You are on page 1of 5

QUESTION 90, ARTICLE 2.

Whether the law is always Reply to Objection 3: Just as nothing stands firm with regard to
something directed to the common good? the speculative reason except that which is traced back to the first
indemonstrable principles, so nothing stands firm with regard to
Objection 1: It would seem that the law is not always directed to the practical reason, unless it be directed to the last end which is
the common good as to its end. For it belongs to law to command the common good: and whatever stands to reason in this sense,
and to forbid. But commands are directed to certain individual has the nature of a law.
goods. Therefore the end of the law is not always the common
good.

Objection 2: Further, the law directs man in his actions. But QUESTION 18, ARTICLE 2. Whether the good or evil of a
human actions are concerned with particular matters. Therefore man's action is derived from its object?
the law is directed to some particular good.
Objection 1: It would seem that the good or evil of an action is not
Objection 3: Further, Isidore says (Etym. v, 3): "If the law is based derived from its object. For the object of any action is a thing. But
on reason, whatever is based on reason will be a law." But reason "evil is not in things, but in the sinner's use of them," as Augustine
is the foundation not only of what is ordained to the common says (De Doctr. Christ. iii, 12). Therefore the good or evil of a
good, but also of that which is directed private good. Therefore the human action is not derived from their object.
law is not only directed to the good of all, but also to the private
Objection 2: Further, the object is compared to the action as its
good of an individual. On the contrary, Isidore says (Etym. v, 21)
matter. But the goodness of a thing is not from its matter, but
that "laws are enacted for no private profit, but for the common
rather from the form, which is an act. Therefore good and evil in
benefit of the citizens."
actions is not derived from their object.
I answer that, As stated above (Article 1), the law belongs to that
Objection 3: Further, the object of an active power is compared to
which is a principle of human acts, because it is their rule and
the action as effect to cause. But the goodness of a cause does
measure. Now as reason is a principle of human acts, so in
not depend on its effect; rather is it the reverse. Therefore good or
reason itself there is something which is the principle in respect of
evil in actions is not derived from their object. On the contrary, It is
all the rest: wherefore to this principle chiefly and mainly law must
written (Osee 9:10): "They became abominable as those things
needs be referred. Now the first principle in practical matters,
which they loved." Now man becomes abominable to God on
which are the object of the practical reason, is the last end: and
account of the malice of his action. Therefore the malice of his
the last end of human life is bliss or happiness, as stated above
action is according to the evil objects that man loves. And the
(Question 2, Article 7; Question 3, Article 1).
same applies to the goodness of his action.
Consequently the law must needs regard principally the
I answer that, as stated above (Article 1) the good or evil of an
relationship to happiness. Moreover, since every part is ordained
action, as of other things, depends on its fulness of being or its
to the whole, as imperfect to perfect; and since one man is a part
lack of that fulness. Now the first thing that belongs to the fulness
of the perfect community, the law must needs regard properly the
of being seems to be that which gives a thing its species. And just
relationship to universal happiness. Wherefore the Philosopher, in
as a natural thing has its species from its form, so an action has
the above definition of legal matters mentions both happiness and
its species from its object, as movement from its term. And
the body politic: for he says (Ethic. v, 1) that we call those legal
therefore just as the primary goodness of a natural thing is
matters "just, which are adapted to produce and preserve
derived from its form, which gives it its species, so the primary
happiness and its parts for the body politic": since the state is a
goodness of a moral action is derived from its suitable object:
perfect community, as he says in Polit. i, 1.
hence some call such an action "good in its genus"; for instance,
Now in every genus, that which belongs to it chiefly is the principle "to make use of what is one's own." And just as, in natural things,
of the others, and the others belong to that genus in subordination the primary evil is when a generated thing does not realize its
to that thing: thus fire, which is chief among hot things, is the specific form (for instance, if instead of a man, something else be
cause of heat in mixed bodies, and these are said to be hot in so generated); so the primary evil in moral actions is that which is
far as they have a share of fire. Consequently, since the law is from the object, for instance, "to take what belongs to another."
chiefly ordained to the common good, any other precept in regard And this action is said to be "evil in its genus," genus here
to some individual work, must needs be devoid of the nature of a standing for species, just as we apply the term "mankind" to the
law, save in so far as it regards the common good. Therefore whole human species.
every law is ordained to the common good.
Reply to Objection 1: Although external things are good in
Reply to Objection 1: A command denotes an application of a law themselves, nevertheless they have not always a due proportion
to matters regulated by the law. Now the order to the common to this or that action. And so, inasmuch as they are considered as
good, at which the law aims, is applicable to particular ends. And objects of such actions, they have not the quality of goodness.
in this way commands are given even concerning particular
Reply to Objection 2: The object is not the matter "of which" (a
matters.
thing is made), but the matter "about which" (something is done);
Reply to Objection 2: Actions are indeed concerned with particular and stands in relation to the act as its form, as it were, through
matters: but those particular matters are referable to the common giving it its species.
good, not as to a common genus or species, but as to a common
Reply to Objection 3: The object of the human action is not always
final cause, according as the common good is said to be the
the object of an active power. For the appetitive power is, in a
common end.
way, passive; in so far as it is moved by the appetible object; and
yet it is a principle of human actions. Nor again have the objects
of the active powers always the nature of an effect, but only when according to Job 21:14: "We desire not the knowledge of Thy
they are already transformed: thus food when transformed is the ways." And this is called "affected ignorance." Secondly,
effect of the nutritive power; whereas food before being ignorance is said to be voluntary, when it regards that which one
transformed stands in relation to the nutritive power as the matter can and ought to know: for in this sense "not to act" and "not to
about which it exercises its operation. Now since the object is in will" are said to be voluntary, as stated above (Article 3). And
some way the effect of the active power, it follows that it is the ignorance of this kind happens, either when one does not actually
term of its action, and consequently that it gives it its form and consider what one can and ought to consider; this is called
species, since movement derives its species from its term. "ignorance of evil choice," and arises from some passion or habit:
Moreover, although the goodness of an action is not caused by or when one does not take the trouble to acquire the knowledge
the goodness of its effect, yet an action is said to be good from which one ought to have; in which sense, ignorance of the general
the fact that it can produce a good effect. Consequently the very principles of law, which one to know, is voluntary, as being due to
proportion of an action to its effect is the measure of its goodness. negligence.

