You are on page 1of 288

Vivarium

Volume

30
1992

Reprintedwiththe permissionoftheoriginalpublisher
by
Periodicals Service Company
Germantown,NY
2013

09:07:05 AM

Printed
onacid-free
paper.
Thisreprint
wasreproduced
from
the
bestoriginal
edition
copyavailable.
NOTETOTHEREPRINT
EDITION:
Insomecasesfullpageadvertisements
which
donotaddto
valueofthisvolume
havebeenomitted.
thescholarly
volumes
somereprinted
Asa result,
mayhaveirregular
pagination.

09:07:05 AM

CONTENTS OF VOLUME XXX (1992)


WilliamJ.Courtenay

Introduction

Constant
J.Mews

Nominalism
and Theologybefore
Abaelard:NewLightonRoscelinof
Compigne

C.H. Kneepkens

Nominalism
and Grammatical
Theory
intheLate EleventhandEarlyTwelfth
Centuries
AnExplorative
34
Study

JohnMarenbon

Vocalism
and the
, Nominalism
Commentaries
on theCategories
from
theEarlierTwelfth
51
Century

StenEbbesen

WhatMustOne Have an Opinion


About

62

C.G. Normore

Abelardand theSchoolofthe
Nominales1

80

Y. Iwakuma

NominalesThe
Twelfth-Century
Posthumous
SchoolofPeterAbelard...97

J.Martin
Christopher

TheLogic oftheNominales,or,The
Rise andFall ofImpossiblePositio

110

David Luscombe

TheSchoolofPeterAbelard
Revisited

127

MarciaL. Colish

PeterLombardandAbelard: The
andDivine
OpinioNominalium
Transcendence

139

WilliamJ.Courtenay

PeterofCapua as a Nominalist

157

IwakumaYukioand
StenEbbesen

Logico- TheologicalSchoolsfromthe
SecondHalfofthe12thCentury
:A
ListofSources1
173

Nominalism
Twelfth-Century
Bibliography

21 1

AllenBck

Avicenna'
s Conceptionofthe
Modalities

P. Mack

Valla'sDialecticintheNorth2: Further
Commentaries
256

217

Reviews

276

BooksReceived

284

09:07:05 AM

Vivarium
XXX, 1 (1992)
INTRODUCTION
WILLIAMJ. COURTENAY
The papers collected in this issue represent voices (sometimes
divergent) in a renewed discussion over the origin and meaning of
Nominalism. Throughout most of the presentcentury
twelfth-century
there was little question over what Nominalism' was or when and
throughwhom it enteredphilosophical debate. From thebriefaccount
given by Johannes Turmair (Aventinus) in the sixteenthcenturyto
the firstfull-scalestudyby Josef Reiners in 1910, Nominalism' was
a position on the ontological status of universal concepts, introduced
by Roscelin and modifiedby Peter Abelard, which rejected the view
that such universais referredto real entitiesor corresponded to common natures that inheredin things(res) but were instead mere names
or labels ( nomina
) that referredto linguistic or conceptual entities.1
Scholarly debate focused almost entirely on differencesbetween
Roscelin and Abelard, and the degree to which the label Nominalism'
was an appropriate descriptionfor Abelard's position on universais.
Althoughby no means the last word, the position arrived at by Jean
chezAblardand in
Jolivet in his magisterialArtsdu langageet thologie
was
to
substitute
in place of
Non-realism'
subsequent publications
Nominalism' as a descriptionfor Abelard's thought.2
Two developmentsin the 1980s fundamentallyaltered the termsof
traditionaldiscussion. The firstwas the gradual collectionof twelfth- a
and thirteenth-century
referencesto the opinions of the Nominales
M.-D.
Chenu
and
Arthur
earlier
in
the
process begun by
Landgraf
centurybut expanded significantlythroughthe manuscript research
and editorialeffortsof scholars in the Netherlands and at the Institut
forgraeskog latinskMiddelalderfilologiin Copenhagen.3 The second
was the suggestion,foreshadowedby Chenu, Landgraf, and Gabriel
Nuchelmans and independentlyproposed by Calvin Normore and
William Courtenay in papers written in 1986, that the label
- and thus the
Nominales
original meaning of nominalism- did not
1J. Turmair,
Annales
ducum
Boicarum
Werke
, VI, c.3, in Smtliche
, vols.2-3,ed. S.
Riezler,vol.3 (Mnchen1884),200-2;Reiners1910.
2 Jolivet1969;
1981.
3 Chenu1934,Jolivet
1935-36;
1943;Pelster1944-46;Hunt1950;De Rijk1962,
Landgraf
1967,1975,1988;Green-Pedersen
1977,1984;Braakhuis
1980;Kneepkens
1982,
and Nielsen1983;Ebbesenand Iwakuma1983,1990;
1987;Ebbesen,Fredborg,
Iwakuma1992a.
1

