You are on page 1of 8

2.

The Philosophy of Archaeology


Robert W. Preucel

Archaeology is a common theoretical hat-rack for all our parochial hats.


L. Clarke 1973]
-David

Seventeen years ago/ in his classic article on the "loss of


disciplinary innocence," David Clarke (7973) observed that AngloAmerican
archaeology had passed through three thresholds of intellectual development.
They were consciousness, self-consciousness, and critical self-consciousness.
According to Clarke, archaeology achieved consciousness when it was first
defined as a discipline and began to be practiced by specialists. Archaeology
emerged into a stage of self-consciousness when it began to evaluate its own
procedures and methodologies. Finally, archaeology reached a stage of
critical self-consciousness with the disciplinary attempts to understand its
own philosophical basis. Clarke (1973:8) further noted that the process of
moving from one stage to the next is an adaptive one, related to both the
changing internal content of the discipline and the external spirit of the times.
Today archaeology is grappling with the deeper implications of the third
phase. At issue are fundamental ontological, epistemological, and practical
issues. Do archaeologists discover an objective past, or do they create
alternative pasts? Is archaeology properly considered a human science or a
natural science? What are the social responsibilities of the archaeologist with
regard to the uses of the past in the present? In the course of dealing with
these and related questions, archaeology has turned once again to philosophy
for guidance. ]ust as positivism was adopted by processual archaeology in
the 1960s, postpositivism is currently being embraced by the movement now
known as postprocessual archaeology. This posrocessual movement is
signified by an attack on the scientism of processual archaeology (Hodder
1982b, 1984a; Shanks and Tilley 7987) and the exploration of alternative
interpretive frameworks (Hodder 1986; Leone et a1.798n.
In this chapter, I examine the philosophical content of three influential
reseach programs in Anglo-American achaeology. Specifically, I focus on

Procsual and Postyocswl Archaeologes: Multiple Ways of Knozaing the Past, edited by Robert
W. Preucel. Center for Archaeological Investigations, Occasional Paper No. 10. @ 1991 by the
BoadofTrustees,SouthenlllinoisUnivesity. Allrightsreserved. ISBN0-88104-074-6.

