the Rage

te.
ga
sh
w.a
Human rights have never been so popular. On the one hand, they are used as

ww
ideological weapons to critique political and cultural adversaries. Liberals attack

m
co
the existing marriage laws for limiting the rights of homosexuals. Conservatives

te.
ga
sh
charge that religious freedom has been eroded by the imposition of secularist

w.a
ww
ideology in the public square. Western democracies denounce other societies for

m
their treatment of dissidents and religious minorities; these democracies are in turn
co
criticized for exploiting the developing world. The United States is singled out for te.
ga
sh
w.a

its use of torture and capital punishment and for its failure to provide universal
ww

health care.
m
co

On the other hand, appeal to human rights is used to advance the causes of social
te.
ga

justice and equality. In advanced liberal democracies, this includes more and more
sh
w.a

of what citizens expect from life. Healthcare, education and sexual orientation
ww

are now increasingly viewed as fundamental to human flourishing. Yet consensus


m
co
te.

on a basic list of human rights has proven elusive. Not a few of the countries
ga
sh

signatory to major human rights agreements exempt themselves from laws that
w.a
ww

contradict the dominant beliefs and customs of their people. And even if abuses
m

like slavery and religious discrimination are declared illegal, the prohibition may
co
te.
ga

not be enforced because the practices are culturally entrenched and ignored by law
sh
w.a

enforcement. In the West, the demand to recognize almost every strong preference
ww

as legally protected has led to contradictory rights claims. The right to life appears
m
co

to be the most fundamental right of all, since, without it, no other right can be
te.
ga

exercised. Yet elective abortion, euthanasia and even infanticide are also claimed
sh
w.a

as human rights. And while believers appeal to freedom of conscience to justify a


ww
m

religious voice in the public square, secularists charge that this violates their right
co
te.

to be free from such intrusion.


ga
sh
w.a
ww
m
co

The Goal of this Collection


te.
ga
sh
w.a

All this disagreement should make us ponder whether our zeal for proclaiming
ww

human rights is matched by a clear understanding of what they are. It is one thing
m
co
te.

to assert that the exercise of a particular interest is a human right. It is quite another
ga

thing to justify that assertion ontologically, epistemologically and pragmatically.


sh
w.a

An ontological justification must locate the basis in objective reality for asserting
ww

© Copyrighted Material
2 Legitimizing Human Rights
© Copyrighted Material
that human beings do have special, fundamental rights, rights that are universal,

m
inherent and inalienable. An epistemological justification must locate an accessible,

co
te.
ga
authoritative source or set of criteria we can use to identify human rights and to

sh
w.a
distinguish between legitimate and spurious human rights claims. A pragmatic

ww
justification must provide a feasible method for promoting the recognition and

m
co
enforcement of human rights protections.

te.
ga
In each of these three cases, the quest for justification must address several

sh
w.a
fundamental questions. Basic questions of ontological justification include:

ww
m
co
te.
1. What is a human right?

ga
sh
2. Why should we think such a thing really exists?

w.a
ww
3. What makes it the case that human beings have special rights?

m
co
te.
Basic questions of epistemological justification include:

ga
sh
w.a
ww
1. How can we know when something is a human right?
m
2. How can we know when something is not a human right? co
te.
ga

3. Which worldview provides the best explanation of human rights?


sh
w.a
ww

Basic questions of pragmatic justification include:


m
co
te.
ga
sh
w.a

1. How can a culture be encouraged to recognize the existence of human


ww

rights?
m

2. How can one reform a society with institutionalized human rights abuses?
co
te.
ga

3. How can human rights legislation be enforced?


sh
w.a
ww

Further, as with all rights, human rights have their limits. At what point shall we
m
co

say that the exercise of an interest no longer qualifies as a right because it infringes
te.
ga
sh

on the equal or stronger claims of others? In justifying human rights, we must


w.a
ww

also consider their proper scope and limits. It is important to be able to show that
m
co

some rights claims are spurious: they merely appropriate the language of rights to
te.
ga

disguise an aggressive or self-serving agenda. For example a country’s “right” to


sh
w.a

protect its own borders may be used to rationalize genocide, and a culture’s “right”
ww

to express a preferred religion may curtail the freedom of religious minorities.


