You are on page 1of 8

CHAPTER TWO

Beyond Art and Technology: The Anthropology of Skill


Tim Ingold

ON THE DISTINCTION BETWEEN words tekhne and ars were used, respectively in Greek
ART A D TECH OLOGY and Roman society, to describe every kind of activity
involving the manufacture of durable objects by people
"ART" AND "TEClINOLOGY" ARE MERE WORDS. AND AS who depended on such work for a living, from the
with all words, their meanings are not fixed but have painter to the cobbler, from the temple architect to the
changed significantly in the course of their history. They builder of pigsties. This is not to say that customers
are still changing. But I believe it remains true of failed to distinguish between aesthetic and utilitarian
modern-if not postmodern-thought that the criteria in their estimations of the objects produced. But
meanings of art and technology are held to be somehow in every case, it was the craft skill of the practitioner that
opposed, as though drawn from fields of human was supposed to ensure a successful outcome (Burford
endeavor that are in certain respects antithetical. This 1972: 13-14).
opposition, however, is scarcely more than a century old, The connotation of skill is preserved in many words
and would have seemed strange to Anglophone ears as derived from the same roots and that remain in common
late as the seventeenth century, when artists were still currency today. On the one hand we have "technics" and
considered no different from artisans, when the "technique"; on the other hand such terms as "artless"-
methods of working in any particular branch of art meaning clumsy or lacking in skill-and, of course,
could be described as "technical," and when the term "artifact." Yet the apparent continuity masks an
"technology" had just been coined to denote the important shift, towards abstracting the components of
scientific study of these methods (Williams intelligence, sensibility and expression that are essential
1976:33-34). Etymologically, "art" is derived from the to the accomplishment of any craft from the actual bodily
Latin artem or ars, while "technology" was formed upon movement of the practitioner in his or her environment.
the stem of a term of classical Greek origin, namely Thus the technique of the pianist comes to refer to the
tekhne. Originally, ars and tekhne meant much the same practiced ability of his fingers to find their way around
thing, namely skill of the kind associated with the keyboard and to hit the desired notes, as distinct from
craftsmanship. As Alison Burford has pointed out in her the inherent musicality of the performance. "A player
study of the craftsmen of ancient Greece and Rome, the may be perfect in technique," wrote Sir Charles Grove,

17
18 / CHA PTER 2 BEYOND ART AND TECHNOLOGY / 19

"and yet have neither soul nor intelligence." Likewise, we Here, then, lies the source of the now familiar division and lenses of the cultural imagination. It mediates a These qualifications aside, it is fair to say that
have come a long way from the days when, as in the year between the respective fields of art and technology. An dialogue, not between human beings and nature, but compared to art, technology has been left largely on the
1610, it was possible to eulogize a certain composer as object or performance could be a work of art, rather among persons in society. Like language, it encodes sidelines as a topic of social or cultural anthropological
"the most artificial and famous AJfonso Ferrabosco" than a mere artifact, to the extent that it escapes or meanings. Thus technology works; art signifies: technical inquiry. Yet for all that, there is a persistent current of
(Rooley 1990:5). As David Lowenthal has observed, "time transcends the determinations of the technological action, as Edmund Leach put it, "produces observable doubt about the cross-cultural applicability of the
has reversed the meaning of artificial from "full of deep system. And its creator could be an artist, rather than a results in a strictly mechanical way," whereas art is a genre concept of art, whereas that of the concept of technology
skill and art" to "shallow, contrived and almost mere artisan, insofar as the work is understood to be an of ritual or expressive action whose purpose is essentially has seldom been seriously questioned. I think it is true to
worthless" (1996:209). By the same token, the artifact is expression of his or her own subjective being. Where communicative-to convey information in a symbolic say that the majority of anthropologists, if called to
regarded no longer as the original outcome of a skilled, technological operations are predetermined, art is code about such matters as identity and cosmology reflect upon the issue, would not deny that there exists a
sensuous engagement between the craftsman and his raw spontaneous; where the manufacture of artifacts is a (Leach )966:403, cf. 1976:9). In short, art has been split sphere of capability in every human population that can
material, but as a copy run off mechanically from a pre- process of mechanical replication, art is the creative from technology along the lines of an opposition be called "technological:' and most, indeed, would be
established template or design. This debasement of craft production of novelty. These distinctions can be between the mental and the material, and between content with the idea that technology varies from the
to the "merely technical" or mechanical execution of multiplied almost indefinitely, but they are all driven by semiotics and mechanics. simple (in nonindustrial societies) to the complex (in
predetermined operational sequences went hand in hand the same logic, which is one that carves out a space for Despite the apparent symmetry of this opposition, the industrial societies). How else are we to interpret those
with the elevation of art to embrace the creative exercise human freedom and subjectivity in a world governed by respective trajectories of the anthropologies of art and regular disclaimers to the effect that in speaking of
of the imagination. As a result, the artist came to be objective necessity. It is a logic that operates as much in technology have been decidedly asymmetrical. The "simple societies" it is technological simplicity that we
radically distinguished from the artisan, and the art-work the field of exchange as in that of production (Ingold anthropology of art has long held a secure place in the have in mind, and that this, in itself, should cast no
