You are on page 1of 21

Journal of Personality Disorders, 20(6), 597617, 2006

2006 The Guilford Press

TOWARD A MODEL OF SELF PATHOLOGY


UNDERLYING PERSONALITY DISORDERS:
NARRATIVES, METACOGNITION,
INTERPERSONAL CYCLES AND DECISIONMAKING PROCESSES
Giancarlo Dimaggio, MD, Antonio Semerari, MD,
Antonino Carcione, MD, Michele Procacci, MD,
and Giuseppe Nicolo`, MD

If we want to explain the links between the various and heterogeneous


elementssymptoms, dysfunctional forms of behavior and poor social
functioningmaking up personality disorders, we need model a self pathology that portrays dysfunctions, the links among them, and how
their interactions maintain disorders over time. In our view, the most
likely elements of self pathology are: a. problematic contents (thoughts
and emotions)experienced subjectively as states of mind and organized in the form of narratives; b. shortfalls in the ability, termed metacognition, to reflect on mental states, both of oneself and of others; c.
pathogenic interpersonal schemas; and d. maladaptive decisionmaking processes. These elements get altered in the various personality
disorders and interact to form typical pathological organizations. This
article seeks to describe a model of self pathology in personality disorders and discuss its current scientific status based on a literature review that spans several disciplines. The model is illustrated with an example of how the pathogenic elements can interact to form personality
disorder. Lastly, the limitations and advantages of the model are discussed.

Personality Disorders (PDs) involve diverse problems: difficult interpersonal relationships, symptoms, behaviors preventing the achievement of
primary goals, poor impulse control, and so on. To comprehend patients
behavior it is not enough to just list these problems; we also need to explain how these features co-occur and remain unchanged over the years.
The explanation we offer is based on a description of how self-functions
are damaged in PDs and how self-functions interact to form the various
disorders. This makes it possible to build a model showing how heterogeneous factors interact to lead to unitary forms of functioning. We consider

From Associazione di Psicologia Cognitiva (APC)Rome, Italy.


Address correspondence to Giancarlo Dimaggio, c/o Terzo Centro di Psicoterapia Cognitiva,
via Ravenna 9/c 00161, Rome, Italy; E-mail: ann.digi@tiscali.it

597

598

DIMAGGIO ET AL.

the following questions: a. What constitutes a PD?; b. Why do these with


PD not adapt to their environment?; c. In what way do distinct psychopathological elements, all present in the same person, lead to particular
forms of dysfunction?
Our goal is limited: We restrict ourselves to analysing clinical and experimental literature to show how we have sufficient knowledge to construct
such a model although we cannot claim that our model has a solid empirical foundation. We start from a general definition which, even if not universally accepted, is considered a valid basis for discussion and is based
on, or is compatible with, the conclusions of various authors (Allport,
1937; Benjamin, 1996; Cantor, 1990; Millon & Davis, 1996; Perris, 1999;
Wakefield, 1992). In Livesleys opinion (1998; 2000), a PD involves:
failures involving three major life tasks: a) failure to establish stable and integrated representations of self and others; b) maladaptive interpersonal functioning as indicated by the failure of [1) to develop the capacity for intimacy, 2) to
function adaptively as an attachment figure, and 3) to establish affiliative relationships]; c) maladaptive societal functioning as indicated by deficit prosocial
behavior, and inability to form cooperative relationships. (p. 143)

Personality disorder is therefore failure to adapt. The general definition


in DSM IV TR (American Psychiatric Association, 2000) that PD involves
enduring and maladaptive patterns of experience embracing cognition,
emotion, interpersonal functioning and impulse control, rounds off Livesleys by adding a subjective experiential element to the definition. In the
light of this definition, the earlier questions can be condensed into: What
features of mental life lead persons to suffer, not integrate their representations of social interactions, and display interpersonal and social dysfunctions? In line with the constructivist tradition (Guidano & Liotti, 1983;
Kelly, 1955; Neimeyer & Feixas, 1990; Winter, 1989), we hypothesize that
PDs get perpetuated (at least partially) over time (Tickle, Heatherton, &
Wittenberg, 2001) and PD patients consistently fail to find solutions to
the problems in the areas identified above (Dimaggio, Semerari, Carcione,
Nicolo` & Procacci, 2006; Livesley, 2003; Maffei, 2002; Millon & Davis,
1996) because of underlying self pathology.

THE ELEMENTS OF SELF PATHOLOGY


To build a model of the self pathology underlying PDs, we need data rooted
in the sciences dealing with how people adapt to social life: cognitive science, clinical theory, psychotherapy research, and personality psychology.
We also then need to explain how the dysfunctional elements of the self are
organized (Cervone & Shoda, 1999; Dimaggio, Carcione, Petrilli, Procacci,
Semerari, & Nicolo`, 2005; McAdams, 1994; Westen, 1998). Finally, the
model needs to be expressed in a form that facilitates treatment planning
(Livesley, 2003; Westen, 1998). We begin with hypotheses about which

SELF-PATHOLOGY AND PERSONALITY DISORDERS

599

elements of the self, when damaged, play a role in PDs and then show how
these dysfunctions interact to perpetuate PDs over time. We propose that
the self pathology underlying PDs involves problems with: (1) organizing
subjective experience into narrative form; (2) the ability to represent ones
own and others minds; (3) interpersonal schemas; (4) decision-making
reasoning processes.
The first element is the form and contents of subjective experience. PD
patients often have intense and extremely negative experiences, from
which they are unable to escape. Alternatively, some experiences are egosyntonic but patients seek them compulsivelylike the gratification due
to anothers presence in dependents or the feeling of superiority in narcissistsand this hinders social adaptation. Individuals communicate by
telling stories, with meaning themes, emotions and their vision of the
world. We therefore need to describe the cognitions and emotions typical
of patients self-narratives and how these stories are organized (or fail to
be). The second is the ability to represent psychological states to oneself.
PD patients have difficulty in building integrated representations of self
and others. Our hypothesis is that this is due to dysfunctions in the ability
to build metarepresentations. The third element is problematical interpersonal relationships. People possess preconceptions or cognitive schemas
that are used to anticipate events and make sense of the myriad of stimuli
impinging on them (Cottraux & Blackburn, 2001; Higgins & Bargh, 1987;
Kelly, 1955; Neisser, 1976; Piaget, 1964). Segal (1988) defined schemas as:
organized elements of past reactions and experience that form a relatively
cohesive and persistent body of knowledge capable of guiding subsequent
perception and appraisals (p. 147). Of particular importance are interpersonal schemas, which anticipate and attribute meaning to relationships
(Baldwin, 1992). There are a limited number of interpersonal schemas in
PDs and they mainly feature negative representations of the self vis-a`-vis
others represented as hostile, rejecting, distant, untrustworthy and so on.
As a result patients, for example, suffer for the expectation that their goals
will not be achieved because of the harm others are going to cause. They
are often incapable of asking for help or co-operating because they foresee
others not assisting. Moreover their anticipatively negative attitude evokes
responses in others that are consistent with the schemas and reinforce
their pathogenic expectations and dysfunctional behavior (Mitchell, 1988;
Safran & Muran, 2000).
Lastly, we need to look at how people reason and choose. As part of
general society, we have to opt between various possible actions and forms
of conduct, e.g., whether to embark on a career requiring travel or to devote ourselves to our children. Making the right choices promotes adaptation, whereas dysfunctional choice mechanisms cause harm. PD patients
find it difficult to set goals or self-regulate when they have set them
(Clarkin, 2005; Dimaggio, Nicolo`, Popolo, Semerari, & Carcione, 2006).
Their decisions are often guided by heuristics and biases that lead them
to adopt goal-reaching strategies doomed to failure.

600

DIMAGGIO ET AL.