1n
18 | R. W.Preucel Philosophy of Achaeolory I 19
positivist archaeology, the dominant framework under which archaeology is virtue of the meanings of the
conducted today, and two recent, but still marginal, developments, known as on the basis of the way things
hermeneutic and critical archaeologies.l I begin by reviewing thei intellectual ientist was thus to develop a
origins within philosophy and then document their use in archaeology,
drawing on the writings of their respective leading exponents, Lewis Binford, The third school is the logical positivism of the 1940s and 1950s, often
Ian Hodder, and Mark Icone. I make no claim of completeness, and in fact, I referred to as the "received view" of science. Its principal exponents were
fully recognize that I do an injustice to many nuanced positions within each of Rudolph Camap, Carl Hempel, Ernest Nagel, and the early Karl Popper. The
the programs in order to highlight specific aeas of contrast between them. logical positivists rejected the analytic/synthetic distinction on the grounds
Finally, I discuss some of the cognitive interests underlying the three that the meanings of statements cannot be established without reference to
approaches and condude that rather than being antithetical, as they are so other statements that ae themselves in need of analysis. As a resul the
often presented in debate, they are in fact complementary projects that must central project of logical positivism shifted away from language to the
be pursued simultaneously if archaeology is to accept the responsibilities of structure of scientific explanation and the verification principle. For the
being a social science. logical positivists, a causal explanation of an event involves deducing a
descriptive statement of the event from one or more general laws in
connection with certain unique statements about initial conditions. The
Positivist Approaches procedure was formalized by Hempel as the deductive-nomological (D-N)
mode of explanation (Hempel 7942; Hempel and Oppenheim 1948). More
Despite its overwhelming impact on the philosophy of science, the recent vesions have emphasized probabilistic rather than deterministic
term postipisrz is surprisingly difficult to define with any precision. A recent modes (e.9., Salmon et al. 1971).
review has distinguished no fewer than twelve different definitions Two different approaches to verification should be distinguished.
(Halfpenny 1982). Notwithstanding this vaiability, most philosophers agree Confirmationists, such as the early Hempel, claimed that empirical evidence
that positivism encompasses the theory of knowledge that seeks to explain could be used to lend support to statements. The greater number of cases that
empirically based observational statements in terms of general laws. Three are found to be in accord with the predictions from the statement and the
distinct but related schools can be identified-Comtean positivism, logical wider variety of circumstances in whidr these cases occur, the more strongly
empiricism, and logical positivism (Outhwaite 798n. k is mainly in the latter confirmed is the statement. Falsificationists, like Popper, take the position
form that positivism was taken up by the new archaeology. that no amount of empirical support can lend validity to a statement since the
Positivism was originally coined in the early nineteenth century by the next observation is just as likely to disconfim as confirm it. Using this logic,
French sociologist Auguste Comte. It was called positive or scientific Popper has suggested that in evaluating the validity of statements, scientists
knowledge to distinguish it from nonpositive and nonscientific knowledge should endeavor to disconfim rather than confirm thei theoies.
characteristic of theology and metaphysics. Comtean positivism has three In archaeology, Lewis Binfod popularized a version of logical positivism to
basic tenets (Halfpenny 1982). The first is that the only kind of admissible counter the unstructued empiricism of aditional achaeology. One problem
knowledge is that which is obtained through the senses by means of the with traditional approaches had been that arguments could only be evaluated
scientific method. That is, meaning can be attached only to those statements on the basis of the authority of their proponents. Positivism and the scientific
about observable phenomena that are testable. The second is that all sciences method were adopted because they provided an objective means of gaining
can be integrated under a single natural science model. This unity-of-science confidence in statements about the past. Binford justified his use of the
thesis reflects the position that, in principle, there are no differences between scientific method in achaeology from a "practical-science point of view"
natural and social phenomena. The third is that the growth of knowledge is (Binford 7972a:78). The statement eveals Binford's instrumentalist position,
responsible for social progress. Specifically, the discovery of laws of sociery is the view that science is useful precisely because it provides a framework for
essential to achieve both stabilify and social reform. evaluating ideas once they have been proposed (Binford 7977a.'2). Science
The second school is the logical empiricism of the Vienna Circle, which thus provides control over individual idiosyncrasy.
arose during the 1920s and 1930s. Led by Moritz Schlick, its regular members Early on, Binford and others (e.g., Watson et a1.1971) sessed the covering
were Rudolph Carnap, Herbert Feigl, Hans Hein, Viktor Kraft, Otto Neurath, law model of explanation and the testing methodology as the two hallmarks
and Friedrich Weismann. The Vienna Circle broke with Comte on two main
issues (Outhwaite 1987). Its members argued that Comte's law of social
development was untestable and therefore metaphysical. They also argued
that human behavior could ultimately be reduced to the principles of physics.
At the cornerstone of their philosophy was the analytic/synthetic distinction. in the linkage of modern observations with past events through laws of
20 | R. W.Preucel Philosophy of Archaeology | 21

