You are on page 1of 12

Available online at www.sciencedirect.

com
R

Journal of Volcanology and Geothermal Research 128 (2003) 287^298

www.elsevier.com/locate/jvolgeores

Logical assessment of observational knowledge in volcanology


C.A. Pshenichny a; , V.P. Moukhachov b , Z.V. Khrabrykh c
a
Levinson-Lessing Earthcrust Institut (NIIZK), Faculty of Geology, St. Petersburg State University, 7/9 Universitetskaya nab.,
199034 St. Petersburg, Russia
b
Logic Department, Faculty of Philosophy, St. Petersburg State University, St. Petersburg, Russia
c
Department of Mechanics of Controlled Motion, Faculty of Applied Mathematics and Control Processes,
St. Petersburg State University, St. Petersburg, Russia
Accepted 15 June 2003

Abstract

A paradox of volcanology is that the most fundamental part of its knowledge ^ the observation of volcanic
processes and objects ^ is less strict and less well organized compared with experimental and theoretical approaches
determined by these observations. The object of this study is the knowledge resulting from volcanological
observations, and the objective is to give this knowledge strict form. For this, we elaborate the methodology of
assessment of observational knowledge by means of propositional logic. Two kinds of assessments are developed:
(1) assessment of individual statements and rationales for truth and satisfiability; and (2) assessment of a set of
statements for self-consistency and deducibility of a statement from the set. Propositional logic allows an analyst to
find controversies and contradictions, build self-consistent domains of observational knowledge, and obtain strict
inference within these domains by means of logical calculi. We believe that the results of reported work can be used in
field volcanological studies for optimization of data interpretation, in hazard assessment for evaluation of
recommendations of experts and in risk mitigation for improving communication between scientists and non-
professionals.
3 2003 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved.

Keywords: logic; volcanology; hazard assessment; consistency; conceptual uncertainty; inference; observations

1. Introduction eling and theoretical considerations are given a


basis by observations and make sense only in re-
Observations of eruptive processes and their lation to them. Moreover, in many cases the vol-
products are the primary, most valuable and reli- canologic reconstruction, forecast and hazard as-
able source of volcanological information. Mod- sessment are based solely or almost solely on
observations, current and preceding, particular
and general. Simultaneously, the reasoning on ob-
servations remains pretty loose and ‘woolly’. As
was stated earlier, the tool for improving the sit-
* Corresponding author..
E-mail addresses: pshenich@kp1306.spb.edu
uation is logic (Pshenichny and Moukhachov,
(C.A. Pshenichny), mukhachev@mail.ru (V.P. Moukhachov), 2001; Pshenichny, 2002). This paper aims to ex-
zkh@mail.ru (Z.V. Khrabrykh). plore the opportunities of the simplest logical sys-

0377-0273 / 03 / $ ^ see front matter 3 2003 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved.
doi:10.1016/S0377-0273(03)00261-0

VOLGEO 2697 4-11-03


288 C.A. Pshenichny et al. / Journal of Volcanology and Geothermal Research 128 (2003) 287^298

tem ^ propositional logic ^ in assessment of rea- Verbal expressions like ‘not true that’, ‘and’,
soning on volcanological observations. ‘or’, ‘if T then’, ‘if and only if T then’, ‘either T
Theoretically, two kinds of assessments can be or’ and some others have the sense of logical con-
made based on propositional logic. These are the nectives. Propositional logic studies the exact
assessment of an individual statement for truth sense of these expressions and general laws of
and assessment for deducibility of a statement their usage.
from other statements (and/or self-consistency of Those statements that do not include logical
a set of statements). We consider the application connectives are termed simple; those that do are
of these assessments to pieces of volcanological compound statements, or compounds. Compounds
knowledge and discuss the theoretical and practi- also are true or false. Their logical values are de-
cal bene¢ts of our approach. termined, ¢rst, by the logical values of elementary
The works on application of logic or related statements, and second, by the logical connectives
approaches in Earth sciences are very scarce (Si- between them.
rotinskaya (1986); Cagnoli (1998); Klir (2002)) The language of propositional logic is an arti-
and consider the logic solely as a means of data ¢cial language capable of disclosing the logical
interpretation but not as a tool to study the rea- structure of compound statements.
soning in a ¢eld of knowledge (Pshenichny and The alphabet of this language includes three
Moukhachov, 2001). Meanwhile, those scientists kinds of signs.
focusing on the structure of knowledge in partic- 1. Propositional variables: p, q, r, s, t, p1 , q1 , r1 ,
ular domains of geology (e.g. in stratigraphy ^ s1 , t1 , p2 , q2 , T, expressing elementary statements.
Dienes, 1978 ^ or tectonics ^ Potts and Reddy, 2. Logical connectives : F negation, p conjunc-
1999) did not use logic in their work that re- tion, K disjunction, a implication, r equivalence
stricted their results solely to these domains. and, possibly, some others.
However, there were attempts at constructing 3. Technical signs : (, left bracket; ), right
(or revealing ?) universal patterns of thinking by bracket.
means other than logic (see e.g. Gould, 1981; The basic concept in propositional logic is the
Fedorov, 1989), which doubtless are of great in- propositional formula. It is de¢ned as follows.
terest but, like any other knowledge except the 1. Propositional variable is propositional for-
logic itself, require an assessment by means of mula (e.g. p is a formula).
logic. 2. If A is a propositional formula, then FA is a
formula too.
3. If A and B are propositional formulae, then
2. Propositional logic (ApB), (AKB), (AaB), (ArB) are formulae too.
A and B are called metaletters. This means that
Propositional logic in its modern form was ela- FA, (ApB), (AKB), (AaB), (ArB) are not nec-
borated in the second half of the 19th to the ¢rst essarily Fp, (ppq), (pKq), (paq), (prq), corre-
half of the 20th century by Frege (1896), White- spondingly, but just principal schemes of formu-
head and Russell (1910), Hilbert and Bernays lae, in which another formulae of any length can
(1956), Kleene (1952) and other researchers. We occupy the places of A and B.
will give a brief account of it based dominantly on The connective expressed in this scheme is
Kleene (1952). called the main connective of the propositional
This logic describes the relations between state- formula. Any part of a given propositional for-
ments, or propositions. These are expressed by mula, which is a propositional formula itself, is
narrative sentences of natural language (English, called a subformula of this formula.
Russian, Greek, etc.). A statement is the sense of By accepted convention, each connective, ex-
narrative sentence. It is either true or false. These cept negation, requires a pair of left and right
two characteristics are logical values, or truth val- brackets, though the entire formula may be not
ues, of statements. taken into brackets.