SUBJECTIVE EXPERIENCE ORGANISED IN NARRATIVE FORM


To understand PDs, we need a theory that allows us to understand, explain, and use the many stories patients tell their clinicians about their
lives. The self is a multifaceted structure. People pass from one form of
self experience to another as situations and contexts change (Hermans &
Dimaggio, 2004; Markus & Nurius, 1986; McAdams, 1999; Muran, 2001;
Stiles, Osatuke, Glick, & Mackay, 2004). In a work interview, we might be
shy and worried about the outcome, whilst on a date we might be eager
and playful. Theoreticians from different schools affirm that people manage this complexity by organized self-information into a narrative form:
They tell themselves and others stories to make sense of and communicate
their experience. Over time, these stories change. Affectively-laden scenes
remembered from our past, intensify with repetition and internal rehearsal
to become overarching schemas for understanding interpersonal interactions. They then guide attention and may bias subsequent behavior to be
consistent with their affective sequences and themes (Angus & McLeod,
2004; Conway & Pleydell-Pearce, 2000; Habermas & Bluck, 2000; Hermans, 1996; McAdams, 1999; Neimeyer, 2000; Salvatore, Dimaggio, &
Semerari, 2004; Sarbin, 1986; Singer & Bluck, 2001; Tomkins, 1979).
Starting with emotions functioning as a core, around which other elements
(concepts, mental images, etc.) form networks of associations, mental
scenes arise and in turn evoke other emotions and images to form stories
(Damasio, 1994; Gazzaniga, 1988). Some primary emotions give rise to
specific micro-narratives (Smith & Lazarus, 1993). Psychotherapy research shows how people spend the majority of the time in sessions telling
stories about their interactions (Luborsky, Barber, & Diguer, 1992) and
how there are specific narratives for certain disorders (Goncalves & Machado, 1999).
The thought themes, emotions, and forms of communication that cluster together in a narrative give rise to the subjective experience of a state
of mind (Horowitz, 1998; Semerari et al., 2003a). A state of mind is a recurring form of experience, featuring the simultaneous and repeated appearance of certain emotions, thoughts and somatic sensations, narrated with
particular facial expressions and intonations of the voice (Horowitz, 1998;
Stiles, 1999). A clinician can deduce a patients state of mind from the
latters in-session narratives and non-verbal communication style (Semerari et al., 2003a). It is easy to distinguish when such states alternate with
each other. While an individual is narrating, there are changes in tone of
voice, contents and emotional experience, new characters come on stage
and the place and time of the action alter. These are signals of the passing
from one state of mind to another.
According to Dialogical Self Theory (Bakthin, 1984; Hermans, 1996;
Hermans & Dimaggio, 2004), the characters inhabiting intra-psychical
and shared narratives are in a continuous dialogue with each other to
negotiate the meaning of events. An individual is populated by various
characters, or voices, and the one with the dominant features at any time

SELF-PATHOLOGY AND PERSONALITY DISORDERS

601

gets identified as I. Each character embodies a facet of the self and the
characters can be pinpointed in patients discourses, in both written texts
(studying transcripts, Stiles et al., 2004) and inflexions of the voice (analyzing audio-files: Osatuke, Glick, Gray, & Stiles, 2004).
Given these theoretical, clinical, and experimental observations, it is
plausible to postulate that when PD patients tell stories they experience
them subjectively as distinct states of mind populated by a cast of voices
typical of their disorder. An additional hypothesis is that each PD is characterized by a typical set of states of mind (Dimaggio, Semerari et al.,
2006). For example, narcissistic personality disorder is characterized by
the following states: a. grandiose; b. depressed/terrified; c. detached emptiness; and d. impulsive and angry state with tendency to acting-out (Dimaggio, Semerari, Falcone, Carcione, Nicolo`, & Procacci, 2002). Youngs
(1990) descriptions of narcissists self-states are similar: self-aggrandizer,
detached self-soother, and vulnerable child. Studies using repertory grids
(Kelly, 1955) show that borderline disorder is characterized by a particular
set of states termed: ideal, abuser rage, powerless victim, angry victim,
coping, and zombie (Bennett, Pollock, & Ryle, 2005; Golynkina & Ryle,
1999).
Explaining PDs in narrative terms induces clinicians to build up a map
of the whole set of stories their patients tell. Clinical experience and session transcript analysis show that, even in the most serious PDs, where
experience is most limited, e.g., paranoid (Salvatore, Nicolo`, & Dimaggio,
2005), the self is multifaceted and a certain number of themes can be observed. The narrative approach is therefore in line with the criticisms made
of the DSM, i.e., that it portrays disorders in an almost caricatural way,
pointing to only one facet of a personality or one narrative theme. The
research by Westen & Shedler (2000; Shedler & Westen, 2004) shows that
PD patients narratives do indeed concentrate on one dominant theme, but
there are also likely to be secondary themes, generally not included in the
corresponding DSM category.
Millon and Davis (1996) similarly consider PDs multifaceted entities. In
their model each disorder has a central part composed of several elements
(beliefs, behavioral styles, etc.), which constitute the core of its prototype,
plus secondary facets representing its subtypes. We can, for example, talk
of avoidant individuals with dependent traits, which, translated into narrative terminology, signifies swinging between a dominant themesensitivity to critical opinions and to feeling ashamed, with a tendency to isolationand dependency on reassuring and nonjudgmental figures, by
whom one lets oneself be guided in ones actions.
Narrative theory has the advantage of being easy to apply clinically: The
amount of inference needed to identify the principal self states contents is
minimal. Moreover, thinking in term of narrative themes is a good basis
for research on the psychotherapy process, both via methods pinpointing
dominant constructs and narratives, such as Kellys repertory grids or
self-investigation (Hermans & Hermans-Jansen, 1995), and via others

602

DIMAGGIO ET AL.

identifying problematic contents and states of mind, such as the analysis


of session transcripts (Luborsky & Crits-Christoph, 1990; Stiles et al.,
2004; Semerari et al., 2003a).
In general, even if it is acknowledged that there needs to be an understanding of how subjective experience gets organized in narrative form in
PDs (Livesley, 2001), it rarely occurs. Westen (1997) suggested that clinicians of all theoretical orientations assess personality pathology by listening to the narratives patients tell about their lives and significant relationships. It is to be hoped that the work of various authors using the narrative
paradigm to assess patients narratives (see Angus & McLeod, 2004) gets
applied on a wide scale to PDs.

METACOGNITIVE SKILLS
Cognitive science, developmental psychology, clinical practice, and philosophy (Dennett, 1991) agree on some basic assumptions for comprehending personality dysfunctions. The first is that there needs to be a set of
mechanisms by which an individual can perceive and express inner experience in language, and also read others minds accurately and sensitively.
For example, the physiological activation of an unpleasant arousal can
induce individuals to distance themselves from a stimulus, but they do
not necessarily recognize it as fear (Zajonc, 1980). The processes by which
one is able to identify inner states, to label them linguistically and reason
about them, to ascribe states of mind to others on the basis of their behavior and to reason about states of mind, are termed: theory of mind (Leslie,
1987; Baron-Cohen, Leslie, & Frith, 1985), reflexive function or mentalization (Fonagy, Gergely, Jurist, & Target, 2002), psychological mindedness
(Applebaum, 1973; Conte, Plutchik, Jung, Picard, Karasu, & Lotterman,
1990), metacognition (Flavell, Miller, & Miller, 1993), and metarepresentative or metacognitive skills (Semerari et al., 2003b; Sperber, 2000).
There is currently a heated debate about the nature and origins of metacognition. Some maintain that reading others minds is done using a true
and proper Theory of Mind (ToM), which gets developed from an innate
brain module (Leslie, 1994); others that this skill is essentially interpersonal and depends on how an infant interacts with caregivers right from
birth (Carpendale & Lewis, 2004; Tomasello, Carpenter, Call, Behne, &
Moll, 2005). The existence of the so-called mirror neurons supports the
interpersonal hypothesis. Mirror neurons get activated both when individuals are about to perform an action, and when they see the same emotion
or behavior activated in conspecifics (see Gallese & Lakoff for a review of
this topic). As a result, the understanding of others does not need to be
based on ToM for them to be represented in our minds in part as if they
were ourselves. Despite the disagreements, several points appear to be
sound and empirically based (Semerari, Dimaggio, Nicolo`, Procacci, & Carcione, in press): (1) Specialized (Baron-Cohen et al., 1985; Tooby & Cosmides, 1992; Leslie, 1994; Murphy & Stich, 2000) mechanisms are re-