from the artifact (Coleman 1988:7). 1995:15-16). Thus the modern distinction between the discipline, whereas the anthropology of technology, as a reflection upon the intelligence, social organization, or
The decisive break, according to Raymond Williams, true work of art and the replicated artifact has its subfield, appears to be a late starter that has only very cultural sophistication of the people in question? When
came in the England of the late eighteenth century, with parallel in that between the "pure gift" and the market recently begun to acquire a significant momentum of its it comes to art, on the other hand, anthropologists have
the exclusion of engravers from the newly formed Royal commodity: the former given spontaneously and own. Admittedly, my perception of the situation may be continually worried about the dangers of ethnocentrism
Academy, which was reserved for practitioners of the motivated (at least in theory) by personal feeling; the biased by my own intellectual background in the British entailed in importing into the field of cross-cultural
"fine" arts of painting, drawing, and sculpture (Williams latter exchanged in line with impersonal calculations of tradition of social anthropological scholarship. In orth comparison a concept that carries such strong evaluative
1976:33). It was, of course, symptomatic of a general supply and demand, following the laws of the so-called America things are rather different, largely on account of overtones, and whose contemporary meaning is so
tendency to distinguish intellectual from manual labor, "market mechanism." In both fields, of production and the continuing recognition of archaeology as a closely bound up with widely held ideas about the rise
along the common axis of a more fundamental series of exchange, fine art and pure gift delineate a residual space subdiscipline of anthropology. It has been customary, on and ascendancy of Western civilization. But this leaves us
oppositions between mind and body, creativity and for the free expression of individual selfhood in a society both sides of the Atlantic, to distinguish archaeology by with something of a paradox. Why should our
repetition, and freedom and determination. But the dominated by the machine and the market. But in both its concern with the material record of human activities, confidence in terms like art and technology, as dimen-
more that "art" came to be associated with the allegedly fields, too, the distinctions are recent, and closely tied to as preserved in durable artifacts, and this has inevitably sions of cross-cultural analysis, be inversely propor-
higher human faculties of creativity and imagination, the rise of a peculiarly modern conception of the human entailed a strong focus on technology. But whereas in tional to the degree of elaboration of the respective
the more its residual connotations of useful but subject. Britain, the distinction has served to keep the study of domains of anthropological inquiry that they delineate?
nevertheless habitual bodily skills were swallowed up by The division between art and technology, as it has technology out of anthropology, and to legitimize I believe this paradox can be explained as follows.
the notion of technology. For by the beginning of the come to be institutionalized in modern society, has anthropology's claim to deal with the people and their Having placed technology beyond the pale of culture
twentieth century this term, too, had undergone a affected anthropology as much as any other field of social relationships rather than the things they used and and society, as a quasi-autonomous system of produc-
crucial shift of meaning. Where once it had referred to inquiry. Until fairly recently, the literatures in the left behind, in North America it is still possible to tive forces, the way was open for anthropologists, at least
the framework of concepts and theory informing the anthropology of art and in the anthropology of present the study of technology as one of archaeology's those of a "sociocultural" persuasion, to ignore it. It was
scien tific study of prod uctive practices, technology came technology remained almost completely isolated from distinctive contributions to the overall anthropological just one of those things, like climate or ecology, that may
to be regarded as a corpus of rules and principles one another. Technology was located within the sphere project. In continental Europe the situation is different or may not be a determining factor in human affairs, but
installed at the heart of the apparatus of production of ecological adaptation, mediating the material relations again. For the shift in the meaning of technology to whose study can be safely left to others. As climate is for
itself, whence it was understood to generate practice as a between human populations and their environments. which I referred earlier, from a systematic mode of meteorologists and ecology for ecologists, so technology
program generates an output. Technology, now, did not For assorted cultural ecologists, cultural materialists, and inquiry to the generative logic of practice, remained is for engineers-or perhaps even, in light of my earlier
discipline the scholar in his study of techniques, but Marxists, the conjunction of environment and more of less confined to the Anglophone world. In remarks, for archaeologists. Whoever claims to "do"
rather the practitioner in his application of them. He technology-if not actually determinant of cultural France, technology continues to this day to mean "the technology, there is no doubt about what it is. Art, to the
became, in effect, an operative, bound to the mechanical form-constitutes the ground (Gnllldlage) upon which study of techniques." For this reason, the word technique contrary, is clearly positioned within a social context
implementation of an objective system of productive the house of culture is built (see Godelier 1986:6). Art, has retained its original connotation of skilled and embodies cultural meaning. It is, therefore, self-
forces, according to principles of functioning that by contrast, along with such forms as myth and ritual, is craftsmanship. And French scholars have taken the lead evidently an object of study for anthropologists. But
remain indifferent to particular human aptitudes and supposed to comprise the patterns on the walls, the world in developing an anthropological approach to craft skills precisely because of its contextualization, the meaning of
sensibilities. (Sigaut 1985). "art" is thrown into question. Not for the first time, the
of sensory experience as it is refracted through the filters
20 / CHAPTER 2
BEYOND ART AND TECHNOLOGY / 21