cultual functioning (Binford 79b:269). According to Binford, the accuracy derived relationships linking behavior and material cultue is flawed. This is
of ou knowledge about the past must be tested in a rigorous fashion, and the because ethnographic data is just as theory laden as ardraeological data with
rigor is uniquely provided through the testing procedure embodied in the the result that the problem of interpretation is simply transferred from one
scientific method (Binford 1968a:16). In practice, it involves making discipline to another. Patty Jo Watson (198) has shown that even if we were
observations on the archaeological record, formulating hypotheses to account able to obtain well-confirmed principles in the present we have no
for observed patterning, and testing those hypotheses against independent justification for using them to explain past societies because we can never
empirical data. know the degree to which our analogy is accurate. As powerful as these two
In the late 1970s Binford began to acknowledge a fundamental aitiques are, we should not jump hastily to the condusion that positivism is
epistemological problem with his program. This is the problem of assigning bankrupt and that all that remains is the spectre of relativism. The testing
meaning to the achaeological record in the absence of direct observation. In methodology can provide at least a "limited confirmation" of our ideas
what has come to be called his "statics-dmarnics" argument, he has pointed especially when it implicates different strands of data drawn from different
out that no amount of studying statics can provide the information necessary sources (Wylie 1989a:15). Trigger (1989) makes much the same point in
t' 'th model and test arguments about the relationship between dynamics arguing that the dramatic increase in arc-haeological data actually constrains
;tatics (Binford "1983b:67). This is because of the paradox that the interpretation.
archaeologist must use "one set of conceptual tools to evaluate another set of
conceptual tools created to explain the past" (Binford 7977a:2). Here we see
Binford struggling with the problem of maintaining a distinction between Hermeneutic Approaches
theoretical (analytic) statements and empirical (synthetic) ones.
In order to circumvent this paradox, Binford has proposed that Hermeneutcs refers to a diverse group of philosophical approaches
archaeologists study those siruations where behavior is continually taking that share a common interest in eliciting meaning through interpretation. It
place. Fieldwork, he argues, should focus on those contexts where the has its origins in the theological problem of interpreting religious texts and
production, use, and discard of material culture is empirically observable. has evolved into a philosophical framework for understanding cultural
Only by making observations in the present will archaeologists be able to phenomena. Most hermeneutic approaches retain their philological heritage
construct a "Rosefta stone" with which Past material culture can be translated. and adopt a textual metaphor whereby understanding the meaning of a social
Binford's approach has come to be known as "middle'range theory" (Binfod practice is related to deciphering the meaning of a historical document Three
7977a:6). In spite of certain theoretical problems (see Raab and Goodyear sepaate schools can be distinguished: romantic hermeneutics, philosophical
1984), middle-range theory has proven to be a extremely productive research hermeneutics, ad textual hermeneutics. In postprocessual archaeology, the
area spinning off the subfields of ethnoachaeology, modern material culture first and the third have received the most attention.
studies, and experimental archaeology. And, indeed, the systematic Romantic hermeneutics developed in Germany in the late nineteenth
integration of these subfields is what Schiffer (1976) calls "behavioral century to provide an epistemological foundation for the sciences of cultue
archaeology." (Geistestissenschaften) (Gadamer 1987; Outhwatte 7987). It is associated with
It is a curious fact that, in adopting logical positivism, processual the writings of Wilhelm Dilthey and his followers, Herman Nohl, George
aitique of positivism