SELF-PATHOLOGY AND PERSONALITY DISORDERS

603

quired for psychological contents to be identified, processed, and integrated with other contents. For example, according to Nichols and Stich
(2001), detecting inner thoughts and reasoning on them are separate
skills. Detecting is the ability to identify specific mental contents in oneself. Reasoning is the ability to draw inferences about mental states and
processes. Ones reasoning skills are used in working out information
about both ones own mental states and others. In the opinion of Nichols
and Stich, the experiments by Gopnik and Slaughter (1991), with tasks
about understanding variations in desire, support the hypothesis that
there is an uncoupling between detecting and reasoning. For example,
three year old children are asked, before their snack time, whether they
want to eat. They normally reply yes. But if, after eating, they are asked
whether, at the time of the first question, they wanted to eat, they tend to
reply no, showing that they are basing themselves on their current desire
and are unaware of the variation therein. The authors interpretation is
that, while the identification of a current desire depends on a monitoring
mechanism, which is already working well at that age, the possibility of
recalling past desires and understanding variations depends on working
out and reasoning processes, which are not yet working at that age. (2)
Mechanisms involved in identifying and reasoning about states of mind
and solving problems related to them can be inadequate or defective due
to problems or lesions that to some extent are independent of the mental
contents that they are processing. For example, autistics are unable to
recognize all their own emotions and also find it difficult to identify their
own thoughts (Baron-Cohen, 1995). (3) An inability to identify states of
mind and reason about them has a negative impact on adaptation by
causing symptoms and interpersonal problems (Dimaggio et al., 2006;
Fonagy et al., 2002; Frith, 1992; Semerari et al., 2003b).
Several attempts have been made to apply these theories to clinical practice. As noted previously, autistics are thought to suffer from a serious
theory of mind deficit. Schizophrenics do not perceive their inner dialogues
as being their own (McGuire et al., 1995). Psychosomatic patients are limited in their descriptions of their emotions and, in particular, are poor at
perceiving what provokes them (Taylor, Bagby, & Parker, 1997). As regards
PD patients, our hypothesis is that they suffer from impaired metacognition, that the impairment is not uniform (Dimaggio, Semerari et al., in
press; Semerari et al., 2003, in press) and that for each PD there are different types of impairment. The malfunctioning ought to be less serious than
in autistics and psychotics; for example, no PD patient fails consistently
to identify his/her thoughts as being his/her own. Any dysfunctions ought
to also be very sensitive to trends in relationships, unlike in autistics and
psychotics, where the impairment is more constant and harder to rectify.
When there is a good emotional atmosphere, PD patients ought to display
problematic moments in relationships (Dimaggio, Semerari et al., in press;
Semerari, et al., 2003, in press). Better metacognition than in Ryle and
Kerr (2002) note that borderlines have poor self-reflective skills and thus

604

DIMAGGIO ET AL.

swing between one self-state and another. Fonagy and colleagues (2002)
observe how borderlines are poor at integrating multiple representations of
self with others, so that they swing chaotically between extreme emotional
states, and also have limited general self-reflective skills (Fonagy et al.,
2002). However, an analysis of psychotherapy transcripts of borderline patients during the first year of therapy using the Metacognition Assessment
Scale (Semerari et al., 2003b) showed that they are good at describing their
inner states but had difficulty integrating the changeable representations
that occur with relationships into coherent narratives and had some problems differentiating fantasy and reality (Semerari, Dimaggio, Nicolo`, Pedone, Procacci, & Carcione, 2005).
Narcissists are out of touch with their own inner states (they are alexithymic; Krystal, 1998), in particular the emotions connected with the activation of the attachment systemfragility, need for attention and so on
and the desires not integrated into the grandiose self (Bowlby, 1982;
Dimaggio, Semerari et al., 2006; Kohut, 1971; Jellema, 2000). They also
find it difficult to identify any external causes for their inner states (Kernberg, 1975). They display limited empathy, are egocentric in a Piagetian
sense and lack a well-developed theory of others mind (Benjamin, 1996;
Fiscalini, 1994; Westen, 1990). Similarly, although in a more serious form,
paranoids do not decenter cognitively. They systematically interpret others gestures and expressions as being ill-intentioned and always feel involved in a relationship (Nicolo` & Nobile, 2006). The personalities that
Westen & Shedler (2000) define as schizoid are poor at making sense of
others people behavior and have little psychological insight into their motives. These same authors consider low self-reflectivity to be typical of PDs
in general.
This theoretical, observational, and empirical information suggests that
PDs are characterized by malfunctionings in specific aspects of the ability
to construct integrated representations of ones own mental representations (metarepresentations; Semerari et al., 2003b). These malfunctionings interfere with interpersonal relationships, a core assumption in Livesleys definition. For example, narcissists are incapable of identifying their
own emotions and ascribing meaning to them, so that they do not consciously seek help when in difficulty. Others do not offer them the attention that they have not asked for but, at a pre-verbal level (spontaneous
activation of attachment), expect. As a consequence, relationships become
dysfunctional.

INTERPERSONAL SCHEMAS
Relationships are problematical if the cognitive structures guiding them
are dysfunctional. Life in a complex society is impossible without tools to
enable one to foresee how interactions will evolve, prescribe which behavior to adopt, proscribe behaviors to avoid, and provide a model of the other
person and his or her intentions towards the self. Interactive procedures

SELF-PATHOLOGY AND PERSONALITY DISORDERS

605

and rules for correct social interaction are also needed. These requirements are met by interpersonal schemas. People enter into relationships
based on structures formed by desires (motivations, goals), self-representations, representations of other and his or her intentions vis-a`-vis self,
and representations of the response self will make depending on others
response. Over the course of their lives, people develop a variety of such
schemas to fit different circumstances. These structures are termed: internal working models (Bowlby, 1982); representations of interactions that
have been generalized (Stern, 1985); interpersonal schemas (Baldwin,
1992; Safran & Muran, 2000); role-relationship models (Horowitz, 1998);
reciprocal role procedures (Ryle & Kerr, 2002); object relations (Fairbairn,
1952); and dialogical relationship patterns (Dimaggio, Fiore et al., 2006).
The rules or schemas develop out of relationships with others. People
look for relationships to meet ethologically determined needs such as being accepted, loved, protected, or admired, self-esteem, and so on. During
development, they create and store images of self (e.g., being undeserving
of love) and other (e.g., rejecting) around certain desires (being loved). Thus
schemas are formed with a structure such as If I ask others for love, given
that Im undeserving, they will reject me. If persons guided by such a
schema do not ask for love they are unlikely to obtain it. Nor will their
elusive attitude stimulate others to give them attention. Their idea about
being unlovable thus gets confirmed. To summarize, the schemas influence both behavior (given that I shall be rejected, I am not going to display
my desire to be loved) and others responses (Millon & Davis, 1996; Mitchell, 1988; Safran & Muran, 2000). To quote Livesley (2003):
The sequence of (1) a triggering situation evoking (2) basic schema that, in turn,
evoke (3) an experiential state, (4) behavioral response, (5) reciprocating responses from others, and (6) evaluation of outcome leading to confirmation of
the basic belief creates a cyclical interpersonal dynamic that is self-maintaining
and difficult to disrupt (p. 36).