very credentials that make a phenomenon eminently practice is a form of use, of tools and of the body. In one cannot be regarded simply as a technique of the body. conditions that are never the same from one moment to
worthy of anthropological study have cast a pall of of his dialogues, Plato has Socrates debate with a This was the position advocated in a now classic essay by the next (Bernstein 1996). Given the freedom of
uncertainty over whether the phenomenon exists "as character called Alcibiades on precisely this question. Marcel Mauss (I979[ 1934]). Taking his cue explicitly movement of the limbs as well as the elasticity of the
such" at all. It happened with the study of kinship, it "What are we to say of the shoemaker?," asks Socrates, from Plato, Mauss observed that technique does not, in muscles, Bernstein had observed, it is just not possible to
happened with the study of art, and now that "Does he cut with his tools only, or with his hands as itself, depend upon the use of tools. Song and dance are control the movements of the body in the same way as
anthropologists are at last beginning to recognize the welI?" Alcibiades is forced to concede that he does obvious examples. The dancer, according to Mauss, uses one might the workings of a machine made up of rigid,
social embeddedness of technological systems, it is indeed cut with his hands, and moreover that he uses his own body as an instrument; indeed so do we all, he interconnecting parts. From a close study of the
happening to the study of technology too. No sooner is not just his hands but his eyes-and by extension his declares, for the body is surely "man's first and most movements of a skilled blacksmith, hitting the iron on
technology reclaimed for anthropological inquiry, than whole body-to accomplish the work. Yet he had natural technical object, and at the same time technical the anvil over and over again with a hammer, Bernstein
we cease to know, for sure, what we are dealing with. already agreed, with Socrates, that there is a means." Moreover in the deployment of these means, found that while the trajectory of the tip of the hammer
The source of the problem, in my view, lies not in the fundamental difference between the user and the things the human agent experiences the resulting bodily was highly reproducible, the trajectories of individual
concept of art, nor in that of technology, but in the he uses. So who is this user? If it be man, counters movements as "of a mechanical, physical or physico- arm joints varied from stroke to stroke. At first glance
dichotomy between them. It is this, along with the idea Socrates, it cannot be his body, which is used. Only one chemical order" (Mauss 1979: 104). This reduction of the situation appears paradoxical: how can it be that the
that art floats in an ethereal realm of symbolic meaning, possibility remains, it must be the soul. "So," he the technical to the mechanical is an inevitable motion of the hammer rather than that of the limbs is
above the physical world over which technology seeks concludes, "do you require some yet clearer proof that consequence of the isolation of the body as a natural or reliably reproduced, when it is only by way of the limbs
control, that is tainted by its association with modernity. the soul is man?" Alcibiades is convinced (in Flew physical object, both from the (disembodied) agency that the hammer is made to move (cf. Latash 1996:286)?
The idea would have made no sense to the craftsmen of 1964:35-37). There is no reason, however, why we that puts it to work and from the environment in which Clearly, the smith's movements cannot be understood as
ancient Greece or Rome. They knew what they meant by should have to follow suit. "It would be wrong to it operates. To understand the true nature of skill we the output of a fixed motor program, nor are they
tekhne or ars, and it was a matter neither of mechanical assume," as Roger Coleman caustically remarks, "that must move in the opposite direction, that is, to restore arrived at through the application of a formula. The
functioning nor of symbolic expression, but of skilled because Plato was a Greek he knew what he was talking the human organism to the original context of its active secret of control, Bernstein concluded, lies in "sensory
practice. It is my contention that by going back to the about." He was no craftsman, and had no practical engagement with the constituents of its surroundings. corrections," that is in the continual adjustment or
original connotations of ars and tekhne as skill, we can experience whatever of shoemaking or any other trade. As Gregory Bateson argued, by way of his example of the "tuning" of movement in response to an ongoing
overcome the deep divisions that currently separate the Plato's objective, in forcing a division between the skilled woodsman notching with an axe the trunk of a perceptual monitoring of the emergent task.
anthropologies of art and technology, and develop a far controlling mind and subservient body, was to establish tree he is felling, to explain what is going on we need to All this has implications for the way skills are learned,
more satisfactory account of the socially and the supremacy of abstract, contemplative reason over consider the dynamics of the entire man-axe-tree system which brings me to my fourth point. If, as Bernstein
environmentally situated practices of real human agents. menial work, or of theoretical knowledge over practical (Bateson 1973:433). The system is, indeed, as much contended, skilled practice cannot be reduced to a
In what follows I shall pursue three aspects of this task. application, and thereby to justify the institution of mental as physical or physiological, for these are, in formula, then it cannot be through the transmission of
First, I explain in more depth what I mean by skill. slavery (Coleman 1988: 11-12). Resurrected in the truth, but alternative descriptions of one and the same formulae that skills are passed from generation to
Secondly, I show how the continuity of tradition in Renaissance, Plato's division anticipated the debasement thing. Skill, in short, is a property not of the individual generation. Traditional models of social learning sepa-
skilled practice is a function not of the transmission of of craft that, as we have seen, came to be one of the human body as a biophysical entity, a thing-in-itself, but rate the intergenerational transmission of information
rules and representations but of the coordination of hallmarks of modernity. To recover the essence of skill, of the total field of relations constituted by the presence specifying particular techniques from the application of
perception and action. Thirdly, I show how a focus on as "both practical knowledge and knowledgeable of the organism-person, indissolubly body and mind, in this information in practice. First, a generative schema or
skill explodes the conventional dichotomy between practice" (Ingold 1990:8), we need a different concept of a richly structured environment. That is why the study program is established in the novice's mind from his
innate and acquired abilities, forcing a radical reappraisal use from the one invoked by Plato. Instead of thinking of skill, in my view, not only benefits from, but demands observations of the movements of already accomplished
of the ways we think about what is "cultural" and of use as what happens when we put two, initially an ecological approach (Ingold 1996: 178). practitioners; secondly, the novice imitates these move-
"biological" in humans. I shall illustrate my argument by separate things together-an agent with certain Granted that the foundations of skill lie in the ments by running off exemplars of the technique in
way of two examples: Maureen MacKenzie's (1991) study purposes or designs, and an instrument with certain irreducible condition of the practitioner's embedded- question from the schema. Now I do not deny that the
of the looping skills involved in making string bags functions-we can take it as the primary condition of ness in an environment, it follows-and this is my third learning of skills involves both observation and imita-
(bilum) among Telefol people of Central New Guinea, involvement of the craftsman, with his tools and raw point-that skilled practice is not just the application of tion. But the former is no more a matter of forming
and the study by N. E. and E. C. Collias (1984) of the nest materials, in an environment. In this sense the hands mechanical force to exterior objects, but entails qualities internal, mental representations of observed behavior
building skills of the male weaverbird. of care, judgment and dexterity (Pye 1968:22). Critically, than is the latter a matter of converting these representa-
and eyes of the shoemaker, as well as his cutting tools,
are not so much used as brought into use, through their this implies that whatever practitioners do to things is tions into manifest practice. For the novice's observation
incorporation into an accustomed (that is usual) pattern grounded in an attentive, perceptual involvement with of accomplished practitioners is not detached from, but
FIVE pO! TS ABOUT SKILL of dextrous activity. Purposiveness and functionality, them, or in other words, that they watch and feel as they grounded in, his own active, perceptual engagement with
then, are not pre-existing properties of the user and the work. As the Russian neuroscientist Nicholai Bernstein his surroundings. And the key to imitation lies in the
I begin by drawing attention to five points which I used, but rather immanent in the activity itself, in the argued some fifty years ago, the essence of dexterity lies intimate coordination of the movement of the novice's
believe are crucial to a proper appreciation of technical gestura I synergy of human being, tool and raw material. not in bodily movements themselves, but in the attention to others with his own bodily movement in the
skills. The first concerns what it means to say that My second point follows from this. It is that skill responsiveness of these movements to surrounding world. Through repeated practical trials, and guided by
BEYOND ART AND TECHNOLOGY / 23
22 / CHAPTER 2