Accordingly, if in either of these ways, ignorance is voluntary, it


cannot cause involuntariness simply. Nevertheless it causes
QUESTION 6, ARTICLE 8. Whether ignorance causes
involuntariness in a certain respect, inasmuch as it precedes the
involuntariness?
movement of the will towards the act, which movement would not
Objection 1: It would seem that ignorance does not cause be, if there were knowledge. Ignorance is "antecedent" to the act
involuntariness. For "the involuntary act deserves pardon," as of the will, when it is not voluntary, and yet is the cause of man's
Damascene says (De Fide Orth. ii, 24). But sometimes that which willing what he would not will otherwise.
is done through ignorance does not deserve pardon, according to
Thus a man may be ignorant of some circumstance of his act,
1 Cor. 14:38: "If any man know not, he shall not be known."
which he was not bound to know, the result being that he does
Therefore ignorance does not cause involuntariness.
that which he would not do, if he knew of that circumstance; for
Objection 2: Further, every sin implies ignorance; according to instance, a man, after taking proper precaution, may not know
Prov. 14: 22: "They err, that work evil." If, therefore, ignorance that someone is coming along the road, so that he shoots an
causes involuntariness, it would follow that every sin is arrow and slays a passer-by. Such ignorance causes
involuntary: which is opposed to the saying of Augustine, that involuntariness simply.
"every sin is voluntary" (De Vera Relig. xiv).
From this may be gathered the solution of the objections. For the
Objection 3: Further, "involuntariness is not without sadness," as first objection deals with ignorance of what a man is bound to
Damascene says (De Fide Orth. ii, 24). But some things are done know. The second, with ignorance of choice, which is voluntary to
out of ignorance, but without sadness: for instance, a man may kill a certain extent, as stated above. The third, with that ignorance
a foe, whom he wishes to kill, thinking at the time that he is killing which is concomitant with the act of the will.
a stag. Therefore ignorance does not cause involuntariness. On
the contrary, Damascene (De Fide Orth. ii, 24) and the
Philosopher (Ethic. iii, 1) say that "what is done through ignorance QUESTION 57, ARTICLE 1. Whether the habits of the
is involuntary." speculative intellect are virtues?

