You are on page 1of 10

Erotic Love: Reading Kierkegaard with and without Marion Pia Sloft 37

Erotic Love: Reading Kierkegaard


with and without Marion
By Pia Sloft
Abstract: The claim of this article is that in Sren Kierkegaards notion of love as a basic urge in
every human being we find a special dialectic between lack and surplus, between need-love and gift-love.
Through a comparison with Jean-Luc Marions description of erotic love in The Erotic Phenomenon, I
demonstrate that Kierkegaards insistence that love is greater than everything and therefore prior to both
existence and knowledge seems, on the one hand, to point in the direction of a metaphysical anchoring
of love, which would be foreign to Marion. But at the same time, Kierkegaard, like Marion, stresses that
we have a universal, human experience of love, which is anchored bodily and sensed phenomenally. This
duality points to the fact that Kierkegaard had a much more nuanced notion of love than that simple
distinction between eros and agape that Anders Nygren invented.

Key Terms: Kierkegaard, Marion, erotic love, phenomenology

It is practically a tradition in Kierkegaard research What is Love?


to view Kierkegaards notion of love in the rather
anachronistic light of Anders Nygrens well-known
differentiation between eros and agape, which hov-
ers over all later theological discussions of love.1 In This question is just as old and just as vast as love
this tradition there seems to be consensus in inter- itself. And most people, no doubt, would think that
preting Kierkegaards notion of love as straightfor- it is a question that simply cannot be answered. In-
wardly agapistic. In this interpretation Kierkegaard deed, the true apologists of love, its most passionate
is most often accused of a rather negative view of proponents, probably go a step further. They main-
erotic love, if not charged with arguing against it tain that it is not just answering the question that
outright. is problematicit is the very question itself. It ab-
In what follows I wish to argue for a much more solutely must not be posed, for it is precisely of
nuanced view of Kierkegaards notion of love. To the essence of love to be and remain a riddle. This
enlighten the discussion I bring in Jean-Luc Mar- argument draws sustenance from the universal ex-
ions phenomenological insights into erotic love, perience that as soon as we attempt to explain and
as well as Kierkegaards own description of the give reasons for our love, it seems to vanish.
sensual-erotic from the first part of Either-Or.2 Sren Kierkegaard shares the view that love is
In this way I hope to broaden the discussion of inexplicable and enigmatic. But that love cannot
Kierkegaards notion of love as well as rehabilitate be explained and rationally justified does not mean
the phenomenon of erotic love in a philosophical that it cannot be sensed by someone who loves.
and theological context. This is due to loves erotic dimension, and to the

Pia Sloft is Director of The Kierkegaard Research Centre and President of The Danish Kierkegaard Society. She teaches ethics and philosophy
of religion at The Faculty of Theology, University of Copenhagen, and publishes in the fields of personal, social, and business ethics;
anthropology; phenomenology; and philosophy of religion.


C 2011 Wiley Periodicals and Dialog, Inc.
38 Dialog: A Journal of Theology Volume 50, Number 1 Spring 2011 March