VOLGEO 2697 4-11-03


C.A. Pshenichny et al. / Journal of Volcanology and Geothermal Research 128 (2003) 287^298 289

Table 1
General truth table for basic logical connectives
A B FA ApB AKB AaB ArB
TRUE TRUE FALSE TRUE TRUE TRUE FALSE
FALSE TRUE TRUE FALSE TRUE TRUE TRUE
TRUE FALSE FALSE TRUE FALSE TRUE
FALSE FALSE FALSE FALSE TRUE FALSE

3. Methodology of logical assessments of p ‘Lava is slowly ejecting’;


observational knowledge q ‘Lava piles up in a dome’;
r ‘There is lava £ow’.
3.1. Assessment of rationales for truth by truth Then we will have this rationale in the follow-
tables ing form:
ððpaqÞaFrÞÞKðparÞ ð1Þ
The exact sense of the logical connectives is
de¢ned by the following truth table (see Table 1). Its truth table (Table 3a) shows that it is always
The truth value of a formula is that of its main true.
connective. There are formulae which can have At the same time, the statement ‘Either slowly
only one truth value (i.e. are always true or al- ejecting lava piles up in a dome or forms a short
ways false) with any values of variables ; e.g. the thick viscous £ow’ is satis¢able:
formula (pKFp) is always true and (ppFp) is ðpaqÞKðparÞ ð2Þ
always false (see Table 2).
If a formula is always true, it is called a logical and the statement ‘Slowly ejecting lavas both pile
law, or tautology. If it is always false, it is a con- up in domes and behave in di¡erent mode’ is a
troversy (not to be confused with the controversy controversy:
as the relation between any two statements, one
ðprqÞpðprFqÞ ð3Þ
of which is the negation of the other; the conjunc-
tion of these statements gives the controversy in (see Tables 3b and c, respectively).
the sense meant here; to avoid ambiguity, we will We should always keep in mind that statements
call this relation a contradiction). Some basic tau- in the logical sense may have various expressions
tologies are listed in Appendix. All the rest of the in a natural language, such as English. A state-
formulae may take both truth values and are ment may be expressed not by a sentence but by a
called neutral, or satis¢able. shorter phrase, and a compound or even several
For instance, the following rationale is tautol- compound statements can be ‘packed up’ in one
ogy. ‘If the lava is slowly ejecting, it piles up in a sentence of natural language. Simultaneously,
dome and does not £ow, or, while ejecting, it one, even simple, logical statement can appear
forms a short thick viscous £ow.’ Let us denote ‘scattered’ in more than one sentence of natural
every simple statement with a propositional vari- language. Logical connectives may be diversely
able: expressed in verbal form. Therefore, we should
be very careful when extracting the sense, always
aiming to ¢gure out what is actually meant in the
Table 2 sentence, written, or said, or thought.
Truth table for most simple tautology (pKFp) and contro-
versy (ppFp) If formulae have similar truth values with the
same truth values of variables (e.g. see Table 4),
p Fp pKFp ppFp
they are called equivalent and can be substituted
TRUE FALSE TRUE FALSE by one another, e.g. formulae (paq) and
FALSE TRUE TRUE FALSE
(FpKq):

VOLGEO 2697 4-11-03


290 C.A. Pshenichny et al. / Journal of Volcanology and Geothermal Research 128 (2003) 287^298

Table 3a
Truth table for tautology ((paq)aFr))K(par), T ^ TRUE, F ^ FALSE
p q r paq Fr (paq)aFr par ((paq)aFr))K(par)
T T T T F F T T
F T T T F F T T
T F T F F T T T
F F T T F F T T
T T F T T T F T
F T F T T T T T
T F F F T T F T
F F F T T T T T