introduced to the techniques of bilum making from a


his observations, he gradually gets the "feel" of things for activity, that is of use, through which real forms emerge
very early age. All young Telefol children, both boys and
himself-that is, he learns to fine-tune his own move- and are held in place. It is the activity itself-of regular,
girls, help their mothers and elder sisters in preparing
ments so as to achieve the rhythmic fluency of the accom- controlled movement-that generates the form, not the
plished practitioner (for an example, see Gatewood fibres for spinning. "From the age of about two onwards
design that precedes it. Making, in short, arises within
1985). And in this process, each generation contributes they begin to experiment with roving, rolling the
the process of use, rather than use disclosing what is,
to the next not by handing on a corpus of shredded fibres down their thigh to make a single ply,
ideally if not materially, ready-made.
representations, or information in the strict sense, but and progress to experiments with spinning. It is not
uncommon to see very young girls, mere toddlers,
rather by introducing novices into contexts which afford
How TO MAKE A STRING BAG diligently attempting to loop the string they have made
selected opportunities for perception and action, and by
into bilum fabric" (MacKenzie 1991:101). Boys, as they
providing the scaffolding that enables them to make use
Consider the following passage from Franz Boas's classic grow older, do not go on to master fully the skills of
of these affordances. This is what lames Gibson
study of 1927, Primitive Art. In it, he describes a basket- looping, for the simple reason that they are soon
(1979:254) called an "education of attention."
maker at work: removed, by the conventions of their society, from the
It is because practitioners' engagement with the
material with which they work is an attentive engage- sphere of women's activities. Men have no need to make
The basketmaker who manufactures a coiled basket, their own bags, as these are willingly supplied for them
ment, rather than a mere mechanical coupling, that handles the fibres composing the coil in such a way that
by women, who thus maintain an effective monopoly on
skilled activity carries its own intrinsic intentionality, the greatest evenness of coil diameter results.... In making
her stitches the automatic control of the left hand that lays bilum making. Girls, by contrast, remain close to their
quite apart from any designs or plans that it may be
down the coil, and of the right that pulls the binding mothers and other female relatives, and continue to
supposed to implement (Ingold 1993:461). My fifth
point follows from this, and has to do with what we
stitches over the coil brings it about that the distances develop their skills, quietly and unobtrusively following
between the stitches and the strength of the pull are
mean by making things. Let me return for a moment to in their mothers' footsteps.
absolutely even so that the surface will be smooth and
the example of Socrates and the shoemaker. Socrates
NI the points I have made about skill, in the previous
evenly rounded and that the stitches show a perfectly
had asked what it means to say of the shoemaker that he regular pattern (Boas 1955:20 [19271).
section, apply to the making of string bags. Apart from
the maker's body-and especially her fingers-the only
uses tools. The other side of the question is to ask what
it means to say that he makes shoes. If use, as Socrates There is no reason to doubt that the basketmaker tools used are the mesh gauge (ding), made from a strip 4
maintained, is what happens when you put an agent begins work with a pretty clear idea of what a well- of leaf, to maintain the constancy of the mesh in an open
woven basket should look like. She has her standards. weave (see Figure 2.1), and the needle (siil), made of
having a certain purpose together with objects having
But watching her at work, it is evident that the form of bone, which is needed for making tightly looped baskets
certain functions, then the purpose must precede the Figure 2-1. The step-by-step procedure for looping a
the basket emerges not from these standards but from a without the use of the gauge (MacKenzie 1991 :73). But
use through which it is realized. In these terms, to refer flat strip of "open, spaced" bilL/m fabric, as practiced by
complex pattern of finely controlled movement. It is, as in use the needle or the gauge, along with the fingers that
to an action as one of making is to refer back to the prior Telefol people of central New Guinea. Steps 1-4 show
Boas, himself observed, the rhythmic repetition of hold it, are as much a part of the user as they are used. how the first row of loops is constructed around the
intention that motivates it. It is as though the form of
movement that gives rise to the regularity of form Moreover the accomplished bilum maker does not mesh gauge (ding), in a series of figure-of-eight loops
the manufactured object were already prefigured, as a
design, in the mind of its maker, such that the activity of (1955:40 [1927]). More generally, the forms of artifacts experience the movements of her body as being of a with each loop connecting into the preceding one. By
making issued directly from the design and served only are not inscribed by the rational intellect upon the mechanical nature. Far from answering to commands Step 5 the first row of loops is completed to the desired
issued from a higher source, they carry their own width. On completion of each row the work must be
to transcribe it onto the material. Indeed, it is often concrete surface of nature, but are rather generated in
intentionality, unfolding in a continual dialogue with the turned over so that the working thread is always on the
assumed that even to ask about the form of things is to the course of the gradual unfolding of that field of forces
material. Telefol people liken this movement to the left-hand side. In Step 6 the work is thus reversed. Step
pose a question about design, as though the latter and relations set up through the active and sensuous
flowing water of a river. Thus the body-in-use is not 7 illustrates how a new strip of ding is inserted at the
contained all one needs to know to account for the form engagement of the practitioner and the material with beginning of each successive row. This linear way of
(Turnbull 1993:319-320). This assumption is as which he or she works. To understand skilled practice, as moved, like a rigid object, but rather becomes one with
working, with each row connecting into the loops of
the flow (MacKenzie 1991:102). However, in order to
prevalent in biology as it is in technology. Thus the form Rubin (1988:375) has succinctly put it, we need to think the preceding one, is then repeated (Step 8) (from
of making in terms not of the simple, mechanical maintain the evenness of the string, in spinning, or of the
of an organism is said to be encapsulated in an evolved MacKenzie 1991 :86-87).
design specification-technically known as the execution of complex structures, but of the form- weave, in looping, it is necessary to make continual
adjustments in the course of the movement itself. "By
genotype-in advance of its phenotypic "expression" in generating potentials of complex processes.
Let me turn to another example: the making of string adolescence," MacKenzie writes, "all girls have mastered
an environment. And in modern architecture the form
bags among Telefol people of central New Guinea. The the technique of spinning, gaining visual acuity in
of a construction is supposed to exist in miniature, in
drawings, plans, and specifications, before any building string bag, or bilum, is one of the most ubiquitous and selecting equal assemblages of filaments during the
work begins (Coleman 1988:16). To take this view, multifunctional accessories to everyday life throughout roving process; and a sensitivity or balance in the amount
however, is to deny the creativity of the very process of this region. It is made by means of a looping technique of pressure applied between palm and thigh during the
rhythmic plying motion" (MacKenzie 1991:76). As this
environmentally situated and perceptually engaged from two-ply string spun from plant fibres. Children are
BEYOND ART AND TECH OLOGY / 25