I answer that, If ignorance causes involuntariness, it is in so far as Objection 1: It would seem that the habits of the speculative
it deprives one of knowledge, which is a necessary condition of intellect are not virtues. For virtue is an operative habit, as we
voluntariness, as was declared above (Article 1). But it is not have said above (Question 55, Article 2). But speculative habits
every ignorance that deprives one of this knowledge. Accordingly, are not operative: for speculative matter is distinct from practical,
we must take note that ignorance has a threefold relationship to i.e. operative matter. Therefore the habits of the speculative
the act of the will: in one way, "concomitantly"; in another, intellect are not virtues.
"consequently"; in a third way, "antecedently." "Concomitantly,"
when there is ignorance of what is done; but, so that even if it Objection 2: Further, virtue is about those things by which man is
were known, it would be done. For then, ignorance does not made happy or blessed: for "happiness is the reward of virtue"
induce one to wish this to be done, but it just happens that a thing (Ethic. i, 9). Now intellectual habits do not consider human acts or
is at the same time done, and not known: thus in the example other human goods, by which man acquires happiness, but rather
given (OBJ 3) a man did indeed wish to kill his foe, but killed him things pertaining to nature or to God. Therefore such like habits
in ignorance, thinking to kill a stag. cannot be called virtues.

And ignorance of this kind, as the Philosopher states (Ethic. iii, 1), Objection 3: Further, science is a speculative habit. But science
does not cause involuntariness, since it is not the cause of and virtue are distinct from one another as genera which are not
anything that is repugnant to the will: but it causes "non- subalternate, as the Philosopher proves in Topic. iv. Therefore
voluntariness," since that which is unknown cannot be actually speculative habits are not virtues. On the contrary, The
willed. speculative habits alone consider necessary things which cannot
be otherwise than they are. Now the Philosopher (Ethic. vi, 1)
Ignorance is "consequent" to the act of the will, in so far as places certain intellectual virtues in that part of the soul which
ignorance itself is voluntary: and this happens in two ways, in considers necessary things that cannot be otherwise than they
accordance with the two aforesaid modes of voluntary (Article 3). are. Therefore the habits of the speculative intellect are virtues.
First, because the act of the will is brought to bear on the
ignorance: as when a man wishes not to know, that he may have I answer that, Since every virtue is ordained to some good, as
an excuse for sin, or that he may not be withheld from sin; stated above (Question 55, Article 3), a habit, as we have already
observed (Question 56, Article 3), may be called a virtue for two and yet he does not reckon it among the speculative virtues,
reasons: first, because it confers aptness in doing good; secondly, which, according to him, reside in the scientific part of the soul.
because besides aptness, it confers the right use of it. The latter
condition, as above stated (Question 55, Article 3), belongs to I answer that, Art is nothing else but "the right reason about
those habits alone which affect the appetitive part of the soul: certain works to be made." And yet the good of these things
since it is the soul's appetitive power that puts all the powers and depends, not on man's appetitive faculty being affected in this or
habits to their respective uses. that way, but on the goodness of the work done. For a craftsman,
as such, is commendable, not for the will with which he does a
Since, then, the habits of the speculative intellect do not perfect work, but for the quality of the work. Art, therefore, properly
the appetitive part, nor affect it in any way, but only the intellective speaking, is an operative habit. And yet it has something in
part; they may indeed be called virtues in so far as they confer common with the speculative habits: since the quality of the object
aptness for a good work, viz. the consideration of truth (since this considered by the latter is a matter of concern to them also, but
is the good work of the intellect): yet they are not called virtues in not how the human appetite may be affected towards that object.
the second way, as though they conferred the right use of a power For as long as the geometrician demonstrates the truth, it matters
or habit. For if a man possess a habit of speculative science, it not how his appetitive faculty may be affected, whether he be
does not follow that he is inclined to make use of it, but he is joyful or angry: even as neither does this matter in a craftsman, as
made able to consider the truth in those matters of which he has we have observed. And so art has the nature of a virtue in the
scientific knowledge: that he make use of the knowledge which he same way as the speculative habits, in so far, to wit, as neither art
has, is due to the motion of his will. Consequently a virtue which nor speculative habit makes a good work as regards the use of
perfects the will, as charity or justice, confers the right use of the habit, which is the property of a virtue that perfects the
these speculative habits. And in this way too there can be merit in appetite, but only as regards the aptness to work well.
the acts of these habits, if they be done out of charity: thus
Gregory says (Moral. vi) that the "contemplative life has greater Reply to Objection 1: When anyone endowed with an art
merit than the active life." produces bad workmanship, this is not the work of that art, in fact
it is contrary to the art: even as when a man lies, while knowing
Reply to Objection 1: Work is of two kinds, exterior and interior. the truth, his words are not in accord with his knowledge, but