Several authors hypothesize that it is possible to define PDs on the basis


of a general theory of human behavior in interpersonal relationships. For
Perris (1999), PDs are personality-based disorders of interpersonal behavior and he classifies PDs according to various attachment behavior subtypes. Along similar lines, interpersonal theory holds that: even the most
outrageous self-destructive behaviors can be seen as repetitions of patterns with important persons (Benjamin & Pugh, 2001). Empirically the
interpersonal model is good at defining PDs, except borderline, compulsive
and passive-aggressive Pds (Pincus & Wiggins, 1990). Livesley (2001) sees
this as a limitation in the use of interpersonal theory for classifying PDs
along with the fact that a description of interpersonal behavior alone does
not amount to a full personality psychopathology.
The fact that the circumplex model does not include all PDs is not a refutation of interpersonal theory. The approach is heuristically valid; There is
no substitute for the concept of interpersonal schema when defining not

606

DIMAGGIO ET AL.

only such patients relationships but also the processes that get activated
during the therapeutic relationship (Safran & Muran, 2000) that are especially likely to have a negative impact on therapy. However, a descriptive
approach is more useful than attempting to deducing which dimensions underlie every human interpersonal process from a general theory.
We need to identify which interpersonal schemas crop up during PD psychotherapy. Once the set of self-other schemas typical of each PD has been
traced, then it will be possible to build a general model of the alterations
in interpersonal behavior.
The authors from the Third Centre for Cognitive Psychotherapy have
noted that each PD has its own set of problematical interpersonal schemas
and that these can be picked out in narratives and in the therapeutic relationship. Their observations regard borderline, narcissistic, dependent,
avoidant and paranoid PDs and are based on a qualitative analysis of psychotherapy transcripts (Dimaggio, Semerari et al., 2006). For example, in
paranoid PD the dominant self-representation is the weak, inadequate and
fragile and the other is seen as ill-intentioned and ready to exploit ones
weaknesses. As a result, the behavior of paranoid individuals swings from
anticipatory counter-attacks, withdrawal from relationships, and dejection due to feeling that they can no longer tackle threats (see also Millon
& Davis, 1996; Stone, 1993). The fact that they have only a limited number
of schemas together with the negative reactions these provoke in others
leads patients to experience a limited number of self-states and miss opportunities to widen their self-knowledge. If their expectations prevent
them from noticing behavior by others not foreseen in their schemas, they
are unable to take advantage of new potentially adaptive experiences. For
example, by being unable to understand that another is offering help and
not attacking, they can not access the self-receiving-help representation.

DECISION-MAKING REASONING PROCESSES


People are continuously making choices in their personal and social domains. The time available (limited), the variables involved (many) and the
problem of comparing different types of elements make it impossible to
apply formal logic when calculating the costs and benefits of choices. Nevertheless, in the majority of cases these choices are essential to survival
and achieving goals. For this reason, people use reasoning strategies that
are automatic and rapidheuristics (Tversky & Kahneman, 1974)which,
even if imprecise, provide them with an adequate level of expertise in their
actions.
Normal reasoning can not therefore be compared to one complying with
formal logic. Baron (2000) pragmatically proposes that good thinking is
the sort by which people are able to achieve their goals. According to this
theory good reasoners need to: a. formulate several alternative hypotheses;
b. look for definitive answers and not limit themselves to looking for data
consistent with the focal hypothesis they are trying to demonstrate; c.

SELF-PATHOLOGY AND PERSONALITY DISORDERS

607

make an optimum use of their time, resources and energies for stages a.
and b., and d. feel fully confident in the credibility of their conclusions.
Examples of reasoning pathology include, for example, inadequate reviewing of the facts, concentrating only on the focal hypothesis and not
the alternatives, and thinking too much. Heuristics are considered a
sound strategy because they render timely decision-making possible when
the information available is limited. Pathological reasoning is systematically of the pseudo-diagnostic type, with an evaluation limited to a focal
hypothesis and the ignoring of any data refuting it (Johnson-Laird, Mancini, & Gangemi, in press). On the other hand, true diagnostic reasoning
takes account of alternative hypotheses and looks for data refuting a focal
hypothesis. Heuristics do not correspond to the cognitive errors or irrational beliefs Beck (1976) or, in general, the standard Cognitive Behavior
Therapy (CBT), talks about. As regards the large majority of the results of
human thought, it is impossible to establish whether they are right or
wrong. The important question is whether a reasoning strategy facilitates
or hampers adaptation and whether people adopt it when appropriate or
use it systematically even when it would be best not to (Baron, 2000).
Overestimating danger may, for example, save ones life (Gilbert, 2002),
but if this leads one to always ascribe threatening intentions to others,
ones relational life will be very poor and affect quality constantly negative.
People make wide use of heuristics for example, in determining their
value, self-enhance (Rosenberg, 1965; Taylor & Brown, 1988). The pathology may feature formally correct reasoning; in fact depressives tend towards a realistic self-evaluation (Alloy, 1988). Certain types of heuristic
and the abuse thereof are linked to the pathology.
Better safe then sorry strategies are a widespread form of heuristic
(Gilbert, 2002; Smeets, De Jong, & Mayer, 2000). People tend to overestimate danger in the belief that it is better not to run even a limited risk
than to face a possibility, however slim, of an event that is judged to be
highly dangerous taking place. People tend, on the other hand, to ignore
that choosing to not run a limited risk also has harmful consequences
(which is in fact the case because by not running risks one can not achieve
goals) (Mancini & Gangemi, 2001). Pseudo-diagnostic reasoning leads hypochondriacs to use confirmation bias: considering only data confirming
a focal hypothesis (Im seriously ill) and ignoring those disproving it (De
Jong, Mayer, & Van den Hout, 1997; Salkovskis, 1989).
Depressives tend to confirmation bias for their pessimistic beliefs (Panzarella, Alloy, Abramson, & Klein, 1999). Obsessive patients focus on the
hypothesis that they could cause harm to themselves or others. Normal
individuals put in an experimental situation of inflated responsibility tend
to use quasi-obsessive heuristics (Ladoucer, Rheaume, Freeston, Aublet,
Jean, Lachance, Langlois, & De Pokomandy-Morin, 1995) and to make
choices of the risk-adverse type (Mancini & Gangemi, 2002). Anxiety disorders involve mainly so-called ex-consequentia reasoning, which can be
summed up by the formula: If I feel anxious, there must be a danger

608

DIMAGGIO ET AL.

(Arntz, Rauner, & Van den Hout, 1995). Social phobics use heuristics of
the better safe then sorry type (Gilbert, 2002).
As well as reasoning processes, choices are also influenced by the information source that one selects. Emotions, for example, are a rapid form of
decision-making reasoning (Frijda, 1986; Oatley & Johnson-Laird, 1987;
Lazarus, 1966). They are so indispensable that when brain injuries hamper the ability to feel complex emotions (e.g., guilt or shame), people are
unable to make choices and their social life deteriorates (Damasio, 1994).
Given that dysfunctional reasoning is well documented in Axis I disorders, it is surprizing that there are few reports on dysfunctional reasoning
in the PDs. However, the little research reported has yielded interesting
results. Paranoids adopt better safe then sorry strategies when they feel
attacked by hostile human groups (Gilbert, 2002). It has been shown in
experiments (John & Robins, 1994; Pauhlus, 1998) and observed clinically
(Dimaggio et al., 2002) that narcissists use self-enhancement strategies to
a greater degree than normal. Narcissistic self-enhancers take credit for
success but externalize or discount failures (Rhodewalt & Morf, 1998).
They also respond to threats to self-esteem by disengaging from tasks that
were previously very important (Sedikides & Strube, 1997). In a population
of college students, those with a strong narcissistic trait tended to overestimate their academic ability, make self-serving attributions about their academic performance, disengage from the academic context when they realized that their results did not correspond to their initial, high, expectations
and show a tendency towards the end of their college courses to view results as less important (Robins & Beer, 2001). Narcissists do not heed
their inner states and let themselves be guided solely by reasoning. They
pursue life goals reinforcing their grandiose self without satisfying other
desires (Dimaggio et al., 2002; Kohut, 1971; Lowen, 1983).
Similarly, avoidant, dependent and borderline patients tend to: a. expect
there to be few satisfactions both now and in the future; b. ask for a lot of
information; c. use mainly rules to interrupt any losses rapidly; d. enjoy
any gains to a lesser extent than normal (Leahy, 2002). Paranoids, on the
other hand, feature low self-efficacy, get easily discouraged and are cautious in the face of change. Summing up, even if the research on PDs is at
an initial stage, we know enough to be able to hypothesize that: PD patients reasoning uses a series of heuristics, some of them similar to those
of non-patients or Axis-I patients, and others typical of PD patients or,
at least, more intense in these than in other populations, e.g., high selfenhancement. PD patients probably also, unlike normal individuals, use
heuristics more pervasively and inappropriately, whereas non-patients
make a more limited use of them and know to change reasoning strategy
when they see that the current one is not working. Probably as a result of
this pervasive use of heuristics patients fail at self-regulation and tend to
experience negative self-states, as occurs in paranoids, who overestimate
danger and, as a result, find it impossible to live in society without terrible
conflicts and a devastating sense of anger or low self-efficacy.