24 / CHAPTER 2

in a double bind, from which the only escape was patient


movements with preCISIOn, depending as it does on
passage clearly reveals, dexterity in spinning depends on bilums, your hands will move easily like running water trial and error. Of course we had resort to the
subtle sensory attunement, is not a natural foundation
~he fine-tuning of visual as well as haptic perception. And (MacKenzie 1991:102). instructions, but far from directing our movements, what
for enskilment but its consequence (cf. Reed and Bril
It IS equally clear that the form of the bilum is an What does it mean to get the "feel" of looping? It they provided was a set of landmarks along the way, a
emergent outcome of rhythmically repeated, controlled could mean that the observation on which learning 1996:438). means of checking that we were still on track. If we were
TelefoI women, according to MacKenzie (1991:103),
movem.ent in the processes of spinning and looping. depends IS as much tactile as visual, or that the skill is not-if the tangle of string in front of us did not match
place great value on the standardization of their looping
The Issue on which I want to focus here, however, embodied as a rhythmic pattern of movement rather the corresponding graph (and that, in itself, was not easy
techniques, since this is a way of confirming tribal
concer~s how bilum-making skills are passed from than a static schema, or that the key to fluent to discern)-there was no alternative but to unravel the
identity. But I would contend that this standardization is
generation to generation. MacKenzie herself describes performance lies in the ability to coordinate perception whole thing and start again!
not brought about, as MacKenzie claims, by conformity
this in terms of a fairly conventional model of social and action. All three are undoubtedly important, but Our experiments seemed to lend strong empirical
to rules. Indeed there appear to be no rules, beyond
learning., ac~ording to which "observation is followed by none more so than the third. For it is this, as MacKenzie support for the view that the practices of knotting-
general exhortations of the kind delivered by the mother
mternalIzatlOn and then mimesis" (MacKenzie 1991: herself observes, that makes the difference between which are, after all, among the most common and
to her daughter in the case described above, or vague
100). Thus by watching the activity of her mother, a clumsiness and dexterity, between having heavy hands widely distributed in human societies-cannot be
"rules of thumb" that help prepare the practitioner for
young girl absorbs and assimilates the "intrinsic rules" of and hands that flow. "Clumsiness, iluun! t'eb'e su [to be understood as the output of any kind of program. They
her impending activity but in no way determine its
the craft. Once these are firmly implanted in her mind heavy handed], is deemed natural at first, and must be cannot, then, be learned by taking any such program "on
course (Such man 1987:52). Like most commonplace
she can proceed to execute them in the production of he; practically worked through" (MacKenzie 1991:103). board;' as part of an acquired tradition, as if all you
practical skills, such as tying shoelaces in Western
own work. The. fact that "each daughter follows exactly It seems, then, that progress from clumsiness to needed to know to make knots could be handed down as
society, looping resists codification in the form of
the motor habits and bodily motions of her mother" dexterity in the craft of bilum-making is brought about a package of rules and representations, independently
generative rules or algorithms (Dreyfus and Dreyfus
leads t~ a remarkable cultural conformity from one not by way of an internalization of rules and and in advance of their practical application (for a
1987). One becomes aware of this simply by looking at
generation to the next (MacKenzie 1991:103). There is representations, but through the gradual attunement of parallel argument, see Schiffer and Skibo 1987:597). In
the elaborate diagrams, accompanied by written
much in Mac.Kenzie's own account, however, to suggest movement and perception. As in any craft, the skilled our experiments, despite having a manual to consult, we
commentary, by means of which MacKenzie attempts to
that conformity to tradition is not a consequence of the maker who has a feel for what she is doing is one whose had to develop the necessary know-how from scratch.
explain the step-by-step procedure for open-spaced
mtergenerational transmission of rules or formulae movement is continually and subtly responsive to the Generally speaking, of course, this is not a problem that
however intrinsic, but rather the result of a process o~
looping (MacKenzie 1991:83-99, and for an example,
modulations of her relation with the material. novices face in real life. They are shown what to do by
see Figure 2.1). Though these diagrams are admirable
g~llded rediscovery in which the role of experienced ~onversely, the clumsy practitioner is precisely one who more experienced hands, as we have already seen in the
for their intended purpose, of ethnographic description,
btlum-makers is to set up the contexts within which I~lplements mechanically a fixed sequence of instruc- case of the acquisition of looping skills by Telefol bilum-
any attempt by the untutored reader to follow them in
no~ices are enabled to gain in proficiency for themselves, tIOns, while remaining insensitive to the evolvin makers. But in seeking to emulate the work of the tutor,
. g practice would likely lead to the same kind of tangle that
or m.other words to "grow into" the skills of spinning and con d ItlOns of the task as it unfolds. The hand that is the novice is guided by the latter's movements, not by
the inexperienced Telefol girl produces, on secretly
loopmg. heavy is experienced as a resistance to be overcome, and formal instructions that have somehow been already
attempting to carry on with her mother's work. It would
First of all, it is clear that to advance in these skills it is has to be moved from position to position in ways that copied into his or her head. As Merleau-Ponty put it,
be quite mistaken to suppose that anything remotely
not enough for the novice to know how their seem c.ontrary to its nature. The light hand, by contrast, citing the pioneering work of Paul Guillaume on
equivalent exists in the native mind. But if standardiza-
constituent movements look "from the outside;" she has find.s ItS way of its own accord. The heavy-handed imitation in children, "we do not at first imitate others
tion does not follow from the application of rules, how
also to know how they feel "from the inside" (cf. novIce does not, of course, move in exactly the same way but rather the actions of others, and ... find others at the
are we to account for the persistence of technique from
Bernstem 1996: 184-185). One young woman, recalling as her light-handed mother, nor can she be expected to point of origin of these actions" (1964: 117, see also
how she learned to loop as a child, told of how she had produce such satisfactory results. This is precisely where one generation to the next? Bourdieu 1977:87). It follows that the reproduction of
Partly in an attempt to answer this question, a group
once tried to carry on with an unfinished bilum that her th~ standard model of the social learning of technical movement patterns is a function not of the fidelity with
of us in the Department of Social Anthropology at the
mother had left in the rafters of the house before leaving s~t1ls goes wrong. For in attributing the intergenera- which information specifying these patterns is copied
University of Manchester have recently been experiment-
to work in the garden. She had been carefully watching tlOnal conformity of movements to rules that are from one generation to the next, but of the coordination
ing with different ways of making knots. One of our
t~e way her mother's hands moved as she looped the transmitted and internalized in advance of their of perception and action that lies at the heart of
experiments was to try making a completely unfamiliar
b~lum. But on trying it out herself, the result was a practical application in mimesis, the model assumes practical mimesis.
and rather complicated knot, guided only by a manual
disaster. When her mother returned, it took her hours to that practice is a matter of executing identical, rule-
which provided detailed verbal instructions and step-by-
undo the mess. At first she was angry, but then she go~er~ed movements over and over again, leading to
step diagrams. It turned out to be an immensely difficult
le~tured her daughter with the following words of gams III speed, efficiency and automation. But a little DISSOLVING TilE DISTI CTION BETWEEN
and frustrating task. The problem we all experienced lay
wisdom: girl, making her first bilum, is quite unable to produce INNATE AND ACQUIRED SKILLS
in converting each instruction, whether verbal or
You mu~t practise to get the proper feel of looping. these movements. Rather than repeatedly carrying out
graphic, into actual bodily movement. For while the
When y?u ve ma~eyour first bilum it will be cranky but the sa~e movements, generated from an already It is obvious that Telefol girls have to learn to make
instruction was supposed to tell you how to move, one
then we l~ throw It m the river. The river will carry your mternalIzed schema, she is repeatedly set the same task string bags. It is not a skill that they are, in any sense,
could only make sense of it once the movement had been
wonky bIlum away, and it will wash away your heavy gene:ated within the social context of mother-daughte; "born with." As MacKenzie notes (1991:103), "talent in
accomplished. We seemed, almost literally, to be caught
handedness. Then your hands will be good at making relatIons. The ability to reproduce her mother's
26 / CHAPTER 2
BEYOND ART AND TECHNOLOGY / 27