ðpaqÞrðFpKqÞ the appearance of a formula, whether it is tautol-


ogy, controversy or satis¢able.
This means, for instance, that the statement ‘If Using equivalent substitutions (see Appendix),
there is a fallout of ¢ne ash, there will be lung any formula can be brought to its conjunctive nor-
diseases in people living in the fallout area’ is mal form (CNF). This is a form in which all im-
equivalent to the statement ‘Either there is no plication and equivalence signs are substituted by
fallout of ¢ne ash, or people have lung diseases’. combination of conjunction, disjunction and neg-
Again, this equivalence is not clearly seen in nat- ation and the formula becomes a conjunction of
ural language but is obvious in the language of elementary disjunctions. ‘Elementary’ means that
propositional logic. Equivalent substitutions are disjunctions disjoin only individual variables and
used to express one logical connective by others the negation refers only to variables too. Simi-
and/or construct strict inference (see below). larly, the formula can be brought to a disjunctive
Naturally, all tautologies are equivalent to each normal form (DNF), which is the disjunction of
other, and similarly all controversies are equiva- elementary conjunctions; the rule for negation is
lent to each other. Basic equivalences of proposi- the same.
tional logic are listed in the Appendix. It is easy to show that:
(1) every formula in propositional logic has at
3.2. Assessment of rationales for truth by reduction least one (maybe more) CNF and DNF;
to normal forms (2) the formula is a tautology if every elemen-
tary disjunction in its CNF includes at least one
If the formula is long enough, the truth table is elementary disjunction of a variable and its neg-
not useful. However, truth tables are not the only ation; and
way to assess formulae for truth. The structure of (3) the formula is a controversy if its DNF in-
a formula and the set of truth values it takes are cludes at least one elementary conjunction of a
interrelated. Therefore, it is possible to say just by variable and its negation

Table 3b
Truth table for satis¢able formula (paq)K(par)
p q r paq par (paqK(par)
TRUE TRUE TRUE TRUE TRUE TRUE
FALSE TRUE TRUE TRUE TRUE TRUE
TRUE FALSE TRUE FALSE TRUE TRUE
FALSE FALSE TRUE TRUE TRUE TRUE
TRUE TRUE FALSE TRUE FALSE TRUE
FALSE TRUE FALSE TRUE TRUE TRUE
TRUE FALSE FALSE FALSE FALSE FALSE
FALSE FALSE FALSE TRUE TRUE TRUE

VOLGEO 2697 4-11-03


C.A. Pshenichny et al. / Journal of Volcanology and Geothermal Research 128 (2003) 287^298 291

Table 3c
Truth table for controversy (prq)p(prFq)
p q Fq prq prFq (prq)p(prFq)
TRUE TRUE FALSE TRUE FALSE FALSE
FALSE TRUE FALSE FALSE TRUE FALSE
TRUE FALSE TRUE FALSE TRUE FALSE
FALSE FALSE TRUE TRUE FALSE FALSE

(for a strict proof, see e.g. Hilbert and Bernays, logic. If the given statement is deducible, or can
1956). be inferred, from some set of statements, the ques-
This can be illustrated by the corresponding tion arises whether it is possible to infer its neg-
forms of formulae 1^3. ation from the same set. If not, then this set of
The CNF for formula 1, which is a tautology, is statements is called self-consistent and valid for
(pKFrKFpKr)p(FqKFrKFpKr). The CNF reasoning, if yes, it is inconsistent and requires
for a satis¢able formula (formula 2) is FpKqKr. correction (adding, removal or re-formulation of
DNFs are longer. We will not give the DNF for the statements it consists of).
formula 2, for it is not illustrative, and a some- Assessment for deducibility and self-consistency
what simpli¢ed DNF for a controversy (formula can be made by logical calculi. Logical calculus is
3) is: a transformation or a succession of transforma-
tions of formulae in accordance with some rules of
ðFppFqpqÞKðFppFqppÞKðFppppqÞK
inference, which reveals that formula B follows
ðFpppÞKðFppppFqpqÞKðFppppFqÞK from formulae A1 , A2 , T, An . (As before, A, B
and other capital letters are metaletters meaning
ðqpFqpFpÞKðqpFqpFpppÞ any kind of propositional formula.) This means
that B has the value TRUE if and only if each
Underlined symbols are variables, with their of A1 , A2 , T, An has this value. Logical conse-
negations occurring within elementary disjunc- quence is denoted A1 , A2 , T, An CB. Formulae
tions or conjunctions. A1 , A2 , T, An are called premises, B consequence.
Reduction to normal forms is the simplest cal-
3.3. Assessment of rationales for deducibility and culus, in which there is one premise and the only
consistency kind of rules of inference is equivalent substitu-
tion. In trivial cases, so-called principal and short-
If we want to know whether a standpoint or ened conjunctive and disjunctive normal forms
decision is substantiated well enough and is ¢rmly help ¢nd all consequences (conjunctive forms)
supported by data and general concepts, we need and hypotheses (disjunctive forms) of given for-
to check it for deducibility from what we take for mulae. However, if the case is more than one
premises (i.e. these very data and concepts). This assumption (that is, actually, the case in most
task is the same as strict proof and inference of cases), more powerful calculi (sequential, natu-
statements that is elaborated well in propositional ral-sequential and others) with speci¢c rules of
inference apply.
Table 4 We will demonstrate strict inference from vol-
Truth table for the formulae (paq) and (FpKq) canological observations by the example of natu-
p q Fp paq FpKq ral-sequential calculus elaborated by Gentzen
TRUE TRUE FALSE TRUE TRUE (1934). It is described below.
FALSE TRUE TRUE TRUE TRUE 1.1. Sequence is expression A1 , A2 , T, Am CB,
TRUE FALSE FALSE FALSE FALSE where A1 , A2 , T, Am , B are propositional formu-
FALSE FALSE TRUE TRUE TRUE
lae. Formulae A1 , A2 , T, Am are front members of