09:07:11 AM

resultfroma position on the ontological statusof universaisbut rather


froma theoryof propositions as bearers of truth,based on a theory
of the unity of nouns and theirfunctionin propositions.4Courtenay
took the furtherstep of calling into question Abelard' s relation to the
group known as the Nominalesand thus his relation to nominalism.
The thrustof these two papers was not to dismiss five centuries of
consensus but to raise the possibilitythat the
historical/philosophical
fifteenth-century
understanding of nominalism adopted and disseminated through Turmair may have been incorrectlysuperimposed
on the twelfthcentury,and thatboth the originalmeaning of the label
and the role played by Abelard need to be re-examinedand proved on
the basis of a freshreading of all the evidence, instead of assuming the
validityof the traditionalview and fittingthe new evidence into that
pre-establishedpicture.
To facilitateand speed up this endeavor, it was thoughtdesirable
for those involved in the assembling and analysis of the texts and
theses of the Nominalesas well as those challengingthe traditionalview
should meet togetherwith otherswho had expertiseon these issues or
who had worked on Abelard and his 'school'. The task at hand was
to abandon as much as possible presuppositionsformedby the traditional view and to constructa picture of the thoughtof the Nominales
initially only from contemporary references to their opinions.
Through the financial support of the National Endowment for the
Humanities and the Burdick-Varyfundsof the InstituteforResearch
in the Humanities at the University of Wisconsin, this goal was
realized at Madison, Wisconsin on October 3-5, 1991.
The sequence of papers as presentedat the conferencewas designed
to move fromquestions of origin and background in the late eleventh
and early twelfthcenturiesto the role of Abelard, the opinions of the
Nominales
, and finallyto the impact on theologyin the second half of
the twelfthcentury. Much of that arrangementhas been retained in
the published sequence, but the presentorder attemptsto group pieces
on the basis of the interrelationof content.The firsttwo papers, those
of Mews and Kneepkens, examine issues in the pre-Abelardian
period, respectivelylogic and theology in Roscelin and the grammatical background forthe theoryof the unityof the noun. The next
paper, thatof Marenbon, directsits attentionto logic and the question
of universais in the generation of Abelard. The theories of the
4 Nuchelmans
1987;Courtenay
1973;Normore
[1986],1991a.
2

09:07:11 AM

Nominalesin the thirdquarter of the twelfthcenturyand theirrelationship to the thoughtof Abelard are examined by Ebbesen, Normore,
Iwakuma, and Martin. Finally, the theologicaltraditionfrom1140 to
1200 is exploredby Luscombe, Colish, and Courtenay fromthe standpoints, respectively,of the followersof Abelard, the use Lombard
makes of 'nominalist' theories, and the place of nominalism in the
thought of Peter of Capua. The footnotesof all articles have been
simplifiedaccording to the textsassembled by Iwakuma and Ebbesen
as well as the bibliographyat the end.
A consensus emerged during the conferenceon several issues- a
result that might otherwise have taken years to achieve, First,
althoughthe reasoningdifferedamong various participants,therewas
, which appear in
agreement that the labels Nominalisand Nominales
texts soon after 1150, designate positions and persons active in the
third quarter of the twelfthcentury,certainlynot before 1140. The
demise of the Nominalesas an active 'school' was variouslydated from
C.1180 (Iwakuma) to 1210 (Courtenay). Second, it was accepted that
the originsof the Nominaleslie in the closely related areas of logic and
grammar,althoughwhethertheywere natural successorsto the Vocales
(Iwakuma, Ebbesen, and Marenbon) or representeda markedlydifferentapproach (Courtenay, and to some extent Normore) was not
resolved. Third, therewas also agreementthatwhatevermeaning lay
behind the label, it did have some connectionwith Abelard, although
the precise nature of that relationshipremained in dispute. Fourth,
what had initiallyseemed opposing views on origin, namely a theory
about universaisvs a theoryabout nouns and propositions,began to
be seen as related elements in a broader and more complex 'system'.
Which of thoseelementswas more importantforthe originof the label
Nominales
, however, still remained in dispute.
It is to be expected (and probably healthy)that the authors of these
papers, each privilegingand interpretinga slightlydifferentgroup of
source texts,should not speak with one voice. And the complexityof
theirreasoning does not easily allow them to be aligned preciselyon
differentsides of the 'unresolved' issues. The points of agreement,
however, have considerably advanced research on the origin and
meaning of nominalism in the twelfthcentury. As others begin to
study the texts assembled and provisionally interpretedhere and in
recent articleslisted in the bibliography,it is expected that the early
decades of nominalism- and thus the history of an important
philosophical movement will come into better focus.
Madison, Wisconsin