bilum making, that is, having hands which flow, is


(Collias and Collias 1984:201,206-207,212,215-220). bird works to a template that is genetically transmitted
[defined as] a physically acquired attribute rather than
an inherent predisposition in the sense that westerners It is evident from the Collias' account that all the five and thus innate. But if, as our experiments with knot-
think of ability and talent." My concern now is to look qualities of skill which, as I have shown, are exemplified making suggested, there can be no program for such
in the making of string bags by people of central New tasks as knotting, looping, and weaving that is not
m~r~ closel: at what it means to say that a particular
skill IS acqLllred rather than innate, I shall do so by way Guinea, are also manifest in the nest building of immanent in the activity itself, then it makes no more
of another example, this time taken from the animal weaverbirds. Though the needle of the bilum-maker is sense to interpret the weaverbird's behavior as the
kingdom, For while we are used to thinking of hu detachable from the body whereas the bird's beak is not, output of a genetic program than it does to interpret the
k'll man in use both are not so much moved as incorporated into bilum-maker's as the output of a cultural one. In all
s ~ s as belonging to this or that cultural tradition, the
skIlls o~ nonhuman animals are commonly regarded as a habitual pattern of movement. The abilities of the likelihood the human-maker of string bags has an idea
propertIes of their genetically encoded, species-specific LOOP TUCK SIMPLE LOOP INTERLOCKING
weaverbird, just like those of the human maker of string in mind of the final form of the construction, whereas
LOOPS
nature. What are we to make, then, of the male weaver- bags, are developed through an active exploration of the the weaverbird almost certainly does not. Yet in both
~ird" whic,h carries O~lt the most intricate knotting and possibilities afforded by the environment, in the choice cases (recalling Boas's point apropos basketry) it is the
ooplng with Its beak In the construction of its nest? The of materials and structural supports, and of bodily pattern of regular movement, not some prespecified
nest-building of weaverbirds has been investigated in a capacities of movement, posture, and prehension. design, that generates the form. And the fluency and
remarkable series of studies by ornithologists N. E. and Furthermore, the key to successful nest-building lies not dexterity of this movement is a function of skills that are
E. C. .Collias, and in what follows I draw on their report so much in the movements themselves as in the bird's developmentally incorporated into the modus operandi
(CollIas and Collias 1984). ability to adjust its movements with exquisite precision of the organism-whether avian or human-through
The nest is made from long strips torn from the leaves in relation to the evolving form of its construction. As practice and experience in an environment.
SPIRAL COIL SIMPLE WEAVE ALTERNATELY

of grasses, which are intertwined in a regular lattice


REVERSED WINDING Collias and Collias report: This last point is absolutely critical. Recall that Telefol
formed by passing successive strips over and under and girls develop their looping skills at a time of life when
In a direction orthogonal to, strips already laid. It is'held
In watching the numerous attempts of young male their bodies are also undergoing rapid growth. These
to,gether, and attached to the substrate, by a variety of weavers to fasten initial strips of nest materials and their skills, then, far from being added on to a preformed
st,ltches and fastenings, some of which are illustrated in gradual improvement in weaving ability, it seemed to LIS body, actually grow with it. In that regard they are fully
FIgure 2.2. The bird uses its beak rather like a needle in that what every young male weaver has to learn is what in part and parcel of the human organism, of its neurology,
sewing. or darning; in this the trickiest part lies in subjective terminology one would call 'judgment' musculature, even anatomy, and so are as much biologi-
threading the strip it is holding under another, HALF HITCH
OVERHAND KNOT SLIP KNOT
(1984:219). cal as cultural. After all, a human being, with its
transverse one so that it can then be passed over the next particular aptitudes and dispositions, is a product of
The strip has to be pushed under, and through, just fa~ One can sense the reluctance with which these hard- neither genes nor culture, nor of both together, but is
enough to enable the bird to let go with its beak in order nosed empirical observers find themselves having to rather formed within a lifelong process of ontogenetic
Figure 2-2. Various common stitches and fastenings resort to a notion of this kind. But the evidence leaves development. To be sure, the skills of looping are
to shift its hold and pull it up on the other side. If the free
used by m~le weaverbirds in constructing their nests them with no alternative. It is clearly judgment, rather acquired, in the sense that at whatever stage in the Iife-
end is left too short, the strip may spring back; pushed (from CollIas and Collias 1984:207).
too far, it could fall to the ground. Mastering this than a program of instructions or a set of design cycle they may be identified, a history of development
operatIon calls for a good deal of practice. From an early specifications to be mechanically applied, that the bird already lies behind them. But the same would have to be
age, ~eaverblrds spend much of their time manipulating acquires through mimetic practice. Finally, the form of said of the knotting and looping skills of the weaverbird,
all kmds of objects with their beaks, and seem to have a the nest results from the iteration of a small number of and indeed of allY skill, human or nonhuman. Moreover
particular in~er~st in poking and pulling pieces of grass, basic movements, and from the fact that the bird stands one could just as well claim that such skills are innate, in
le~ves, and sImIlar materials through holes. In females throughout on the same spot while it weaves all the sense that so long as the necessary environmental
thIS i~terest declines after about the tenth week from around-above, below, and in front-pushing out the conditions are in place (including the presence and
hatching, whereas in males it continues to increase. developing shell of the main chamber as far as its beak activity of already skilled practitioners) they are more or
Expenments showed that birds deprived of opportuni- will reach, and then tilting gradually backwards to less bound to develop. All Telefol girls learn to make
tIes to practIce and denied access to suitable materials complete the antechamber and entrance (Collias and string bags, just as they all learn to walk or to speak. All
are subsequently unable to build adequate nests, or even Collias 1984:193,209-210). male weaverbirds learn to make nests, unless opportuni-
to buIld at all. Indeed, fiddling about with potential nest Given that weaverbirds, in their nest building, exhibit ties for practice are artificially removed. Conversely,
maten~1 ap.pears to be just as essential for the bird, in the same properties of skill as are manifested in the Telefol boys and female weaverbirds never develop full-
prepanng Itself for future building, as are the first looping techniques of the Telefolmin and their neigh- blown looping and weaving skills, since their respective
ex~er~ments of Telefolmin toddlers in roving and bors, wherein lies the difference? The conventional activities and concerns take them too soon into other
splnnmg shredded fibres for their future bilum making answer is to claim that the human bilum-maker follows fields of practice. In short, whatever the difference
the dictates of an acquired cultural tradition, while the between the two sets of skills, avian and human, it
28 / CHAPTER 2