VOLGEO 2697 4-11-03


292 C.A. Pshenichny et al. / Journal of Volcanology and Geothermal Research 128 (2003) 287^298

the sequence, and B is the back member. There y !A


may be no front members at all, but the back one v !B
must always be present: CB. y; v ! ðApBÞ
1.2. Inference in natural-sequential calculus con-
sists of a number of sequences. Each of these Elimination of conjunction (henceforth Rule
either is ‘main sequence’ (see below) or is derived EC):
from a previous one by a structural transforma-
y ! ApB y ! ApB
tion (see below) or a rule of inference (see below). y! A y! B
The last sequence of an inference has no front
members and its back member is a ¢nite formula. Introduction of disjunction (henceforth Rule
1.3. There are two types of main sequences, ID):
called ‘logical’ and ‘mathematical’ ones. A logical
y! A y! B
main sequence is a sequence of general form y ! AKB y ! AKB
CCC, where C is a propositional formula (this
sequence arises if the inference is based on as- Elimination of disjunction (henceforth Rule
sumption expressed by C). A mathematical main ED) :
sequence is a sequence of general form CD,
where C is an axiom of mathematics. y ! AKB
1.4. Allowed structural transformations (for A; v ! C
propositional logic; a horizontal line means that B; 3 ! C
the below sequence follows from the above se- y; v; 3 ! C
quences).
1.4.1. Transposition of two front members: Introduction of implication (henceforth Rule
II):
C; D; y ! v
D; C; y ! v A; y ! B
y ! AaB
1.4.2. Withdrawal of a front member, which is
the same as another front member: Elimination of implication (henceforth Rule
C; C; y ! v EI) :
C; y ! v y ! A
v ! AaB
1.4.3. Addition of any propositional formula to y; v ! B
front members :
y !v Introduction of negation (henceforth Rule IN):
C; y ! v
A; y ! B
There is a speci¢c rule for predicate logic, A; v ! FB
which we do not cite here. y; v ! FA
1.5. Rules of inference (for propositional logic).
Let A, B and C denote any propositional for- Elimination of double negation (henceforth
mulae and y, v and 3 any (possibly empty) lists Rule EN):
of formulae divided by commas. The formulae of
y ! FFA
these lists are front members of some sequences. y ! A
The following rules of inference of natural-se-
quential calculus are applicable to propositional In the above expressions, the symbols put to
logic. the left of the arrow can be regarded as the ‘mem-
Introduction of conjunction (henceforth Rule ory’ of the inference, and those to the right are its
IC): ‘working part’.

VOLGEO 2697 4-11-03


C.A. Pshenichny et al. / Journal of Volcanology and Geothermal Research 128 (2003) 287^298 293

Fig. 1. (Figure 6 in Fisher (1990).) Locality N33.3, 9.5 km from the source. Upper contact of layer A1 shows innumerable tiny
gas pipes extending upward into layer A2.

