You are on page 1of 25

Internationales Jahrbuch

des Deutschen Idealismus


International Yearbook
of German Idealism
8 2010

Philosophie und Wissenschaft


Philosophy and Science

Herausgegeben von/edited by
Fred Rush (Notre Dame) und/and Jrgen Stolzenberg (Halle/S.)
Redaktion/Associate editors
Paul Franks (Toronto) und/and Lars-Thade Ulrichs (Halle/S.)
Wissenschaftlicher Beirat/Editorial Board
Karl Ameriks (Notre Dame), Andreas Arndt (Berlin), Manfred Baum (Wuppertal), Frederick C. Beiser (Syracuse), Robert Brandom (Pittsburgh), Daniel Breazeale (Lexington),
Rdiger Bubner (Heidelberg), Claudio Cesa (Pisa), Konrad Cramer (Gttingen), Klaus
Dsing (Kln), Michael N. Forster (Chicago), Eckart Frster (Baltimore), Manfred Frank
(Tbingen), Hans Friedrich Fulda (Heidelberg), Karen Gloy (Luzern), Henry S. Harris
(Toronto), Vittorio Hsle (Notre Dame), Rolf-Peter Horstmann (Berlin), Michael Inwood (Oxford), Wilhelm G. Jacobs (Mnchen), Jrg Jantzen (Mnchen), Walter Jaeschke
(Bochum), Salvi Turr (Barcelona), Charles Larmore (Chicago), Batrice Longuenesse
(New York), Frederick Neuhouser (New York), Robert B. Pippin (Chicago), Claude
Pich (Montreal), Terry Pinkard (Georgetown), Alain Renaut (Paris), Michael Rosen
(Oxford), Birgit Sandkaulen (Jena), Hans-Jrg Sandkhler (Bremen), Dieter Schnecker
(Siegen), Ludwig Siep (Mnster), Pirmin Stekeler-Weithofer (Leipzig), Dieter Sturma
(Essen), Charles Taylor (Montreal), Violetta L. Waibel (Wien), Michael Wolff (Bielefeld),
Allen W. Wood (Stanford), Gnter Zller (Mnchen)

De Gruyter

Online-Zugang fr Subskribenten/Online access for subscribers:


http://www.degruyter.de/journals/ijbdi

ISSN 1613-0472
ISBN 978-3-11-022285-2 (Br.)
ISBN 978-3-11-022286-9 (online)
ISBN 978-3-11-022287-6 (Br./online)

Bibliografische Information Der Deutschen Nationalbibliothek


Die Deutsche Nationalbibliothek verzeichnet diese Publikation in der Deutschen Nationalbibliografie; detaillierte bibliografische Daten sind im Internet ber <http://dnb.d-nb.de>
abrufbar.

2012 Walter de Gruyter GmbH & Co. KG, Berlin/Boston


Datenkonvertierung/Satz: Werksatz Schmidt & Schulz GmbH, Grfenhainichen
Gedruckt auf surefreiem Papier, das die US-ANSI-Norm ber Haltbarkeit erfllt.
Printed in Germany
www.degruyter.com

Gideon Freudenthal

Maimons Philosophical Program.


Understanding versus Intuition
Maimon entwickelt seine Philosophie anhand einer Analyse der Mathematik, die,
seiner Ansicht nach, das Beste an menschlicher Erkenntnis darstellt. Aber nicht
einmal die Mathematik gengt seinem Kriterium der Rationalitt, das in der Einsehbarkeit durch den Verstand und nicht in der Evidenz der Intuition oder Einbildungskraft besteht. Maimon versucht die Mathematik auf analytische Aussagen
zurckzufhren, und, wo sich dies als unmglich erweist, sie zumindest so zu formulieren, dass sie seinem synthetischen Kriterium gengen. Dieser Satz der Bestimmbarkeit unterscheidet reelle Synthesen von Kategorienfehlern. Beide Programme konnten ihr Ziel nicht erreichen, aber Maimon gab sein Kriterium der
Verstandeseinsicht nicht auf, sondern stellte einen unendlichen Fortschritt auf dieses Ziel hin in Aussicht.

1. The Argument
Maimons philosophy is imbued with mathematics. To him, only mathematics is
knowledge proper, and he develops his theses in discussion of mathematical
examples. However, even mathematics does not satisfy his criteria of rationality.1
Maimons main concern is intelligibility. His criterion of rationality is insight of the understanding as opposed to intuition and imagination. Intelligibility is specified to analytic and synthetic criteria, which form the bases for two
comprehensive philosophical programs, one of which is more demanding than
the other. The first criterion is logical truth, and the program consists in the
reduction of all synthetic propositions to analytical ones, concepts of substance
to concepts of function. The less demanding criterion was Maimons Principle
(or Law) of Determinability. The principle formulates the conditions of a real
synthesis. In real synthesis a new object is produced, from which new consequences follow, that follow neither from the original subject nor from the
predicate concepts alone, but only from their synthesis. Thus a triangle has certain consequences (e. g., that the sum of its internal angles equals two right
angles), whereas the Pythagorean Theorem is a consequence of the synthesis of
triangle and right angle. This criterion does not dispense with intuition,

There have been a number of cursory discussions of Maimons philosophy of mathematics, but the only serious analysis is Lachterman, 1992.

84

Gideon Freudenthal

nor does it substitute analytic for synthetic judgments, but it accepts the (temporary) reality of synthetic judgments (a priori). Both criteria presuppose one
supreme concept from which they proceed either analytically or synthetically.
The central motif of Maimons philosophy is hence that proper knowledge
must be based on the understanding. Intuition is not only opaque to reason but
may also deceive us. Maimon learned this lesson from The Guide of the Perplexed of Maimonides, his early source of philosophical education. Maimonides discusses asymptotes. The imagination (or intuition) shows that these two lines
must intersect; the understanding proves that this is false. Which source of
knowledge do we trust, the imagination (or intuition) or the understanding? In
his commentary, Maimon emphasizes the prerogative of reason over imagination as that which alone establishes the preeminence of man over beasts, and
supplies three pages of discussion with a simplified version of Apollonius
proof accompanied by a diagram. He was evidently very proud of this proof,
mentioning it also in his Lebensgeschichte.2
Maimons philosophical program was not successful in either version.
Mathematics depends on axioms, postulates, and natural numbers, which are
not the product of the understanding but are imposed on us in intuition. He
therefore concludes that even mathematics is only subjectively necessary and
not objectively necessary and apodeictic. We thus have before us the following
hierarchy: pure logic is objective and apodeictic; arithmetic and, even more so,
geometry are subjectively necessary; mathematical physics is contingent; and
propositions dependent on perception (the surface is red) are not yet knowledge in this form.
The uniqueness of Maimons philosophy consists in upholding these criteria
of rationality, on the one hand, and claiming that they have not been met even
by the best of human knowledge, on the other. The gap between actual and ideal
knowledge is a permanent challenge and because it diminishes through the
progress of knowledge it is also a motivation to further efforts. The complete
fulfillment of the program is the prerogative of the infinite intellect. The present state of mathematics and its gradual transcendence towards the ideal of
the infinite intellect! are the share of the finite intellect. Insisting that our
knowledge is not based on firm ultimate foundations and does not conform to
the criteria of proper knowledge, that it rather begins and stops in the middle
in a mixture of logic and intuition, and also that philosophy his own included! is merely hypothetical, is the core of Maimons anti-Kantian philosophy of
human finitude. The optimistic counterpart is the claim that we proceed
towards ever more objective knowledge. If indeed an isomorphism obtains be2

Maimonides example is the leg of a hyperbola and its asymptote, which is the outline
of the cone itself. See The Guide of the Perplexed I, p. 73. See Apollonius Conica II,
pp. 1, 2, 14. See Maimons commentary in GM, pp. 142149, esp. 146148; Lebensgeschichte I, p. 381; see also GW III, p. 232.