archaeologists paid almost no attention to the mounting Misch, and Bernhad Groethuysen. Dilthey's project was to overcome the
within philosophy itself. Binford, by his conspicuous silence on the subject, dilemma of historical knowledge, that is, the different frames of reference of
seems to imply that the debate is irrelevant to archaeology. Yet, in the historian and the crlhre under study. In order to address that problem,
philosophy, the edifice was already being shaken at the hands of its own he developed the methodology of ahistorical transfeence or empathic
builders. Both Hempel (1965) and Quine (1951) have siticized the trin pillars understanding (Verstehn). According to Dilthey, the historian must perform
of positivism-the theory-independent nature of data and the logical struchre the empathetic act of transporting oneself into the past and thereby become
of scientific explanation. Kuhn (1970) and Feyerabend (1975) contributed to part of the culture being studied. The procedure involves the total
this situation by stressing that nonscientific (sociological) factors directly subsumption of self in order to transcend lived experience, worldview, and
affect the outcome of scientific researc-h. In philosophy, this reassessment has professional interest.
esulted in some radical modifications to positivism (Glymour 1980) and Philosophical hermeneutics is assocjated with the writings of Hans-Georg
engendered the rise of posositivist approaches (Dallmayr and McCarthy Gadamer. It differs from traditional hermeneutics in its rejection of ahistorical
79m. ansference and its advocacy of a method of dialectical mediation (Gadamer
In archaeology, a number of these issues have been raised in connection 198. The concepts of historicity and prejudice are particularly important in
with Binford's processual program. Alison Wylie (1989a) argues that the Gadamer's method. Ir Gadamer's view interpretation of the past is always
attempt to ground archaeological explanation upon a body of observationally predicated upon the point of view of the present. That is to say, interpretation
221 R.W. Preucel Philosophy of Archaeology | 23
can only take part by virtue of its own historicity. He further states that show how inferred symbolic meanings regarding ritual and domestic
objectivity is illusory since it is part of the historical reality of being an architecture "make sense" within active social strategies concerned with
individual (Gadamer 7975:267). Prejudices, rather than being something to legitimating contol over productive and reproductive resources.
eliminate or repress, are thus necessary conditions for understanding. And Hodder's textual approach is outlined in his book Reading the past (Hodder
understanding can only be achieved through the dialectical confontation of 1986) and elaborated upon in a series of recent articles (Hodder 1988, 1989c).
prejudice and openness that results in a working out of a projection through Here he puts forth the i
the controlled movement between past and present. This controlled analogous to the reading
movement is the famous hermeneutic cirde. direct since material cultu
The third school can be distinguished in the work of Paul Ricoeur who speech (Hodder 7989c:72).
develops a theory of action as a text. Ricoeur (1971) distinguishes,two kinds a continuous dialogue of moving between sense and referent. Stated another
of textual readings, naive readings and stuctual analysis. Naive readings are way, this reading involves the transfer of meaning from one context to
appropriate for certain texts whee meaning proceeds directly from sense to another through an interpretative exercise in which each individual actor
referent and, consequently, there is no impediment to understanding. must decide upon appropriate signification. FIow, then, is it possible for
Structual analysis is required for texts such as literary works where there is a different readers to arive at the same or similar meanings? Hodder answers
second indirect referent along with the direct referent. Readings of the latter this question in two ways. First, he notes that ambiguity is always present,
texts are achieved by "guessing" the figurative meaning in a naive reading and since the meaning of an object is neve fixed and is always subject to