fact that there is an intimate connection between ing both the proverb and Plato.5 But what does it
love and the body. It is a connection that is not, in mean to say that love is older than everything else?
the first instance, sexual, but simply allows love to It could mean that love is older than everything
be noticeable in and through the body of a person in the sense of greater than the person and her
who loves. experience with lovethat love per se transcends
Plato already had said that loves fundamental human experience, and therefore exists before the
form is erotic. Jean-Luc Marion said it again, in person exists as an experiencing subject. Such an
his own way, in his book The Erotic Phenomenon;3 interpretation points in the direction of a religious
and in what follows, I too wish to argue that anchoring of love in a divine source. Kierkegaard
Kierkegaard, in some sense, shares this view of again and again repeats the declaration that God is
erotic love as a fundamental and bodily situated love from the First Epistle of John, as well as Pauls
form of love. Kierkegaards notion of erotic love assurance in 1 Corinthians 13 that love is greatest,
seems to extend that of Plato, and thereby both an- which precisely attempts to place loves source out-
ticipates Marions insights and, with respect to the side of time, prior to any human experience of and
description of love as an erotic phenomenon, also with love.
goes beyond them. In Works of Love Kierkegaard Kierkegaard seems to share such a religious in-
states: terpretation of loves source. This shows itself not
One has sought in various ways to name and
just in his diligent quoting of John and Paul.
describe how love is felt in one in whom it Kierkegaard says quite explicitly in Works of Love
is present, the state of love, or what it is like that human love is grounded enigmatically in Gods
to love. One calls love a feeling, a mood, a love.6 And the same religious conception of loves
life, a passion; yet this being so general a def- source applies when, in the discourse Love Will
inition, one has sought to describe it more Hide a Multitude of Sins, from the Three Up-
precisely. One has called it a privation, but, building Discourses of 1843, Kierkegaard emphasizes
note well, what the lover constantly lacks, he that a humans love bears a mark of Gods love.7
nonetheless possesses; a longing, but, note The divine anchoring makes love larger than hu-
well, a constant longing for something the
man life, if we wish to speak spatially, and prior to
lover already ownsfor otherwise it is an
unhappy love that one is describing.That human existence, if we wish to speak temporally.
simple wise man of old has said, Love is a The latter is indeed the basis for the declaration,
son of Affluence and Poverty.4 which Kierkegaard comes back to again and again,
that it was God who loved first.8
Kierkegaard approves of this platonic interpre- But such a religious anchoring of loves source
tation of love as a combination of a lack and a in God raises another question. For is love, then,
surplus, and this points in the direction of a much not part of human nature? If one were to ask Paul
more nuanced view of the traditional separation be- Tillich, the answer would be that love is just as
tween eros and agape. But let us not be too hasty old as being itself. Love is thereby understood as
in our conclusion. Let us continue by asking a anchored ontologically. It is an inalienable part of
question just as big and just as impossible as the human nature.9 Kierkegaard also stresses that love
question we began with. Let us ask: Where does has its source in human nature. He poses the ques-
love come from? tion, Where does love come from, from where
does it have its origin and its source, where is the
Where Does Love Come From? place, where is the abode from which it proceeds?
And he answers himself with these words: Yes, this
place is hidden or is in the hidden. It is a place
An old proverb tells us that love is older than every- in the persons innermost recesses; loves life pro-
thing else. Plato has Phaedrus assert the same thing ceeds from this place, for the life proceeds from
in The Symposium, and Kierkegaard is fond of cit- the heart.10
Erotic Love: Reading Kierkegaard with and without Marion Pia Sloft 39

A persons interior is thus the source of loves life, something that does not exist yet. Here he alludes
of its utterances. For this reason, we even can speak to the love of parents for their as yet unborn child.
of love making itself known in a person purely And we can, again according to Marion, remain
physically; this is why, on a purely human level, in love with a person we no longer see or have
we are acquainted with love and feel it within us. a relationship with, which corresponds to the way
But in the continuation of the quote just cited, in which Kierkegaard describes a persons ability
Kierkegaard, as previously mentioned, also stresses to preserve love even when that loves object now
that a humans love is grounded unfathomably in perhaps belongs to someone else.12
Gods love. Marion further argues that one also can love
One can say, therefore, that Kierkegaard simul- something that no longer exists. Here we are speak-
taneously both underscores loves religious source ing of love for someone we once loved, but who
and stresses that we also have a universal experi- now has died. This experience of love also occupies
ence of loves power on the human levelan expe- Kierkegaard in one of the last discourses in Works
rience that also makes sense of the statement that of Love, where he dwells on precisely this love for
love is greater than life, and therefore overcomes the deada love that, on the human level, defies
death within a purely human horizon of under- death and chooses life, by applying this capacity
standing. And it is here that we can find obvious to remain faithful to ones love paradigmatically as
points of similarity between Jean-Luc Marion and a pattern for loving the living.13 Kierkegaard, like
Kierkegaard. Marion, here seems to be of the opinion that love
is also greater than a humans existence on a human
Marion and Kierkegaard: The level, because it can defy death and choose life.
Erotic Reduction In all these ways, which are discussed by Marion
and can be recovered from Kierkegaard, universal
experience shows us that love is greater than being
and therefore prior to ontology. It therefore will be
In The Erotic Phenomenon Marion indeed suggests a basic contention of the following discussion that
that we have a universal human experience of loves when it comes to the question of loves source,
strength and transforming power. But in the same Kierkegaard is fully in line with Marions phe-
place he also rejects the proposition that a non- nomenological description of the human experience
religious anchoring of love necessarily must be on- of loves power; yet at the same time, Kierkegaard
tological. He propounds the view that if love is would not dream of abandoning the thought that
understood exclusively as a property of existing be- God is the source of love. Kierkegaards dialec-
ings, as for example is the case in Tillichs work, tic between the human and the religious offers
then there is an ontological reduction. Marion, like us a refreshing and far more workable view of
Emmanuel Levinas, stresses that ontology has a ten- love than Anders Nygrens dangerously oversimpli-
dency to ask only what a things essence is. And fied idea that love can be understood only as a
that means that the experience of what it is to love human craving to possess the other (eros), or as
or to be loved acquires only a secondary signifi- a divine giving of itself (agape). Nygrens sharply
cance. Ontology says that one must be in order to drawn line subsequently has been developed further,
love. Marions basic assumption is the other way particularly by C. S. Lewis and Vincent Brummers
around: love is the greatest, the most important, distinction between need-love and gift-love14
because it comes before both being and knowledge.11 a distinction that is therefore just as incapable of
capturing Kierkegaards view of love as the division
Love as Prior to Ontology of eros and agape.
We could regard this double-anchoring of love as
This is precisely what experience shows us, accord- Kierkegaards attempt to assimilate and reformulate
ing to Marion. Specifically, we supposedly can love Socrates conception of eros as a middle-entity
40 Dialog: A Journal of Theology Volume 50, Number 1 Spring 2011 March