4. Application and can be expressed as the equivalence of the


following statements: ‘Layer A2 has ¢ner grain
We apply this calculus to a fragment of paper size’r‘Layer A2 is less permeable’, but for sim-
by Fisher (1990) on turbulent pyroclastic £ow de- plicity of proof we omit this equivalence;
posits of the Mt. St. Helens May 1980 eruption. r ‘Gas pipes form’ (we may also add, ‘T form
The fragment consists of a paragraph of text (see distinctly enough to be preserved by the moment
below) and a ¢gure (see Fig. 1), which gives in- of observation’);
formation also involved in reasoning. s ‘Material of layer A1 was gas-rich’ (again,
‘The contact relationship between layer A2 and here we actually have the equivalence, ‘ Material
A1 suggests that layer A1 was gas-rich during of layer A1 was gas-rich’r‘The gas pressure in
transport, but because it lacked abundant ¢nes layer 1 was high’);
it was permeable, gases were usually expelled t ‘Material of layer A2 was in place’ (by the
quickly during transport. Except in a few places, moment of formation of layer A1 in a given
gas loss occurred before layer A2 was fully in place);
place, allowing development of a sharp contact u ‘There is a sharp top of layer A1’ (speaking
by movement of A2 after A1 had come to rest. about formation of the sharp contact, Fisher says
At a few localities, however, layer A2 was em- that, in his view, it is sharp exactly because ¢rst it
placed fast enough to seal o¡ the gas within was not a contact between two layers but just the
layer A1 before it completely escaped, and the top of one of them).
gas pressure was great enough to cause continued Having introduced such statements, we can for-
upward movement of gas into layer A2, resulting mulate the assumptions that led Richard Fisher to
in preservation of the gas pipes’ (Fisher, 1990, the conclusions he made.
p. 1042). sap ! sap ðassumption 1Þ
Let us denote relevant statements of this frag-
ment. ‘If the layer A1 was gas-rich, gas had to be
p ‘Gas escapes from the layer A1’ (or, in terms escaping from it’. Fisher obviously means this,
of Fisher, ‘gases escaped quickly during trans- though he does not put this explicitly (perhaps
port’); because he considers this notion obvious):
q ‘Layer A2 is less permeable than the layer A1’ ðppqÞar ! ðppqÞar: ðassumption 2Þ
(this is not explicitly said but shown in the ¢gure
(see Fig. 1) as ¢ner grain size of layer A2 than A1 ‘If gas was escaping from layer A1 and layer A2

VOLGEO 2697 4-11-03


294 C.A. Pshenichny et al. / Journal of Volcanology and Geothermal Research 128 (2003) 287^298

is less permeable than A1, gas pipes must form’. 2. (ppFt)auC(ppFt)au (assumption 3)
The third assumption is: 3. sCs (assumption 6)
4. FtCFt (assumption 7)
ðppFtÞau ! ðppFtÞau ðassumption 3Þ
5. sap, sCp (Rule EI for lines 1, 3)
‘If gas was escaping from layer A1 and layer A2 6. sap, s, FtCppFt (Rule IC for lines 4, 5)
was not yet in place, A1 will form a sharp top.’ 7. sap, s, Ft, (ppFt)auCu (Rule EI for lines
In addition, we can make some obvious as- 3, 6)
sumptions in the form accepted in natural-sequen- 8. sap, Ft, (ppFt)auCsau (Rule II for
tial calculus : line 7)
p!p ðassumption 4Þ
9. sap, FtC((ppFt)au)a(sau) (Rule II for
line 8)
q!q ðassumption 5Þ 10. sapC(Fta((ppFt)au)a(sau)) (Rule II
for line 9)
s!s ðassumption 6Þ 11. C(sap)a(Fta((ppFt)au)a(sau)) (Rule
II for line 10)
Ft ! Ft ðassumption 7Þ The back member of the ¢nal sequence is a
tautology. Conclusion 2 is proved. This means
Then the conclusions of Fisher will look like: that the conclusions of Fisher on the relationship
sar ðconclusion 1Þ
between the two tu¡ layers are strictly proved.
However, this does not mean that they have
(‘if layer A1 was gas-rich, then there will form become an absolute truth. Let us widen the set
gas pipes’), and of assumptions by adding few new statements
sau ðconclusion 2Þ
(propositional variables) re£ecting some obvious
facts of volcanology.
(‘if layer A1 was gas-rich, then this layer will The variables are:
have a sharp top’). f ^ pyroclastic material £ows,
The ¢rst one can be proved based on assump- g ^ pyroclastic material degasses quickly.
tions 1, 2, 5 and 6, using structural transforma- (Following Fisher, herewith we consider pyro-
tions where necessary. The inference is below. clastic £ows only, not tephra, hence the negation
1. sapCsap (assumption 1) of f, Ff, would mean that pyroclastic material
2. (ppq)arC(ppq)ar (assumption 2) becomes a layer.) Then we can make the following
3. qCq (assumption 5) assumptions:
4. sCs (assumption 6)
f !f ðassumption 8Þ
5. sap, sCp (Rule EI for lines 1, 4)
6. sap, s, qCppq (Rule IC for lines 3, 5) g!g ðassumption 9Þ
7. sap, s, q, (ppq)arCr (Rule EI for lines 6, 2)
8. sap, q, (ppq)arCsar (Rule II for line 7) gaFs ! gaFs ðassumption 10Þ
9. sap, qC((ppq)ar)a(sar) (Rule II for line 8)
10. sapC(qa(((ppq)ar)a(sar))) (Rule II for ðf pgÞaFs ! ðf pgÞaFs ðassumption 11Þ
line 9)
11. C((sap)a(qa(((ppq)ar)a(sar)))) (Rule II Assumption 10 means that a natural measure of
for line 10) ‘quickness’ is that every next time the material is
The back member of the ¢nal sequence is a notably poorer in gas than before. Assumption 11
tautology. Conclusion 1 is proved. means that if pyroclastic material £ows and de-
The second conclusion is also deducible, from gasses quickly, the material of the resulting layer
assumptions 1, 3, 6 and 7 (with appropriate struc- (A1 in our case) is not gas-rich (otherwise the
tural transformations). degassing cannot be considered quick indeed ^
1. sapCsap (assumption 1) see above).

