You are on page 1of 7

Habermas and the Fate of Democracy

Boston Review (April 17, 2017)

Philosophy & Religion

Habermas and the Fate of Democracy

William E. Scheuerman

Habermas: A Biography

Stefan Mller-Doohm, translated by Daniel Steuer Polity Press, $39.95 (cloth)

Jrgen Habermass career, with its prodigious philosophy and social theory now translated into
forty different languages, can be interpreted primarily as an effort to make intellectual sense of
democracy and its untapped possibilities. But the Habermas who emerges in the German
sociologist Stefan Mller-Doohms illuminating new biography (Habermas: A Biography) also
appears as an intensely political creature, an intellectual whose public interventions over the
course of sixty years have regularly galvanized popular debate in Germany and beyond. Beginning
in the 1950s, when he was perhaps the first in his generation to take on Martin Heidegger and
other older intellectuals who had embraced the Nazis, Habermass public political interventions
have been instrumental in shaping our understanding of and aspirations for democracy.

Habermas himself has drawn a sharp distinction between his political interventions and his more
systematic scholarship. But Mller-Doohm suggests a fuzzier border, with the more abstract
Habermas often giving voice to concrete political experiences. This is true even today, with
Habermass scholarship eerily applicable to current waves of populism around the world. And at
the age of eighty-seven, Habermas continues to address democratic decay and nationalist
nostalgia as he energetically defends the embattled European Union.

Jrgen Habermas grew up in Gummersbach, a sleepy German town about thirty miles east of
Cologne. It is a bit surprising that Habermass storythe story of a cosmopolitan and radical
democratstarts here since the provincial, upper-middle class, deeply conservative milieu in
Gummersbach and elsewhere helped pave the way for Hitlers rise.

Habermass father, Ernst, was a right-wing conservative who joined the Nazi Party in 1933. The
young Jrgen was forced to join the Hitler Youth, and then in February 1945, when he was fifteen
years old, got news of his call-up from the Wehrmacht. Good luck spared him the fate of other
teenagers mobilized during the wars final months: It was sheer coincidence, Habermas later
recounted, that I was somewhere else for one night, and on that night the military police came to
look for me. Then, thank Godthe Americans came.
Habermas is an intensely political thinker whose ideas are eerily applicable to contemporary global
politics.

Germanys defeat helped free Habermas from the provincial social climate. He listened to live
radio broadcasts of the Nuremberg Trials and, shocked by the horrors recounted, seems to have
quickly grasped the criminal nature of the regime under which he had grown up. Revealingly
perhaps, his academic interests shifted away from medicine, a more professionally secure field, to
philosophy. His 1954 University of Bonn doctoral dissertation on the Romantic philosopher
Friedrich Schelling offers little evidence of Habermass growing radicalism, but his early journalistic
pieces, published during the early and mid 50s in major German newspapers and intellectual
journals, anticipate his life-long political concerns. Directed against right-wing intellectuals (for
example, Heidegger), they criticize an older generation for failing to take democracy seriously
that magic word, according to Habermas, that brought together otherwise disparate voices
within his own postwar generation who sought a clean break from Nazism.

Because Habermas took the magic word of democracy so seriously, he found himself disenchanted
not only with established conservative intellectuals but also political elites who preferred to keep
their mouths shut about their Nazi entanglements, and for whom Germanys new liberal order
was primarily about stability and security, not democratic self-government. Dictatorship and the
racism that motored it still haunted his country. Democracy was not a fortunate historical
inheritance one could simply take up, but instead an unfinished project. As he has more recently
claimed, democracy represents the surviving remnant of utopia: only democracy is capable of
hacking through the Gordian knots of otherwise insoluble problems. Thus his life-long intellectual
project of trying to understand democracys promise and possibilities.

For a democrat with leftist sympathies in 1950s Germany, where ex-Nazis still dominated many
university faculties, the Frankfurt-based Institute for Social Research offered an obvious
intellectual home. Made up of heterodox Marxists and Jews recently returned from American
exile, the so-called Frankfurt School shared Habermass anxieties about Germanys unfinished
democracy and refusal to break cleanly with the Nazi past. In 1956 he joined the eclectic group of
interdisciplinary scholars based at the Institute and began working closely with the philosopher
and cultural critic Theodor Adorno, its most creative thinker and prominent public intellectual.
Adornos habit of speaking his mind, even when politically inconvenient, clearly influenced
Habermas.