that bridges the human and the divine. In Works of closer look at the sensual-erotic as the basic form
Love we find the following definition of love, which of love in Kierkegaard.
seems to support such a view: What is it, precisely,
that binds the temporal and the eternal, what is it
other than love, which just for that reason is prior The Sensual-Erotic
to everything else, and remains when everything
else is over.15
The sensual-erotic is the first and most immedi-
Love as Prior to Knowledge ate form love assumes in a person. The sensual-
erotic designates an immediate, passionate urge or
desire, which the pseudonymous writer A, author
In The Erotic Phenomenon Marion further stresses
of The Musical Erotic Stages in the first part
that love is not merely experienced as something
of Either/Or, cannot imagine humans being with-
greater than beinglove is also prior to knowl-
out.17 It is not sexuality or the libido that forms
edge. Therefore, according to Marion, it is not the
the focal point of the thesis about the erotic stages.
Cartesian cogito that fundamentally defines us; if
As development of the category of the sensual-
we were to insist upon that, we would end up
erotic is inspired by the Greek concept of eros,
in an epistemic reduction. Against this, Marion
and contains a contention that love in a person
claims that we are always-already placed in an erotic
must fundamentally be understood as an erotic
situationin the broad, Greek sense of the term
striving.
whenever we attempt to comprehend something.
The sensual-erotic imposes itself on a person as
Knowledge is driven by love. The erotic compo-
an immediate urgean urge that is anchored both
nent of the situation lies in the fact that we are
in the body and in consciousness (even before con-
never neutrally placed in relation to that of which
sciousness is conscious of it), which corresponds to
we seek knowledge. Our cognition is always em-
the way in which love is described as an essential
bedded. This springs from a longing, a passion for
need to love and to be loved in Works of Love:
understanding, which Marion calls the erotics of wis-
dom.16 It is in this sense that the word philosophy How deeply loves need is grounded in hu-
means love of wisdom. The person is not de- man nature! The first observation, if we dare
fined by logos or being, but as an entity that hates to say it, that was made of the person, and
and loves. The person can quite simply be defined, which was made by the only one who could
truly do it, by God, and of the first per-
according to Marion, as a loving animal.
son, says just this. We read just this in the
It is my contention that Marions insistence that holy scripture: God said, it is not good for
love as an erotic engagement precedes comprehen- the man to be alone [. . .] so deeply is this
sion is a very accurate description of the sensual- need grounded in the persons being that,
erotic, such as Kierkegaard describes in The Im- since the first persons creation, it has un-
mediate Erotic Stages or The Musical Erotic in dergone no alteration, no new discoveries
the first part of Either/Or. Here Kierkegaard dis- have been made, but that self-same desig-
cusses loves first, unconscious form within a per- nation has only been confirmed in the most
son, which wholly determines a persons quest to various ways, diversifying from generation to
become herself and to relate to others. The sensual- generation in expression, in presentation, in
the productions of thought. So deeply is this
erotic as the fundamental form of love corresponds
need grounded in the persons essence; and
precisely to Marions idea that one can experience so essentially does it belong to a person that
oneself as loving someone who has not yet ap- to be human, to be He that was one with
peared, because love is a mode of relation we bring the Father, and in loves society with the Fa-
with us, which determines our self-relation and our ther and the Holy Spirit, that even He who
relation to the world. Let us now, therefore, take a loves the whole race, our Lord Jesus Christ,
Erotic Love: Reading Kierkegaard with and without Marion Pia Sloft 41

