You are on page 1of 8

See

discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: http://www.researchgate.net/publication/239547225

Where Mathematics Comes From: How the


Embodied Mind Brings Mathematics Into Being

ARTICLE in THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL MONTHLY AUGUST 2002


Impact Factor: 0.25 DOI: 10.2307/3072449

CITATIONS READS

485 20

3 AUTHORS, INCLUDING:

James J. Madden
Louisiana State University
43 PUBLICATIONS 767 CITATIONS

SEE PROFILE

Available from: James J. Madden


Retrieved on: 19 November 2015
rev-madden.qxp 10/15/01 10:20 AM Page 1182

Book Review

Where Mathematics Comes


From: How the Embodied Mind
Brings Mathematics into Being
Reviewed by James J. Madden

Where Mathematics Comes From: How the best-known re-


Embodied Mind Brings Mathematics into Being marks, translated
George Lakoff and Rafael E. Nez as the essay Math-
Basic Books, 2000 ematical Creation
ISBN 0-465-03770-4 in [P1], include
speculations about
$30.00, hardcover/$20.00, softcover
the unconscious
processes that pre-
A metaphor is an alteration of a cede discovery.
woorde from the proper and naturall This is where we
meanynge, to that which is not proper, read the famous
and yet agreeth thereunto, by some story of how, while
lykenes that appeareth to be in it. boarding a bus in
Coutances, Poin-
Thomas Wilson,
car suddenly real-
The Arte of Rhetorique (1553) [Wi], page 345
ized the identity of
Conceptual metaphor is a cognitive the transformations used to define the Fuchsian
mechanism for allowing us to reason functions with those of non-Euclidean geometry.
about one kind of thing as if it were In his 1905 essay LIntuition et la Logique en
another. It is a grounded, inference- Mathmatiques, which appears in translation in
preserving cross-domain mappinga [P1], pages 210222, Poincar looks at mathemat-
neural mechanism that allows us to use ical production from a different angle. He pictures
the inferential structure of one concep- two different kinds of mathematician. One kind is
tual domain (say, geometry) to reason devoted to explicit logical precision. Ideas must be
about another (say, arithmetic). broken down into definitions and deductions. Even
conceptions that seem clear and obvious must be
Where Mathematics Comes From,
subjected to analysis, cut apart, and examined
page 6
under the microscope of logic. The other kind of
mathematician is guided by geometric intuition,
In his philosophical writings, Poincar reflected physical analogies, and images derived from ex-
on the origins of mathematical knowledge. His perience. This mathematician is like Klein, who
proved a theorem in complex function theory by
James J. Madden is professor of mathematics at imagining a Riemann surface made of metal and
Louisiana State University. His e-mail address is
considering how electricity must flow through it.
madden@math.lsu.edu.