m
co

The purpose of this collection is to address these fundamental questions of the


te.
ga
sh

legitimacy of human rights claims and to consider the merits of both secular and
w.a

religious perspectives. It is divided into three parts. The first part (“The Foundation
ww
m

of Human Rights”) discusses the relative merits of theism and naturalism as


co
te.

foundations for human rights, with authors defending both sides of the question.
ga
sh

The second part (“Religious Liberty and the Secular State”) considers the nature,
w.a
ww

scope and limits of religious freedom in the West and around the world. The final
m
co

part (“Enforcing and Motivating Human Rights”) ponders the best way to persuade
te.
ga

people to recognize, respect and protect human rights.


sh
w.a
ww

© Copyrighted Material
Introduction 3
© Copyrighted Material
The Foundation of Human Rights

m
co
te.
ga
In Chapter 1, Paul Copan focuses on the primary question of ontological

sh
w.a
justification and argues that without the biblical teaching that humans are made in

ww
m
the image of God, no list of our natural capacities provides an adequate foundation

co
te.
for human rights. A major problem for non-theistic ethics is that even the best are

ga
sh
incomplete: they simply assume humans have special dignity and worth without

w.a
ww
showing why this is to be expected on the basis of their underlying ontology.

m
co
Indeed, many of the most incisive atheist philosophers (such as Bertrand Russell,

te.
ga
J.L. Mackie and Kai Nielsen) have concluded that objective moral values cannot

sh
w.a
be grounded in an unintended physical universe. Copan further argues that as

ww
a matter of historical fact, the secular insistence on human rights itself derives

m
co
from borrowed theistic capital, and that it is this capital which provides the actual

te.
ga
sh
foundation for our claims of human worth and dignity. At the end of his chapter,

w.a
ww
Copan offers an extensive rebuttal to the well-known Euthyphro dilemma, which

m
seeks to show that theism cannot ground moral obligations.
co
In the next chapter, Paul Cliteur advances the contrary view, that human te.
ga
sh
w.a

rights are the child of secularism. Cliteur argues that theism is inadequate as a
ww

foundation for human rights because it promotes the harm of other people (holy
m
co

wars, stoning of homosexuals, male and female circumcision) and animals. He


te.
ga

uses an example of the latter (unstunned ritual slaughter) to argue that the secular
sh
w.a

state has the right to limit religious freedom where it promotes cruelty, violence
ww

or other harm, or where it violates standards of equality or reasonableness. In


m
co
te.

the process, Cliteur implicitly argues for the more general thesis that secular
ga
sh

reason can recognize a framework for evaluating human rights claims which is
w.a
ww

independent of any religious revelation. If a believer cannot demonstrate that a


m

practice is consistent with this framework, Cliteur argues, he or she cannot expect
co
te.
ga

the law to protect that practice.


sh
w.a

It will be observed that a primary disagreement between Copan and Cliteur


ww

is whether secular reason actually can provide a framework for adjudicating


m
co

conflicting human rights claims without drawing on theistic capital. If it can,


te.
ga

then there must be some way of grounding human rights in nature (or specifically
sh
w.a

human nature) without appeal to God.


ww
m

A popular way of dispensing with a theistic explanation is to argue that morality


co
te.

can be understood as an outgrowth of human evolution. In my contribution to this


ga
sh

collection, I consider the prospects of Evolutionary Ethics (EE) as a foundation


w.a
ww

for human rights. My analysis distinguishes Weak EE, which claims only that
m
co

our moral psychology is explained by our natural history, and Strong EE, which
te.
ga

asserts that this history explains the existence of moral values. The main thrust
sh
w.a

of the chapter is that human rights discourse is incompatible with grounding


ww

morality in the contingencies of naturalistic evolution. If Strong EE is true, the


m
co
te.