SELF-PATHOLOGY AND PERSONALITY DISORDERS

609

PATHOLOGICAL PERSONALITY ORGANIZATION


So far we have listed those individual aspects of the self that we hypothesize are problematical in PDs, but a list of the problematical elements does
not amount to a full description of self pathology. The main point is that a
personality consists of a cohesive organisation of elements (Allport, 1937;
Cervone & Shoda, 1999; Dimaggio, Semerari et al., in press; Guidano &
Liotti, 1983; Livesley, 2003; McAdams, 1997) and the idea of organization
would get lost with a description based solely on interactions between separate traits (Maffei, 2002). It is not moreover an established fact that similar groupings of elements systematically give rise in turn to the same personality profiles. We shall clarify what we mean with the language from
the Five Factor Model (FFM; Costa & Widiger, 1994; Widiger, 2000): will a
combination of high conscientiousness and low attractiveness automatically take the form of obsessive-compulsive personality disorder? The most
reasonable answer is No; perhaps such a person is simply scrupulous
and shy. To perceive how a person works it is essential to understand what
processes connect his/her reasoning style to his/her expectations about
how others will respond, and how he/she is able to perceive by what affects and personal history he/she is driven in his/her actions. FFM does
not furnish this type of description.
Moreover, the same personality components can give rise to different
phenomena, depending on the elements with which they interact. Let us
imagine a woman whose dominant life theme in her self-narratives is feeling threatened by others. If she has a well-developed theory of mind (ability
to decenter), she should be able to deduce from others facial expressions
and behavior that in many cases there is no reason to be afraid. If she
lacks this skill, she will probably be paranoid. This example shows how
effective metacognition protects against pathology even when there is a
problematical life theme. Not having these skills has a decisive role in developing a disorder. To explain pathological personality it is necessary to
take account of both any damaged elements and the way these elements
interact. We need to understand, for example, how a state of mind influences reasoning strategies and activates particular interpersonal schemas
and how these schemas lead to behaviors that lead others to act in a particular way. Furthermore, we also need to understand how the effects of
maladaptive interpersonal processes activated by the schema are modulated (if at all) by metacognitive skills. Suppose the paranoid woman mentioned earlier has to work in a group. Her dominant life theme gets expressed in thoughts such as: Youre fragile. Others are going to take
advantage of you. You should be on the alert. This schema leads to a
threatened state of mind. In this state her narrative continues with an
inner dialogue such as: Your colleagues have hostile intentions. Watch
how they behave and be quick to note every sign of aggression however
small otherwise you could end up paying for it. Decide whether to back off
or counter-attack. Dont let the others know anything about you that they
might be able to use to their advantage. At this point, our paranoid person

610

DIMAGGIO ET AL.

is using pseudo-diagnostic reasoning in which she considers only her focal


hypothesis and disregards any conflicting evidence. Moreover, her wary
and mistrusting attitude is likely to provoke irritation in others thus confirming her in her belief that she is threatened. If she had a well-developed
theory of mind, she would realize that a colleagues smile signifies an offer
of help rather than an attempt to deceive her but she lacks such metacognitive skills and so is unable to change her problematical state of mind.
This example shows how Paranoid PD is not the result of a particular
dysfunctional element: the fear of threat thought theme is not sufficient
to explain the syndrome nor is the inability to decenter and differentiate.
Borderline individuals also feel threatened and narcissistic individuals do
not decenter. It is the combination and interaction of elements that leads
to a recognizable paranoid personality profile. Similarly, narcissists central life theme could be the need to keep up a grandiose self-image. At the
same time, they have another more fragile self-image that causes them to
feel threatened when others fail to support the grandiose one. This attitude
leads them to either show off their qualities or protect themselves with
aggressive self-defence, substance abuse or disengagement from tasks
that were previously important, in order to protect self-esteem from expected failures. Seized by their search for perfection, narcissists do not
spend time on activities that are simply enjoyable or in tune with their
wishes rather than their ambitions. As a result their experience remains
limited. At the same time, for fear of showing their fragile side, they avoid
asking for help and this prevents them from benefiting from others support when this is needed. A narcissists grandiose attitude and silent but
continuing need for reassurance are likely to evoke in others either rivalry
or the feeling that they are not receiving attention from him. This activates
an interpersonal cycle in which both participants feel disappointed and
hurt. The negative interaction and hurt are likely to be obstacles to the
use of metacognition that could help to disrupt the cycle. When the narcissist feels hurt, he is unlikely to notice signs of weariness and annoyance
in others or consider them important. When comparing narcissists and
paranoids, it is clear that the two function very differently even though a
number of elements are similar (both are prone to feeling attacked and are
unable to decenter, that is read others minds without thinking that their
thoughts refer systematically to oneself). The differences between the two
disorders lie in the interaction between dysfunctional elements.

DISCUSSION AND CONCLUSIONS


We have shown that the self is impaired in various ways in PDs. Patients
possess problematical self-states, inadequate self-representations and restricted self-narratives, and poor self-reflection and self-regulatory strategies. The model of the self expounded in this article has several advantages. First, it is founded on wide range of empirical, observational, and
research data. For example, ideas about heuristics and reasoning pro-

SELF-PATHOLOGY AND PERSONALITY DISORDERS

611

cesses and the Theory of Mind in general and metacognition in particular,


are solidly supported by empirical research. This provides a solid rationale
for extending these ideas to PD. Second, the model is expressed in a language easily understood by clinicians and portrays patients mental contents and functions in a manner is close to their subjective experience.
This makes it easy for patients to understand the idea of states of mind
and the thoughts and emotions that form their dominant states. The same
applies to interpersonal schemas and reasoning strategies. This is an advantage over other descriptive theories like the Five Factor Model.
Third, it integrates dimensionalindispensable in describing personality from an empirical point of view and in terms of relations with a normal
personality (Livesley, 2001, 2003)and categorical models of personality.
For example, a malfunction in metacognition that enable one to identify
ones inner states, label them as emotional, and link them to events in
ones environment (alexithymia) has trait-like properties and is dimensional (Taylor et al., 1997). On the other hand, an interaction of dysfunctional elements leads to particular types of malfunctioning that are welldefined categories.
Fourth, the model embraces the overall properties of a system and tries
to provide an account of the rules governing transitions between different
aspects of the self. For example, we hypothesize that in narcissistic personalities wounds to self-esteem promote a transition from grandiosity to
acting-out with activation of self-enhancement heuristics. If clinicians are
to intervene, they need information on the rules governing transitions
among self-states and on the links between the interpersonal context and
state of mind. Radically dimensional theories fail to define and explain
transitions between states, the rules guiding them and the triggers setting
them off.
Despite these advantages, the model has several limitations. First, although there is evidence for some components, many aspects of the model
remain speculative. For example, heuristics specific to the various PDs are
relatively unexplored and there is only modest empirical evidence for specific states of mind associated with each PD. We hypothesize that there
are no states specific to one disorder. What distinguishes one category
from another and PD patients from nonpatients is the combination of
states and how transitions occur between them (Dimaggio et al., 2005,
Dimaggio, Fiore, Lysaker et al., 2006). For example, a diffident state is
common to normal individuals, narcissists and paranoids. Our hypothesis
is that normal individuals experience it when required by the context, narcissists when they feel a threat to their self-esteem and react by detaching
from relationships (He hasnt promoted me at work because hes corrupt
and he doesnt deserve my company) and paranoids almost always, with
their reaction being anger aimed at righting the wrongs they have suffered.
Second, testing these ideas would be difficult and time consuming. It is
necessary in analysis of the psychotherapeutic process to evaluate which
schemas and interpersonal cycles get activated in a therapeutic relation-

612

DIMAGGIO ET AL.