Even as he worked under Adornos tutelage, Habermas maintained his intellectual independence.
For him, the Frankfurt School never constituted a closed research agenda or shared orthodoxy.
Mller-Doohm recounts a series of political and intellectual battles with the Institutes autocratic
Director, Max Horkheimer, who worried about Habermass radicalism and at one juncture
demanded his dismissal. By the late 1950s, Habermas had become a tough Marxist critic of not
only postwar Germany but also liberal democracy more generally. Already at this point, however,
Habermass Marxism served mainly as a starting point for exploring tensions between capitalism
and democracy, not an all-encompassing philosophical framework promising ready answers.
Habermas remained first and foremost a democrat, though one ensconced on the political left and
preoccupied with capitalisms threats to democracy.

During this early period, he published The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere in 1962,
a major theoretical contribution that chronicles the decline of the nineteenth-century liberal
public sphere. The book provides a dreary portrait of contemporary society as increasingly
authoritarian, with top-down executive-centered government depicted as replacing an earlier
mode of liberal rule in which deliberative publicsgroups of people partially realizing the
communicative ideal of free and open discussion among equalsexerted influence via powerful
legislatures. Though the volumes Marxist framing located the main source of liberal decay in the
transition from liberal competitive to modern organized capitalism, it also sketched Habermass
most important intuition: because democracy rests on public deliberation and exchange,
participants in discourse should possess equal chances to express their views and must not be
unfairly limited when doing so. Those impacted by any decision must be allowed to deliberate
freely and equally about it without being hindered by social inequalities.

His efforts even won Horkheimer over, who soon changed his mind about his young colleague and
worked behind the scenes to make sure Habermas was named his successor at Frankfurt
University in 1964. With one interlude during the 1970s, when Habermas relocated to the bucolic
lake district outside Munich to direct a research institute, he spent the rest of his career at
Frankfurt as a professor of philosophy and sociology. He soon became the Frankfurt Schools most
prolific and prominent representative.

When The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere was translated into English in 1989,
Habermas distanced himself both from its bleak diagnostic claims and the Marxist framework.
Nevertheless, some of his early observations remain eerily prescient. Habermas observed, for
example, that politics and entertainment were becoming blurred by personalization and
scandalization, with new technologies dumbing down political and cultural debate. Rather than
active citizens and participants in a shared cultural life, Habermas saw compliant consumers
unable to distinguish between new products and political proposals. He also worried about the
dismantlement of legal and constitutional safeguards and novel types of popular but illiberal and
effectively authoritarian rule. Despite its limitations, Structural Transformation can be read as
anticipating the emergence of authoritarian populism, along the lines of Recep Tayyip Erdogans
Turkey or Viktor Orbns Hungary. With the erstwhile protagonist of The Apprentice propelled to a
new starring role in the White House, thanks in large part to fake news and bots, it also
sometimes makes for an illuminating reading of Donald Trumps United States.

He was one of the first in his generation to take on Heidegger and other intellectuals who had
embraced the Nazis.

For uncharitable critics, Habermas remains a nave defender of pristine or ideal speech, where
actors somehow miraculously engage in rational discourse in a space free of power. With his
efforts focused mostly on formulating a rigorous model of idealized communication, Habermas
ignores the harsh realities of political life and overstates its rational traits. His theory, they say,
seems suited to a philosophical seminar, not the rough and tumble of politics.

But such critics overlook the fact that his theory is not intended as a recipe book for reformers
aspiring to cook up perfect deliberation at short notice. Discourse in the most demanding and
hypothetical sense, Habermas concedes, is rarely if ever achievable in ordinary communication.
Why then worry about it? For Habermas, if we interpret democracy as a way of life where people
make binding decisions based on arguments, we need to grasp how deliberation works, and how
best to delineate reasonable and legitimate from unreasonable and illegitimate public exchange.
Real-life democracy hardly looks like the idealized communication community Habermas
describes. Yet absent some sense of that ideal community, we can neither distinguish
manufactured from independent public opinion, nor deepen democracy.