Maimons Philosophical Program. Understanding versus Intuition

85

tween the knowledge of the finite and the infinite intellect, then we may hope
that we progress in the right direction. But because we cannot know this, our
progress may be an aberration. This is Maimons radical skepticism. The hope
that from the middle we progress towards proper knowledge, and the
skeptical fear that this might be an illusion, designate the opposite poles of
Maimons Rational Dogmatism and skepticism.

2. Construction in Geometry
Kant famously stated that mathematics is so successful because it constructs its
concepts in intuition (CpR, A 714/ B742).3 Does it really?
In an optimistic presentation of his project, Maimon compares construction
in mathematics to creation, man to God:
God, as an infinite power of representation [Vorstellungsvermgen], from all
eternity, thinks himself as all possible essences [Wesen], that is, he thinks himself as
limited in every possible way. He does not think as we do, discursively; rather, his
thoughts are at one and the same time presentations/complete exhibitions [Darstellungen]. If someone objects that we have no concept of such a way of thinking,
my answer is: We do in fact have a concept of it, since we possess it in part. We
think and at the same time exhibit all mathematical concepts as real objects [reelle
Objekte] by construction a priori. In this, we are similar to God (Progressen,
p. 20).

Our cognition stands in the same relation to the objects of mathematics as the
infinite intellect to all objects of nature. This intellect thinks human beings as
we think triangles. In fact, it resolves all objects to real definitions, to the
rules of their construction (Bruno, p. 54; Tr, p. 377). To the infinite intellect all
mathematical truth is analytic (KU, p. 76; Tr, pp. 61, 181).
Now, if we could replace the object (in intuition) with rules of construction
(of the understanding) and forsake intuition, at least know that our operations
in intuition correspond to logical operations, then, at least in this respect, we
would be similar to God for whom thinking and creating are one and the
same. The attempts to fulfill this promise taught Maimon that in geometry construction depends on givens in intuition, not on the concept alone (Logik,
p. 125; Kat, pp. 163164; Tr, pp. 105106).

See also Prolegomena 4; AA IV, p. 272 and AA VIII, pp. 191n192n.

86

Gideon Freudenthal

2.1. The Construction of the Straight Line


The inquiry as to whether geometry can construct its objects and dispense with
intuition reasonably begins with the straight line and the circle. This is so because Euclid introduces these two objects with postulates and then constructs
all other objects from these. If their construction requires intuition, then all of
geometry depends on intuition. In his Critique of Pure Reason, Kant claims that
[w]e cannot think a line without drawing it in thought, or a circle without
describing it (CpR, B 154). However, Kant does not explain by what rule we
can think or draw the straight line. In order to construct an object we need a
construction rule and a definition to which the constructed object should conform. How, then, do we distinguish drawing a straight line from drawing a
curve if we have neither an adequate definition nor a construction rule for the
former? Kant never answers the question. As if making a pun on Kants assertion [w]e cannot think a line without drawing it in thought, in which understanding and intuition seem confused, Maimon presents this rationalist alternative:
For the understanding to think a line, it must draw it in thought, but to present a
line in intuition, it must be imagined as already drawn. For the intuition of a line,
only consciousness of the apprehension (of the taking together of mutually external parts) is required, whereas in order to comprehend [begreifen] a line, a real definition [Sacherklrung] is required, i.e. the explanation of the way it arises [die
Erklrung der Entstehungsart] (Tr, pp. 3536).

Drawing in thought hence means formulating a rule of construction of the


line (an equation), neither synthesizing the successive perceptions of the parts,
nor imagining the motion of a point. Like Kant, Maimon has no rule of construction for the straight line and cannot construct it.

2.2. The Proof that the Straight Line is shortest between two Points
To substantiate his claim that geometry is based on synthetic judgments a priori,
Kant argued:
[T]he straight line between two points is the shortest is a synthetic proposition, for
my concept of the straight contains nothing of quantity, but only a quality. The
concept of the shortest is therefore entirely additional to it, and cannot be extracted out of the concept of the straight line by any analysis. Help must here be gotten
from intuition, by means of which alone the synthesis is possible (CpR, B 16).

Maimon, who wishes to demonstrate that intuition is but confused knowledge, attempts to prove that this proposition is in fact analytic, i. e. that the
property shortest between two points can be inferred from the definition of a
straight line.

Maimons Philosophical Program. Understanding versus Intuition

87

The proof proceeds from Maimons interpretation of Christian Wolffs definition of a straight line. The definition states that the straight line is the line,
the parts of which are similar to the whole. Maimon interprets this as stating
that all parts have the same direction. If we abstract from the magnitude, the
parts of a line can be distinguished from each other only by their direction
(Richtung) or their position (Lage). But if this is so, then a straight line
(abstracted from its magnitude!) has no parts or is one line only, since it is defined by its singular direction. A not-straight line is in fact several lines individuated by the change of direction. This reduction of a perceptual quality
(straight) to quantity (one, several) contradicts, of course, Kants view
that the concept of the straight contains nothing of quantity, but only a quality (CpR, B 16). Now, Kant leveled the criticism that we cannot define direction without using straight (AA XI, pp. 5354) and that the definition is,
therefore, circular. Maimon answered that no better definition than Wolffs has
been proposed (Tr, p. 68), and he ventured to prove that the predicate shortest
between two points is implied by the subject term straight line. If successful,
this proves that the allegedly synthetic proposition, a straight line is the shortest between two points, is in fact analytic.
Suppose that between points A and C there is one (i.e. straight) line segment

and also the line segments AB and BC . The broken line ABC forms a triangle

with the sides: AB , BC , and AC . Euclids Elements I, prop. 20 proves that two

sides of a triangle are longer than the third, and hence AB + BC > AC . Now,
since any multilateral figure can be analyzed into triangles to which Euclids I,
prop. 20 applies, it follows that several line segments, i. e. all other line seg
ments between points A and C are longer than the unique [straight] line AC
(Tr, pp. 6567).
However, curved lines are not considered by Euclid. Maimon attempts to
apply Euclids proposition also to curved lines. The proof proceeds, as Maimon
says, per substitutionem: the curve between two points is substituted by a broken straight line, which can be resolved into triangles to which Elements I,
prop. 20 apply (Tr, pp. 6566, 68). The equivalence between a curved and a broken line was widely accepted; in fact, it was part of the definition of the curved
line. Christian Wolff, whose definition of a straight line Maimon adopted (a line
the parts of which are similar to the whole), defined in a complementary way
the curved line as the line the parts of which are not similar to the whole line or
can be well distinguished from it, and which is compounded of infinitely
small straight lines or a many-sided polygon of infinitely many and infinitely
small sides (Wolff, 1978, pp. 749, 460461).
Maimons proof depends on the substitution of the polygon for the curved
line salva veritate. However, in his discussion of the circles construction Maimon discovered that these are not equivalent.