nonetheless humanly felt this need to love able urge in the person, which presents itself both
and be loved by an individual person.18 as an urge to receive love, to become loved, and
The Musical Erotic Stages describes three which therefore proceeds from a lack, a need-love;
stages of the sensual-erotic, which must be viewed and as a craving to give love, a craving to love an-
as different modes in which the unshakeable love- other, which proceeds from a surplus, a gift-love.
urge expresses itself in a person. There is no sug-
gestion here that one stage supersedes the other;
The Dreaming Desire
instead, they describe different aspects of loves ba-
sic erotic form. All three stages are indeed imme-
diate, and the sensual-erotic thereby appears as a
fundamental, pre-conscious urge in the person. In Kierkegaard calls one mode in which the sensual-
what follows, we will only concern ourselves with erotic manifests itself in its most immediate form
the first two stages: the dreaming desire and the the dreaming desire. The term desire (in Danish
searching desire, as these two forms of the sensual- attra) properly designates a strong desire or in-
erotic precisely express the above-mentioned dialec- clination, which is fundamentally sexually defined
tic between lack and surplus that is essential to un- and therefore situated bodily. But it is crucial for
derstanding Kierkegaards nuanced view of love. Kierkegaard to clarify that the desire, in its first, im-
mediate form, is a craving that does not yet want
something determinate, and neither, therefore, is it
Lack and Surplus: Need-Love
directed at another, concrete person.
and Gift-Love Nor is the dreaming desire, properly understood,
sexually oriented, but it is nonetheless essential that
it is precisely the word desire that is used. The point
The discussion in The Musical-Erotic Stages in- is that the inclination or craving that is spoken of
cludes the claim that the sensual-erotic expresses in the first, tentative form of the sensual-erotic is
itself both as lack and surplus. Both aspects are a craving that is passionately felt in and with the
present in loves basic form. At the outset, the body.
sensual-erotic manifests itself as an unconscious At its inception, the desire is an immediate urge,
urge in the person, which causes her to long for which develops within itself and is determined by
something other than her own selfwithout know- itself in unity with its naturalness. It is therefore
ing just what it is that the longing is directed to- not the case that the desire is directed toward some-
ward, because it is not yet directed toward anything thing outside of itself. There is no object that de-
concrete. The sensual-erotic is therefore the expres- termines the desire, for there is as yet absolutely
sion for a form of yearning19 in which one has a no object that one desires. The desire is an in-
longing even though one lacks nothing. definable intimation of something that is not yet
But at the same time, the sensual-erotic also ex- known. And therefore it is not a case of a cognized
presses itself as a surplus. This shows itself in a per- longing for someone or something determinate. Yet
sons urge to give herself over to the excess of life, the desire is experienced as a sweet turmoil.
craving, and passion that also is contained within
the sensual-erotic. The sensual-erotic imposes itself
as something that overflows and causes the person Objectless Desire
to turn his attention away from himself and out
toward the world. The sensual-erotic therefore con- In defining the dreaming desire as objectless, there
tains both elements of a need-love and a gift-love, lies an indirect challenge to the idea that it is
and this is precisely the dialectic between lack and merely the object, and therefore the object that one
surplus that is constitutive of loves fundamental loves, that defines love. If we were to follow that
form. According to Kierkegaard, love is an unshake- line of thought, then love for a lover or partner
42 Dialog: A Journal of Theology Volume 50, Number 1 Spring 2011 March