During the last thirty years or so, as Habermas has moved from being a Marxist and left-socialist to
a social democrat, he has constructively engaged with the ideas of left-liberal American thinkers
such as Ronald Dworkin and John Rawls. He now speaks of the need to tame or civilize capitalism
but no longer toys with the prospect of a basically different economic order. The shift has been
widely noted by more radical critics. Once fashionable on the left, Habermass name is now
sometimes met with skepticism by a younger generation for whom the recent global economic
crisis underscores the need for a fundamental attack on capitalism.

Habermass life-long interest in the nexus between democracy and capitalism, however, remains.
Mller-Doohm devotes nearly a quarter of his thick volume to a discussion of Habermass
cosmopolitanism, a longstanding component of his thinking that in recent decades has taken on a
central role. Habermas has always expressed sympathy for Immanuel Kants idea of a perpetual
peace founded on cosmopolitan law. Structural Transformation posited that modern means of
mass destruction underscore the need to transcend the state of nature in international relations
that is so threatening for everybody. His early security-centered call for a new post national
politics was then supplemented in the 1990s by the thesis that economic globalization outstrips
the nation-states capacity to regulate its own affairs. Like many on the left, Habermas has become
increasingly worried about global-level economic transformations that make it difficult especially
for small and medium-sized states to maintain a generous welfare state. This diagnosis has
motivated him to provide an account of how best to move towards the post national order he
thinks we need.

Against those on both left and right who seek what he views as a retrograde rolling back of
globalization, Habermas wants political decision-making to be scaled up to our globalizing
economy. Democracy and the welfare state not only need to catch up to globalization if they are
to survive, but can only do so when reconstituted in new and more inclusionary ways beyond the
nation state. He considers it a mistake to try to shore up the nation state with outdated ideas of
political identity based on common ethnicity or far-reaching cultural or linguistic sameness, and he
attacks nationalists and populists for doing so. For todays Europeans, he believes, only a more
democratic and politically robust European Union (EU) can navigate economic globalizations rocky
waters and preserve democracys social presuppositions. And only in a stronger more democratic
EU could more porous and tolerant political identities flourish.

Habermas has harbored a life-long interest in the nexus between democracy and capitalism.

Simultaneously, Habermas rejects the idea of a world state or even a federal European state.
Instead, he proposes a three-tiered framework for global governance, with existing national
governments to be complemented by new modes of what he describes as binding supranational
(that is, global or worldwide) and transnational (regional or continental) decision-making. At the
global or supranational level, a reformed UN would better secure world peace and protect human
rights. Because we presently lack anything approaching a robust global demos, however, its
authority should remain circumscribed. At the transnational level, environmental, financial, and
social and economic policies, or what he dubs global domestic politics, would be negotiated by
global actors tasked with generating new modes of cross-border regulation. With the EU in mind,
Habermas believes that regional political and economic blocs possess the requisite muscle to get
the job done. At the national level, existing states would preserve core features of sovereignty,
though they would lack any legal right (as per the UN Charter) to wage aggressive war. Both
supranational and transnational decision making would continue to rely on the nation-state and its
military and police powers for enforcement.

Habermas lauds the EU for successfully delinking key political decisions from the nation state; in
Crisis of the European Union (2012), he goes so far as to claim that its institutional innovations
provide a model for others elsewhere hoping to tackle globalization. The EU divides sovereignty
between nation states (and their citizenries) and European citizens: nation-states maintain control
over coercive authority but share sovereignty with European citizens. Unfortunately, the EUs
achievements are threatened by recalcitrant political elites who now impede further progress:
they are chiefly responsible for the dire crisis Europe faces. Habermass main target is a post-
democratic executive federalism in which powerful national leadersincluding Germanys
Chancellor Angela Merkelexpropriate far-reaching powers of crisis management absent
sufficient public oversight. In the recent financial and Euro crises, for example, ordinary political
and constitutional procedures were circumvented, and vast authority placed in the hands of
institutional actors operating behind closed doors. Instead, the EUs crises should have been an
opportunity for both we the people of Europe and we the peoples of Europes nations to
figure out how best to exercise popular control over controversial matters of economic policy
presently exercised by a small group of elite political players.