1182 NOTICES OF THE AMS VOLUME 48, NUMBER 10


rev-madden.qxp 10/15/01 10:20 AM Page 1183

Poincar goes on to argue that logic and intu- the basis of mathematical truth. Metaphor is the
ition play complementary roles in mathematics. key word in this book.
Logic provides rigor and certainty by substituting Much of the book is devoted to the examination
precise notions for vague and ambiguous ones of prominent topics in standard mathematics cur-
and by moving in sure, syllogistic steps. Logic, ricula. These topics include grade school arith-
however, does not perceive goals and does not metic, algebraic structures and their models, logic,
grasp that which motivates and organizes our set theory, limits, real numbers, and a little bit of
mathematical activity. We may follow the logical nonstandard analysis. Chapters 13 and 14 have a
trail through an argument yet fail to see the idea historical orientation, discussing the contributions
in it. For this we need intuition, which provides in- of Dedekind and Weierstrass to the foundations of
sight, purpose, and direction. But intuition is some- analysis. Chapters 15 and 16 treat philosophical
times ambiguous, and some- issues. The book ends with
times it even deceives. So an extended discussion of the
ultimately it is only by the How do equation e i + 1 = 0 intended
combination of logic and in- to illustrate mathematical
tuition that mathematics metaphors idea analysis, a technique
advances. that was invented by the au-
Poincar set his ideas down function in the thors and that they use to un-
at a time when revolutionary cover the metaphorical ele-
advances in mathematical mathematical ments in mathematical ideas.
logic were just beginning. He The arguments do not fol-
could not have foreseen what activities of low a direct path. The book
the next century would
achieve in foundational stud-
actual people? builds on many fronts, elab-
orates subgoals, and spins off
ies. Today, we cannot claim
to have the final word, but we
On this, Lakoff subsidiary projects. While
reading the book, I sometimes
clearly understand much and Nez are found it difficult to keep track
more about logic and the role of what the authors were aim-
it plays in mathematics than not very clear. ing at. For this review, there-
we did one hundred years ago. fore, I shall simplify things by
How about intuition? What picking out three major
more do we know about this? strands and commenting on
A few references come to them separately. I have men-
mind: Hilbert and Cohn-Vossens book [HC], tioned them already. They are:
Hadamards essay [H], and perhaps a couple of
a hypothesis about the role of metaphors in
more recent items, particularly S. Dehaenes work
mathematical cognition,
on the number sense [Dh] and Devlins book [De].
a philosophical position about mathematical
I find noteworthy the essay [T], written by a young
truth, and
Oxford mathematics student who went on to be-
the technique of mathematical idea analysis.
come a neuroscientist of high repute at the Uni-
versity of California Los Angeles. Overall, how- In many ways the three strands are interdepen-
ever, it seems that intuition has remained largely denta point to be remembered, even though my
unanalyzed and poorly understood. discussion is divided into three parts. I find the
A good way to approach the book of Lakoff and metaphor hypothesis the most interesting, and
Nez is to see it, as the authors suggest in the pref- accordingly I devote more space to this than to the
ace, as an empirical study of the precise nature of other two items.
clear mathematical intuitions (page xv). Lakoff and Let me state the metaphor hypothesis as I in-
Nez promise in the introduction to give an ac- terpret it. When people think about mathemat-
count of how normal human cognitive mecha- icseven very deep, advanced mathematicsthey
nisms rooted in the brain are used to formulate somehow activate links to mundane experiences
mathematical concepts, reason mathematically, that occur in everyday functioning in the world and
and create and understand mathematical ideas. links to other mathematical experiences as well.
Logic and formal rigor do not figure prominently These links are not logical or deductiveoften, they
in this account. Rather, the book is about the in- are not even conscious. They involve very complex
tuitive side; the focus is on certain conceptual pattern-matching, by means of which people trans-
metaphors which, the authors hypothesize, are the fer abilities and concepts that are relevant or adap-
basic building blocks of mathematical intuition. tive in familiar, natural settings to new settings that
Moving beyond cognitive science into philosophy, are less familiar and more abstract. The lifting or
the authors even suggest that metaphors account retooling of cognitive categories and abilities in
for the meaning of mathematical concepts and are this fashion is what the authors call conceptual