09:07:11 AM

Vivarium
XXX, 1 (1992)
Nominalism and TheologybeforeAbaelard:
New Light on Roscelin of Compigne
CONSTANT J. MEWS
Roscelin of Compigne is commonly remembered as one of those
modern "heretics of dialectic'' who, according to St Anselm, "do not
thinkuniversal substances to be anythingbut the puffof an utterance
(flatumvocis),who cannot understand colour to be other than a body,
or the wisdom of man differentfrom the soul."1 Anselm accused
Roscelin of blindlyapplying to the Trinityan inane logic that denied
the real existence of universais. Roscelin reportedlyargued that the
Father, Son and Holy Spirit had to be three separate things in God
ifone was not to argue that the Father had become incarnate withthe
Son. Anselm considered such speculation both logically absurd and
spirituallydangerous.
Anselm' s savage summary,deliveredc. 1093, has been instrumental
in moulding subsequent perception of Roscelin as an unspiritual
'
'
logician a 'maverick' in the words of Richard Southern.2A more
positive angle on his achievementwas presentedalmost seventyyears
later by Otto of Freising, who remarked that Roscelin was the first
vocumin logic.3 Otto was comparing
person to establish the sententia
Abaelard' s rash application of this doctrineto theologywith the prudent reflectionof Gilbert of Poitiers on the vocesof trinitarianbelief.
Far fromcriticizingRoscelin's thought,Otto supportedpreciselythat
definitionof the three divine persons as three things which Anselm
1 Anselm,De incarnatione
verbi
Anselmi
Opera
[henceforward
DIV'> ed. F.S. Schmitt,
II 9.20-10.1.Fora fulldiscussion
ofAnselm's
Omnia
1938-68,
VI, Rome-Edinburgh
aboutRoscelin,see Mews 1991,55-97.Fullertreatment
ofcontemporary
writing
as wellas arguments
aboutRoscelin,
forhisauthorship
ofvariouswritings
testimony
in a forthcoming
in thispaperwillbe putforward
mentioned
study.
2 Cf. RichardSouthern,
in SaintAnselm.
A Portrait
ina Landscape
, Cambridge
1990,
he went,buthe was irrepressible,
and he
176: "Roscelinmadeenemieswherever
touchednothingthathe did notexacerbate.Far morethaneitherBerengar
or
execration
and condemnation
on their
Abelard,who- thoughtheybothbrought
soberand wellversedtheologians,
heads- wereessentially
Roscelinwas alwaysa
causeofdissension
wherever
he went."
3 OttoofFreising,
I 48, ed. G. WaitzandB. De Simson,HannoverGesta
Frederici
Leipzig1912,69.
4

09:07:18 AM

had abhorred. In Otto's mind, Abaelard had blurred the substantial


distinctionbetween persons which he considered Gilbert to uphold.
Unlike Anselm, Otto thought that there was nothing intrinsically
wrong with the new emphasis on vocesin logic.
AlthoughJohn of Salisbury considered Roscelin a logician whose
opinions on voceshad fallenintooblivion, Otto's judgement has tended
to prevail.4 His comments about Roscelin and the sententiavocum
inspiredAventinus in the early sixteenthcenturyto identifyRoscelin
as founder of 4'a new way of philosophizing" that came to include
Abaelard, Ockham, Buridan, and Marsilius of Inghen. Aventinus
considered medieval philosophy to have been an inane civil war
betweenrealistsand nominalists,initiallyinstigatedby Roscelin.5 The
mythology which subsequently developed around Roscelin as
nominalist"hero and rebel" has shown no sign of abating, notwithstandingFranois Picaves dissectionof the legend.6 In focussingon
nominalism as a cohesive school of medieval thought prefiguring
"modern philosophy", we are heir not only to Aventinus' reading of
the historyof philosophy, but perhaps to his misreading as well.
Anselm never claimed that Roscelin had established a new school
of dialectic, only that he was just one of a new breed of "modern"
dialecticians. The author of the HistoriaFrancica, writingin the early
twelfthcentury, noted in a less polemical vein that Roscelin, like
Robert of Paris and Arnulfof Laon, was a followerof a certainJohn
who taught dialectic to be an ars vocalis.7 Robert of Paris may be the
4 Metalogicon
II 17 (ed. Webb93).
5 Annales
Ducum
Boiariae
VI 3, ed. S. Riezler,Munich1884,II 200-2[initially
publishedIngolstadt
on hisencounter
withnominalist
1554].GeraldStrausscomments
inParisinHistorian
inanAgeofCrisis.TheLifeandWork
Avenphilosophers
ofJohannes
tinus
1477-1534
Mass. 1963,33-5.
, Cambridge
6 See forexampleHeinrichChristian
derBegriffe.
Der
Meier,MachtundWahnwitz
Ketzer
Aalen 1974,whichadds littleto Picavespioneering
Roscelin
Roscellinus,
,
ettholgien
la lgende
etd'aprs
l'histoire
philosophe
, Paris19112,a muchenlarged
d'aprs
version
ofthe1896edition.See tooEike-Henner
W. Kluge,Roscelin
andtheMedieval
Problem
of Philosophy,
14 (1976),405-14.
, in:JournaloftheHistory
ofUniversals
Medievalnominalism
hasitsownnotinconsiderable
formostrecent
views
literature;
see Normore
1991a.I am indebted
to Courtenay
for
1987,201-17and Courtenay
metoseethisarticle
intypescript,
as forthesamereasontoYukioIwakuma,
allowing
whois preparing
an articleon Vocales
nominalists.
, orearly
7 Historia
Francica
Historiae
Francorum
, ed. A. Duchesne,
IV, Paris1641,89Scriptores
90 andbyM. Bouquet,Recueil
deshistoriens
desGaules
etdela France
XII, Paris1781,
4
3: 'Hoc tempore
tamindivinaquamin humanaphilosophia
floruerunt
Lanfrancus
Cantuariorum
episcopus,Guido Langobardus,
MaingaudusTeutonicus,Bruno
In dialcticaquoque hi potentes
Remensis,
qui posteavitamduxitheremiticam.
extiterunt
vocalemessedisseruit,
Ioannes,qui eandemartemsophisticam
sophistae:
5