Habermass cosmopolitan aspirations seem increasingly unachievable in a political context where


Donald Trump mocks the UN as just a club for people to have a good time, and Brexit and
influential anti-European political parties block a stronger and more immediately democratic EU.
Of course, populists also worry about unaccountable elites in Brussels. But for them ideas of a
European-wide citizenry and robust EU democracy are dangerous myths and part of the problem,
not the solution.
Laying out two intertwined explanations, Habermas has struggled to make sense of the nationalist
and populist backlash. Like others, he thinks that populist and nationalist movements draw
support disproportionately from economic globalizations losers. He chides his friends on the
social democratic left for pursuing economic policies barely distinguishable from those of the
political right. The anti-EU backlash can be attributed precisely to that failure to recalibrate
political and economic processes that has so vexed him since the 1990s, a failure exacerbated by
mainstream politicians who allow populists to pose disingenuously as best able to provide
economic security to voters suffering globalizations worst consequences. In an interview with a
political journal last November, Habermas reiterated his longstanding call for left-leaning parties in
Europe to join arms and go on the offensive against social inequality by embarking upon a
coordinated and cross-border taming of unregulated markets. Though sometimes vague on
details, Habermas believes that only new transnational social and economic measures and
regulations can extinguish populist political fires.

Simultaneously, Habermas criticizes European leaders for failing to pursue political reforms that
might strengthen Europe-wide democracy. In his view, their preference for opaque, top-down
decision-making feeds political resentment against Brussels. In 2014 he cautiously greeted right-
wing populists, not of course because of their policy views, but only because he hoped they might
inadvertently spur mainstream politicians to start a serious conversation about political and
institutional reform. On this second view, the immaturity of the EUs version of transnational
democracy is the main culprit behind long simmering and now apparently explosive populist
anger.

Only new transnational social and economic measures and regulations can extinguish populist
political fires.

Habermass economic and political explanations both help make sense of present-day political
quagmires. Yet neither does justice to the sizable hurdles faced by flesh-and-blood politicians who
risk being attacked by populists for putting general European interests ahead of national interests.
Europes main political players, after all, still answer not to a European demos but to national and
local constituencies. Given existing electoral and political incentives it seems a lot to ask of them
to transcend their parochial preoccupations. He sometimes gives politiciansand especially his
left-leaning alliestoo little credit for the genuine quagmires they face, as they respond to angry
voters who blame global elites for declining life prospects.

It also seems ironic that our most impressive contemporary theorist of democracy spends so much
time attacking elected leaders and other political elites for failing to take on unpopular political
tasks. What about grassroots political and social movements, or a European public sphere? Why
do we still see so few genuinely cross-border popular or citizen-based initiatives to reform or
strengthen the EU? Habermas stylizes himself as a radical democrat, and has always emphasized
that democracy remains principally a grassroots affair between and among active citizens who
argue and debate about competing views. However, he has had relatively little to say about that
part of the story.
Whether Habermass preferred loose, multi-tiered system of European governance, rather than a
robust federal European state, might tame globalizing capitalism also remains unclear. Most
successful attempts to regulate capitalism have gone hand in handjust think of the New Deal
with institutional enhancements to centralized state power. Redistribution within the EU, as in
many existing political entities, would seem to demand relatively autonomous, more centralized
institutions able to take on powerful local interests (e.g., within the EU, Germany, the main
bulwark behind austerity policies). Of course, Habermas is probably right to deem lingering calls
today for a European federal state politically unrealistic. Yet this hardly renders his own model of a
decentralized, non-statist, yet simultaneously more egalitarian and redistributionist, EU any less
difficult to fathom politically.

Since the 1950s Jrgen Habermas has used his enormous intellectual and political energies to
deepen democracy. Mller-Doohm occasionally seems overwhelmed by his subject. He neglects,
for instance, the fascinating story of Habermass massive global dispersionhow his ideas have
been taken up and creatively reworked by admirers and disciples. Mller-Doohms broad
sympathies for Habermas also make him more cautious about expressing criticism. Still, he does a
service in methodically outlining Habermass theoretical trajectory, highlighting its strengths as
well as ambiguities and dead-ends. And he recounts Habermass activities as an outspoken public
contrarian, in which Habermas has regularly confronted revanchist voices in Germany reluctant to
confront the Nazi past and cramped views of national identity. While it seems unlikely that
Habermas will win his battle to extend democracy beyond the nation state anytime soon, he has
defined a path of intellectual and political engagement that others with similar commitments
willwe can only hopecarry forward.

You might also like