ship, which metacognitive skill profiles are typical of each PD (if this is the
case), and how therapy can help patients to improve these skills. It requires single case designs that are costly and time-consuming. Moreover,
it involves organizational aspects, for example, the processes bringing
about transitions, that it is difficult to verify empirically. However, when it
is not possible to induce laws, collect empirical data or calculate algorithms, sciences (i.e., biology) make ample use of models defining how any
observed phenomena are regulated by general principles. Cosmology and
the theory of evolution have had to face problems like this but this has not
resulted in them dying out.
Overall, the elements listed and the links between them seem to have
the right characteristics for being a good description of the self pathology
to be found in Livesleys definition of PD where we started out. The model
we have expounded explains how individuals fail in: a. integrating multiple
representations of self and other (metacognitive dysfunctions hamper
uniting states of mind and images of self with other); b. interpersonal adaptation (interpersonal schemas leading to problematical behavior and
generating actions that alienate others); and c. social functioning (interpersonal schemas again and the heuristics used leading them to make
negative and detrimental choices). In spite of the limitations and partly
speculative nature of the approach described, we believe that it is sufficiently well-grounded to be considered a scientific hypothesis worth discussion and investigation.
REFERENCES
Alloy, L. B. (Ed.). (1988). Cognitive processes
in depression. New York: Guilford.
American Psychiatric Association. (2000).
Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of
Mental Disorders. 4th edition. DSMIV-TR. Washington, DC: American
Psychiatric Association.
Angus, L., & McLeod, J. (Eds.). (2004). The
handbook of narrative and psychotherapy: Practice, theory and research.
Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Allport, G. W. (1937). Personality: A psychological interpretation. New York:
Holt.
Applebaum, S. A. (1973). Psychologicalmindedness: Word, concept and essence. International Journal of Psychoanalysis, 54, 3545.
Arntz, A., Rauner, M., & Van den Hout, M.
(1995). If I feel anxious there must be
dangers: Ex-consequentia reasoning
in inferring danger in anxiety disorder.
Behaviour Research and Therapy, 33,
917925.

Bakthin, M. (1984). Problems of Dostoevskys


poetics. Minneapolis, MN: University of
Minnesota Press. (Original publication
date 1929)
Baldwin, M. W. (1992). Relational schemas
and the processing of social information. Psychological Bulletin, 112, 461
484.
Baron, J. (2000). Thinking and deciding. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Baron-Cohen, S. (1995). Mindblindness. An
essay on autism and theory of mind.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Baron-Cohen, S., Leslie, A., & Frith, U.
(1985). Does the autistic child have a
theory of mind? Cognition, 21, 3746.
Baumeister, R., & Leary, M. (1995). The need
to belong: Desire for interpersonal attachment as a fundamental human
motivation. Psychological Bullettin, 117,
497529.
Beck, A. T. (1976). Cognitive therapy and the
emotional disorders. New York: International University Press.

SELF-PATHOLOGY AND PERSONALITY DISORDERS


Benjamin, L. S. (1996). Interpersonal Diagnosis and Treatment of Personality Disorders, 2nd edition. New York: Guilford.
Benjamin, L. S., & Pugh, C. (2001). Using interpersonal theory to select effective
treatment interventions. In W. J. Livelsey (Ed.), Handbook of personality
disorders, (pp. 414436). New York:
Guilford.
Bennett, D., Pollock, P., & Ryle, A. (2005).
The States Description Procedure: The
use of guided introspection in the case
formulation of patients with Borderline Personality Disorder. Clinical Psychology and Psychotherapy, 12, 5057.
Bowlby, J. (1982). Attachment and Loss. Vol.
I (2nd. Ed.). London: Hogarth Press.
(Original publication date 1969)
Cantor, N. (1990). From thought to behavior:
Having and doing in the study of
personality and cognition. American
Psychologist, 45, 735750.
Carpendale, J.I.M., & Lewis, C. (2004). Constructing an understanding of mind:
The development of childrens social
understanding within social interaction. Behavioral and Brain Sciences,
27, 79151.
Cervone, D., & Shoda, Y. (1999). Socialcognitive theory and the coherence of
personality. In D. Cervone & Y. Shoda
(Eds.), The coherence of personality
(pp. 133). New York: Guilford.
Clarkin, J. F. (2005). Conceptualization and
treatment of personality disorders.
Psychotherapy Research, 16, 111.
Conte, H. R., Plutchik, R., Jung, B. B., Picard, S., Karasu, T. B., & Lotterman,
A. (1990). Psychological mindedness
as a predictor of psychotherapy outcome: A preliminary report. Comprehensive Psychiatry, 31, 426431.
Conway, M. A., & Pleydell-Pearce, C. W.
(2000). The construction of autobiographical memories in the self-memory system. Psychological Review, 107,
261288.
Costa, P. T. Jr., & Widiger, T. A. (Eds.).
(1994). Personality disorders and the
five factor model of personality. Washington, DC: American Psychological
Association.
Cottraux, J., & Blackburn, I. (2001). Cognitive Therapy. In W. J. Livesley (Ed.),
Handbook of Personality Disorders (pp.
377399). New York: Guilford.
Damasio, A. R. (1994). Descartess error:

613

Emotion, reason and the human brain.


New York: Grosset/Putnam.
De Jong, P. J., Mayer, B., & Van den Hout,
M. (1997). Conditional reasoning and
phobic fears: Evidence for a fearconfirming reasoning. Behaviour Research and Therapy, 35, 507516.
Dennett, D. C. (1991). Consciousness explained. London: Little, Brown & Co.
Dimaggio, G., Carcione, A., Petrilli, M., Procacci, M., Semerari, A., & Nicolo`, G.
(2005). States of mind organization in
personality disorders. Typical states
and the triggering of inter-state shifts.
Clinical Psychology and Psychotherapy, 12, 346359.
Dimaggio, G., Nicolo`, G., Popolo, R., Semerari, A., & Carcione, A. (2006). Selfregulatory dysfunctions in personality
disorders: The role of poor self-monitoring and mindreading. Applied Psychology: An International Review, 55,
397407.
Dimaggio, G., Semerari, A., Carcione, A.,
Nicolo`, G., & Procacci, M. (2006). Psychotherapy of personality disorder:
Metacognition, states of mind and interpersonal cycles. London: Routledge.
Dimaggio, G., Semerari, A., Falcone, M.,
Nicolo`, G., Carcione, A., & Procacci, M.
(2002). Metacognition, states of mind,
cognitive biases and interpersonal cycles. Proposal for an integrated model
of Narcissism. Journal of Psychotherapy Integration, 12, 421451.
Dimaggio, G., Fiore, D., Lysaker, P. H.,
Petrilli, D., Salvatore, G., Semerari, A.,
& Nicolo`, G. (2006). Early transference
patterns in narcissistic personality
disorder: A single case explorator
study from the perspective of dialogical self theory. Psychology and Psychotherapy: Theory, Research and Practice.
Fairbairn, R.W.D. (1952). Psychoanalytic
Studies of the Personality. London:
Tavistock/Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Fiscalini, J. (1994). Narcissism and coparticipant inquiry: Explorations in contemporary interpersonal psychoanalysis.
Contemporary Psychoanalysis, 30,
747776.
Flavell, J. H., Miller, P. H., & Miller, S. A.
(1993). Cognitive development. Hemel
Hempsted: Prentice Hall International.
Fonagy, P., Gergely, G., Jurist, E. L., & Target, M. (2002). Affect regulation, men-