88

Gideon Freudenthal

2.3. The Circle


Kant considers the definition and the construction of a circle in the context of
his discussion of definition in general. He maintains that only in mathematics
do we encounter appropriate definitions. The example is the circle (CpR, A
234/B 287).
Kant refers to the construction of the circle by turning a segment around
one of its ends.4 This is the real definition of the circle and it proves not only
that the concept is free of contradiction, but also that the object defined is possible, in contradistinction to Leibnizs decahedron or Kants biangle. The latter
objects can be flawlessly defined and yet prove impossible: they cannot be constructed. Here, in contrast, the possibility [of a circle] is [] given in the definition of the circle, in that it is actually constructed by means of the definition
itself.5
However, this definition is not the Euclidean definition of the circle. In
Euclid, the definition reads: A circle is a plane figure contained by one line
such that all the straight lines falling upon it from one point among those lying
within the figure are equal to one another (Elements I, def. 15). The definition
demands that the circumference of the circle be one line, i. e. continuous. It is
hence not enough to show that every point or all points considered on the
circumference are equidistant from the center, but it is required that all points
on the continuous line are equidistant, or all radii be equal.
Kants definition does not mention this differentia specifica of the circle; it
rather seems implied because the same radius constructs all points on the circumference. This construction certainly appeals to the imagination, but it also
involves paradoxes that were known since antiquity and discussed again by
Galileo and others (including Abraham Gotthelf Kstner, a mathematical authority recognized by Kant), e. g. the rota Aristotelis.6 If we do not presuppose
that motion constructs continuous lines (straight or curved), then we have to
prove that the line so constructed is continuous. This Kant explicitly denies:
In the concept of a circular line, nothing more is thought than that all straight lines
drawn from it to a single point (the centre) are equal: this is a merely logical function of the universality of the judgement in which the concept of a line constitutes
the subject and refers merely to each [eine jede] of the lines, not to the totality [das
All] of the lines that can be described on a plane to a given point; if it did not, then

4
5
6

Letter to Marcus Herz, May 26, 1789: Correspondence, p. 315; AA XI, p. 53. See also
the letter to Reinhold of May 19, 1789: Correspondence, p. 306; AA XI, p. 43.
Letter to Marcus Herz, May 26, 1789: Correspondence, p. 315; AA XI, p. 53. Cf. Letter to Reinhold, May 19, 1789: Correspondence, p. 306; AA XI, p. 43.
For Maimons discussion of the rota Aristotelis, see Tr, pp. 230238 and my Definition and construction in Freudenthal, 2006. A revised version of this extended essay
will appear in my forthcoming book on Maimons philosophy.

Maimons Philosophical Program. Understanding versus Intuition

89

every line would with equal right be an idea of the understanding [this is Maimons
term GF], because they all contain lines (as parts) that can be thought between
any two arbitrary [nur denkbaren] points in them, whose number equally goes to
infinity (Letter to Hertz, May 26, 1789: AA XI, pp. 5253).

Discussing the construction of a circle, Maimon proceeds from Euclids and not
from the alleged real definition of a circle by motion. We assign a point and
mark around it equidistant points. For simplicitys sake, let these points be also
equidistant from each other. All these point do not form the one line required, they must be connected. Every two points can be uniquely connected only
by a straight line (applying postulate 1 and 2 of the Elements). The apexes of the
figure are equidistant from the center, but the figure is not a circle but a regular
polygon. Maimon therefore says: A regular polygon is in respect to a circle
[] [a] concept (PhWb, pp. 162, 170, 172).
The attempt to construct the elementary objects of geometry and to prove
that the straight line is shortest between two points showed that the duality
of understanding and intuition appears here also in this form; in intuition, spatial objects appear continuous but we have no concept of the understanding for
them. The rationalist alternative to Kants treatment of geometry failed in three
points: it failed to replace the property straight given in intuition with a concept of the understanding. It also failed to prove that the straight line is the
shortest between two points; this, too, is obvious in intuition but cannot be
proven by the understanding. Finally, it failed to construct a continuous circle
from its concept. Whereas Kant accepted geometrical practice and, therefore,
also intuition as authoritative, Maimon upheld criteria of rationality that he
could not satisfy. Because axioms and postulates are not transparent to reason
but are imposed on intuition, geometry cannot be accepted as objectively necessary. It is merely subjectively so.

3. Number
Maimon devotes incomparably less space to arithmetic than to geometry. This is
true with regard to both explicit discussions of the foundations of arithmetic in
comparison to those of geometry and references to arithmetic (respectively geometry) as exemplifying philosophical issues. Geometry is ubiquitous in Maimons
writings, arithmetic rare. Maimon (and not only Maimon, but also others of his
contemporaries) often writes mathematics when he means, in fact, geometry.
Maimon does not explicitly define the concept of number. We find only an
informal elucidation of the concept and a few casual references. The elucidation
follows Maimons philosophical objectives to dispense with intuition. Number
should not be understood as a collection of units (given in intuition), but
rather as ratios of magnitudes. Concepts of ratio and relations in general are
pure concepts of the understanding and independent of intuition.

90

Gideon Freudenthal

The brief discussion of number in Transcendentalphilosophie reads thus:


I view the understanding as merely a capacity for thought, that is, for producing
pure concepts by means of judging. No real objects are given to it as material for it
to work on. Its objects are merely logical and they only become real objects in the
first place by means of thought. It is an error to believe that things (real objects)
must be prior to their relations. The concepts of the numbers are merely relations
and do not presuppose real objects because these relations are the objects themselves. For example, the number 2 expresses a ratio [Verhltnis] of 2 :1 at the same
time as it expresses the object of this relation []. These pure concepts of the
understanding and relations (that always come in pairs) define one another reciprocally, i. e., in a circle (Tr, p. 191; cf. Logik, pp. 115116).

The origin of the idea that this relation, in fact: a correlation (2 :1; 1: 2) is analytic is in Aristotles Categories 10. Aristotle discusses there correlation as one
kind of opposition. The idea is that, if one of the members and the specific
correlation are known, then the other member is determined. If x is the double
of y, then y is the half of x. In his first book, Maimon claimed that propositions
based on correlatives are identical, in later years that they are not strictly identical, but nevertheless analytical (Tr, p. 37; cf. Kat, p. 66).
It is clear that in the above Maimon does not define the number 2, for this
would be an obvious petitio principii: 2 in the expression 2 :1 would be used
to define 2 as a cardinal number. Moreover, Maimon also refers without further ado to intuition in order to introduce the numbers 1 to 10, and also for
addition of any two numbers between 1 and 9. He concedes that the proposition 3 + 2 = 5 is given to me in intuition (Tr, p. 323), as Kant claimed. The propositions of arithmetic that do not exceed the base of the number system (10 in
the case of the decimal system) are synthetic, cannot be proven, and are to be
counted among the principles (Grundstze) since they are known by no analysis but immediately synthetically in intuition (KU, pp. 176177; cf. also Bacon
pp. 182183; Logik, pp. 273274).7
What remains of the claim that number is a ratio is that it should be
understood as the ratio of specific number to the absolute unit, not as the
multitude of units as in Euclid (Elements VI, def. 2) even if it is so constructed. Like his predecessors in the seventeenth century, Maimon insists that the
unit (in Maimons terms: the absolute unit) is 1, an abstract number (the
ancient unit is not a number because it is not a multitude), that can be thought
and does not refer to whatever may be called one in intuition.8 It is not that by
virtue of which each of the things that exist is called one (Elements VI, def. 1)
but a symbol of the absolute unit in thought. Whereas natural numbers can be
7
8

In German geometry books of the eighteenth century Euclids axioms and postulates
were put together under the heading Grundstze.
Here and subsequently I follow Klein, 1968. On the distinction between the one as
the unit of arithmetic and one counted object, see especially pp. 3940, 49, 54.