Accordingly the practical or active faculty which is contrasted with contrary thereto. Wherefore, just as science has always a relation
the speculative faculty, is concerned with exterior work, to which to good, as stated above (Article 2, ad 3), so it is with art: and it is
the speculative habit is not ordained. Yet it is ordained to the for this reason that it is called a virtue. And yet it falls short of
interior act of the intellect which is to consider the truth. And in this being a perfect virtue, because it does not make its possessor to
way it is an operative habit. use it well; for which purpose something further is requisite:
although there cannot be a good use without the art.
Reply to Objection 2: Virtue is about certain things in two ways. In
the first place a virtue is about its object. And thus these Reply to Objection 2: In order that man may make good use of the
speculative virtues are not about those things whereby man is art he has, he needs a good will, which is perfected by moral
made happy; except perhaps, in so far as the word "whereby" virtue; and for this reason the Philosopher says that there is a
indicates the efficient cause or object of complete happiness, i.e. virtue of art; namely, a moral virtue, in so far as the good use of
God, Who is the supreme object of contemplation. Secondly, a art requires a moral virtue. For it is evident that a craftsman is
virtue is said to be about its acts: and in this sense the intellectual inclined by justice, which rectifies his will, to do his work faithfully.
virtues are about those things whereby a man is made happy;
both because the acts of these virtues can be meritorious, as Reply to Objection 3: Even in speculative matters there is
stated above, and because they are a kind of beginning of perfect something by way of work: e.g. the making of a syllogism or of a
bliss, which consists in the contemplation of truth, as we have fitting speech, or the work of counting or measuring. Hence
already stated (Question 3, Article 7). whatever habits are ordained to such like works of the speculative
reason, are, by a kind of comparison, called arts indeed, but
Reply to Objection 3: Science is contrasted with virtue taken in the "liberal" arts, in order to distinguish them from those arts that are
second sense, wherein it belongs to the appetitive faculty. ordained to works done by the body, which arts are, in a fashion,
servile, inasmuch as the body is in servile subjection to the soul,
ARTICLE 3. Whether the intellectual habit, art, is a virtue? and man, as regards his soul, is free [liber]. On the other hand,
those sciences which are not ordained to any such like work, are
Objection 1: It would seem that art is not an intellectual virtue. For called sciences simply, and not arts. Nor, if the liberal arts be more
Augustine says (De Lib. Arb. ii, 18,19) that "no one makes bad excellent, does it follow that the notion of art is more applicable to
use of virtue." But one may make bad use of art: for a craftsman them.
can work badly according to the knowledge of his art. Therefore
art is not a virtue. ARTICLE 5. Whether prudence is a virtue necessary to man?
Objection 2: Further, there is no virtue of a virtue. But "there is a Objection 1: It would seem that prudence is not a virtue necessary
virtue of art," according to the Philosopher (Ethic. vi, 5). Therefore to lead a good life. For as art is to things that are made, of which it
art is not a virtue. is the right reason, so is prudence to things that are done, in
respect of which we judge of a man's life: for prudence is the right
Objection 3: Further, the liberal arts excel the mechanical arts. But
reason about these things, as stated in Ethic. vi, 5. Now art is not
just as the mechanical arts are practical, so the liberal arts are
necessary in things that are made, save in order that they be
speculative. Therefore, if art were an intellectual virtue, it would
made, but not after they have been made. Neither, therefore is
have to be reckoned among the speculative virtues. On the
prudence necessary to man in order to lead a good life, after he
contrary, The Philosopher (Ethic. vi, 3,4) says that art is a virtue;
has become virtuous; but perhaps only in order that he may Reply to Objection 3: As stated in Ethic. vi, 2, truth is not the same
become virtuous. for the practical as for the speculative intellect. Because the truth
of the speculative intellect depends on conformity between the
Objection 2: Further, "It is by prudence that we are of good intellect and the thing. And since the intellect cannot be infallibly in
counsel," as stated in Ethic. vi, 5. But man can act not only from conformity with things in contingent matters, but only in necessary
his own, but also from another's good counsel. Therefore man matters, therefore no speculative habit about contingent things is
does not need prudence in order to lead a good life, but it is an intellectual virtue, but only such as is about necessary things.
enough that he follow the counsels of prudent men. On the other hand, the truth of the practical intellect depends on
conformity with right appetite. This conformity has no place in
Objection 3: Further, an intellectual virtue is one by which one
necessary matters, which are not affected by the human will; but
always tells the truth, and never a falsehood. But this does not
only in contingent matters which can be effected by us, whether
seem to be the case with prudence: for it is not human never to
they be matters of interior action, or the products of external work.
err in taking counsel about what is to be done; since human
Hence it is only about contingent matters that an intellectual virtue
actions are about things that may be otherwise than they are.
is assigned to the practical intellect, viz. art, as regards things to
Hence it is written (Wis. 9:14): "The thoughts of mortal men are