proper conclusion is that no such things as human rights exist. There simply
ga
sh

are no universal, inherent, inalienable rights humans have simply in virtue of


w.a
ww

being human because if humans had different biological histories these rights
© Copyrighted Material
4 Legitimizing Human Rights
© Copyrighted Material
would not exist. For example, there cannot be a human right to life since, if

m
co
we had been raised like hive bees, fratricide and female infanticide would be

te.
ga
permissible (perhaps obligatory). On the other hand, if Weak EE is true, while

sh
w.a
human rights may exist, we are in no position to know them, since it would

ww
be at best a lucky coincidence if our moral sensibilities tracked moral reality.

m
co
Either way, Evolutionary Ethics fails to vindicate the project of justifying human

te.
ga
sh
rights discourse by appeal to secular reason. This appears to leave a transcendent

w.a
foundation for human rights as a live option.

ww
m
To the contrary, in the last chapter of the section, Friedrich Toepel worries

co
te.
that religious pluralism makes it impractical to derive human rights from a

ga
sh
transcendent source. After all, theistic religions have scriptures which disagree,

w.a
ww
not only about the nature of God and humanity, but also about specific human

m
co
rights: for example, the prohibition of apostasy in Islamic Shariah law is regarded

te.
ga
as a violation of religious liberty by Christians and Jews. The same problem arises

sh
w.a
for secularists, since they also have conflicting visions of the good. For example,

ww
Kantians, utilitarians and ethical egoists have fundamental disagreements about
m
the nature of human flourishing. Toepel’s conclusion is that, even if there is a co
te.
ga
sh

correct ethical foundation for human rights, the lack of moral consensus makes
w.a
ww

this an impractical basis for implementing human rights protections. What is


m

needed instead are credible institutions that can create a framework of positive law
co
te.

recognized across ideological divides. Toepel is not a pure legal positivist and does
ga
sh
w.a

not claim that human rights can simply be reduced to what is recognized by positive
ww

law. Rather, as a “constructo-positivist,” he suggests merely that, as a practical


m
co

and linguistic matter, it is most helpful to restrict human rights discourse to what
te.
ga

can be institutionalized. From my perspective, this means that Toepel’s proposal


sh
w.a

is not attempting to establish the ontological or epistemological foundation for


ww

human rights. Instead, it aims to show the best pragmatic foundation—one that
m
co
te.

will maximize human rights protections in an ideologically pluralist milieu.


ga
sh
w.a
ww
m
co

Religious Liberty and the Secular State


te.
ga
sh
w.a

How can the state protect religious liberty and refrain from establishing a favored
ww

religious position? One of the founding ideals of the United States is that religious
m
co

freedom is best protected by a secular state, one which remains neutral between
te.
ga

religions. Yet it is not so easy to say what counts as a secular state. The word “secular”
sh
w.a

means “not religious,” and that means that state neutrality between religions can
ww

only be achieved if the state operates with a correct definition of religion. In his
m
co
te.

chapter, John Calvert argues on the basis of authorities in both philosophy and
ga
sh

law, that the correct definition of religion must be an inclusive, functional one. If
w.a
ww

the state adopts a narrow definition of “religion” as theistic belief, then the state
m
co

will favor non-theistic religions, such as Secular Humanism and Atheism. This
te.
ga

leads to the intrusion of religious bias in public schools because textbooks and
sh
w.a

instruction may contain religious material wrongly classified as secular. In fact,


ww

© Copyrighted Material
Introduction 5
© Copyrighted Material
Calvert argues that this has already happened. While Methodological Naturalism

m
co
(the claim that science can only appeal to unintelligent causes) can have great

te.
ga
value as a limited heuristic in many areas of science, when it is used to define

sh
w.a
the scientific method, students are not permitted to see the evidence that might

ww
m
support a theistic understanding of nature. The actual effect of this is to promote

co
te.
the religious views of materialist atheists (and theists who deny that God’s actions

ga
sh
are detectable in the natural world) and to discriminate against theists who believe

w.a
in natural theology. This can be avoided if a broader, functional definition of

ww
m
co
religion is used, which the Supreme Court has recognized in other cases.