NOVEMBER 2001 NOTICES OF THE AMS 1183


rev-madden.qxp 10/15/01 10:20 AM Page 1184

metaphor. The second quote at the beginning of arithmetic, or in riding a bike, are cognitively quite
this review is as close to a definition of this as any- complex. This is most obvious in the fact that
thing that the authors give. learning them is not at all trivial. I would even sug-
Lakoff and Nez present the metaphor hy- gest that evidence in favor of the metaphor hy-
pothesis within the framework of a general theory pothesis can be found in the fact that exposure to
of human cognition that Lakoff himself played an different metaphors influences the learning
important role in creating; see [LJ]. In addition to process. In the appendix of [MC], Robert Moses dis-
the idea that most abstract concepts are metaphor- cusses a strategy he developed for teaching arith-
ical, this theory has two other basic tenets. One is metic with signed numbers. Moses does not men-
that thought is mostly unconscious and mostly in- tion metaphors explicitly, but in the terminology
volves automatic, immediate, implicit rather than of Lakoff and Nez, what he did was hypothesize
explicit understanding (page 28). Conceptual that certain children were failing to progress be-
metaphors may be unconscious; they support and cause they were inappropriately bound by the col-
influence our thinking without our necessarily lection metaphor. So Moses developed a teaching
being aware of them. The other tenet is that human strategy intended to strengthen the trip metaphor,
conceptual structures are deeply influenced by and this strategy succeeded quite well.
the particulars of our concrete, physical being. We Here is another example of a grounding
reason with the same equipment we use to observe metaphor. In Chapter 8 Lakoff and Nez intro-
our immediate surroundings, move about in them, duce what is the single most important metaphor
and interact with people and things. Even the most in the book, the Basic Metaphor of Infinity (BMI),
abstract concepts, if analyzed properly, show the and illustrate its occurrence in several mathemat-
marks of their origin in, and dependence on, basic ical contexts. Like all conceptual metaphors, the
perceptual and motor schemata. In summary, all BMI involves a correspondence between a source
conceptsmathematical concepts in particular domain, which is familiar and often concrete, and
are metaphorical and rest upon unconscious un- a target domain, which is less familiar and usu-
derstandings that originate in bodily experience. ally more abstract. In the BMI, the source is the gen-
Let us look at some examples. There are vari- eral idea of an iterative process that reaches a
ous kinds of conceptual metaphors. Grounding completion. Examples would be walking to a des-
metaphors transfer conceptual abilities acquired tination or picking all the berries off a bush. The
in concrete experiences (like putting things in piles target is any iterative process that potentially goes
or traveling) to abstract domains like arithmetic. on and on, like counting One, two, three . The
Linking metaphors make connections between dif- BMI simply shifts the idea of a completed process
ferent abstract domains. What struck Poincar as from its natural context into a new context, like
he stepped aboard the bus, for example, was a counting, in which the idea does not exactly fit but
linking metaphor at a very high level that had to which it bears a likeness or analogy. Thus, we
somehow evolved in his unconscious and then can reason about the collection of all natural num-
made its way to the surface. bers by extending or generalizing the patterns by
Basic arithmetic has several grounding which we reason about things like the set of all
metaphors, all discussed in Chapter 3. One of steps taken on a walk somewhere. It is not claimed
these metaphors connects experiences with col- that the use of this metaphor is conscious, but just
lections of objects on the one hand and the basic that there is a common pattern. We are prepared
arithmetic operations on the other. Joining two col- to think about infinite processes by experiencing
lections, for example, corresponds to addition, finite ones, and the descriptive categories we apply
while splitting a collection into many subcollections in the finite case have analogues in the infinite. Of
of equal size corresponds to division. The com- course, there are vast differences between the logic
mutative law of addition corresponds to the fact of finite and infinite processes, but the authors do
that when two collections are thrown together, it not seem very concerned about such differences.
does not matter which goes first. Understanding I suppose that the authors consider such details
the commutative law presumably involves some to be peripheral to the cognitive science, despite
sort of reference back to this property of collec- their mathematical importance.
tions and thus the activation of this metaphor. How do metaphors function in the mathemati-
Other aspects of arithmetic are associated with cal activities of actual people? On this, Lakoff and
other grounding metaphors. Adding positive and Nez are not very clear. When they do talk about
negative numbers may be understood metaphor- the mathematical activities of real people, they
ically by referring to forward and backward trips describe them in generic terms: people entertain
along a linear path. ideas or use cognitive mechanisms of one sort
One might react to this with the feeling that it or another to conceptualize this or that. Pre-
is all pretty trivial. Of course, once the arithmetic sumably, when an individual is engaged in math-
metaphors are internalized, using them is as easy ematical work, that person is guided by metaphors
as riding a bike. But the skills involved in using that are somehow represented in his or her own