09:07:18 AM

Robert who, according to notes attached to the Glosuleon Priscian in


the Chartres MS Bibl. mun. 209, f. 86v, held that the substantive
verb did not 4'have any substances'' but signified substantial differencesof a thing.8All we know of Arnulfof Laon is thathis teaching
about voces
, like that of Roscelin, was satirised withina poem in the
Codex Udalrici
. 9 I will come back to the unknown John later in my
paper. While scholars have often glumly lamented the paucity of
documentaryevidence relatingto early nominalism, I want to suggest
that our sources may not be so scarce, if we extend our gaze to
theology and grammar.
The Trinitarian
of Roscelin
theology
Roscelin' s dialecticand theologyare known more throughhis critics
than throughhis own words. Anselm was informedof his argument
about the Trinityin 1090 byJohn, a highlyplaced Roman cleric and
formermonk of Bee sent by Pope Urban II to act as advisor to Fulco,
the newly appointed monastic bishop of Beau vais. He reported that
Roscelin argued thatthe threepersons could not be one thingor otherwise the Father must have become incarnate with the Son.10 We can
RotbertusParisiacensis,
RoscelinusCompendiensis,
Arnulfus
Laudunensis.Hi
Ioannisfuerunt
etiamquamplures
habuerunt
auditores."
sectatores,
qui
8 Noteseditedby Hunt 1941-43;repr.in Collected
Papers31: "Magisteruero
Ruobertus
dixithocuerbum
nonhaberesubstantias
aliquas,sedpotiussubstantiales
diferentias
cuiuslibet
reisignificare
de qua predicatur
et illasdifipsumsubiectum,
ferentias
esseactionem
illiusuerbi,utcumdicimus'Homoest',hie 'est' significai
rationalitatem
etmortalitatem,
etinaliissimiliter."
On thisChartres
MS, seebelow,
p. 14.
9 Ph. Jaff,
Bibliotheca
rerum
Berlin1869,V 187.
Germanicarum,
10Anselmreproduces
theargument
III
128(ed. Schmitt
quotedbyJohnin Epistola
inDIV {I 282,285;II 4, 6-9):"Si < + indeoDIV2> tres
270-71),almostverbatim
suntunatantum
resetnonsunttresres< + unaquaequeDIV12> perse
personae
< + separatim
DIV2> , sicuttresangeliauttresanimae,ita tarnen
utvolntate
et
omninosintidem:ergopateretspiritus
sanctus
cumfilioincarnatus
est.' "
potntia
In Epistola
136 (III 279) to Fulco,bishopofBeauvais,Anselmomitsthesyllogistic
formofRoscelin'sargument
in orderto makeit seemevenmoreabsurd:"dicitin
deotrespersonas
essetresresab invicem
sicutsunttresangeli,itatarnen
separatas,
ut sitvoluntas
et potestas;
autpatrem
et spiritum
sanctum
esseincarnatum;
et tres
deosverepossedici,siususadmitteret."
GillianR. Evans'claiminAnselm
andTalking
about
GodyOxford1978,98 that"Apparently
hadbeensaying
Roscelin
thatLanfranc
andAnselmhadbothagreedthattheFatherandtheHolySpirithadbeenincarnate
withtheSon" is a considerable
distortion
of theargument
to Anselm.
reported
inaccurate
is Southern's
claim(StAnselm.
A Portrait
, 176) thatRoscelin
Similarly
musteitherbe so separatethatthey
"assertedthatthethreePersonsoftheTrinity
could(ifconvention
thatallthreemust
Gods;orsounited
allowed)be saidtobe three
6