VOLGEO 2697 4-11-03


C.A. Pshenichny et al. / Journal of Volcanology and Geothermal Research 128 (2003) 287^298 295

With these assumptions, the following can be reported by Moukhachov and Netchitailov
proved (keeping in mind the structural transfor- (2001).
mations) :
1. fCf (assumption 8)
2. gCg (assumption 9) 5. Discussion: practical bene¢ts and future
3. f, gCfpg (Rule IC for lines 1, 2) research
4. (fpg)aFsC(fpg)aFs (assumption 11)
5. f, g, (fpg)aFsCFs (Rule EI for lines 3, 4) Assessment of individual statements for truth, if
6. gaFsCgaFs (assumption 10) it were to become practice of ¢eld volcanological
7. f, (fpg)aFsCFg (Rule IN for lines 5, 6) studies, would ensure a check on thinking and
8. f, g, (fpg)aFsCFgpFs (Rule IC for lines instant correction. As was shown here by a trivial
5, 7) example of formulae 1^3 (see Section 3.1), similar
9. f, g, (fpg)aFsCfpFgpFs (Rule IC for information may be given in many di¡erent ways,
lines 1, 8) and recording it in terms of propositional logic
10. f, gC((fpg)aFs)a(fpFgpFs) (Rule II helps us understand what we actually mean and
for line 9) whether what we mean is correct (i.e. expressed by
11. fCga(((fpg)aFs)a(fpFgpFs)) (Rule II satis¢able formulae or tautologies). It is unlikely
for line 10) that we will be able to formulate many of our
12. Cfa(ga(((fpg)aFs)a(fpFgpFs))) ideas as tautologies. What is more probable is
(Rule II for line 11) that a combination of di¡erent standpoints, or
Based on the main tautologies of propositional even the thoughts of similar scientists at di¡erent
logic (see Appendix), it can be shown that the stages of research, can lead to controversy, which
inferred formula f and Fg and Fs is equivalent may pass unnoticed if not revealed by truth tables
to F((f and Fg)as). Literally, it means that ‘it is or normal forms.
not true that if pyroclastic material £ows and not However, even more important is the assess-
degasses quickly, the material of the resulting ment for deducibility and self-consistency by the
layer will be gas-rich’ or, in simpler words, if py- procedure of strict inference. It allows us to ex-
roclastic £ow degasses quickly, the resulting de- plicitly formulate premises of reasoning, follow
posit will not be gas-rich. This contradicts the idea the pathway of thought and discern thinking
taken for assumption 1, thus exposing a hidden from intuition. This is especially important in haz-
contradiction between the two premises formu- ard assessment, where recommendations of di¡er-
lated verbally as: (1) ‘gases escaped quickly dur- ent experts (often made by intuition) require ob-
ing transport’, and (2) ‘layer A1 was gas-rich jective and unbiased trial. Even formalized expert
upon deposition’. To avoid it, a statement was judgement procedures so far have been based on
required that gases had not escaped during trans- consensus or poll, possibly with statistical weigh-
port, which could invoke a special consideration ing of opinions (Aspinall and Cooke, 1998; Aspi-
why this had not happened, and so forth, until nall and Woo, 1994; Ross, 1989). However, an
new self-consistency is achieved. opinion, both individual and collective, may be
Other calculi than natural-sequential can also in£uenced by purely psychological factors, and
be applied in volcanology. There are theorems weighing demands a supreme ‘experienced techni-
proved in propositional logic that no contradic- cal facilitator T to supervise elicitations’ of experts
tive results can be deduced by two di¡erent calcu- (Aspinall and Cooke, 1998, p. 2115), who would
li, hence, their choice is solely a matter of conven- unavoidably rely on his/her own intuition, which
ience. Their detailed consideration is outside the cannot be veri¢ed. Raising no objection to scien-
scope of this work. Special software is being ela- ti¢c intuition, we think that it should be accom-
borated for automatic inference of formulae for panied by strict assessment, especially for insur-
deducibility and processing of big sets of formulae ance and judicial items. ‘Scienti¢c uncertainty’
by various calculi. First results of this work were pinned down by these authors or, to put it more

VOLGEO 2697 4-11-03


296 C.A. Pshenichny et al. / Journal of Volcanology and Geothermal Research 128 (2003) 287^298

explicitly, conceptual uncertainty (Pshenichny, duce a conceptual probability of a statement as a