Maimons Philosophical Program. Understanding versus Intuition

91

understood as counting units of some kind, the ratio of two numbers or magnitudes is given by the quotient, which is indifferent to the nature of the magnitudes compared. The absolute unit in thought cannot be divided in infinity as a
unit (object) in intuition. Number is not affected by the nature of what it is
applied to (Tr, pp. 35051, 35354; KU, p. 29). Because of the failure to construct numbers from ratios on the one hand and the interpretation of number as
a ratio and not as a multitude of units on the other, we find in Maimon discussions in which number seems to conform both to the ancient and to the
modern concept of number. Maimons conception is very similar to the views of
John Wallis (see Klein, 1968, pp. 211224; esp. 220222).
Consider the analogous case of cause and effect which Maimon mentions but does not elaborate. These, too, are correlative terms, and therefore, as
Hume and Maimon observed: analytic.9 The proposition x is the cause of y
implies logically the proposition y is the effect of x. However, the correlative
terms cause and effect do not replace physics; specific causal relations cannot
be derived from them. They rather subsume single regularities under a universal
category. Apart from their application to concrete cases cause and effect have
no meaning (Tr, p. 368).
Thus, Maimon does not construct the individual numbers from the notion
of number as a ratio any more than he constructs specific physical connections
from the pure concept of cause. Rather, he begins with the natural numbers
given in intuition we count fingers and add small numbers by means of grouping single representations in intuition and observes that they fall under the
category of correlatives. The common property of 1, 2, 3 is that they stand
for ratios to 1, not for a quantity. The numbers and the objects numbered are
thus strictly severed:
It is not the number but that which is subsumed under the concept of a number
that can be greater or lesser [grer oder kleiner], i. e. be subsumed under a greater
or lesser number. Hence the concept of magnitude has no meaning whatever in
pure arithmetic, abstracted from its usage. It is not a number, but that which can be
counted which is a magnitude, and is determined by a specific number. Likewise, it
is not an arbitrarily assumed unit that is at the basis of a number, but the absolute
unit, which as such cannot be constructed but merely thought. The doctrine of
fractions, which is based on an arbitrarily assumed unit, has no place in arithmetic.
We thus see that the concepts of unity and number on which arithmetic is based
presuppose the concept of a continuous magnitude (which is the object of geometry), without which they have no meaning. (KU, p. 26; cf. Tr, pp. 353354; Logik,
pp. 115116).

The exclusion of fractions from arithmetic and the reference to geometry sound
strange, but here too, Maimon reflects the transition to the modern concept of
number, apparent also in Wallis and Wolff. Wallis hesitated to include fractions
9

Hume, Treatise on Human Nature, Bk. I, Pt. iii, 3.

92

Gideon Freudenthal

among the numbers and referred to geometry to justify the divisibility of the
unit, and he, too, conceived number as a ratio. Whether Maimon was acquainted with Wallis or not, he was certainly acquainted with Christian Wolffs textbook of mathematics; in fact, Maimon wrote a Hebrew textbook on the basis of
Wolffs Latin textbook.10 And in Wolff we find similar views to Wallis. On the
basis of Euclids definition, it cannot even be proven that one itself is a number, observed Christian Wolff (1734, Zahl, p. 1345). Wolff, too, defines in a
way similar to Wallis number as everything that refers to unity as a straight
line to another (1732, def. VIII, p. 18). In Scholion II to this definition Wolff
explains what the advantage of this definition is that [n]umber is to be defined
in general so that it be valid for integers as well as fractions, for rational as well
as irrational numbers (1732, def. VIII sch. II, p. 18). And the advantage of a
general definition is that we can apply arithmetical operations to lines: The
utility of this shows when we apply algebra to geometry (Wolff, 1734, Zahl,
pp. 13451346).
Maimon differs from Wolff in some respects. For him number is the ratio
not of continuous magnitudes, but of a number to the absolute unit, distinguished from a unit given in intuition and that can be infinitely divided
(Tr, pp. 350351, 353354; KU, p. 29). Moreover, Maimon does not recognize
irrational numbers as numbers. The reason is that an irrational number cannot
be constructed; it cannot be definitely given although it can be approached ever
more. It is, therefore, not an object, but an idea. And yet, we can operate with
this concept by moving from the object to its real definition, to the rule of its
production. When we have the rule of a series we can produce the series. We
cannot present an infinite series in intuition, but we can by all means think the
rule of its production and substitute it for the series itself, and thus also dispense
with the intuition of time. Moreover, convergent series and objects (numbers)
may be substituted for each other (Tr, pp. 227228). If we substitute real definition for objects, we can accept also irrational numbers although their construction cannot be completed. 2 is, therefore, not a possible object, but it is
a possible concept (i. e. it does not contain a contradiction).11 Thinking of 2 as
a number, i. e. as an object, means thinking of it both as a convergent and
non-convergent series, as rational and irrational, and this thought contains a
contradiction, since it is both an object and not an object at the same time
(Tr, p. 164). This impossibility applies to the number, not to the magnitude. The
magnitude itself can be constructed as a geometrical magnitude (Tr, pp. 374
375). Moreover, although it is contradictorily determined as an object of arith10
11

The textbook was not printed; the manuscript seems lost. Lebensgeschichte II, p. 236.
In this it is different from -a. The latter is a contradictory concept because the product of two identical numbers cannot be negative; see Tr, pp. 5860, 361362. And yet,
Maimon does not reject even the use of -a, because it enables the consistent application of mathematical rules without restrictions.

Maimons Philosophical Program. Understanding versus Intuition

93

metic, we can know its ratio to other magnitudes (Lebensgeschichte II, p. 43).
Finally, and most important: the value of 2 can be ever more approximated.
Although 2 is therefore not a number, i. e. not an object, it is not nothing, it is
an idea (Tr, p. 229).
We have seen that numbers can be interpreted as ratios, but they cannot be
constructed from ratios. Intuition cannot be dispensed with entirely. Purely
relational thought is apparently the privilege of the infinite intellect. A year
after the publication of the Transcendentalphilosophie, Maimon conceded that
only God can construct number from ratio, matter from its form alone:
The infinite intellect, may He be exalted, actualizes by means of the forms of the
understanding their subjects which are the objects of knowledge (mv>klvt). But
this possibility will become clear by the example of the objects of arithmetic,
because the numbers are nothing but known ratios, I wish to say the forms of
knowledge and their subjects. But the finite intellect must necessarily distinguish
in its knowledge the form of apprehension from the object apprehended itself, not
an essential but at least a formal distinction, namely that with it [the finite intellect]
the form of apprehension is an apprehended ratio; and the apprehended object,
although it is in itself also an apprehended ratio, nevertheless it is for it [the finite
intellect] the subject of the ratio [nv>X hir?], since it [the finite intellect] does not
apprehend this ratio clearly [deutlich] (GM, pp. 107108).

There is, hence, an important difference between what numbers are and how
they are known to the finite intellect. Whatever is given as an object is not clearly apprehended. If it were, it would be a pure relational concept not an intuition. A finite intellect cannot apprehend without unclear rests, i. e. without intuition, i. e. without given objects, which resist analysis, and it cannot construct numbers from mere ratios. A few years later Maimon finally answered
the question concerning form and matter of number first raised in his
Transcendentalphilosophie: the ratios between the objects of mathematics are
the form of their knowledge, but their matter determines them as specific
objects (Logik, p. 115).12 Differently put, to human beings number (matter)
must be given in intuition, the ratios of numbers (including n :1) are the form by
which they are thought by the understanding. The infinite intellect constructs
the object from pure relations with nothing given to it. This gap between the
finite and the infinite intellect can be reduced but not closed.