09:07:18 AM

onlylament thatAnselm was unable to findany of Roscelin' s writings


which mighthave explained this argument.
Roscelin's logic has similarly been made notorious by negative
'
caricature. Abaelard mocked as 4'insane' his opinion that no thing
was made up of parts, parts being only vocesjust like species
, and that
since a house was nothingotherthan wall, roofand foundation,ifone
of its parts was a thing, that thing would have to be part of itself.11
Abaelard makes Roscelin look a fool by transformingobsession with
vocesinto an atomised view of realitywhich failedto recognisethat the
partswere only a whole whenjoined together.In a letterto the bishop
of Paris (c. 1120) Abaelard similarlyridiculed his teacher for explaining the scripturalwords "the part of a piece of fish" (Luke 24: 22) as
referringto part of a vox rather than of a thing.12Like Anselm,
Abaelard wanted to present Roscelin as an incompetentdialectician
whose insistenceon definingtermsas vocesled to conclusions thatwere
patentlyabsurd. In the face of such a bad press, can we make any
sense of these ideas?
The only document so far confidentlyattributedto Roscelin is a
long and angryletterto Abaelard, castigatinghis ungratefulpupil for
a varietyof offences,of which the most serious was to minimise the
differencesbetween the threepersons of the Trinity. It was identified
13
by Schmellerwithin a BenediktbeuernMS in 1849. The malicious
havebeenincarnate
inChrist."Roscelinwassayingthattheyhadtobe threethings
with
thattheFather
becameincarnate
(notthree
gods),ifonewastoavoidconcluding
theSon.
11Dial., 554-5:"Fuitautem,memini,
nostri
taminsanasententia
Roscellini
magisti
ut nullamrempartibus
constare
veliet,sed sicutsolisvocibusspecies,itaet partes
adscribebat.
Si quisautemremillamquedomusest,rebusaliis,pariete
scilicet
etfunconstare
si resillaque est
taliipsumargumentatione
damento,
diceret,
impugnabat:
paries,reiilliusque domusest,parssit,cumipsadomusnichilaliudsitquamipse
et fundamentum,
pariesettectum
parserit.
profecto
pariessui ipsiuset ceterorum
Atveroidemquomodosuiipsiusparsfuerit?
Amplius:omnis<pars> naturaliter
cumse nullomodo
priorestsuototo.Quomodoautempariespriorseetaliisdicetur,
priorsit?"
12Epist.14, ed. E.R. Smits,Peter
Letters
IX-X1V,
Abelard.
1983,280:"Hic
Groningen
sicutpseudodialecticus,
itaet pseudochristianus,
cumin Dialcticasua nullamrem
sedsolamuocempartesastruat,
itaetdiuinampaginamimpudenter
uteo
peruertit,
locoquo dicitur
dominuspartempiseisassicomedisse,
partemhuiusuoeisque est
reiintelligere
piseisassi,nonpartem
cogatur."ThetextinPL 178,358Dis corrupt.
Thiswas possibly
a veiledsuggestion
thatRoscelinwas skating
nearBerengarian
in hisexegesis
ofa traditional
"eucharistie"
verse.
heresy
13J.A. Schmeller
thetextwitharguments
foritsauthenticity
from
Munich,
published
Clm4643,ff.93v-99r
der
in
the
Klasseder
Abhandlungen
(s. xii)
philosophisch-philologisch
derWissenschaften
Akademie
Bd. 5.3 Munich1849,187-210;itwas
Kniglich
Bayerischen
re-edited
62-80.
byReiners1910as an appendix,
7