1184 NOTICES OF THE AMS VOLUME 48, NUMBER 10


rev-madden.qxp 10/15/01 10:20 AM Page 1185

brain. The details would depend on the specific task another. After a while, the notion of metaphor
or problem. Unfortunately, Lakoff and Nez do seems to become a catchall. In the discussion be-
not provide any illustrations of what they sup- ginning on page 384, for example, metaphor is
pose goes on in real time, so this is about as much used to refer to the following: the algebra/geom-
as I can say. etry dictionary in analytic geometry; the defini-
This brings me to my first main criticism con- tion of function addition, (f + g)(x) := f (x) + g(x) ;
cerning the metaphor hypothesis: What is the qual- the Unit Circle Blend, which involves various
ity of the evidence for it? If, as the authors say on things one might attend to in a diagram showing
page 1, their goal is to determine what mecha- the unit circle at the origin in a Cartesian coordi-
nisms of the human brain and mind allow human nate system, together with a central angle; the
beings to formulate mathematical ideas and rea- Trigonometry Metaphor, i.e., thinking of the co-
son mathematically, then one would expect some sine and sine of as the x - and y -coordinates of
data about the actual the point reached after mov-
thoughts and actions of peo- ing counterclockwise from
ple in the process of doing (1, 0) along the unit circle
mathematics. Such data do Mathematics is through an angle of ; the
exist; the work of Robert Recurrence Is Circularity
Moses provides one example.
constantly Metaphor, which refers to
However, essentially the only
kind of evidence Lakoff and
absorbing what connections between mathe-
matical concepts and the lan-
Nez provide comes from it learns about guage of recurrence used in
the examination of the con- nonmathematical settings to
tents of texts and curricula. itself by gazing describe things like the sea-
How much can we infer about sons; and, finally, polar coor-
the basic cognitive mecha- at itself. dinates. Other parts of the
nisms used in mathematics book add yet more variety. In
from what we find in texts abstract algebra the relation-
and curricula? A study of nav- ship of an abstract structure
igation based on the standard manuals would tell (e.g., a group) to a model of that structure (a group
us very little indeed about how the task was actu- of rotations) is an example of a metaphor. Cauchy,
ally accomplished on the bridge of a large ship. How Dedekind, and Weierstrass contributed to the foun-
exactly do people use metaphors when they are dations of analysis by creating the Arithmetic Cut
learning new material, solving problems, proving Metaphor, the Spaces Are Sets of Points
theorems, and communicating with one another? Metaphor, and many others. When mathemati-
I would like to have seen direct support for the cians write axioms, they are using the Essence
metaphor hypothesis from the observation of Metaphor. Set-theoretic foundations give us an
mathematical behaviors. After a demonstration instance of the Formal Reduction Metaphor. With
that metaphors are indeed as common as the au- examples of so many differing kinds serving such
thors believe, I would want a detailed examination diverse functions, the notion of metaphor begins
of the ways metaphors are used in a wide variety to lose its meaning. If I had been given the origi-
of settings. The authors report no such informa- nal definition and a couple of examples and then
tion, and in fact they acknowledge the lack of di- had gone looking for conceptual metaphors in
rect empirical support for their hypotheses in mathematics, I would never have come back with
many places. Carefully designed studies might many of the things listed in this paragraph. The idea
lead to very different ideas about how metaphors that metaphors play a role in mathematical think-
function in mathematics or mathematics learning. ing is quite attractive, but what is needed is a no-
For example, at the AMS meeting in New Orleans tion specific and precise enough so that people
in January 2001, Eric Hsu and Michael Oehrtman, working independently and without consulting
mathematics education research postdocs at the one another can discover the same metaphors and
Dana Center at the University of Texas at Austin, agree on the functions they perform. I do not think
spoke about their study of calculus learners. They we have this yet.
found students making up their own, often dys- Let me turn now to the philosophical parts of
functional, metaphors, and they raised the fasci- the book. The authors devote many pages to por-
nating question of how it is that some learners shed traying a sort of philosophy/ideology that they
the idiosyncratic metaphors they initially build call the Romance of Mathematics, which they
and acquire the ones that are standard. contrast with their own philosophy. This is a good
My second main criticism concerns lack of pre- rhetorical strategy, since the so-called romance
cision in the concept of metaphor. By rough page would probably be disliked by all readers except
count, more than half the text is devoted to dis- some superficial and self-congratulatory mathe-
playing mathematical metaphors of one sort or maticians. For the sake of brevity, I will not