be made, and prudence, as regards things to be done.
fearful, and our counsels uncertain." Therefore it seems that
prudence should not be reckoned an intellectual virtue. On the
contrary, It is reckoned with other virtues necessary for human life,
when it is written (Wis. 8:7) of Divine Wisdom: "She teacheth QUESTION 61, ARTICLE 2. Whether there are four cardinal
temperance and prudence and justice and fortitude, which are virtues?
such things as men can have nothing more profitable in life."
Objection 1: It would seem that there are not four cardinal virtues.
I answer that, Prudence is a virtue most necessary for human life. For prudence is the directing principle of the other moral virtues,
For a good life consists in good deeds. Now in order to do good as is clear from what has been said above (Question 58, Article
deeds, it matters not only what a man does, but also how he does 4). But that which directs other things ranks before them.
it; to wit, that he do it from right choice and not merely from Therefore prudence alone is a principal virtue.
impulse or passion. And, since choice is about things in reference
Objection 2: Further, the principal virtues are, in a way, moral
to the end, rectitude of choice requires two things: namely, the
virtues. Now we are directed to moral works both by the practical
due end, and something suitably ordained to that due end. Now
reason, and by a right appetite, as stated in Ethic. vi, 2. Therefore
man is suitably directed to his due end by a virtue which perfects
there are only two cardinal virtues.
the soul in the appetitive part, the object of which is the good and
the end. And to that which is suitably ordained to the due end man Objection 3: Further, even among the other virtues one ranks
needs to be rightly disposed by a habit in his reason, because higher than another. But in order that a virtue be principal, it needs
counsel and choice, which are about things ordained to the end, not to rank above all the others, but above some. Therefore it
are acts of the reason. Consequently an intellectual virtue is seems that there are many more principal virtues. On the contrary,
needed in the reason, to perfect the reason, and make it suitably Gregory says (Moral. ii): "The entire structure of good works is
affected towards things ordained to the end; and this virtue is built on four virtues."
prudence. Consequently prudence is a virtue necessary to lead a
good life. I answer that, Things may be numbered either in respect of their
formal principles, or according to the subjects in which they are:
Reply to Objection 1: The good of an art is to be found, not in the and either way we find that there are four cardinal virtues. For the
craftsman, but in the product of the art, since art is right reason formal principle of the virtue of which we speak now is good as
about things to be made: for since the making of a thing passes defined by reason; which good is considered in two ways.
into external matter, it is a perfection not of the maker, but of the
thing made, even as movement is the act of the thing moved: and First, as existing in the very act of reason: and thus we have one
art is concerned with the making of things. On the other hand, the principal virtue, called "Prudence." Secondly, according as the
good of prudence is in the active principle, whose activity is its reason puts its order into something else; either into operations,
perfection: for prudence is right reason about things to be done, and then we have "Justice"; or into passions, and then we need
as stated above (Article 4). Consequently art does not require of two virtues. For the need of putting the order of reason into the
the craftsman that his act be a good act, but that his work be passions is due to their thwarting reason: and this occurs in two
good. Rather would it be necessary for the thing made to act well ways.
(e.g. that a knife should carve well, or that a saw should cut well),
if it were proper to such things to act, rather than to be acted on, First, by the passions inciting to something against reason, and
because they have not dominion over their actions. Wherefore the then the passions need a curb, which we call "Temperance."
craftsman needs art, not that he may live well, but that he may Secondly, by the passions withdrawing us from following the
produce a good work of art, and have it in good keeping: whereas dictate of reason, e.g. through fear of danger or toil: and then man
prudence is necessary to man, that he may lead a good life, and needs to be strengthened for that which reason dictates, lest he
not merely that he may be a good man. turn back; and to this end there is "Fortitude."

Reply to Objection 2: When a man does a good deed, not of his


own counsel, but moved by that of another, his deed is not yet
quite perfect, as regards his reason in directing him and his
appetite in moving him. Wherefore, if he do a good deed, he does
not do well simply; and yet this is required in order that he may
lead a good life.
In like manner, we find the same number if we consider the simply. The others are principal, each in its own genus.
subjects of virtue. For there are four subjects of the virtue we
speak of now: viz. the power which is rational in its essence, and Reply to Objection 2: That part of the soul which is rational by
this is perfected by "Prudence"; and that which is rational by participation is threefold, as stated above.
participation, and is threefold, the will, subject of "Justice," the
Reply to Objection 3: All the other virtues among which one ranks
concupiscible faculty, subject of "Temperance," and the irascible
before another, are reducible to the above four, both as to the
faculty, subject of "Fortitude."
subject and as to the formal principle.
Reply to Objection 1: Prudence is the principal of all the virtues

You might also like