12

In a note to his Transcendentalphilosophie, Maimon asked: What is a determinate


number? It is not an a posteriori object (something given), because it is merely a determinate way of thinking an object. It is not an a priori form because it is not a condition
of an object. It is not an a posteriori form because this has no meaning at all, as each
form can be nothing other than an a priori condition. What is it then? (Tr, p. 424).

94

Gideon Freudenthal

4. Differentials
Maimon valued the infinitesimal calculus even more than arithmetic. In fact,
Maimon ascribed to the calculus a quasi-religious meaning. The differential calculus is a sparkle of divinity and a patent of nobility testifying to the origin
of the human spirit in the pure intelligences (Logik, p. 266). The concepts of
the infinite in mathematics teach man to transcend his finitude, to assume the
perspective of an infinite intellect. The interest behind the engagement with the
mathematical infinite is the same that also directs man to contemplate God,
universe, immortal soul, etc. (KU, pp. 163165). The ideas of the infinitely
large in mathematics, Maimon says elsewhere, are sublime (PhWb, Erhaben, pp. 3031).
But above all, the infinitesimal calculus was essential to Maimons reformed
monadology, or as he expressed himself to his improved Leibnizianism
(Baco and Kant, p. 121). He attributed the close connection between monadology and the calculus to Leibniz himself: in the Transcendentalphilosophie he suggests that the great Leibniz came upon the discovery of the differential calculus through his system of the Monadology; in his Progressen he reverses the
assertion: Leibniz is here said to have come upon his monadology through his
calculus.13

4.1. Improved Leibnizianism


Before turning to the calculus, we should consider what philosophical problems
the calculus should help solve. Maimons concept of differentials appears
according to context in two versions. In the epistemological context (in his
critique of Kant), Maimon speaks of differentials of sensations, in the ontological context (in his critique of Maimonides and the philosophy of Kalam) of
elements of bodies. In Maimons monadology, the world consists of individual substances, which are forces of representation differing from each other by
the degree of this force;14 these two versions are thus not alternatives but rather
complementary perspectives.15 If this is accepted, then the dualism of mind and
matter disappears and is replaced by the degrees of the forces of representation
within consciousness. That the same individual substance represents different
external bodies means that the same force of representation determines itself
13
14
15

Tr, pp. 27n28n; Streifereien, p. 31.


See GM, pp. 8, 126127, 136137.
Achim Engstler argues that the function of the differentials is the solution of the
quid juris? question and not, as Kuntze suggested, to explain different representations of the same cognitive faculty; see Engstler, 1990, pp. 143 and 47 ff., 167. I suggest
that these are two aspects of the same philosophy.

Maimons Philosophical Program. Understanding versus Intuition

95

in different ways. The dualism between the continuum of the forms of intuition space and time and the discrete the individual substances assumes
the form that the interaction of the individual substances appears in (human)
consciousness as an unclear continuous representation, as matter or space.
Kants quid juris question is here part of a much more comprehensive problem: in Aristotelian language the question is how form relates to matter,
and the question is posed within consciousness itself. Specifically, it is no longer
a matter of how concepts are applied to the totally heterogeneous intuitions,
but how clear representations (pure concepts of discrete substances) are applied
to confused representations (continuous intuitions, both a priori and a posteriori):
If we want to consider the matter more carefully, we will find that the question
quid juris? is one and the same as the important question that has occupied all
previous philosophy, namely the explanation of the community [Gemeinschaft]
between soul and body, or again, as the explanation of the worlds arising (with
respect to its matter) from an intelligence. For, we ourselves as well as the things
outside of us (insofar as we are conscious of them) can be nothing other than our
representations themselves, representations that are rightly divided into two principal classes. 1) The forms, i. e. the representation of the universal modes of our
operations [Arten unserer Operationen], which must be in us a priori. 2) The matter, or the representation of particular objects that is given to us a posteriori and
that, in connection with the first, yields consciousness of particular objects [].
How can the understanding subject something (the given object) to its power (to
its rules) that is not in its power? In the Kantian system, namely where sensibility
and understanding are two totally different sources of our cognition, this question
is insoluble as I have shown; on the other hand in the Leibnizian-Wolffian system,
both flow from one and the same cognitive source [Erkenntnisquelle] (the difference lies only in the degree of completeness of this cognition) and so the question
is easily resolved (Tr, pp. 6263, 191192; cf. p. 362).16

4.2. Indivisibilia
The concepts of the understanding, the categories, apply to the differentials,
which are the principles of the sensual world but not sensual themselves.17 Maimon himself seems to have been well-informed about the calculus. He mentions
and quotes Newton and Leibniz, evidently studied Euler,18 and he also com-

16

17
18

Cassirer calls this more comprehensive question an berraschende and khne Wendung (Cassirer, 1920, pp. 128129). Kant summarizes Maimons conception in his
letter to Hertz of May 26, 1789; see Correspondence, pp. 311316.
GM, p. 18; Tr, pp. 355356; Bacon, p. 193.
See Lebensgeschichte II, p. 246: I taught Eulers Algebra to a young man; cf. Wolff,
1813, p. 89.

96

Gideon Freudenthal

pares the style of presentation in Kstners and Clairaults textbooks.19 And yet,
when discussing it in connection with his metaphysics, he uses indiscriminately
infinitely small [magnitudes], differentials, fluxions, and indivisibilia
(Tr, p. 274; KU, pp. 159160, 209210). When discussing the circles construction Maimon referred to the antique method of exhaustion, and when discussing the conceptual problems of the infinite he repeatedly refers to Euclid X.1,
not to contemporary discussions.20 Euclid X.1 (with the porism) reads:
Two unequal magnitudes being set out, if from the greater there is subtracted a
magnitude greater than its half, and from that which is left a magnitude greater
than its half, and if this process be repeated continually, there will be left some
magnitude which will be less than the magnitude set out. And the theorem can
similarly be proved even if the parts subtracted are halves (Elements III, pp. 14, 15).

Maimon distinguishes between a magnitude smaller than any given magnitude as here in Euclid and a magnitude smaller than any magnitude that
can be thought. The first involves no contradiction, the second does; the former suffices for the mathematician, the latter is of concern to the philosopher
(KU, p. 164). Infinitesimals are limit-concepts (Grenzbegriffe), or ideas,
i.e. representations, which cannot be fully presented as an object, the complete
presentations of which we can nevertheless approach ever more in infinity
(KU, p. 155).21 We see that the same considerations apply to the infinitesimal as
to 2. The question whether the limit belongs to the class or not is frequently
discussed by Maimon, and his answers vary. Is the infinitesimally small cosine
of a right angle still a cosine? The only reason we are nevertheless able to designate these states (that quanta can never reach) is because they are limit
concepts, i.e. a merely symbolic infinitely small []. The symbolic infinite is
merely an invention of mathematicians that lends generality to their claims
(Tr, p. 353; cf. Tr, pp. 165, 286288). No object corresponds to the concept
(Tr, p. 412). The dilemma is this: if the infinitesimal is an object, a magnitude (in
intuition), it must be infinitely divisible. The concept of an infinitely small line
is contradictory (Tr, p. 288). If it is not a magnitude in intuition, then the integral cannot be a finite magnitude and the concept loses its function. At times,
Maimon suggests that the differential is a magnitude, at times that it is not a
determined magnitude (the area is not composed of lines) but a ratio of magnitudes (Tr, pp. 352355), at times that it designates a changing numerical ratio
(Tr, pp. 373374), at times that it is merely a fiction, a concept useful to understand phenomena but with no ontological import. Maimon himself remarked
that elucidating philosophical notions by means of the calculus may appear to

19
20
21

PhWb, p. 154: Vortrag und Stil.