becomes romantic love, love for a friend becomes a person. It wants to get out, but it has no place
friendship, love for a child parental love, for the to go. It is not homeless; it seeks nothing and
neighbor neighbor love, for oneself self love, and so therefore lacks nothing. But it has wanderlust. The
forth. The character of the object determines the dreaming desire expresses itself as a surplus of be-
form of love. This is, of course, not entirely incor- ing, a surplus of life, craving, and passion. In de-
rect. And it harmonizes with, among other things, scribing the dreaming desire it is therefore impor-
the view of eros that Socrates propounds in The tant to note that the thought of love as a surplus
Symposium. Plato, and the long tradition that fol- leads to the thought that the dreaming desire al-
lows him, have therefore believed that the different ready has imposed itself, already expressed itself,
forms of love are generated by variations in the before the encounter with the other, the beloved.
objects of love.20 As dreaming, the desire is a sort of anticipatory
But in Kierkegaards development of the erotic pleasure, which does not yet know what it antic-
stages the stress is the other way around: the desire, ipates. It looks forward to something that it does
at its inception, and therefore in its first, tentative not know. It is dangerously fascinated, elated, and
form, appears as an undefined surplus of life, crav- turbulent, but it does not know why.
ing, and passion, which in no way is directed at a Sexuality, and therefore the libido, is, as yet, only
definite object and thus is not determined by an present as a weak intimation within the dreaming
object. The dreaming desire belongs to the subject. desire, and is so undefined that Kierkegaards A
The dreaming desire bursts forth in the person does not hesitate to call the desire at this stage
as, in itself, an immediate urge, and must not be androgynous: The urge is so undefined, the object
induced first by the encounter with the other, a so little differentiated, that the thing desired rests
beloved, or an object of desire. The dreaming de- androgynously within the urge, just as in plants
sire absolutely is not directed toward anything out- He and She sit on the same flower. The desire
side the subject. The driving force in the dreaming and the desired are joined in this unity, such that
desire is not a longing for (or association with) an they both are neutrius generis.21
object. And thus this early form of erotic love is It is therefore an aspect of overabundance that
not characterized by an element of lack. We are characterizes the dreaming desire as a peculiar, un-
not speaking of a lust-oriented love (a need-love), conscious form of gift-love. There is too much life,
which is (or contained within) Nygrens definition craving, and passion to be able to be contained
of eros and the subsequent development of that within the individual subject. The immediate urge
thought. The dreaming desire is therefore a form opens the subject up to something, or rather some-
of erotic love that is not determined by an object, one who is not yet known and therefore is neither
which cannot be defined as controlled by a lack, a lacked nor properly longed for. The substantial sigh
longing, a lust, or a genuine need. it emits is neither remorseful nor resigned, but is
nonetheless melancholic, because it springs from a
fundamental urge for an expansion that does not
Surplus and Wanderlust yet know its direction and shape. The dreaming
desire dreams of something without knowing what
The dreaming desire does not long for anyone or it is, and writhes restlessly in its sleep.
anything. However, there is a substantial longing,
a primordial longing, which is not directed at an
object, but which develops within itself as an un- The Searching Desire
conscious longing for longing. It is for this reason
that the dreaming desire, although undefined, is
nonetheless to be understood as a fullness, a sur- By contrast, the searching desire is built upon an
plus, a passion that cannot be contained within the element of lack within the sensual-erotic as the ba-
subject. The dreaming desire imposes itself within sic form of love. But it is important to emphasize
Erotic Love: Reading Kierkegaard with and without Marion Pia Sloft 43

that the elements of lack and surplus are of equal The searching desire is not, strictly speaking, di-
weight and are present at the same time, as two rected toward a determinate object, but in a certain
sides of one and the same love in its most imme- sense it is directed toward all objects. The plurality
diate form. of objects does indeed cause the seeking urge to
The seeking desire is also objectless, strictly discover a range of various objects that can incite
speaking. The seeking desire seeks something that craving and awaken the lust. The searching desire
it can desire, but it struggles and to a certain extent can be understood as a relishing lust for life, one
gets lost in the plurality of objects. that is not really directed at a specific other per-
The searching desire is, qua searching, outwardly son, but toward the very fact that it is able to desire
directed, whereas the dreaming desire primarily something outside of itself. The dreaming desire is
rests within itself and its own overabundance. The awakened, and, As soon as the desire awakens, or
searching desire wants to set out on a journey of rather, in and with the awakening, the desire and
discovery. The longing to set out, which is al- the object are separated for the desire; now the de-
ready characteristic of the overabundance within the sire breathes free and healthy, whereas previously it
dreaming desire, leads to the figure of the searching could not breathe for the desired.24 Moreover,
desire, the desire to go out of itself and direct its
gaze toward its surroundings, to view the objects At this stage of the sensual-erotic all objects
that lie outside the self. are therefore equally desirable. The searching
desire enjoys enjoyment; it does not search
But it is crucial here to maintain that the wan-
in order to find, but searches in order to
derlust lies within the searching desire itself. It does search, discovers in order to discover. In a
not first arise upon seeing a desirable object. The deeper sense it does not desire a specific
desire seeks to go out of itself by itself, not because other person; it desires being able to desire
it has been affected by an object in its surround- itself. Therefore the sensual-erotic is also, at
ings. If we were to remain in the realm of metaphor this stage, indeterminate both in relation to
we could say that the searching desire is already on its object and in relation to the sexual. Both
the hunt before it knows for certain that there is a elements are responsible for the transitori-
quarry. ness that characterizes the searching desire
and makes it glittery like a firefly, incon-
stant and transitory like the summer birds
touch, and just as harmless; countless kisses,
Passion Directed Outward but enjoyed so quickly that it is as if there
was only one taken from the one object what
was given to the next.25
In the dreaming desire the sensual-erotic presents
itself as an infinite depth and substantial longing, In the moment in which the desire awakens as
which pervades a person and directs her passion a desire for someone, it is no longer determined
inward in spite of the dimension of surplus. In merely as a resting-in-itself, but is equally deter-
the searching desire the sensual-erotic appears as an mined by its object. But even though the searching
awakened desire, which directs itself outward and desire is directed toward an object outside of it-
seeks an object. The searching desire therefore fo- self, it is important to underscore that it is not
cuses passions direction outward. The sensual-erotic the desirability of the object that creates the de-
in its immediate form thus has two directions: sire. The sensual-erotic proceeds from a substantial
partly directed outward, partly moving within it- longing, an unshakeable urge within the subject,
self.22 The inward direction is described via the which arises as both a fullness and a privation.
dreaming desire and the aspect of overabundance. The relationship between the desire and the
In the searching desire this inward direction is com- object therefore plays out as a peculiar dialectic
bined with the outward direction: the relation to between separation and reconciliation. With the
the other, or rather, the others.23 awakening of the desire there arises knowledge of
44 Dialog: A Journal of Theology Volume 50, Number 1 Spring 2011 March