2002) underlies even quantitative methods of haz- measure of conceptual uncertainty in application to
ard and risk assessment (see below). the natural world. Its ¢rst and rough estimation
However, the revealing of ‘illogical’, contradic- can be de¢ned as (minimum required number of
tive concepts may enlighten not the fallacies of steps of inference)31 . For instance, in the example
thinking but peculiarities of the studied object. given above (see Section 4), each of the conclu-
In such cases, scientists should seek to eliminate sions of Fisher was deduced from the correspond-
the contradiction by re-examination of their views ing assumptions by 11 steps, so their conceptual
in a wider context; e.g. in the fragment of text probability can be estimated as 1/11, or 0.09. Fur-
analyzed above two incompatible pieces of evi- ther development of logical assessments would
dence (sharp contact and gas pipes at the contact lead to better evaluation of conceptual probabil-
of similar layers) were interpreted jointly and did ity. However, even in its present form, in the au-
not lead to contradiction, although, as was shown thors’ view, this probability can be used in the
in the same example, widening the context may Bayes formula as the probability of hypothesis
readily lead to contradiction. and in the event trees as the probability of each
If no contradictions are encountered, the logical branch. We do admit that this is not the best
calculi allow us to build long chains of inference possible solution but, hopefully, it is a better op-
incorporating any kind of relevant knowledge, tion than ascribing numerical values of probabil-
e.g. from seismic signals to social disorder. The ity by intuition, which is what scientists are forced
more diverse knowledge is involved, the more to do at present (Aspinall and Cooke, 1998; New-
the ultimate consequences of observed events hall and Hoblitt, 2002).
can be quickly predicted. Logic may appear espe- It should be noted that the chains of inference
cially useful in predicting the hazards with long may be based solely on observational evidence,
return periods, unique disasters, or catastrophes which, contrary to concepts arising from theoret-
which have never happened in human history. ical considerations and modeling, is: (1) abso-
When the data are scarce or absent, we can oper- lutely reliable; (2) independent of premises ac-
ate with our concepts. Even our fantasy, if given cepted by one and not accepted by another
strict form, may become a tool for hazard assess- scientist; and (3) easily understandable by non-
ment. For this, the following rationale can be professionals. Hence, not only the application of
suggested. logic to observational knowledge would optimize
Any application of a logical calculus to the nat- the research work and evaluation of the work of
ural world is its interpretation by the latter, i.e. the experts, but also help scientists communicate
every propositional formula is an event or a with civil authorities, journalists and population.
group of related events, and each step of inference At the same time, compact domains of knowl-
is a succession of events in time. But logic de- edge, which describe particular eruptive phenom-
scribes our reasoning about these events, not the ena (extrusive dome growth and collapse, pyro-
events themselves and, contrary to mathematics, clastic £ows, lahars, etc.) and have proved self-
does not mean that the thought events must take consistent, can be subject to logical modeling, i.e.
place in reality. Therefore, in application to the thorough application of logical calculi to any of
natural world, every step of inference, which is its statements. Any question formulated in terms
100% reliable in terms of logic, acquires a proba- of these domains (or ¢nite worlds, as logicians
bilistic sense. An inference of the form ACA is say) will make sense and have a correct answer.
absolutely reliable, because it denotes an event These will be the ¢rst self-consistent ‘islands’ of
that actually takes place (i.e. ‘we think what we strict knowledge, the ¢rst ‘crystallized’ fragments
see’). However, the more steps are required to in the ‘hot and viscous stu¡’ of volcanological
‘reach’ the deduced formula, the less probable it observations. Maybe some commonly accepted
becomes that a succession of events takes place in statements will require re-formulation to become
reality exactly as inferred. Hence, we can intro- deducible formulae. Widening of these domains

VOLGEO 2697 4-11-03


C.A. Pshenichny et al. / Journal of Volcanology and Geothermal Research 128 (2003) 287^298 297

would eventually lead to an increased formaliza- 1. Aa(BaA))