NOVEMBER 2001 NOTICES OF THE AMS 1185


rev-madden.qxp 10/15/01 10:20 AM Page 1186

comment on the romance but just go directly to can acknowledge a role for intuition without ig-
the authors philosophical ideas. noring the ways that logic and conventional rigor
According to my reading, Lakoff and Nez support the kind of knowledge that mathemati-
want us to view mathematics as a natural human cians build and share.
activity, about which their cognitive theory informs Let me move now to the third and last of the
us. They would like us to use words like meaning, three major strands on which I promised to com-
existence, and truth to describe aspects of this ment. The authors argue that mathematical ideas
activity. In particular, they say that mathematical occur within elaborate networks of interconnected
entities are metaphorical entities that exist con- metaphors. Mathematical idea analysis is the
ceptually only in the minds of beings with [ap- technique of teasing apart the network to reveal
propriate] metaphorical ideas (pages 3689). They the metaphorical parts. The reason for doing this
also say that when we speak of the truth of a math- is to characterize in precise cognitive terms the
ematical statement, we must speak only relative to mathematical ideas in the cognitive unconscious
a particular person, and we may mean no more than that go unformalized and undescribed when a for-
this: that persons understanding of the statement malization of conscious mathematical ideas is
accords with his or her understanding of the sub- done (page 375).
ject matter and the situation at hand; see page The appendix contains an extended discussion of
366. Such a view of mathematical truth appears to the equation e i + 1 = 0 that is intended to illus-
be at odds with the reality of how mathematicians trate the method. The authors say that they want to
communicate. If my mathematics depends on the characterize the meaning of the equation and pro-
metaphors that happen to be in my head, and your vide an understanding of it (page 384). What a math-
mathematics depends on the metaphors in yours, ematician will find here is a detailed description of
then how is it that we can share mathematical the geometric interpretation of complex exponen-
ideas? And why is it that we agree on so much? tiation. Building from basic high-school-level ideas
Lakoff and Nez make a couple of hypotheses up to college-level complex analysis, the treatment
that might address these objections. First, they is, at different times, insightful, entertaining, opaque,
claim that the metaphors on which mathematics interesting, breezy, ponderous, and muddled.1 Math-
is based are not arbitrary. Many grounding ematicians will find the images and metaphors dis-
metaphors, in particular, are forced on us by our cussed here to be very familiar, scarcely unconscious.
physical nature. Second, they claim that natural Many come directly from the pages of calculus books
metaphors have a very elaborate and precise struc- and are things most of us describe over and over to
ture; see page 375. These, of course, are empirical our calculus classes. To me, these mental images
hypotheses. Some day we might acquire good are certainly very helpful in understanding. The mys-
evidence for or against them. If they are borne tery has always been how difficult it is for students
out, they might support the kind of naturalistic ap- to absorb them and use them productively.
proach to the philosophy of mathematics that the Lakoff and Nez seem to want to open up that
authors have begun to sketch. In my opinion, whatever-it-is that makes mathematics into a co-
though, a naturalistic approach should certainly not herent, meaningful whole and expose it for all to
dismiss the way mathematicians share definitions see and appreciate. If only there were a way! Poin-
with one another, understand and criticize one car himself speculated about how best to teach
anothers reasoning, and use a precise, if artificial, mathematics, concluding finally that understand-
logical language to put their ideas in writing so that ing means different things to different people at
those ideas can be judged by the world. Surely we different times and for different purposes; see

1 See the website http://www.unifr.ch/perso/ make a point of saying that, once the meanings and
nunezr/errata.html for a list of errata. One error in metaphors are combined with some simple algebraic
the first printing (pages 4168) was fairly serious. The cor- manipulations, there is nothing mysterious (errata,
rection that I found at the website and that appears in page 419) about the result. I would retort that what is re-
the recently distributed softcover edition of the book is a ally the most basic question is: How do we know that
1
kind of mathematical red herringa passage that appears there is any number at all to which the values of (1 + n )n
to answer a question but in fact misleads. The authors pref- tend as n increases? The authors create the appearance
ace this passage by criticizing other texts for failing to an- of simplicity only by suppressing this issue, and in fact they
swer the most basic of questions: Why should this par- create a path that can lead to error. The book [Do], on
1
ticular limit, limn (1 + n )n , be the base of the exponential the other hand, contains a nice self-contained treatment
function that is its own derivative? (pages 4156). In the of this limit, beginning, appropriately, with a non-myste-
revised explanation (errata 4168), the unacknowledged rious demonstration of its existence; see page 45. The cen-
1
assumption that limn (1 + n )n exists is used in an es- tral claims of the book under review, which are in cogni-
sential way. (There are situations that are analogous in tive science and philosophy, may not be threatened by such
all explicit details but in which the pattern of explanation mathematical infelicities, but perhaps they serve as use-
that the authors use would explain a falsehood.) When ful reminders of the importance of logical discipline in
the authors complete their proffered explanation, they mathematics.