ones separation from the object. Now one desires outward direction) it is within itself (in the inward
something outside of oneself, something, or rather direction), and in the same moment it is within it-
someone, which is not oneself nor is contained self it goes out of itself; therefore this outgoing and
within oneself. But in the same moment that this this returning, this returning and this outgoing, are
separation is felt, there arises an urge to be unified simultaneously one and the same.28
with that from which one is separated: But this Kierkegaards insistence that love is greater than
movement of the senses, this earthquake momen- everything and therefore prior to both existence and
tarily rends the desire and its object infinitely apart knowledge seems, on the one hand, to point in
from each other; but as the motivating principle the direction of a metaphysical anchoring of love,
shows itself in an instant to be one of separation, which would be foreign to Marion. But at the same
it thereby reveals itself again as wanting to unify time Kierkegaard, like Marion, stresses that we have
what has been separated.26 a universal, human experience of love, which is
It is the separation and, at the same time, the anchored bodily and sensed phenomenally.
urge for unification that drives the searching de- This duality is especially apparent in the phe-
sire out into the plurality of objects. Whereas the nomenological description of the sensual-erotic as
dreaming desire lies within what we have previously loves first, immediate form. This duality in the
called loves aspect of overabundance, the searching view of loves foundation and the experience of love
desire lies implicit within the conception of love as as a sensual-erotic urge prevents a strong distinction
founded upon a lack. between a humanly based and a religiously based
It is important to stress that these two stages of love. Further, it points to the fact that Kierkegaard
the sensual-erotic do not succeed each other, such had a much more nuanced notion of love than the
that the first is abandoned in favor of the next. simple distinction between eros and agape that Ny-
Rather, as is always the case with Kierkegaards dis- gren invented, which a whole tradition after him
cussions of stages, the one stage is incorporated into also has ascribed to Kierkegaards view of love.
the next.27 Thus the substantial drive, the outward
longing, which was characteristic of the dreaming
desire, still remains a part of the searching desire,
but this substantial drive is now directed toward Endnotes
an object outside of the self, whereby the surplus
that initiated the outward movement is combined 1. It is of course impossible to mention all these interpretations.
with a lack, the desire to enjoy (not possess) the One could say that K. E. Lgstrup with the polemical epilogue to Den
etiske fordring (Copenhagen: Gyldendal, 1956) and later in Opgr med
other. Kierkegaard (Copenhagen: Gyldendal, 1968) paved the way for such an
agapistic interpretation of Kierkegaards notion of love; Lgstrup also
established the ground for any later critique of Kierkegaard as being totally
The Dual Nature of Love oblivious to, if not directly against, erotic love. To mention some recent
interpretations that follow this line we can put forward Troels Nrager
in Hjertets lngsel (Copenhagen: Anis, 2003), where he directly links
Kierkegaards notion of love in Philosophical Fragments with Anders Nygren
(see p. 47, note 22); Nrager also interprets the topic of love in Works
The dialectic between lack and surplus, between of Love as fully agapistic in opposition to any formulation of erotic love
(p. 61). In 2007 Jakob Wolf continues this traditional interpretation of
need-love and gift-love, is, for Kierkegaard, con- Kierkegaards notion of love with direct reference to Lgstrup in the study
stitutive of the love that is an unshakeable urge Naturlig krlighed. Kritik af pligtetik og nytteetik (Copenhagen: Anis, 2007),
57-69; and Jakob V. Olsen supports such an interpretation albeit not in a
within the person. This dialectic can be illustrated critical manner in his book Kierkegaard, krlighed og kristendom (Fredericia,
via the relation between the first two stages of the Denmark: Credo, 2008). In his A Theology of Love (London: T&T Clark,
2010), Werner G. Jeanrond argues for a unity of love and desire, eros
sensual-erotic, but it is the same dialectic we find and agape, continuing the above-mentioned agapistic interpretation of
again in Works of Love, which tells us that love has Kierkegaards notion of love and concluding his chapter on Kierkegaard
with the statement that Kierkegaard and Nygren denounce human eros
two directions: So now with love. What love does, in love (134).
it is, what it is, it doesand in the same moment; 2. Sren Kierkegaard, Either/Or: A Fragment of Life (New York: Pen-
in the same moment it goes out of itself (in the guin, 1992).
Erotic Love: Reading Kierkegaard with and without Marion Pia Sloft 45