then modifying that reading according to structural referents in the external reinterpretation. Second, he states that context, defined as organized
world. Guesses then ae evaluated using the logic of probability such that the experience brought to bear upon an event, determines the extent to which the
best reading is the one that can relate the figurative meaning to the structural same thing can be said to possess the same meaning.
meaning in the deepest, most consistent way. The critique of hermeneutic archaeology is as yet relatively unsophisticated
The intoduction of hermeneutics to archaeology has been almost (cf. Binford 1988; Earle and Preucel 1987; Watson 1986). Most studies have
singlehandedly accomplished by Ian Hodder. In late 1970s Hodder, a former adopted an externalist position in arguing that the hermeneutic approach is
student of David Clarke, experienced an intellectual crisis that caused him to debilitated by the lack of any explicit interest in theory or method. That
reexamine the philosophical basis of processual archaeology. He puts it critique cannot stand, however, if one takes seriously the hermeneutic claim
succinctly as follows: "[T]he ditemma apparent for achaeologists is that there that interpretation should not be codified and should in fact differ from
is a widespread desire for science and objective tests, a fear of speculation and context to context. What I would like to take up instead is Hodder's use of a
the subjective, and yet we want to say something about the past' . . . Yet to textual metaphor. In literary criticism, the project is to mediate between the
say anything about the past, and past ideas, involves moving beyond the data text and the author for an audience. When this approach is imported to
to interpret them, and there can be no testing of these interpretations because archaeology, a number of difficulties immediately manifest themselves.
the data themselves are part of the same argument as the theories" (Hodder Except in perhaps some extremely rare circumstances, there is no single
7984a:28). Hodder is thus led to reject processual archaeology on two author to be interpreted in the reading of the archaeological text. The
grounds: first, because of its failure to deal with such basic anthopological archaeological record is a palimpsest of the actions of multiple authors, each
issues as intentionality and social action and, second, because of the with their own interests and identities. This fact suggests that we need to pay
limitations of its positivist testing program due to the theory ladenness of more attention to who these authors wee, how texts are created and assigned
data. meaning, who our audience is and what thei interests are.
Hodder's thought is extremely eclectic, drawing liberally from the
traditional and textual hermeneutics. As a primary intellectual influence, he
cites R. G. Collingwood the philosopher of history and amateur archaeologist. Critical Theory Approaches
A follower of Dilthey, Collingwood believed that the only way the past can be
known is through reliving it. Essentially, the historian (or achaeologist) seeks The term critical theory has been used to chaacterize avariety of
to project him,/herself back in time into a particular context to discover the philosophical approaches that shae the common goal of the emancipation of
significance underlying a given action. Like Dilthey and Collingwood, the individual. The approaches have thei origin in German idealism and the
Hodder argues that the empathic procedure is justified on the basis of a writings of Karl Max. Critical approaches view society as being composed of
continuity between the past and present, a commonality of feeling such that inherent contradictions. The critical project is to expose those ideologies that
"each event, although unique, possesses a significance which can be systematically mask the contradictions within society and to manipulate them
comprehended by all people at all times" (Ilodder 1986:95). As an example of in order to effect change. Critical theorists thus seek to simultaneously
the procedure, Hodde cites his study of the Neolithic in western Europe to explain the social world, criticize it, and empower their audience to overthrow
241R.W.Preucel Philosophy of Archaeology | 25