tion of volcanology. 2. (Aa(BaC))a((AaB)a(AaC))
3. Aa(Ba(ApB))
4. (ApB)aA
6. Conclusions 5. (ApB)aB
6. Aa(AKB)
Propositional logic may be used as an assess- 7. Ba(AKB)
ment tool and thus have wide application to the 8. (AaC)a((BaC)a((AKB)aC))
knowledge derived from volcanological observa- 9. (AaB)a((AaFB)aFA)
tions. The assessments of individual statements 10. Aa(FAaB)
and rationales for truth and satis¢ability can be 11. FFAaA
done by truth tables and reduction to normal Basic equivalences
forms. Assessments of a set of statements for 1. ApB is equivalent to F(FAKFB)
self-consistency and deducibility of a statement 2. ApB is equivalent to F(AaFB)
from the set are accomplished by various logical 3. AKB is equivalent to F(FApFB)
calculi, the simplest of which is reduction to nor- 4. AaB is equivalent to FAKB
mal forms. These procedures allow us to ¢nd con- 5. ArB is equivalent to (AaB)p(BaA)
tradictions, build self-consistent domains of ob- 6. ArB is equivalent to (FAKB)p(FBKA)
servational knowledge and obtain strict inference 7. FFA is equivalent to A
within these domains. The latter will eventually 8. ApB is equivalent to BpA
lead to the logical modeling of volcanic objects. 9. Ap(BpC) is equivalent to (ApB)pC
Logical processing of knowledge may be useful 10. AKB is equivalent to BKA
in ¢eld volcanological studies and in hazard assess- 11. AK(BKC) is equivalent to (AKB)KC
ment for optimization of research work, of recom- 12. AK(BpC) is equivalent to (AKB)p(AKC)
mendations by experts and of communication with 13. Ap(BKC) is equivalent to (ApB)K(ApC)
non-professionals. It would especially bene¢t for- 14. ApA is equivalent to A
malized expert judgement procedures and may be 15. AKA is equivalent to A
useful for optimization of event trees and Bayesian 16. F(ApB) is equivalent to FAKFB
approach. The results of this study show that strict 17. F(AKB) is equivalent to FApFB
reasoning is possible in the area of volcanology 18. (AKB)p(FAKB) is equivalent to B
that has been considered least certain and most 19. Ap(AKB) is equivalent to A
intuitive ^ its observational knowledge. 20. AK(ApB) is equivalent to A
21. (AKC)p(BKFC) is equivalent to (AKC)p
(BKFC)p(AKB)
Acknowledgements 22. (ApC)K(BpFC) is equivalent to (ApC)K
(BpFC)K(ApB)
The authors are deeply obliged to Willy Aspi-
nall and an anonymous reviewer for their careful
attitude and very useful comments, which, hope-
References
fully, have helped to eliminate the ambiguities and
better relate this paper to the practice of decision- Aspinall, W., Cooke, R.M., 1998. Expert judgement and the
making in volcanic crises. Montserrat Volcano eruption. In: Mosleh, A., Bari, R.A.
(Eds.), Proceedings of the 4th International Conference on
Probabilistic Safety Assessment and Management PSAM4,
September 13^18, 1998, New York, vol. 3, pp. 2113^2118.
Appendix. Basic tautologies and equivalences of
Aspinall, W.P., Woo, G., 1994. An impartial decision-making
propositional logic procedure using expert judgement to assess volcanic haz-
ards: Large Explosive Eruptions. In: Accademia Nazionale
Basic tautologies dei Lincei ^ British Council International Symposium,

VOLGEO 2697 4-11-03


298 C.A. Pshenichny et al. / Journal of Volcanology and Geothermal Research 128 (2003) 287^298

Rome, 24^25 May 1993. Atte dei convegni Lincei 112, pp. Klir, G., 2002. Fuzzy Logic In Geology. Academic Press, 380
211^220. pp.
Cagnoli, B., 1998. Fuzzy logic in volcanology. Episodes 21, Moukhachov, V.P., Netchitailov, I.V., 2001. An improvement
94^96. of Brodsky’s coding method for the sequent calculus of First
Dienes, I., 1978. Formalized stratigraphy: Basic concepts and Order Logic. In: Gore, R., Leitsch, A., Nipkov, T. (Eds.),
advantages. In: Merriam, D.F. (Ed.), Recent Advances in International Joint Conference on Automated Reasoning
Geomathematics, International Symposium. Pergamon Short Papers, Siena, pp. 113^121.
Press, Oxford, pp. 81^87. Newhall, C.G., Hoblitt, R.P., 2002. Constructing event trees
Fedorov, B.G., 1989. The Earth’s Surface and the Problems of for volcanic crises. Bull. Volcanol. 64, 3^20.
Planetary Geodynamics. St. Petersburg University Publish- Potts, G.J., Reddy, S.M., 1999. Construction and systematic
ers, 215 pp. assessment of relative deformation histories. J. Struct. Geol.
Fisher, R.V., 1990. Transport and deposition of a pyroclastic 21, 1245^1253.
surge across an area of high relief: The May 1980 eruption Pshenichny, C.A., 2002. Investigation of geologic reasoning as
of Mount St. Helens, Washington. Geol. Soc. Am. Bull. 102, a new objective of geoscience and geohazard assessment.
1038^1054. Earth Science Computer Applications 17, 1^3.
Frege, G., 1896. Uº ber die Begri¡sschrift des Herrn Peano und Pshenichny, C.A., Moukhachov, V.P., 2001. Volcano-Logic:
meine eigene. Berl. math. Gl. Kgl. Sa«chs. Wiss. Leipzig. reasoning research in volcanology. IAVCEI News 1, 2.
Gentzen, G., 1934. Untersuchungen u«ber das logische Schlies- Ross, B., 1989. Scenarios for repository safety analysis. Eng.
sen, I-II. Math. Z. 39, 3. Geol. 2, 285^299.
Gould, P., 1981. A structural language of relations. In: Craig, Sirotinskaya, S.V., 1986. Logical Methods of Analysis of Geo-
R.G., Labowitz, M.L. (Eds.), Future Trends in Geomathe- logic Information. Nedra Publishers, 158 pp. (in Russian).
matics. Pion, London, pp. 281^312. Whitehead, A.N., Russell, B., 1910. Principia Mathematica.
Hilbert, D., Bernays, P., 1956. Crundlagen der Mathematik, Cambridge University Press, London.
I. Springer.
Kleene, S.C., 1952. Introduction to Mathematics. D. Van
Nostrand, Inc., New York.

VOLGEO 2697 4-11-03

You might also like