te.
ga
In the next chapter, Vito Breda considers how matters of religious liberty are

sh
w.a
complicated by the greater religious diversity of modern Western democracies. His

ww
discussion focuses on Lautsi v. Italy, a recent case concerning religious symbols

m
co
in the classroom. In this case, the European Court of Human Rights took the view

te.
ga
sh
that, in the context of religious pluralism, secularism cannot simply be assumed to

w.a
ww
be the default, neutral position. This does not mean that religious expression cannot

m
be limited (it can, as soon as there is a clear threat to public order, or evidence of
co
coercive proselytization). Yet, Breda contends, in a pluralistic society, the mere te.
ga
sh
w.a

presence of religious symbols in some classrooms can be understood as part of a


ww

cultural dialogue, rather than an attempt to impose religious belief on others. In


m
co

this vein, the European Court allowed signatory states some discretion on deciding
te.
ga

whether religious symbols can be displayed. Breda sees this as an important case,
sh
w.a

because it represents a move away from the binary conflict between a supposedly
ww

neutral secularism and “religion,” to one that allows states to accommodate a


m
co
te.

plurality of religious perspectives.


ga

Still, just when can religious freedom legitimately be restricted? In the next
sh
w.a
ww

chapter, John Warwick Montgomery explores this thorny topic, noting that while
m

the major human rights instruments do recognize limitations on religious liberty,


co
te.
ga

they do not provide clear guidelines for discerning when these limitations apply.
sh
w.a

Today, for example, some Islamic countries either refuse to ratify human rights
ww

covenants or do so with reservations, indicating that they recognize no obligation


m
co

to comply if those covenants conflict with Shariah law. If we find this dissent
te.
ga

from basic human rights agreements unacceptable in some cases (for example, the
sh
w.a

imposition of the death penalty for apostasy), what criteria can we use to restrict
ww

these practices? As a precedent for limiting religious freedom, Montgomery


m
co

considers the Mormon polygamy case, Reynolds v. US, and finds it wanting because
te.
ga
sh

it creates a false dichotomy between religious belief and religious action. This can
w.a
ww

easily rationalize the ghettoization of believers in their places of worship found in


m
co

totalitarian states. Religious freedom will always entail some public expression,
te.
ga

so the real question is at what point, and on what grounds, this expression can
sh

be restricted. Montgomery argues that this limit cannot be adequately defined by


w.a
ww

appeal to natural law (it is too vague), neo-Kantian ideas (neither individuals nor
m
co
te.

states are willing to forego their special advantages), or legal positivism (it allows
ga
sh

obnoxious states to institutionalize religious discrimination). More generally,


w.a

due to their self-interest, humans are incapable of defining universal, inalienable


ww

© Copyrighted Material
6 Legitimizing Human Rights
© Copyrighted Material
rights: they must come from a transcendent source. In response to concerns that

m
co
this is impractical due to religious pluralism, Montgomery argues that even if the

te.
ga
proper basis for religious freedom is found in scripture, this can still be defended

sh
w.a
on independent grounds as good for society, and that the superior textual and

ww
historical reliability of the Bible over rival religious texts can be upheld.

m
co
te.
ga
sh
w.a
Enforcing and Motivating Human Rights

ww
m
co
te.
To say that something is a human right rings hollow if there is no effective means

ga
sh
of redress for human rights abuses. Hendrik Kaptein explores the unpopular idea

w.a
ww
of retribution, and argues that it is best understood as the attempt (not always

m
co
realizable) to restore victims to their original situation, as if no abuse had occurred.

te.
ga
As developed by Kaptein, retribution in this sense means, in effect, doing the

sh
w.a
right that should have originally been done. So understood, retribution is not

ww
something over and above respecting human rights: it is part of what it means to
m
co
say that human rights are respected. It is meaningless for a state to say that it has te.
ga
sh

a commitment to human rights and then to do nothing to redress violations when


w.a
ww

they occur. Kaptein argues that the de facto gap between human rights law and
m

actual enforcement requires urgent reform.


co
te.