09:07:18 AM

insultsin thisletterhave tended to attractmore attentionthan its solid


speculative reflection.Although Reiners re-editedthe letterin 1910,
he did not analyse its contents,presumably because it did not touch
on what he believed to be the essence of nominalism- universais and
the relationshipbetween parts and whole. The letteris mostlyabout
the argument that one had to respect the pluralityof persons within
the Trinity.14Roscelin was fascinated by Augustine's comment that
what the Greeks described as one essence, three substances, that
Latins called one substance or essence and threepersons.15The identificationof person and substance made sense in the lightof Priscian's
definitionthat a nomensignifiedsubstance and quality. In the case of
names applied of God:
onethingandanother,
whether
topartsor
anynounsdo notsignify
according
toqualities,
buttheysignify
neither
dividedintopartsnor
itself,
onlysubstance
We do nottherefore
changedthrough
qualities.
signify
person
through
anything
otherthanthrough
substance
thatwe are accustomed
outofa certain
, granted
habitofspeechtotriple
totri, notsubstance
, as theGreeksareaccustomed
person
. Neither
indeedis ittobe saidthattheyerrin beliefin theTrinity
plesubstance
- as
becausetheyspeakdifferently
from
us,fortheybelievethesameas us,since
we havesaid- person
or essence
. substance
thesamethingin
signify
completely
God. Forinspeechthereis diversity,
inbelief
therewouldnot
unity;otherwise
be a Church
amongtheGreeks.Foriftheythemselves
sayonething
byspeaking
thus,I do notsee whywe lie bysayingthesamething.16
Roscelin does not deny the unityof God (as Anselm maintained), but
emphasizes thatplural names are applied out of linguisticconvention.
14Augustine's
Detrinitate
isthemostfrequently
citedwork;there
areextracts
toofrom
hisDe baptismo
De coniugiis
adulterinis
adlitteram,
De anima
, Deagone
christiano,
, De Genesi
eteiusorigine,
InIohannis
124, Epist.147, De doctrina
tractatus
Christiana.
Other
euangelium
arefrom:Prudentius,
extracts
; Gregory,
, Moraliainlob; Leo,
Peristephanon
Epistolae
Sermo
De fide
22, Ambrose,
, De spiritu
sancto'Isidore,Etymologiae
; Jerome,Contra
Vigilantium.
15Cf.Epist.adAbaelardum,
ed. Remers70,72,74,quoting
VII
De trinitate
Augustine,
4 n. 7 (CCSL 50, 259). See tooDe trinitate
V 8-9(CCSL 50, 216-7).
16Epist.adAbaelardum,
ed. Reiners72: "Sciendum
estvero,quodinsubstantia
sanctaetrinitatis
nominanonaliudetaliudsignificant,
ad partes
sivequantum
quaelibet
sive quantum
ad qualitates,
sedipsamsolamnoninpartesdivisam
necperqualitates
mutatamsignificant
substantiam.Non igiturper personamaliud aliquid
licet ex quadam loquendiconsuetudine
significamus,
quam per substantiam,
soleamus
nonsubstantiam,
sicutGraecitriplicare
soientsubstantriplicare
personam,
tiam.Nequeverodicendum
errent
est,quodinfidetrinitatis
substantiam,
triplicando
credunt
sive
quia licetaliterdicantquamnos,id tarnen
quodnos,quiasicutdiximus
siveessentiain deo prorsus
idemsignificant.
In locutione
personasivesubstantia
enimtantumdiversitas
est,in fideunitas.Alioquiniam nonessetapud Graecos
ecclesia.Si autemipsisic loquendoverumdicunt,quarenos idemdicendomentiamur,nonvideo."
8

09:07:18 AM

Following Priscian's definitionpersonasignifiesa substance, although


not- in God's case - a quality, as this would suggest mutabilityin
God. The argument runs diametricallycounter to Abaelard's identificationof a divine person with an attributelike power or wisdom.
We use eithersingular or plural names of God "only on behalf of the
wish of speakers to whom such a convention of speech is pleasing".
In language thatrecalls Abaelard's summaryof his teachingon parts,
Roscelin argues:
Whentherefore
we varythesenamesor proffer
themin thesingular
or in the
onething
rather
thananother,
but
plural,wedo thisnotbecauseitmight
signify
towhomsucha habitofspeechis pleasbyvirtue
onlyofthewillofthespeakers
weredifferent
ing.Forifthere
partsthere[inGod]so as tospeakofoneperson
and another
substance,
perhapstherewouldbe a reasonwhywe speakofone
another
in thepluralas we sayofa man- sincea body
thingin thesingular,
- thatthereis onesoulbutmanybodiesbecause
is onepart,thesoulanother
of thedifferent
is thereone qualitysignified
partsof thebody;but neither
- as we have
substance
or essence
, or anotherthrough
through
person
, because
no quality.17
alreadysaid- in God thereis completely
There is an inexorable logic to his argument that the proper names
'Father', 'Son' and 'Holy Spirit' must each signifya substance ifnone
signifya quality. This is not language about the substance of God, but
discussionofthreedifferent
nomina
, each of whichhad itsown identity,
as the cityof Rome was Rome and water was water.18The Greek definition of the Trinity as a pluralityof substances appealed because it
fittedwith Priscian's definitionof a noun, modifiedin only a limited
way. All utterancesused of God had to obey the rules of language.
One of these rules was the every noun, even those used of God,
signifieda substance. Such "grammatical Platonism" (to use a term
coined by Jean Jolivet) might be uncomfortableto those who prefer
to believe with Anselm that modern logicians did not believe in
17Ibid.73: "Quando
sivesingulariter
sivepluraliter
ergohaecnominavariamus
prononquia aliudunumquamalterumsignificet
hoc facimus,
sed prosola
ferendo,
Si enimdiversae
volntate,
loquentium
quibustalisloquendiususcomplacuit.
partes
ibi essent,utalterapersona,
alterasubstantia
fortassis
ratioaliquaesset,
diceretur,
curunumsingulariter,
alterum
uthominis,
pluraliter
proferremus,
quia alia parsest
aliaanima,unamanimam
sedpluracorpora
corpus,
dicimus,
propter
corporis
partes
diversas.Sed equealia qualitasperpersonam,
alia persubstantiam
velessentiam
in deo nullaprorsus
sienificatur,
quia sicutiamdiximus,
qualitasest."
18Ibid.74:
in hac pluralitate
secundum
"Quae ergodifferentia
personarum
nos,
substantiarum
vero secundumGraecossit, perquiramus.
Nihilenimaliud est
substantia
filiiquamfilius,
sicuturbsRomaeRoma
patris
quampater,etsubstantia
est,et creatura
aquae aqua est."
9