614
talization, and the development of the
self. New York: Other Press.
Frith, C. D. (1992). The cognitive neuropsychology of schizoprenia. Hove: Erlbaum.
Frijda, N. H. (1986). The Emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Gazzaniga, M. S. (1988). The dynamics of cerebral specialization and modular interactions. In L. Weiskrantz (Ed.),
Thought without language (pp. 430
450). Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press.
Gallese, V., & Lakoff, G. (2005). The brains
concepts: The role of the sensorymotor system in reason and language.
Cognitive Neuropsychology, 22, 455
479.
Gilbert, P. (2002). Evolutionary approaches
to psychopathology and cognitive therapy. Journal of Cognitive Psychotherapy, 16, 263294.
Golynkina, K., & Ryle, A. (1999). The identification and characteristics of the partially dissociated states of patients
with borderline personality disorder.
British Journal of Medical Psychology,
9, 429445.
Goncalves, O. F., & Machado. P. P. (1999).
Cognitive narrative psychotherapy:
Research Foundations. Journal of Clinical Psychology, 55, 11791191.
Gopnik, A., & Slaughter, V. (1991). Young
children understanding of changes in
their mental states. Child Development, 62, 98110.
Guidano, V. F., & Liotti, G. (1983). Cognitive
processes and emotional disorders.
New York: Guilford.
Habermas, T., & Bluck, S. (2000). Getting a
life: The emergence of the life story in
adolescence. Psychological Bulletin, 126,
748769.
Hermans, H.J.M. (1996). Voicing the self:
From information processing to dialogical interchange. Psychological Bulletin, 119, 3150.
Hermans, H.J.M., & Dimaggio G. (Eds.).
(2004). The dialogical self in psychotherapy. London: Brunner-Routledge.
Hermans, H.J.M., & Hermans-Jansen, E.
(1995). Self-narratives: The construction of meaning in psychotherapy. New
York: Guilford Press.
Higgins, E. T., & Bargh, J. A. (1987). Social
cognition and social perception. Annual
Review of Psychology, 38, 369425.
Horowitz, M. J. (1998). Cognitive psychodinamics: From conflict to character. New
York: Wiley.

DIMAGGIO ET AL.
Jellema, A. (2000). Insecure attachment
states: Their relationship to borderline
and narcissistic personality disorders
and treatment process in cognitive analytic therapy. Clinical Psychology and
Psychotherapy, 7, 138154.
John, O. P., & Robins, R. W. (1994). Accuracy and bias in self-perception: Individual differences in self-enhancement
and the role of narcissism. Journal of
Personality and Social Psychology, 66,
206219.
Johnson-Laird, P. N., Mancini, F., & Gangemi,
A. (in press). A hyper-emotion theory
of psychological illnesses. Psychological Review.
Kelly, G. (1955). The psychology of personal
constructs. New York: Norton.
Kernberg, O. F. (1975). Borderline conditions
and pathological narcissism. Northvale, NJ: Aronson.
Kohut, H. (1971). The analysis of the self.
New York: International University
Press.
Krystal, H. (1998). Affect regulation and narcissism: Trauma, alexithymia and psychosomatic illness in narcissistic patients. In E. F. Ronningstam (Ed.),
Disorders of narcissism: Diagnostic,
clinical, and empirical implications (pp.
299326). New York: American Psychiatric Press.
Ladoucer, R., Rheaume, J., Freeston, M. H.,
Aublet, F., Jean, K., Lachance, S.,
Langlois F., & De Pokomandy-Morin,
K. (1995). Experimental manipulations of responsibility: An analogue
test for models of obsessive-compulsive disorder. Behaviour Research and
Therapy, 33, 937946.
Lazarus, R. S. (1966). Psychological stress
and the coping process. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Leahy, R. L. (2002). Decision making and
personality disorders. Journal of Cognitive Psychotherapy: An International
Quarterly, 16, 209225.
Leslie, A. M. (1987). Pretense and representation: The origin of theory of mind.
Psychological Review, 94, 412426.
Leslie, A. M. (1994). ToMM, ToBy, and
Agency: Core architecture and domain
specificity. In L. Hirschfeld & S. Gelman
(Eds.), Mapping the mind: Domain specificity in cognition and culture. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.
Livesley, W. J. (1998). Suggestions for a
framework for an empirically based

SELF-PATHOLOGY AND PERSONALITY DISORDERS


classification of personality disorder.
Canadian Journal of Psychiatry, 43,
137147.
Livesley, W. J., & Jang, K. L. (2000). Toward
an empirically based classification of
personality disorders. Journal of Personality Disorders, 14, 137151.
Livesley, W. J. (2001). Conceptual and taxonomic issues. In W. J. Livelsey (Ed.),
Handbook of personality disorders (pp.
338). New York: Guilford.
Livesley, W. J. (2003). Practical management
of personality disorders. New York:
Guilford.
Livesley, W. J., & Jang, K. L. (2000). Toward
an empirically based classification of
personality disorders. Journal of Personality Disorders, 14, 137151.
Lowen, A. (1983). On narcissism. Denial of
the true self. New York: Mac Millan.
Luborsky, L., Barber, J. P., & Diguer, L.
(1992). The meaning of narratives told
during psychotherapy: The fruits of a
new observational unit. Psychotherapy
Research, 2, 277290.
Luborsky, L., & Crits-Christoph, P. (Eds.).
(1990). Understanding transference:
The CCRT Method. New York: Basic
Books.
Maffei, C. (2002). Personalita` e sviluppo. In
C. Maffei, M. Battaglia, & A. Fossati,
Personalita`, sviluppo e psicopatologia
(pp. 359). Roma-Bari: Laterza.
Mancini, F., & Gangemi, A. (2002). Role of responsibility in conditional reasoning.
Psychological Reports, 91, 275288.
Markus, H., & Nurius, P. (1986). Possible
selves. American Psychologist, 41,
954969.
McAdams, D. P. (1994). Can personality
change? Levels of stability and growth
in personality across the life span. In
T. F. Heatherton & J. K. Weinberger
(Eds.), Can personality change? (pp.
299313). Washington, DC: American
Psychological Association.
McAdams, D. P. (1997). A conceptual history
of personality psychology. In R. Hogan,
J. Johnson, & S. Briggs (Eds.), Handbook of personality psychology (pp. 3
39). San Diego, CA: Academic Press.
McAdams, D. P. (1999). Personal narratives
and the life story. In L. Pervin and O.
John (Eds.), Handbook of personality:
Theory and research (2nd Ed., pp.
478500). New York: Guilford.
McGuire, P. K., Silbersweig, D. A., Wright, I.,
Murray R. M., David, A. S., Fracko-

615

wiak, R.S.J., & Frith, C. D. (1995) Abnormal monitoring of inner speech: A


physiological basis for auditory hallucinations. Lancet, 2, 596600.
Millon, T., & Davis, R. D. (1996). Disorders of
personality. DSM-IV and beyond.
Chichester: Wiley.
Mitchell, S. A. (1988). Relational concepts in
psychoanalysis. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Muran, J. C. (2001). An introduction: Contemporary constructions and contexts.
In J. C. Muran (Ed.), Self-relations in
psychotherapy (pp. 341). Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Association Press.
Murphy, D., & Stich, S. (2000). Darwin in the
madhouse: Evolutionary psychology
and the classification of mental disorders. In P. Carruthers & A. Chamberlain (Eds.), Evolution and the human
mind. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.
Neimeyer, R. A. (2000). Narrative disruptions
in the construction of the self. In R. A.
Neimeyer & J. D. Raskin (Eds.), Constructions of disorder (pp. 207241).
Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Association Press.
Neimeyer, R. A., & Feixas, G. (1990). Constructivistic Contribution to Psychotherapy Integration. Journal of Integrative and Eclectic Psychotherapy, 9,
420.
Neisser, U. (1976). Cognition and reality. San
Francisco: Freeman.
Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2001). Mindreading.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Nicolo`, G., & Nobile, M. S. (2006). Paranoid
personality disorder: Model and treatment. In G. Dimaggio & A. Semerari,
with A. Carcione, G. Nicolo`, & M. Procacci (Eds.), Psychotherapy of personality disorders: Metacognition, states of
mind, and interpersonal cycles. London: Routledge.
Oatley, K., & Johnson Laird, P. N. (1987). Towards a cognitive theory of emotions.
Cognition and Emotion, 1, 2950.
Osatuke, K., Glick, M. J., Gray, M. A., &
Stiles W. B. (2004). Hearing voices:
Methodological issues in measuring
internal multiplicity. In H.J.M. Hermans & G. Dimaggio (Eds.), The dialogical self in psychotherapy (pp. 237
254). London: Brunner-Routledge.
Panzarella, C., Alloy, L. B., Abramson, L. Y.,
& Klein, K. (1999). Cognitive contribu-