BEYOND ART AND TECHNOLOGY / 29

cannot be aligned on the axis of a distinction between


generic properties of skill to which I have already drawn However the situation facing the male weaverbird science between theoretical conjecture and experimental
the innate and the acquired.
attention. Like any other skill, speech develops along with who would build a nest for its mate, or the Telefol observation. And significantly, the process by which the
This conclusion, however, leaves us with our earlier
the growth of the organism, is continually responsive to woman setting out to make a string bag, or indeed any architect or theoretical scientist arrives at novel ideas, as
question unanswered. How, exactly, do human skills,
perturbations in the perceived environment, and is
s~ch as those exemplified in the making of string bags, animal-human or nonhuman-making a living in its opposed to their subsequent implementation or testing,
learned through repeated practical trials in socially usual environment, is just the opposite of that facing is often described as more akin to art-the spontaneous
dIffer from those of animals such as the weaverbird? To
scaffolded contexts. Above all, it cannot be reduced to the Visalberghi's capuchins in the artificially structured work of the human imagination. Indeed the opposition
be frank, I do not pretend to know. I remain perplexed
mechanical execution of a rule-governed system, or environment of the laboratory. For in these cases the between art and technology has, in recent times, become
by the question, and have yet to find an answer that is
"gramma.r." Yet s~eech is no ordinary skill. Weaving problem is, as it were, already solved. The solutions are such an established part of contemporary thinking on the
wholly convincing. Once again, however, MacKenzie's
together, III narratIve, the multiple strands of action and there for all to see, in the form of previously constructed "human condition" that we are inclined to use it as a
study of the Telefol offers a possible clue. It lies in the
perception specific to diverse tasks and situations, it artifacts. Neither the bird nor the human bilum-maker window through which to view practices of all kinds, past
observation, to which I have already alluded, that Telefol
serves, if you will, as the Skill ofskills. And if one were to is in the business of creating novel designs. It is the and present, Western and non-Western, human and
people liken the dextrous manual movements of the
ask where culture lies, the answer would not be in some process of implementation that is tricky, calling as it animal. Thus we imagine that the practical implementa-
fluent bilum-maker to running water (MacKenzie
shadowy domain of symbolic meaning, hovering aloof does for a good measure of dexterity. To build a nest or tion of any task, from a laboratory experiment to a
1991:136). For these inhabitants of intermontane
from the "hands on" business of practical life, but in the make a bag is, as we say, "easier said than done." Merely building project, from making a string bag to
valleys, the current of water in a river or stream is as
very texture and pattern of the weave itself. to witness the finished works, or even the successive constructing a nest, entails the mechanical application of
familiar a part of experience as is the motion of the
~and~ in looping. Now it seems reasonable to suppose, steps in their construction, does not suffice to enable a set of operational principles-something akin to an
likewise, that the weaverbird has as much of a "feel" for novice observers to copy these steps for themselves. My instruction manual-which the practitioner is bound to
CONCLUSION
air currents, while on the wing, as it has for nest contention is that to explain how they manage to do this put into effect, regardless of context or previous
materials in building with its beak. However what the requires us to shift our analytic focus from problem- experience.
D~scussions of the toolmaking and tool-using accom- solving, conceived as a purely cognitive operation In the absence of written manuals, which of course do
bird does not do, so far as we know, is to tie these
plishments of human and nonhuman animals in the distinct from the practical implementation of the not exist in primarily oral cultures and are a rarity even
different strands of perception and action together.
literatures of both anthropology and animal b'ehavior solutions reached, to the dynamics of practitioners' in literate ones, such a perspective could only lead us to
Human beings, it seems, differ from other animals in
studies, tend to turn on a fundamental distinction engagement, in perception and action, with their suppose that these operational principles are engraved
that they are peculiarly able to treat the manifold
between design and implementation. The comparative environments. Or in short, we need to regard technical on the minds of practitioners in the form of words,
threads of experience as material for further acts of
question is posed in terms of a concept of technical processes not as products of intelligence but as practices diagrams, charts or formulae. Like the linguist who
weaving and looping. In so doing, they create intricate
intelligence, understood as capacity to design solutions of skill. But this also means dispensing with the assump- naively assumes that the "language" of a nonliterate
patterns of metaphorical connection, such as-in the
to problems of adaptation arising in the sphere of the tion that cognition can be distinguished from practice community already exists, complete with grammar and
Telefol case-between the movement of the hands and
individual's interactions with its physical environment along the lines of a dichotomy between design and lexicon, implanted in the unconscious minds of its
flowing water. This interweaving of experience is
(Whiten and Byrne 1988). As a result, technical implementation. I do not mean, by this, to deny the speakers, the student of technology is led to believe that
generally conducted in the idioms of speech, as in
processes are understood, in the first place, as exercises existence of designs or plans. But we have to realize that a body of context-free, propositional knowledge about
storytelling, and the patterns to which it gives rise are
in problem-solving rather than as forms of skilled planning, too, is a skilled, environmentally situated tools, their interrelations and how to use them, lies fully-
equivalent to what anthropologists are accustomed to
calling "culture." practice. From this perspective, everything depends on practice which, like rehearsal, prepares one for the formed inside people's heads, simply waiting to be
working ~ut a novel plan of action for achieving a goal, action that follows without actually specifying it in all its revealed and written down. Indeed writing itself has
However culture, thus conceived, cannot be
one that IIlvolves the use of a detached object. Once the concrete detail (Leudar and Costall 1996). often been regarded as a kind of technology (Ong 1982),
understood to comprise a system of intrinsic rules or
pla~ is worked out, implementation is mechanically However the division between design and implemen- and it is tempting to suggest that writing codifies the art
schemata by means of which the mind constructs
stralght~orward. For example, Elizabetta Visalberghi of tation, or between the operations of intelligence and real of speech in much the same way that technology codifies
representations of the external world from the data of
the InstItute of Comparative Psychology in Rome has bodily movement, is so deeply embedded in modern technical skill. It has been argued, I think with some
bodily sensation, nor can speech be regarded simply as a
carried out some fascinating experiments with capuchin
~ehlcle for the articulation of these mental representa- thought, and so heavily institutionalized in diverse justification, that writing leads us to reify language as an
monkeys, in which she sets them the task of extracting a domains of contemporary Western society, that it is autonomous, rule-governed system. We have been
tIOns. Speakers no more "use" their voice, as Plato would
nut from inside a long perspex tube, and provides them
~ave had it, as the mere instrument of a language-based proving peculiarly hard to dislodge. It is on the grounds disinclined, as Roy Harris (1980:6-18) has observed, to
with a variety of sticks of different length and thickness.
IIlt~lhgence, than they "make" sense by superimposing of this division, for example, that architecture is presently recognize the extent to which our view of what language
By using. a stick which is long enough and thin enough, opposed to the building industry: the architect, classically is, and our theories of language, are affected by taking
theIr pre-existing designs upon the raw material of
or ~y uSlllg one stick to push another, it is possible to
~xperience. Rather, in speech, the voice is incorporated a "master-builder," is now a creator of structures that are written language as the paradigm case.
retneve the nut. Some monkeys can do it, others cannot left to the industry to put up. The architect designs the I believe the same may be true of technology, and that
IIlto a current of sensuous activity-namely, narrative
(Visalberghi 1993). Yet the operation itself involves house, the builder implements the architect's design. One we need to recognize how our understanding of the
performance-from which, as it unfolds, form and
virtually no skill at all-no more, we could say, than the creates but does not implement; the other implements technical practices of non industrial peoples may be
meaning are continually generated. For speaking is itself
skill required to move a chess piece accurately from one but does not create (Coleman 1988:15-16). An identical being distorted by the assumption that they, too,
a form of skilled practice, and as such, exhibits alJ the
square to another across the board.
logic, incidentally, underwrites the distinction in natural constitute an autonomous system, a "technology," which
BEYOND ART AND TECHNOLOGY / 31
30 / CHAPTER 2