09:07:18 AM

universal substances.19Roscelin believed thatwords signifiedthingsat


a very literal level. He wanted to respect the identityof every proper
noun invented by man. His proper nouns are like the individualised
reliefsof a Romanesque capital, each a human utterancesignifyingin
its own way a substantial realitybeyond.
Astonishingly neither Schmeller nor Reiners noticed that
immediately preceding Roscelin's letter in the Benediktbeuern
manuscriptoccur two shorttheologicalessays closelyrelatedin literary
style.The firstexplores both common ground and differencesbetween
God and creation, with particularreferenceto the Trinity,definedas
a pluralityof things. The second, inspired by a homily of Augustine
on John, explains the contrastbetween Christ's special love forJohn
and Peter's special love forChrist in termsof the contrastbetween the
active life of this world and the contemplative life of the world to
come.20 These are the only theological items within an otherwise
secular manuscript.21
The firstessay, which we shall call Notandumest after its incipit,
helps explain the argument criticized by St Anselm. In some things
God and creation are similar: just as differentaccidents of the same
substance cannot be identifiedwith each other, so the Father cannot
be identifiedwith the Son or the Holy Spirit. In God however, unlike
creation, the divine persons are not divided between substance and
accident. There is a trinityin God, which can be described as three
persons or threeres.The authoritycited forthisclaim is the Greek definition of the persons as three ousieor substances.22The underlying
19Cf. Jolivet,1966and, in relationto Abaelard,
Jolivet,1975a,532-43.Jolivet
on
of Bernardof Chartres
of theteaching
foundations
examinesthegrammatical
desrapports
inElments
oftheproblem
a widersurvey
within
substance
pourunetude
imMittelalter
undErkenntnis
au moyen
etl'ontologie
entre
la grammaire
, ed.
ge, in: Sprache
within
his
Berlin1981, 135-64.Allthesepapershavebeenreprinted
A. Zimmerman,
dulangage
Doctrines
Ablard.
mdivale.
dela pense
, Paris1987.
Aspects
20Augustine,
toAnne-Mane
124(CCSL 36,680). I amindebted
inIohannem
Tract,
Bouchforthisidentification.
21Thesetextsfollow
worksol Seneca(copiedin thesamehand),lhe letter
on from
on Boethius'De
a commentary
is followed
by adviceon castinga horoscope,
anda late
oflearning
fromHughofSt Victoron thedivision
an excerpt
arithmetical
a separate
oflogic.The firstpartofClm 4643,originally
treatise
twelfth-century
texts.Foran editionofthesetwotexts,
ofhistorical
a variety
contains
manuscript,
Some
NewTexts
andRoscelin:
seemystudy
StAnselm
oftheir
anddiscussion
authorship,
1
n.
andTheir
//,
above).
(see
Implicationsforthcoming
22f.91v:"In istisconueniunt
Namincreatuns
etcreature.
In alusdifferunt.
creator
eiusdemsubuelpluraaccidentia
uelplurespartes,
ueleru<n>t pluressubstantie,
Namindeosunt
estibi.Hoc autemnonesti<n> creatore.
exquo pluralitas
stantie,
10