3. Jean-Luc Marion, The Erotic Phenomenon (2003; reprint, Chicago: you have the criteria by which you can test yourself. The one who uses
University of Chicago Press, 2007). this criteria shall easily be able to shorten the most complex relationships
extensiveness, and he shall learn to loath the mass of excuses, which
4. Sren Kierkegaard Research Centre, Sren Kierkegaards Skrifter 55
actuality otherwise has immediately to hand, which say that it is the
vols. (Copenhagen: Gads Forlag, 1997), 9:175. (This and all subsequent
other, who was self-interested, the other who is himself to blame for
Kierkegaard quotes are translated by Patric Stokes and taken from this
being forgotten, because he does not bring himself into recollection, the
series, hereafter cited as SKS.)
other who is faithless. Remember one dead, then you have, apart from
5. Kierkegaard introduces the first of the Three Upbuilding Discourses, the blessings which are inseparable from this work of love, also the best
Love Will Hide a Multitude of Sins, with the words: What is it that instruction in understanding how to love the living properly: that it is a
is older than everything? It is love. What is it that survives everything? It duty to love the people we do not see, but also those we see. The duty
is love (SKS 5:65), here playing upon both the proverb and Phaedrus to love the people we see cannot cease because death separates them from
speech in Platos Symposium. us, for the duty is eternal; but therefore neither can the duty towards the
dead separate us from those living with us, such that they do not remain
6. Loves hidden life is in the innermost, unfathomable, and there
an object for our love (SKS 9:351).
again in an unfathomable connection with the whole of existence. Just
as the still lake has its source deep in the hidden wellspring, which no 14. C. S. Lewis first employs the categories need-love and gift-love
eye sees, so the source of a persons love is yet deeper, in Gods love. If to differentiate between different facets of love in The Four Loves (1960;
no fount was at the bottom, if God was not love, then there would be reprint, London: Harper Collins, 2002). This is a distinction that is also
no still lake, nor would there be human love. Just as the still lake has developed further by Vincent Brummer in The Model of Love (Cambridge:
its source obliquely in the hidden fount, so is a humans love grounded Cambridge University Press, 2002), although neither Lewis nor Brummer
enigmatically in Gods. Just as the quiet lake invites you to look at it, but favors a sharp distinction between need-love and gift-love. A radical dis-
through the darkness mirror image forbids you to see through it, so loves tinction between a lust-oriented eros-love and a pure, giving agape-love
enigmatic origin in God forbids you to see its source; when you think goes back to Nygrens now-classic study The Christian Idea of Love Through
you see it, then it is a mirror image that deceives you, as was the source, the Ages (Stockholm: Swedish Church Diaconal Board, 1938).
that which only covers over the deeper source. Just like the ingenious,
15. SKS 9:14.
which precisely in order to hide what it covers looks like the bottom,
so that which deceptively looks like the depths of the source only covers 16. In order to attain the truth, it is necessary, in every case, first
over something deeper still (SKS 9:17f ). to desire it, and therefore to love it, Marion, 2.
7. For this is the secret of earthly love: that it bears a mark of 17. SKS 2:53-136.
Gods love on it, without which it would remain something ridiculous,
18. Ibid., 9:155ff.
or a stale pandering (SKS 5:83).
19. In The Concept of Anxiety Vigilius Haufniensis indeed draws at-
8. In Works of Love Kierkegaard states: Let a human, humanly speak-
tention to the ambiguity that lies in speaking of a longing; that one
ing, love God in the sincerity of the heart, alas, God has nonetheless loved
already at the outset anticipates what one longs for, and at the same time
him first, God is an eternity aheadso far is a human behind (SKS
he points to a clear parallel between desire and anxiety in their earliest
9:106).
forms. A quote from The Concept of Anxiety for illumination: With ex-
9. Love, power, and justice are metaphysically speaking as old as pressions and determinations such as Longing, Yearning, Expectation and
being itself. They precede everything that is, and they cannot be derived so forth, one often overlooks the fact that these involve a pre-existing
from anything that is. They have ontological dignity. Paul Tillich, Love, state, and that this state is therefore present and applicable at the same