"one of how we got from the past to the present but rather what is
communicated by going from the present to the past" (Leone 1981a:13, my
emphasis).
Leone (1982b) directly confronts the notion of self-consciousness in an
article on the state of cognitive archaeology. He identifies two different forms
of self-consciousness-a phenomenological view and a critical view. The
phenomenological view involves immersing oneself in another cultue ad
suspending one's own biases in order to achieve understanding. This
approach is closely related to the familiar participant-observer approach
adopted by some anthropologists. The critical view is associated with the
analysis of one's own social and political context through a process of self-
reflection. For Leone, a self-conscious archaeology is a study of the "history"
of ideology. Here the notion of history is particularly important since
ideology, by definition, seeks to mask its own history. The approach is well
illustrated in his critique of the outdoor museum at Shakertown, Kentucky. In
that analysis, Leone (1981b) reveals how our modern ideals of thriff industry,
and productivity are served by an exhibit that selectively emphasizes the
economic basis of Shaker society at the expense of the religious and social
foundations of Shaker life.
Recently, Leone ad his colleagues Parker Potter and Paul Shackel have
explored the uses of critical theory in demystifying the way in which different
pasts are constructed (Leone et al. 198n. A critical approach is required, they
argue, for two reasons. First, archaeology has been appropriated by those in
power to serve political ends in particular contexts. For example, Hatl (1990)
has recently shown how achaeology served colonial interests in South Afica
by denying the time depth of black history. Second, ideology existed in the
past and is characteristic of individuals attempting to mask or naturalize
existing class stratification, wealth holdings, and power relations. Leone and
others provide an example of that approach in practice with an analysis of
historic Annapolis. They show how a critical analysis of the segmentation of
tasks and standardization of products leads to an understanding of the racial
and institutional contradictions within current Annapolis society that can, in
turn, be used to guide the structure of public proglams.
Critical archaeology has been attacked on a numbe of different grotrnds
(see comments to Leone et al. 1987). Some critics take the position that it is of
little use in achaeology and the insights that it offets ae self-evident. Others
argue that if it is applicable to archaeology at all, it is only applicable to
historic contexts where written documents are available. L" view, both of
^y
those critiques are misguided. Critical theory involves, among other things,
an analysis of ourselves as archaeologists, and as any comPetent psychiatrist
will relate, we are anything but self-evident. With respect to prehistoric
contexts, there seems to be no reason not to experiment with critical theory
since ideology was as rnuch a component of prehistoric social life as it is of
modern social life. The more telling critique, then, is the critique that critical
theorists are themselves not adequately self-reflective. This observation is
certainly true and is something that must be continually confonted by oitical
theorists through practice.
Philosophy of Achaeolo gy ZT
261 R. W.Prancel I
possible. This ambiguitn while not unique to archaeology, is compounded in
Discussion archaeology by the simple fact that there is no infimant who can be
consulted for meaning statements. Archaeologists, even more than
Inowwanttodawoutseveralconclusionsfromthisbrief practitioners of the other social sciences (with the notable exception of
overview of the philosophy of archaeolo history), are forced to "rethink the thoughts" of past individuals in rder to
the curent research Programs draws understand the intentions of past human actions. Iowever, because method
is there is
lit ,s
craim
as well' That th s seems
PhilosoPhical basis problematic, since he is reluctant to offer any internal criteria for a "best ft."
Tradition of German PhilosoPhers
while that may be understandable in terms of encouraging a multiplicity of
and citical theorists. Therefore, those who dismiss postprocessual readings, it does pose certain practical problems.
be cognizant of the fact that they are
?elhaps the most veng problem in qitical theory turns on its relationship
al tradion that has had and continues to
with history. To what extent is aitique historically determined, and to wht
modern anthropology (Macus and Fische
extent is it historically situated? The first position is the view that our
1986). western theoies and language actually impede our communication with
Second, these philosophical position those of radically different worldviews. Critique is thus a historical
one another that interact to determ movement determined by our own biases and experiences. The alternative
constructed his scientific position is that it is possible to construct a basis for citique that is part of
historical aPProach of ]am historical reality but at the same time distant from it. In this latter sense that it
hermeneutic and critical o might be said to be objective. For Habermas, the "ideal speech situation," a
similar sihration obtains in philosophy' communi is a symmetrical distribution of power,
provides In practice, however, his ideal lpeectr
situation fficult to implement and even when
implemented it cannot gua-rantee the resolution of competing interests.
Fourth, each of these approaches can be seen to represent different
t must be satisfied by all human
Processual archaeology represents
ce. These sciences are concerned