Justice Dallas Miller agrees, and shows that on an international level, even
ga
sh
w.a

where human rights legislation is in place, massive abuses continue. Miller


ww

focuses on what motivates the recognition and protection of human rights. While
m
co

some claim this motivation derives from the Enlightenment, Miller argues that
te.
ga

the historical and contemporary data show that culturally effective human rights
sh
w.a

movements are most often the result of Judeo-Christian principles. Miller points
ww

out that the various secular rationales for human rights (such as utilitarianism,
m
co

neo-Kantian approaches and Marxism) all fail to transform the selfish human
te.
ga
sh

orientations that fuel abuses. And secularist attempts to justify human rights have
w.a
ww

failed to answer the skeptical critique of cultural relativists, undercutting the


m
co

rationale for human rights activism, and providing cover for tyrannical regimes. By
te.
ga

contrast, Miller argues, the drafting of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights
sh

was significantly shaped by a Judeo-Christian worldview, and this had a lasting


w.a
ww

influence on subsequent human rights instruments. At the same time, the actual
m
co

state of human rights protections is abysmal in many countries. For example, the
te.
ga

“new slavery” and other forms of human trafficking are actually increasing. While
sh
w.a

legal remedies are needed, it is naïve to think they will be accepted or enforced
ww
m

unless there is widespread cultural recognition of human rights. Miller argues,


co
te.

however, that some of the most effective promoters of this recognition have been,
ga
sh

and continue to be, committed Christians, who firmly believe that all people are
w.a
ww

valuable before God, and that we should treat others as we ourselves expect to be
m
co

treated. Faith, Miller concludes, has an important role in producing actual human
te.
ga

rights protections and enforcement.


sh
w.a
ww

© Copyrighted Material
Introduction 7
© Copyrighted Material
Dobrochna Bach-Golecka agrees and argues that a vital player in propagating

m
co
a high view of human value and dignity is the Christian Church. Focusing on

te.
ga
the example of Catholic social teaching, she shows how the Church supports

sh
w.a
human rights recognition in three ways. First, the Church has a general influence

ww
m
on the moral norms a culture accepts. Second, the Church provides criteria for

co
te.
distinguishing right and wrong behavior. Among these, most important are the

ga
sh
virtues of charity and solidarity: if a culture embraces these, it cannot passively

w.a
ww
accept the victimization of one group in its midst. Rather, it will stand with and for

m
co
that group until its mistreatment ends. Third, while the Church has no means of

te.
ga
coercive enforcement, it can call its members and the wider society to repentance,

sh
w.a
and can offer the peace of reconciliation. Bach-Golecka goes on to show how

ww
Catholic teaching motivates respect for human rights at several levels: the

m
co
congregational (where members are influenced by social teaching), the regional

te.
ga
sh
(through a conference of bishops) and the international (through the Vatican). At

w.a
ww
every level, the Church promotes the interdependence and solidarity of all human

m
beings before God, a powerful basis for opposing the oppression of the powerless
co
and the despised. te.
ga
sh
w.a
ww
m
co

A Continuing Dialogue
te.
ga
sh
w.a

While there are many other issues and perspectives that might have been included,
ww

my chief hope for this collection of chapters is that it will reinvigorate the
m
co
te.

conversation about the proper foundation for human rights. If we seek to protect
ga
sh

human freedom and dignity, we can only hope to make that a reality if we can
w.a
ww

convince people that fundamental human rights are real, knowable and vitally
m

important. So it is essential to find the best possible grounding for human rights
co
te.
ga

ontologically, epistemologically and pragmatically. While contributors to this


sh
w.a

volume do not all agree on the best answers here, they do share the conviction that
ww

human rights theory must translate into real-world protections. The alternative is
m
co

that academics continue the comfortable path of using human rights as rhetorical
te.
ga

machines de guerre for their preferred political agendas. This not only corrupts
sh
w.a

the discussion with self-serving motives, it also has no discernible impact on


ww
m

the widespread human rights abuses suffered disproportionately by members of


co
te.

developing nations. For this reason, I hope that the connection many contributors
ga
sh

draw between the theoretical justification and the practical implementation of


w.a
ww

human rights will not merely be intellectually interesting, but will also inspire
m
co

the work of lawmakers, political and religious leaders, and human rights activists.
te.
ga
sh
w.a
ww
m
co
te.
ga
sh
w.a
ww

© Copyrighted Material

You might also like