1186 NOTICES OF THE AMS VOLUME 48, NUMBER 10


rev-madden.qxp 10/15/01 10:20 AM Page 1187

[P1], page 432. Surely there will always be good defend, clarify, and refine their mathematical
reasons to experiment with new formats for math- understandings ([W], page 224). Isnt this a minia-
ematical exposition, and Lakoff and Nez are not ture version of what a group of research mathe-
alone in exploring. Zalman Usiskin, for example, maticians might be found doing in front of a
has proposed something he calls concept analy- tentative proof sketched on a blackboard? Or what
sis, intended for people who are learning to teach you do alone when you draft a proof and then
mathematics; see [U]. Concept analysis examines read, correct, and redraft it?
various methods of representing and defining If mathematical thinking is like other kinds of
mathematical ideas, as well as how those methods thinking in its use of metaphors, what distinguishes
evolved over time, how they are used, the problems mathematical thinking may be the exquisite, con-
people have understanding them, and strategies scious control that mathematicians exercise over
that are useful in explaining them. how intuitive structures are used and interpreted. We
This concludes my comments on the three strands can step back from our own thinking and critically
I identified earlier. If I think about the portrayal of examine our attempts at meaning-making. This, I
mathematics in the book as a whole, I find myself would venture, is as fundamental a cognitive mech-
disappointed by the pale picture the authors have anism as any mentioned by Lakoff and Nez. Math-
drawn. In the book, people formulate ideas and ematics is constantly absorbing what it learns about
reason mathematically, realize things, extend itself by gazing at itself. In Al Cuocos memorable
ideas, infer, understand, symbolize, calculate, phrase, mathematics is its own mirror on the very
and, most frequently of all, conceptualize. These thinking that creates it ([CC], page x). In a similar
plain vanilla words scarcely exhaust the kinds of vein, Schoenfelds classic study [S] showed how im-
things that go on when people do mathematics. They portant self-observation is in solving mathematical
explore, search for patterns, organize data, keep problems. Today we can associate the ability to ob-
track of information, make and refine conjectures, serve and control our own thought processes with
monitor their own thinking, develop and execute certain clearly demarcated regions of the brain, and
strategies (or modify or abandon them), check their we understand much about how these regions func-
reasoning, write and rewrite proofs, look for and tion in normal brains and how they fail in certain
recognize errors, seek alternate descriptions, look diseased brains; see [M].
for analogies, consult one another, share ideas, Where does mathematics come from? Poincar
encourage one another, change points of view, viewed mathematical intuition as that which in-
learn new theories, translate problems from one vents and logic as that which proves. Perhaps in
language into another, become obsessed, bang their this sense mathematics starts with intuition. But
heads against walls, despair, and find light. Any one Poincar also said that without proof there is no
of these activities is itself enormously complex understanding, no communication, no meaning
cognitivelyand in social, cultural, and historical ([P2], page 956). Most mathematicians would prob-
dimensions as well. In all this, what role do metaphors ably agree that mathematics is both invention and
play? proof and that it comes from the cooperation of
Moving to a different perspective, I want to note intuition and logic.
that there are areas not even hinted at in the book What about the question I asked earlier: what
where cognitive science is prepared to contribute do we know today about mathematical intuition
to our understanding of mathematical thought. that we did not know one hundred years ago?
Consider this: Metaphorical ideas are frequently Lakoff and Nez have suggested that intuition is
misleading, sometimes just plain wrong. Zariski not as formless and elusive as perhaps we had
spent most of his career creating a precise language thought. To the contrary, or so they claim, it works
and theory capable of holding the truths that the on the basic mechanism of metaphor, and it has
Italian geometers had glimpsed intuitively while a profound structure that is dictated by human na-
avoiding the errors into which they fell. What cog- ture. These are interesting and appealing ideas, or
nitive mechanisms enable people to recognize that perhaps intuitions, about the nature of mathe-
a metaphor is not doing the job it is supposed to matical intuition.
do and to respond by fashioning better conceptual Among the sciences, mathematics is not alone
tools? in building on intuition. Nor is it alone in requir-
From early childhood people comment on their ing more. Every science also needs concepts that
own thinking or on the things they create in order are precise enough to frame testable hypotheses,
to represent their thinking, and they use this com- and every scientific theory needs proofnot in
mentary to adjust and correct themselves. In a the mathematical sense, but at least in the sense
fascinating article about her own first-grade class- that the theory has been subjected to the most rig-
room, Kristine Reed Woleck describes how children orous trials we can devise and has survived. Lakoff
talk to themselves and to one another while draw- and Nez have shared with us their intuitions
ing and revising pictures to depict mathematical about the way the mathematical mind operates.
ideas, in the process coming to question, debate, More work remains to be done. We do not know