Power, and Justice (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1954), 21. time as the longing unfolds itself. The expectant person is not put into
this state by accident etc., so that he finds himself totally alien in it, but
10. SKS 9:16f.
he produces himself at the same time. Anxiety is the expression of such
11. Marion, 21. a longing; for in anxiety the state from which he longs proclaims itself,
12. If love was solely a relationship between two, then the one and proclaims itself, because longing alone is not enough to save him
would constantly be in the others power, insofar as the other was a (SKS 4:362).
mean person who wanted to break the relationship. When a relationship 20. In his concept-analytic study of loves motivational structure Ur-
is only between two, then the one constantly has overwhelming power ban Forell stresses precisely the following: An important point of depar-
over the relationship by being able to break it, for as soon as the one ture for the conceptual analysis is the elementary fact that love always
has broken it, then the relationship is broken. But when there are three, has an object, and this object also determines, to a large extent, the
the one cannot do this. The third is, as said, Love itself, which the loves nature and type. The Motivational Structure of Love: An Ethical and
innocent sufferer in the breakup can hold on to, and so the break-up Concept-Analytical Study (Lund: Lund University Press, 1989).
has no power over him [. . .] But the true lover never falls away from
21. SKS 9:14.
love, and so for him it can never come to a break-up; for love abides.
Yet in a relationship between two, can one prevent the breakup when the 22. cf. SKS 2:86.
other one breaks it? One should indeed think that one of two is enough
23. The desire awakens, and just as it always happens that one
to break the relationship, and if the relationship is broken off, then it is
first notices that one has been dreaming the moment one awakens, so
broken off. In a certain sense this is also the case, but if however the
also here, the dream is over. This awakening, whereby the desire wakes
lover does not fall away from love, then he can prevent the break-up,
up, this shock, separates the desire and the object, gives the desire an
he can perform this miracle, for when he abides, then the break-up can
object. This is a dialectical definition, which must be sharply maintained,
never really come about. By abiding (and in this abiding the lover is in
that when the object first exists, the desire exists, and when the desire
a pact with the Eternal) he retains power over the past, such that he
first exists, so does the object. The desire and the object are twins, of
transforms what is in the past, and through this the break-up exists as a
which the one comes into the world not the smallest fraction of a second
possibility in the future (SKS 9:302).
before the other. But though they absolutely come into the world at
13. The work of love in remembering one dead is therefore a work once in this way, and do not even have the interval of time between
of the most disinterested, the freest, the most faithful love. So go forth them that twins can otherwise have, the significance of this coming into
and carry it out; remember the dead, and just thereby learn how to love existence is not that they are unified, but, on the contrary, that they are
the living disinterestedly, freely, faithfully. In the relation to one dead separated. But this movement of the senses, this earthquake momentarily
46 Dialog: A Journal of Theology Volume 50, Number 1 Spring 2011 March

rends the desire and its object infinitely apart from each other; but as the 27. No stage exists independently. The one stage is not outside the
motivating principle shows itself in an instant to be one of separation, it other and therefore it is emphasized that the expression metamorphosis
thereby reveals itself again as wanting to unify what has been separated. is actually more comprehensive than the expression stage: The various
The result of the separation is that the desire is torn out of its substantial stages, taken together, constitute the immediate stage, and one can see
resting-within-itself, and as a consequence, the object no longer falls under from this that the individual stage is more a revelation of a predicate,
the determination of subtantiality, but instead disperses into a manifold so that all predicates come crashing down into the richness of the last
(SKS 2:85). stage, for this is the genuine stage. The other stages have no independent
existence; for themselves they are only for representation, and from this
24. SKS 2:86.
one can also see how accidental they are when compared to the final
25. Ibid. stage (SKS 2:80).
26. SKS 2:85. 28. SKS 9:278.

You might also like