See KU, pp. 164, 209, 213; Tr, p. 353.
See Tr, pp. 9, 82, 118, 192, 373, 377. Compare the discussion of five kinds of ideas and
the different meanings of fluxions in KU, pp. 160161.

Maimons Philosophical Program. Understanding versus Intuition

97

be clarifying the obscure by what is even more obscure (Tr, pp. 2728). In order
to maintain that the infinitesimal is a magnitude, Maimon tacitly changes the
traditional definition of magnitude. Instead of that which can be augmented
and diminished, Maimon substitutes either [] or. Magnitude is that of
which something either larger or smaller can be thought; consequently what is
omni dabili majus as well as what is omni dabili minus, i.e. the infinitely large
and the infinitely small, is a magnitude (Tr, p. 353). In this, the differential is
similar to the absolute unit in arithmetic which is treated as an object of pure
arithmetic itself because it can be augmented even if it cannot be diminished,
and both should not be thought of as actual (in intuition) but as symbols
(Tr, pp. 353534). Conceiving an infinitesimal magnitude as actual (in intuition)
originates neither in reason nor in sensibility but in imagination (Einbildungskraft). The understanding thinks a rule, imagination presents it as an object
(Logik, pp. 204206), the understanding thinks discrete entities, imagination
presents a continuum (Logik, pp. 218219). This may be at times helpful in
mathematical practice (Tr, pp. 274275; Bacon, p. 282), but it is not true. Philosophical analysis exposes this mistake. Finally (probably following one of Leibnizs suggestions), Maimon also considers infinitesimals as fictions:22
The method of indivisibles, the infinite series, the differential calculus and such like
necessarily lead to contradiction if they are considered to be more than mere
methods. Imagination palters with us and presents its fictions as real objects. But
reason does not mind this and declares them to be what they really are: mere fictions (Logik, pp. 205206).

Fictions are not opposed to reality but to actuality, to existence in intuition.

4.3. Fictions in Mathematics and Philosophy


We have seen that Maimon suggested conceiving of some rules or ratios as concepts of objects, with the proviso that they be understood as fictions. The
same should also apply to philosophy. What does fiction mean? Fiction
[Erdichtung] in its most general meaning is an operation of the imagination
[Einbildungskraft] by which a not objectively necessary unity of the manifold
of an object is produced (PhWb, p. 36).
In our context fiction refers, more specifically, to conceiving something as
an object which cannot be given as an object: [a]n object which in some respect
is variable according to rule may be considered as if it arrives at the highest
grade of its variation, i.e. as if it were the same and not the same object at the
22

Bendavid suggested that infinitesimals are qualities, not quantities. Maimon first
accepted this suggestion (Tr, pp. 291292); later he rejected it (Tr, pp. 355356).

98

Gideon Freudenthal

same time (Progressen, p. 17). 2, so Maimon maintained, is thus conceived


both a convergent and non-convergent series, a rational and irrational number,
and both an object and not an object at the same time (Tr, p. 164). And yet,
the method of fictions is productive (and deceptive) not only in mathematics,
but also in physics: the parallelogram of forces, the backbone of mechanics of
point masses, is a good example (Pemberton, pp. 198201).23
These considerations should also apply in philosophy. Leibnizs monadology appears inconsistent since it seems to claim that an infinitely divisible
body is compounded of indivisible monads. But what if his philosophy is to be
understood as a methodus invidisibilium, i.e. as a method and not a dogmatic
ontology? On this view, monads are understood as concepts defined by the
theory of which they form part and applied to determine relations of bodies and
yet as fictions in an ontological perspective (Progressen, pp. 2930)? Moroever, what if Leibniz didnt conceive of monads as things-in-themselves but
as fictions and merely retained the traditional ontological modus loquendi (Progressen, p. 56), if they are not real objects but merely what differential magnitudes are in mathematics, limits of ratios (Streifereien, p. 271)?24 We learn two
lessons. The first is that la rigueur metaphysique ontological language can be
understood as fictional. The second lesson is more important. Philosophy can
lay claim to truth in the same way that the sciences do; its concepts and theories
are developed to account for phenomena, and they are ascribed validity according to their success. They are not supposed to offer absolute knowledge of the
first and last elements of reality. This is the prerogative of the infinite intellect.25
4.4. Taking Stock
The central motif of Maimons philosophy is his insistence that proper knowledge must be based on the understanding. Intuition is not only opaque to reason but may also deceive us. If knowledge dependent on this medium is valid,
23

24
25

Compound motion is constructed by conceiving the action of simultaneous forces as


successive accelerations and assuming the time each such force acts as infinitely
small; But then the conception of a compound motion is a mere idea or fiction
which our presentation may approach ever closer but never fully reach (Pemberton,
pp. 200201).
On Maimons method of fictions and its critique by Reinhold, see Breazeale, 2003.
Engstler maintains that this interpretation undermines Maimons claim to have solved
the quid juris question: [w]enn Maimon die Differentiale nmlich tatschlich als
Begriffe fiktiver Elemente auffate, wre seine Theorie nicht in der Lage, die Mglichkeit objektiv gltiger empirischer Urteile zu erklren, und sie bte mithin auch keine
Lsung des Problems quid juris (Engstler, 1990, p. 140). This is so if philosophy
claims absolute truth, or truth more valid than ascribed to the differential equations of
classical mechanics. I argue that Maimons unique stance is that he ascribes them the
same validity, neither more nor less.

Maimons Philosophical Program. Understanding versus Intuition

99

then it is the task of philosophy to analyze it and show that it can be reformulated in terms of the understanding. Maimons attempts to reduce intuition to the
understanding and objects to ratios and construction rules were not successful.
The conclusion he draws from his failure to prove that the straight line is shortest is rather surprising:
By contrast [to Kant GF], I pose the question in the following way. Since all a
priori cognition must be analytic, and can be derived from the principle of contradiction, how can we make those propositions that are synthetic due to a lack in our
cognition into analytic ones? [] I do not want to take on the task of developing
all such propositions in this way in order to make them satisfy my requirement; it
is enough that I hold it not to be impossible (Tr, pp. 17879, my emphasis; cf. Tr,
p. 323).26

The failure to reform mathematics is no reason to change our criteria of rationality.

5. Philosophizing in the Middle


Absolute knowledge of the infinite intellect assumes two forms, producing
objects from relations and producing concepts of objects (respectively objects)
by synthesis of more general concepts and specific difference. The former program failed. The latter, synthetic program is repeatedly alluded to in the construction of geometrical objects. Maimon maintains that if there are synthetic
judgments a priori, there must also be a principle of reason such judgments.
This is his Principle of Determinability.27 The principle examines the construction of concepts top-down, i. e. by further determination of given general
objects. The procedure conforms to Aristotles notion of definition by genus
proximum and differentia specifica. In geometry, this means that objects should
not be constructed from more elementary objects but, to the contrary, from
more complex ones, not by composition, but by specification, in fact by determination according to the Law of Determinability. The necessity and universality required for science could be attained, so Maimon believed, if we could
subordinate all objects of human knowledge to one and the same concept.
(Progressen, pp. 4243). With this suggestion, Maimon presents an entirely
different and new notion not only of construction, but also of a conceptual
system, philosophy included.
Take, for example, the construction by conic sections. From a general algebraic definition we can infer the properties not only of the circle but also of
26

27

The universality of the mathematical truths certainly must have an objective ground,
i. e., to an infinite understanding the proposition must be analytic; but we cannot have
any insight into this ground (Tr, p. 181).
On Maimons principle of determinability, see Schechter, 2003.