NOVEMBER 2001 NOTICES OF THE AMS 1187


rev-madden.qxp 10/15/01 10:20 AM Page 1188

what scientists may some day build upon these in-


tuitions.
Acknowledgments. I would like to thank Roger
Howe for sharing with me his reactions to this
book and for reading and commenting on an ear-
lier version of this review. I would also like to
thank Allyn Jackson and two unknown referees for
useful comments. Most of this review was written
while I was visiting Wesleyan University, where I
received partial support from the mathematics de-
partment. I would like to thank the university and
the department for their excellent hospitality.

References
[CC] ALBERT A. CUOCO and FRANCES R. CURCIO, eds., The
Roles of Representation in School Mathematics, Year-
book, National Council of Teachers of Mathematics,
2001.
[De] KEITH DEVLIN, The Math Gene: How Mathematical
Thinking Evolved and Why Numbers Are Like Gos-
sip, Basic Books, 2000.
[Dh] STANISLAS DEHAENE, The Number Sense: How the Mind
Creates Mathematics, Oxford University Press, 1997.
[Do] HEINRICH DRRE, 100 Great Problems of Elementary
Mathematics: Their History and Solutions, translated
by David Antin, Dover, New York, 1965.
[H] JACQUES HADAMARD, The Psychology of Invention in the
Mathematical Field, Princeton University Press, 1945.
[HC] DAVID HILBERT and S. COHN-VOSSEN, Anschauliche
Geometrie, Julius Springer, Berlin, 1932; translated
as Geometry and the Imagination, Chelsea, New
York, 1952.
[LJ] GEORGE LAKOFF and MARK JOHNSON, Philosophy in the
Flesh: The Embodied Mind and Its Challenge to West-
ern Thought, Basic Books, 1999.
[M] EARL K. MILLER, The prefrontal cortex and cognitive con-
trol, Nature Reviews in Neuroscience 1 (2000), 5965.
[MC] ROBERT P. MOSES and CHARLES E. COBB JR., Radical
Equations: Math Literacy and Civil Rights, Beacon
Press, Boston, 2001.
[P1] HENRI POINCAR, The Foundations of Science, authorized
translation by G. B. Halsted, The Science Press, New
York, 1913.
[P2] , Dernires Penses, Flammarion, Paris, 1913;
reprint 1963.
[S] ALAN SCHOENFELD, Mathematical Problem Solving, Aca-
demic Press, Orlando, FL, 1985.
[T] PAUL THOMPSON, The nature and role of intuition in
mathematical epistemology, Philosophia: Philos.
Quart. Israel 26 (1998), 279319.
[U] ZALMAN USISKIN, Teachers mathematics: A collection
of content deserving to be a field, UCSMP Newslet-
ter, No. 28, Winter 2000-01, 510.
[Wi] THOMAS WILSON, Arte of Rhetorique (Thomas J. Derrick,
ed.), Garland Publishing, Inc., New York and London,
1982.
[W] KRISTINE REED WOLECK, Listen to their pictures: An in-
vestigation of childrens mathematical drawings,
in [CC].

1188 NOTICES OF THE AMS VOLUME 48, NUMBER 10

You might also like