616
tions to mental illness and mental
health. In F. T. Durso, R. S. Nickerson,
R. W. Schvaneveldt, S. T. Dumais,
D. S. Lindsay, & M.T.H. Chi (Eds.),
Handbook of applied cognition. New
York: Wiley.
Paulhus, D. L. (1998). Interpersonal and
intrapsychic adaptiveness of trait selfenhancement: A mixed blessing? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 74, 11971208.
Perris, C. (1999). A conceptualization of personality-related disorders of interpersonal behaviour with implications for
treatment. Clinical Psychology and
Psychotherapy, 6, 239260.
Piaget, J. (1964). Six etudes de psychologie.
Paris: Gonthier, Mediations.
Pincas, A. L., & Wiggins, J. S. (1990). Interpersonal problems and conceptions of
personality disorders. Journal of Personality Disorders, 4, 342352.
Rhodewalt, F., & Morf, C. C. (1998). On selfaggrandizement and anger: A temporal
analysis of narcissism and affective reactions to success and failure. Journal
of Personality and Social Psychology,
74, 672685.
Rosenberg, M. (1965). Society and the adolescent self-image. Princeton: Princeton
University Press.
Robins, R. W., & Beer, J. S. (2001). Positive
illusions about the self. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 80,
340352.
Ryle, A., & Kerr, I. (2002). Introducing cognitive analytic therapy. Principles and
practice. Chichester: Wiley.
Safran, J. D., & Muran, J. C. (2000). Negotiating the therapeutic alliance. A relational treatment guide. New York: Guilford.
Salkovskis, P. M. (1989). Cognitive-behavioural factors and the persistence of
intrusive thoughts in obsessional
problems. Behaviour Therapy and Research, 27, 677682.
Salvatore, G., Dimaggio, G., & Semerari, A.
(2004). A model of narrative development: Implications for understanding
psychopathology and guiding therapy.
Psychology and Psychotherapy, 1,
125.
Salvatore, G., Nicolo`, G., & Dimaggio, G.
(2005). Impoverished dialogical relationship patterns in paranoid personality disorder. American Journal of
Psychotherapy, 59, 247265.

DIMAGGIO ET AL.
Sarbin, T. R. (1986). The narrative as a root
metaphor for psychology. In T. R. Sarbin (Ed.), Narrative psychology: The
storied nature of human conduct (pp.
127). New York : Praeger.
Sedikides, C., & Strube, M. J. (1997). Selfevaluation: To thine own self be good,
to thine own self be sure, to thine own
self be true, and to thine own self be
better. In M. P. Zanna (Ed.), Advances
in experimental social psychology (pp.
209269). New York: Academic Press.
Segal, Z. V. (1988). Appraisal of the self
schema: Construct in cognitive model
of depression. Psychological Bulletin,
103, 147162.
Semerari, A., Carcione, A., Dimaggio, G., Falcone, M., Nicolo`, G., Procacci, M., &
Alleva, G. (2003a). How to evaluate
metacognitive funtioning in psychotherapy? The Metacognition Assessment Scale and its applications. Clinical Psychology and Psychotherapy, 10,
238261.
Semerari, A., Carcione, A., Dimaggio, G., Falcone, M., Nicolo`, G., Procacci, M.,
Alleva, G., & Mergenthaler, E. (2003b).
Assessing problematic states inside
patients narratives. The Grid of problematic conditions. Psychotherapy Research, 13, 337353.
Semerari, A., Dimaggio, G., Nicolo`, G., Pedone, R., Procacci, M., & Carcione, A.
(2006). Metarepresentative functions
in borderline personality disorders.
Journal of Personality Disorders, 19,
690710.
Semerari, A., Dimaggio, G., Nicolo`, G., Procacci, M., & Carcione, A. (in press).
Understanding minds, different functions and different disorders? The contribution of psychotherapeutic research.
Psychotherapy Research.
Shedler, J., & Westen, D. (2004). Dimensions of personality pathology: An alternative to the Five Factor Model.
American Journal of Psychiatry, 161,
17431754.
Singer, J. A., & Bluck, S. (2001). New perspectives on autobiographical memory: The integration of narrative processing and autobiographical reasoning.
Review of General Psychology, 5,
9199.
Smeets, G., De Jong, P. J., & Mayer, B.
(2000). If you suffer from a headache,
than you have a brain tumor: Domain
specific reasoning bias and hypo-

SELF-PATHOLOGY AND PERSONALITY DISORDERS


chondriasis. Behaviour Research and
Therapy, 38, 763776.
Smith, C. A., & Lazarus, R. S. (1993). Appraisal components, Core Relational
Themes and the emotions. Cognition
and Emotion, 7, 233269.
Sperber, D. (Ed.). (2000). Metarepresentation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Stern, D. N. (1985). The interpersonal world
of the infant: A view from psychoanalysis and developmental psychology.
New York: Basic Books.
Stiles, W. B. (1999). Signs and voices in psychotherapy. Psychotherapy Research,
9, 121.
Stiles, W. B., Osatuke K., Glick, M. J., &
Mackay H. C. (2004). Encounters between internal voices generate emotion: An elaboration of the assimilation
model. In H.J.M. Hermans & G.
Dimaggio (Eds.), The dialogical self in
psychotherapy (pp. 91107). London:
Brunner-Routledge.
Stone, M. H. (1993). Abnormalities of personality. New York: Norton.
Taylor, G. J., Bagby, R. M., & Parker, J.D.A.
(1997). Disorders of affect regulation.
Alexithymia in medical and psychiatric
illness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Taylor, S. E., & Brown, J. D. (1988). Illusion
and well-being: A social psychological
perspective on mental health. Psychological Bulletin, 116, 193210.
Tickle, J. J., Heatherton, T. F., & Wittenberg,
L. G. (2001). Can personality change?
In W. J. Livelsey (Ed.), Handbook of
personality disorders (pp. 242258).
New York: Guilford.
Tomasello, M., Carpenter, M., Call, J., Behne, T., & Moll, H. (2005). Understanding and sharing intentions: The
origin of cultural cognition. Behavioral
and Brain Sciences, 28, 675691.
Tomkins, S. S. (1979). Script theory: Differential magnification of affects. In H. E.
Howe and R. A. Dienstbier (Eds.), Nebraska symposium on motivation, vol.
26 (pp. 201236). Lincoln: University
of Nebraska Press.
Tooby, J., & Cosmides, L. (1992). Psychological foundations of culture. In J. H.

617

Barkow, L. Cosmides, & J. Tooby


(Eds.), The adapted mind: Evolutionary
psychology and the generation of culture (pp. 19136). New York: Oxford
University Press.
Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1974). Judgement under uncertainty: Heuristics
and biases. Science, 185, 11241131.
Wakefield, J. C. (1992). Disorders as harmful
dysfunction: A conceptual critique of
DSM-III Rs definition of mental disorder. Psychological Review, 99, 232
247.
Westen, D. (1990). The relations among narcissism, egocentrism, self-concept and
self-esteem: Experimental, clinical and
theoretical considerations. Psychoanalysis and Contemporary Thought, 13,
183239.
Westen, D. (1997). Divergences between clinical and research methods for assessing personality disorders: Implications
for research and evolution of Axis II.
American Journal of Psychiatry, 154,
895903.
Westen, D. (1998). Case formulation and
personality diagnosis: Two processes
or one? In J. Barron (Ed.), Making diagnosis meaningful: Enhancing evaluation and treatment of psychological
disorders (pp. 111137). Washington,
DC: APA Press.
Westen, D., & Shedler, J. (2000). A prototype
matching approach to diagnosing personality disorders: Towards the DSMV. Journal of Personality Disorders, 14,
109126.
Widiger, T. A. (2000). Personality disorder in
the 21st century. Journal of Personality Disorders, 14, 316.
Winter, D. A. (1989). An Alternative Construction of Agoraphobia. In K. Button
(Ed.), Agoraphobia: Current perspective
on theory and treatment. London:
Routledge.
Young. J. E. (1990). Cognitive therapy for
personality disorders: A schema focused approach. Sarasota, FL: Professional Resource Exchange.
Zajonc, R. B. (1980). Feeling and thinking.
Preferences need no inferences. American Psychologist, 39, 117123.

You might also like