100

Gideon Freudenthal

all other objects that fall under this general definition, as well as the relations
among these (Progressen, p. 42). Moreover, we also obtain rules of construction
for these objects from this definition:
Thus in ordinary geometry the circle e. g. is defined as a line all parts of which are
equally distant from a certain point (the center). The consequences to be drawn
from this concept are only valid for the circle, not also for other curved lines. In
higher geometry, the circle is determined as a curved line of the second order by a
general equation. The consequences to be drawn from this equation are therefore
valid not only for the circle, but for all lines of this order, etc. (Ueber die Schwrmerei, p. 44).28

parabola

point

hyperbola
circle

ellipse

straight line

Fig. 1

Consider a simple case: a circular cone cut by a plane. The boundary curve of
the intersection is a conic section. According to the angle of intersection, this
conic section is an ellipse, a circle, a parabola or a hyperbola, yes even a point; a
straight line and intersecting straight lines can be thus produced. If the plane
intersects the apex of the cone parallel to its napes it produces a straight line
(or intersecting lines), if it intersects the vertex of the cone parallel to its base, it
produces a point.
We see here genetic definitions or construction rules by genus proximum
and differentia specifica. In this way the relations between these different objects are transparent (especially in the algebraic representation). But in the case

28

Kant, too, once considered the construction of a circle as a conic section. Moreover, he
also noted that then a property that Euclid proved for the circle (Elements III, p. 35)
can be proved for all conic sections. However, he does not draw from this example
consequences concerning mathematics but rather that physics has to conform to the
geometrical properties of space as proven in geometry. See Prolegomena, 38; AA IV,
pp. 320321.

Maimons Philosophical Program. Understanding versus Intuition

101

of the finite mind, the petitio principii is obvious: In order to construct the circle
and the straight line as conic sections, we need a cone (and a plane). In order to
construct a cone, we need a circle and a straight line.29 The attempt to construct
geometry ab ovo fails either way.

5.1. Hypothetical Metaphysics


Conceiving the entire fabric of human knowledge as constructed top-down
requires that we begin with the most general concept of a determined object,
know all its possible determinations, use them as specific differences, and thus
produce the more specific concepts, and so on to the most specific concepts. If
this were possible, the principle of determinability would serve as the rule of
construction of all further objects. A project of this kind fails for two reasons.
First, the most general concept, the I or consciousness in general (Bewutsein berhaupt),30 analogous to space in geometry, remains for the finite
intellect an unattainable idea.31 Second, the principle does not produce all possible determinations, but is only a criterion by which we judge whether a given
determination is proper or produces a category mistake. The principle shows
that right-angle triangle is a possible synthesis (but, sweet triangle is not),
but it cannot suggest right angle as a specific predication of an angle. There
is nothing in the concept angle that suggests that right angle is a property
distinct from all other inclinations of two straight lines.
How, then, can philosophy proceed? We should note, says Maimon:
that both the primitive consciousness of a constituent part of a synthesis [] as
well as the consciousness of the complete synthesis are mere ideas, i. e. they are the
two limit-concepts of a synthesis, in that without synthesis no consciousness is
possible, but the consciousness of the completed synthesis grasps the infinite in itself, and is consequently impossible for a limited cognitive faculty []. So we
begin in the middle with our cognition of things and stop in the middle again. It is
the same as, for example, in calculating with our number system, where we
proceed according to the very same rules both forwards and backwards in relation
to an extended magnitude (through decimal fractions) []. The absolutely first in
the consciousness of a thing is a mere idea that we reach by infinitely decreasing it,
i.e. that we never reach in intuition (Tr, pp. 350351).

29

30
31

In fact, this is the definition of a cone in Elements XI, def. 18: When a right triangle
with one side of those about the right angle remains fixed is carried round and restored again to the same position from which it began to be moved, the figure so comprehended is a cone. Appollonius definition of the cone involves the rotation of a
straight line around the circumference of a given circle.
See the references in Bergmann, 1967, pp. 164166.
Tr, p. 193; Logik, 243245. Object as such (Gegenstand berhaupt) is the subject
matter of logic.

102

Gideon Freudenthal

The analogy Maimon draws here between philosophy and arithmetic is not at
all accidental. He conceives philosophy as a science, a science a priori of the
form of knowledge, distinguished from mathematics by its greater generality:
Philosophy is the idea of a science of the possibility of a system [das Ganze] of
knowledge, i. e. its object is merely the form of a science or of a whole of knowledge. Here the difference between philosophy and mathematics (which are both pure
sciences a priori) becomes obvious. The object of (pure) philosophy which abstracts from determined subjects is only the form or the way in which a system of knowledge in general is possible. Also [the object of] mathematics, as a science, which
refers to determined objects (albeit a priori), is the possibility of a system, but not
a system of knowledge in general [berhaupt], but a system of knowledge of the
determined objects of mathematics (Kat, pp. 120121; cf. p. 118).

Two important consequences follow from this beginning and stopping in the
middle: the hypothetical and uncertain nature of metaphysics, and the infinite
quest for truth. As is often the case, Maimon attributes his own views to the
philosophers he discusses. In Maimons interpretation, Kant assumes the apodeictic truth of Newtonian science and mathematics as an answer to the question quid facti, and then develops his transcendental philosophy as a hypothesis to account for the possibility of such knowledge:
Mr. Kant takes experience as an indubitable fact as the basis of his critical system
and demonstrates hypothetically from there the reality of the principal concepts
and propositions a priori (Obereits Widerruf, p. 108: GW III, p. 420).32

This sounds like an ironical commentary on Kants announcement in the preface to the second edition of Critique of Pure Reason that he will first present
his Copernican turn as a hypothesis in order to draw attention to the character of these first attempts at such a change, but then prove it apodeictically
not hypothetically (CpR, B xxiii). Maimon himself accepts only logical inference as apodeictically not hypothetically; all the rest is as hypothetical as
science is (in his interpretation). However, the ever better approximation of
intuition by mathematics and physics suggests that we may proceed in the right
direction.
If philosophy never reaches a secure beginning or end but begins and stops
in the hypothetical middle, however, then it follows that the progress of inquiry
continues forever and also retains its hypothetical character. This is the deep
meaning Maimon ascribes to a Talmudic quote which he repeatedly used and
with which he also closed his Transcendentalphilosophie:
Our Talmudists (who, from time to time, have certainly expressed thoughts worthy of a Plato) say, the students of wisdom find no rest, neither in this life nor yet

32

See also Antwort auf Obereit, pp. 102103: GW III, pp. 458459; Streifereien,
pp. 203204, 207.

Maimons Philosophical Program. Understanding versus Intuition

103

in the life to come, to which they relate, in their own way, the words of the Psalmists: They go from strength to strength, to appear before the Almighty in Zion
(Tr, p. 444).