emancipatory science. These sciences are concerned with distinguishing


reference to emPirical observa between regularities of social action that are universal and those that ar
modern observations are just as ideologically determined and which can, in principle, be overthrown.
human behavior. The situation doe

thelastcenturyactuallyimposesasignificantconstraintuponinterpretation
(Trigger 1989).
The problem of interpretive adequacy is of interest to a number of
^.,1t," is an extremely- difficult text to
hermeneuric -.h";i;;ir'tr. rurut"ri But the resolution of these competing interests is, I argug the wrong goal for
read because it is arnfirous in the sense that
multiple readings are always
281 R. W.Preucel Philosophyof Archaeology | 29
both the social sciences in general and archaeology in particular. Instead, to evaluate these explanations and interpretations. To do this, archaeology
what should be of central concern ae the specific forms that interests take as must adopt a subject-co-subject relationship between the practitioners f
they are being played out in actual practice. In what ways are they archaeology and the general public. This is effected by adopting a historically
transforming existing research programs through their interaction with one self-conscious, critical framework. Each of these three projects must be
another? pursued simultaneously if archaeology is to continue to grow and develop as
In their extreme forms, processual and posrocessual programs represent a social science.
fundamentally different kinds of approaches to knowledge acquisition. The
underlying goal of processual archaeology is to obtain an explanation of
human behavior. To explain something means to show how it is logically Conclusion
entailed given certain initial assumptions. In processual archaeology, most
explanations are concerned with those cause-and-effect relationships that give In this chapter, I have argued that positivism, hermeneutics, and
rise to cultural process. Hermeneutic archaeology seeks to achieve an critical theory represent different cognitive interests, each of which has a
understandinc of past actions. To understand something means to be able to legitimate place within the philosophical pantheon of achaeology. Rather
fuse present and past contexts to see how a particular action was warranted. than champion one of the approaches at the expense of the others, I have
In hermeneutic archaeology, suc-h understanding involves interpretation of instead attempted to point out areas where each of the projects require work
the archaeological record by taking advantage of common or universal and to emphasize their necessary interrelationships as mutually reinforcing
principles of human nature in such a way that an empathic linkage between projects. If the analysis is correct, then it suggests that archaeology should
the past and the present is established. Critical archaeology attemPts to seek to explain the operation of culture process as empirically observed by
provide self-understandng of the archaeologist conducting an analysis. Self- means of neo-positivist approaches, to understand the meaning of cultural
understanding is essential to perrnit moral action, that is, how one individual systems for those participants within it using hermeneutic procedures, and to
acts upon another. In critical archaeology, that involves examining oneself evaluate the degree to which such systems are transformations of both past
with respect to why particular questions ae deemed worthy of being asked and present power relations from a critical framework. Only then will
and exposing the nature of any intellectual investment in a particular answer. archaeology be able to contribute to the difficult questions confronting the
Rather than being antithetical, it is essential to recognize that the three postmodern world.
approaches ae in fact complementary (see Schaafsma, this volume). One key
to their relationship is provided by Karl-Otto Apel's (1984) complementary
thesis, which posits that explanation and undestanding can be viewed in Acknowledgments
tems of two different kinds of subject-object relationships. The first of these
involves interaction between a real subject (the interpreter) and a second real ' I am grateful to David Freidel, Ian Hodder, Mark Johnson, Carl
subject (the objecO. Because the second subject is objectified, the interpreter Lamberg-Karlovsky, Mark Leone, Randy McGuire, Michael Schiffer, Patty Jo
can maintain an "objective" distance between him/herself and the second Watson, Red Watson, Gordon Willey, and Alison Wylie, who were kind
subject. That allows for the ability to act in an analytical fashion. The second enough to read and comment on earlier versions of this chapter. My
addresses interaction between a real subject (the interpreter) and a second real characterization of Karl-Otto Apel's position comes in part from informal
subject (co-subject). In this case, the second real subject is a cesubject and comments he made at the C. S. Peirce Sesquicentennal Conference held at
participates more or less equally in the Process of communication and Harvard University, Fall 1989.
cooperation. In this context there is no possibility for objective distance. This
underwrites the ability to take socially responsible action.
Extending the analysis to archaeologlr, there are three mutually reinforcing Note
projects that lie ahead. First, there is the project of explaining the past in
terms of patterns and processes. In order to achieve this, archaeology must 1. For alternative characterizations of the philosophy of archaeoloty/ see Dunnell
adopt a subject-object relationship with the archaeological record. This is best (1989); Hodder (1986); Kelley and Hanen (1988); Patterson (7989c); Salmon (1982);
accomplisheC through a form of neo-positivism that makes use of statistical Schiffer (1981); Shanks and Tilley (1987); Watson et al. (7984); Wylie (1985c).
rather than universal laws. Second, there is the project of rnderstanding what
happened in the past in terms of meanings and subjective intentions. This
involves developing a subject-cesubject relationship between the interpreter
and past actors, which only seems to be possible through a hermeneutic
exercise. Third, there is the project of interacting with various interest grouPs
Center for
Ar cha eolo gical Ina esti gtions
Processual and
Southern Illinois University Postprocessual
at Carbondale
Archaeologies
Visiting Scholar Conference Volumes

Lithic Resouce Procuement:


Proceedings fom the Second Conference
Multiple Ways of
on Prehistoric Chert Exploitation
(Occasional Paper No. 4)
Knowi^g the Past
edited by Susn C. Vehik

Foraging Collecting, and Harvesting: Edited by


Achaic Period Subsistence and Settlemmt
in the Eastern Woodlands
Robert W. Preucel
(Occasional Paper No. 6)
edited by Sarah W. Neusius

Emergent Horticultual Economies


of the Eastern Woodlands
(Occasional Paper No. Z)
edited by WIIiam F. IGegan

Tracing Ardraeology's Past:


The Historiogaphy of Archaeology
(Southern trlinois University Press,
Publications in Archaeology)
edited by Andr al L. Christercon

Between Bands and States


(Occasional Paper No. 9) Center for Ar chaeolo gicI Inoestigations
edited by Suxn A- Gregg Southern Illinois University at Carbondale
Occasional Paper No. L0

You might also like