Pye,D.
1993 Technology, Language, Intelligence: A
is already in place pending its discovery by the visiting REFERENCES CITED 1968 The Nature and Art of Workmanship.
Reconsideration of Basic Concepts. In Tools,
anthropologist. Indeed, attempts to render such Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Language and Cognition in Human Evolution,
practices in propositional form misconstrue the very Reed, E. S., and B. Bril
Bateson, G. edited by K. R. Gibson and T. Ingold, pp.
1996 The Primacy of Action in Development. In
nature of skill, which, as we have seen, consists not in 449-472. Cambridge University Press,
1973 Steps to an Ecology oJ Mind. Fontana, London. Dexterity and its Development, edited by M.
acquired mental representations or cognitive models Cambridge.
Bernstein, N. A. Latash and M. T. Turvey, pp. 431-451.
but in developmentally embodied capacities of attention
1996 On Dexterity and its Development. In 1995 Time, Work and Industry. Time and Society
Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Mahwah, New
and response. As Maurice Bloch (1991) has pointed out, Dexterity and its Development, edited by M. 4:5-28.
Jersey.
in writing technology we do not simply copy onto the 1996 Situating Action V: The History and Evolution
Latash and M. T. Turvey, pp. 3-244. Lawrence Rooley, A.
page what has already been copied, by some process of of Bodily Skills. Ecological Psychology
Erlbaum Associates, Mahwah, New Jersey. 1990 Performance: Revealing the Orpheus Within.
learning, into the minds of practitioners. For the Bloch, M. 8:171-182. Element Books, Shaftesbury, Dorset.
codification of skill as technology, like the codification 1991 Language, Anthropology and Cognitive Latash, M.
The Bernstein Problem: How Does the Rubin, D.
of speech as language, does not merely describe, but Science. Man (N.S.) 26:183-198. 1996 1988 Go for the Skill. In Remembering Reconsidered:
Central Nervous System Make Its Choices? In
actually transforms, the practical activities involved. But Boas, F. Ecological and Traditional Approaches to the
Primitive Art. Dover Publications, New York. Dexterity and its Development, edited by M.
once written, a technology can set standards of procedu- 1955 Stndy oJ Memory, edited by U. Neisser and E.
Bourdieu, P. Latash and M. T. Turvey, pp. 277-303. Winograd, pp. 374-382. Cambridge University
ral correctness which may profoundly affect judgments Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Mahwah, New
1977 Outline oJ a Theory oJ Practice. Cambridge Press, Cambridge.
of practice, in much the same way that writing has
University Press, Cambridge. Jersey.
affected the estimation of propriety in speech. And just Schiffer, M. B., and j. M. Skibo
Burford, A. Leach, E. R. 1987 Theory and Experiment in the Study of
as the rationalization of speech to conform with the 1966 Ritualization in Man. Philosophical
1972 CraJtsmen in Greek and Roman Society. Technological Change. Current Anthropology
regulations of written language has spawned a special- Cornell University Press, Ithaca, New York.
Transactions oJ the Royal Society oJ London,
28:595-622.
ized genre of "poetry" whose expressive power lies in its Coleman, R. (Series B), 251:403-408.
Culture and Comnlllllication. Cambridge Sigaut, F.
freedom from the established rule, so the rationalization 1988 The Art oJ Work: An Epitaph to Skill. Pluto 1976 1985 More (and Enough!) on Technology. History
of skilled practice as technology has turned what is now Press, London. University Press, Cambridge.
and Technology 2:115-132.
called "craft" into an equally specialized genre of Collias, N. E., and E. C. Collias Leudar, I., and A. Costall
1996 Situating Action IV: Planning as Situated Suchman, L.
expressive art. 1984 Nest Building and Bird Behavior. Princeton 1987 Plans and Siwated Actions. Cambridge
Action. Ecological Psychology 8: 153-170.
University Press, Princeton. University Press, Cambridge.
Dreyfus, H. L., and S. Dreyfus Lowenthal, D.
1996 The Past is a Foreign Country: For the Motion Turnbull, D.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
1987 The Mistaken Psychological Assumptions 1993 The Ad Hoc Collective Work of Building
(1). In Key Debates in Anthropology, edited by
Underlying the Belief in Expert Systems. In Gothic Cathedrals with Templates, String, and
T. Ingold, pp. 206--212. Routledge, London.
Cognitive Psychology in Question, edited by A. Geometry. Science, Technology and Human
Many of the ideas developed here were first "tried out" MacKenzie, M.
Costall and A. Still, pp. 17-31. Harvester Press, Values 18:315-340.
in a course of lecture-seminars on The Anthropology of 1991 Androgynol/s Objects: String Bags and Gender
Brighton. Visalberghi, E.
Art and Technology, presented at the University of Flew, A. (editor)
in Central New Guinea. Harwood Academic,
1993 Capuchin Monkeys: A Window into Tool Use
Manchester in 1993-1994, and subsequently in 1964 Body, Mind, and Death. Crowell-Collier, Chur. Activities by Apes and Humans. In Tools,
1995-1996. I am grateful to the students who have taken London. Mauss, M. Language and Cognition in Human Evolntion,
this course for their many insightful comments and Gatewood, J. B. 1979 [1934] Body Techniques. In Sociologyalld edited by K. R. Gibson and T. Ingold, pp.
Psychology: Essays by Marcel Mal/SS, part IV,
suggestions. In addition, over the last couple of years, a 1985 Actions Speak Louder Than Words. In 138-150. Cambridge University Press,
translated by B. Brewster, pp. 95-123.
group of us have been meeting in Manchester on a Directions in Cognitive Anthropology, edited by Cambridge.
Routledge and Kegan Paul, London.
regular basis to talk about issues on the interface J. W. Dougherty, pp. 199-219. University of Whiten, A., and R. Byrne
Illinois Press, Urbana and Chicago. Merleau-Ponty, M. 1988 The Machiavellian Intelligence Hypothesis:
between art, architecture and anthropology. We have 1964 The Primacy of Perception, and Other Essays on
called ourselves the Art, Architecture and Anthropology Gibson, J. J. Editorial. In Machiavellian Intelligence: Social
Phenomenological Psychology, the Philosophy of
1979 The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception. Expertise and the Evolution oJ Intellect in
seminar. I would like to thank fellow members of the Art, History and Politics, edited by J. M. Edie.
Houghton Mifflin, Boston. Monkeys, Apes, and Humans, edited by R.
seminar for some exceptionally stimulating discussions, Northwestern University Press, Evanston,
Godelier, M. Byrne and A. Whiten, pp. 1-9. Clarendon
n:any of which have directly influenced this essay. Illinois.
1986 The Mental and the Material. Verso, London. Press, Oxford.
Fmally I am grateful to the British Academy for the Harris, R. Ong, W. J.
Orality and Literacy: The Teclll1010gizing of the Williams, R.
award ofa two-year Research Readership (1997-1999), 1980 The Language-Makers. Duckworth, London. 1982 1976 Keywords. Fontana, London.
which has given me the time I needed to read and write. Ingold, T. Word. Methuen, London.
1990 Society, Nature and the Concept of
Technology. Archaeological Review from
Cambridge 9:5-17.

You might also like