Or not.33

References
Apollonius (1710): Apollonii Pergaei Conicorum libri octo etc., ed. Halley, Edmond,
Oxford. (Cited as Conica.)
Bergmann, Shmuel Hugo (1967): The Philosophy of Solomon Maimon, trans. Noah J.
Jacobs, Jerusalem.
Breazeale, Daniel (2003): Reinhold gegen Maimon ber den Gebrauch der Fiktionen
in der Philosophie, in: Bondeli, Martin (ed.): Die Philosophie Karl Leonhard
Reinholds, Fichte-Studien-Supplementa, Bd. 16, New York, pp. 123151.
Bruno, Giordano (1793): Auszug aus Von der Ursache, dem Prinzip und dem Einen in:
Gnothi Seauton oder Magazin zur Erfahrungsseelenkunde als ein Lesebuch fr
Gelehrte und Ungelehrte, Bd. X/2, pp. 4984 (in: GW IV, pp. 617652).
Cassirer, Ernst (1920): Das Erkenntnisproblem in der Philosophie und Wissenschaft der
neueren Zeit, Bd. 3: Die nachkantischen Systeme, Berlin.
Engstler, Achim (1990): Untersuchungen zum Idealismus Salomon Maimons, Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt.
Euclid (1926): The Thirteen Books of Euclids Elements, trans. Thomas Heath, 2nd ed.,
New York. (Cited as Elements.)
Freudenthal, Gideon (2006): Definition and Construction. Salomon Maimons
Philosophy of Geometry, Preprint 317 of the Max Planck Institute for the History
of Science, Berlin.
Hume, David (2000): Treatise on Human Nature, ed. Norton, David Fate, Oxford.
Kant, Immanuel (1903 ff.): Kants gesammelte Schriften, ed. Preuische Akademie der
Wissenschaften etc., Berlin. (Cited as AA.)
Kant, Immanuel (1999): Correspondence, ed. Zweig, Arnulf, Cambridge (cited as Correspondence).
Klein, Jacob (1968): Greek Mathematical thought and the Origin of Algebra, Cambridge (Mass.) and London, (originally in German, 1934, 1936).
Kuntze, Friedrich (1912): Die Philosophie Salomon Maimons, Heidelberg.
Lachterman, David R. (1992): Mathematical Construction, Symbolic Cognition and
the Infinite Intellect: Reflections on Maimon and Maimonides, in: Journal of the
History of Philosophy, vol. 30, no. 4, pp. 497522.
Maimon, Salomon (19651976): Gesammelte Werke, ed. Verra, Valerio, 7 Bde. Hildesheim. (Cited as GW, all page numbers in the text refer to the original pagination
reproduced in GW.)

33

This essay has been written during my stay at the Max-Planck-Institute for the
History of Science, Berlin. I am grateful to the director of Department I, Jrgen Renn,
for the invitation to work in this inspiring setting.

104

Gideon Freudenthal

Maimon, Salomon (1790): Baco und Kant. Schreiben des H.S. Maimon an den Herausgeber dieses Journals in Berlinisches Journal fr Aufklrung, Bd. VII/2, pp. 99122
(in: GW II, pp. 499522). (Cited as Baco and Kant.)
Maimon, Salomon (1790): Versuch ber die Transcendentalphilosophie mit einem
Anhang ber die symbolische Erkenntnis und Anmerkungen, Berlin (in: GW II,
pp. 1442). (Cited as Tr.)
Maimon, Salomon (1791): Philosophisches Wrterbuch, oder Beleuchtung der wichtigsten Gegenstnde der Philosophie, in alphabetischer Ordnung, von Salomon Maimon, Erstes Stck, Berlin (in: GW III, pp. 1246). (Cited as PhWb.)
Maimon, Salomon (1792): Antwort auf das Schreiben des Herrn Obereit an Herrn
S. Maimon, in: Gnothi Seauton oder Magazin zur Erfahrungsseelenkunde als ein
Lesebuch fr Gelehrte und Ungelehrte, Bd. IX/3, pp. 100105 (in: GW III,
pp. 456461). (Cited as Antwort auf Obereit.)
Maimon, Salomon (1792): Obereits Widerruf fr Kant. Ein psychologischer Kreislauf, in: Gnothi Seauton oder Magazin zur Erfahrungsseelenkunde als ein Lesebuch fr Gelehrte und Ungelehrte, Bd. IX/2, pp. 106143 [author: J.H. Obereit;
notes: S. Maimon] (in: GW III, pp. 418455). (Cited as Obereits Widerruf.)
Maimon, Salomon (1792/93): Salomon Maimons Lebensgeschichte. Von ihm selbst
geschrieben und herausgegeben von K.P. Moritz, in zwei Theilen, Berlin (in: GW I,
pp. 293588). (Cited as Lebensgeschichte.)
Maimon, Salomon (1793): Bacons von Verulam Neues Organon. Aus dem Lateinischen
bersetzt von George Wilhelm Bartoldy. Mit Anmerkungen von Salomon Maimon.
Mit Kupfern, Berlin (in: GW IV, pp. 295530). (Cited as Bacon.)
Maimon, Salomon (1793): Anfangsgrnde der Newtonischen Philosophie von
Dr. Pemberton. Aus dem Englischen mit Anmerkungen und einer Vorrede von
Salomon Maimon. Erster Theil mit vier Kupfertafeln, Berlin (in: GW IV, pp.
531580, cited as Pemberton).
Maimon, Salomon (1793): Ueber die Progressen der Philosophie in Salomon Maimons
Streifereien im Gebiete der Philosophie. Erster Theil, Berlin (in: GW IV,
pp. 2380). (Cited as Progressen.)
Maimon, Salomon (1793): Salomon Maimons Streifereien im Gebiete der Philosophie.
Erster Theil, Berlin (in: GW IV, pp. 1294). (Cited as Streifereien.)
Maimon, Salomon (1793): Ueber die Schwrmerei, in: Gnothi Seauton oder Magazin zur Erfahrungsseelenkunde als ein Lesebuch fr Gelehrte und Ungelehrte, Bd. X/2, pp. 4348 (in: GW IV, pp. 611616). (Cited as Ueber die Schwrmerei.)
Maimon, Salomon (1794): Die Kathegorien des Aristoteles. Mit Anmerkungen erlutert und als Propdeutik zu einer neuen Theorie des Denkens dargestellt, Berlin (in:
GW VI, pp. 1271). (Cited as Kat.)
Maimon, Salomon (1794): Versuch einer neuen Logik oder Theorie des Denkens. Nebst
angehngten Briefen des Philaletes an Aenesidemus, Berlin (in: GW V). (Cited as
Logik).
Maimon, Salomon (1797): Kritische Untersuchungen ber den menschlichen Geist oder
das hhere Erkenntnis- und Willensvermgen, Leipzig (in: GW VII, pp. I373).
(Cited as KU.)
Maimon, Salomon (1965, 2000): Givat Hammore (commentary on Maimonides The
Guide of the Perplexed, Part I), ed. Bergmann, S.H./Rotenstreich, N., Jerusalem.
(Cited as GM.)

Maimons Philosophical Program. Understanding versus Intuition

105

Maimon, Salomon (2010): Essay on Transcendental Philosophy, trans. Nick Midgley,


Henry Somers-Hall, Alistair Welchman and Merten Reglitz, London / New York.
Maimonides, Moses (1969): The Guide of the Perplexed, trans. Shlomo Pines, Chicago.
Schechter, Oded (2003): The Logic of Speculative Philosophy and Skepticism in Maimons Philosophy: Satz der Bestimmbarkeit and the Role of Synthesis, in: Freudenthal, Gideon (ed.): Salomon Maimon: Rational Dogmatist, Empirical Skeptic;
Critical Assessments, Dordrecht, pp. 1853.
Wolff, Christian (1734): Vollstndiges mathematisches Lexicon, Leipzig.
Wolff, Christian (1732): Elementa matheseos universae, in Qui Commentationem de
Methodo Mathematica, Arithmeticam, Geometriam, Trigonometriam Planam, &
Analysim, tam Finitorum quam Infinitorum complectitur, Tom. I, Geneva.
Wolff, Christian (1978): Mathematisches Lexicon, ed. Hofmann, J.E., Hildesheim /
New York.
Wolff, Sabattia Joseph (1813): Maimoniana oder Rhapsodie zur Charakteristik Salomon Maimons, Berlin.

You might also like