09:07:18 AM

argumentis the same as in Roscelin's letter:with each divine person


thereis no accidental quality, only a distinctsubstance. Human words
inevitablysuggest plurality. Such language is far removed from the
eternal simplicity.
A similarantithesisis central to an anonymous essay found within
a Durham Cathedral manuscript(A. IV. 15) containing the firstbook
of Abaelard's TheologiaChristiana
in its earliestknown recension.23This
which
we shall call Est una afterits incipit, explains on rational
text,
4
groundshow thereexisted a 'one and perfectunityin which there is
'
a certainwonderfultrinity.' The images used to describe this trinity
are unconventional. The standard Augustinin explanation,
developed by Boethius, had been that the three divine persons were
threerelationswithinGod. Est una describes each as differentiated
by
- a term used by Aristotlein the
a habitudo
to describe an
Categories
individual's disposition. 'Father', 'Son' and 'Holy Spirit' are names
invented to signifythree ineffabledistinctionsin God.
Each is described
to theproperty
of theGreek
singlyas a person;according
as threesubstances.
Forwhatsubstance
is forthe
languagetheyare described
Greeks,thisis soundedbyLatinsas person
; and thesethreepersonsarefound
in certain
to be spokenofas things,
butinfrequently.24
manuscripts
The author then answers the conundrum "if the Father and the Holy
Spirit are of the same substance, then the Son is begotten of the
substance of the Holy Spirit" by identifyingeach attributeas a propriumof each person. The essay closes with an allusion to Romans 1:
19-20: "To such a thoughtyou may say that the philosophersof the
world rose throughvisible created things." One can arrive at the doctrine of the Trinity by reflectingon categories of the natural world.
necintelligere.
Nonsunttressubstanquedamtria;homodicere(f.92r)nonpotest,
eiusdem
substantie.
Trespersone
ueltres
tie,equetrespartes,
equetriaaccidentia
resdicipotest.
Hoc enimdicitautoritas.
Grecidicunttresusie,id esttressubstantie,
sedaccipiunt
substantias
propersonis.
Quid autemsintillepersoneuel illetresres,
nonpotest.
Namnequesuntsubstantia
Sed indeononsunt
explicari
equeaccidens.
inmediata
etaccidens.Ita aliutestincreatore,
aliutincreaturis.
Necest
substantia,
mirum
si factor
a sua factura
diffrt."
23I firstnotedthistextwithin
of theDurhamMS in Peter
Abelard's
description
Christiana
andTheologia
'Scholarium'
in:RTAM, 52 (1985),113-5,
re-examined,
Theologia
in thisstudyI had notthenrealisedthatit was followed
although
by threeother
texts.
patristic
"
24D f.66v: Persona
tarnen
dicitur
de hiset singulariter
ut dicaturprimo,persona
secundoet tertio;et ita dicaturiii personeet etiamsecundum
proprietatem
grece
tressubstantie.
linguedicuntur
, hoca latinis
Quod enimestapudgrecossubstantia
sonatpersona
etinueniuntur
isteiiipersone
inquibusdam
codicibus
dicires
, sedrare."
11

09:07:18 AM

Its author imitatesthe methodof Anselm's Monologion


: initialreflection on divine unity is transformedinto reflectionon the necessary
4
pluralityin God, to which the names of persons' and 'substances' are
variously applied by Greeks and Latins. This argument, which St
Anselm reminded potential criticshad been upheld by Augustine, is
central to Notandumestand to Roscelin' s letterto Abaelard as well as
to Est una. Their common theme is that 'Father', 'Son' and 'Holy
Spirit' are each proper nouns with an identityas distinctas plural
substances or things. Roscelin picked up Anselm's perception
(inspired by Augustine) that there were differentpossible ways of
describing the ineffabletruthof the divine trinity.However, where
Anselm tended to emphasise the continuity between human and
divine language, Roscelin focussed on the gulf between human
language and divine simplicity.
and the "Glosule" on Priscian
Person-things
Where did the idea come from,so reprehensibleto St Anselm, that
a divine person could be identifiedwith a thing?Althoughthese texts
buttresstheirargument by quoting Augustine, the image is not to be
found in his writings.Even Abaelard in his Sic etNon only raked up
one, relatively obscure text by Rufinus, to support the claim.25
Anselm's invectivehas tended to make us search forits stimulusin his
dialectic, in particular his supposed belief thatjust as the world was
composed of radically discrete entities,none of which shared a common or universal nature, so the three divine persons were also
radically discrete. It is oftenassumed that Roscelin was not a serious
theologian. Did not Abaelard mock his literalism in considering a
whole (like a house) simply as its parts (a wall, roof and foundation)
instead of recognisingthatthe partswere only a whole when theywere
joined together?Such criticismcan mislead us ifwe read it as a guide
to Roscelin' s ontology rather than as a comment on his analysis of
every term, genus, species or part, as a vox. Roscelin' s unstated
authorityin his letterto Abaelard was Priscian, the great analyst of
voces.The names Father, Son and Holy Spirit, are voceseach of which
25Onlyn. 37 of forty-two
in q. 8 "Quod non sit multitudo
rerumin
excerpts
oftheSicetNon, ed. B. BoyerandR. McKeon,Chicago1976-77,135
trinitate...",
speaksof pluralthings,Rufinus,Comm.in Symb.
Apostolorum
(CCSL 20, 139):
luciset producit
"Quomodoigniscaelestis
generaiex se ipsosplendorem
vaporem,
et cumsinttriain rebus,unumsuntin substantia,
ita trinitas
estuna maiestas."
12

09:07:18 AM

refersto somethingcalled eithera person (by the Latins), a substance


(by the Greeks) or a thing. As this kind of person could not signifya
quality in God, it had to signifya substance. This theologyderives
fromrigorousacceptance of the universal validityof Priscian's definition of the meaning of a noun.
Anselm classifiedRoscelin as one of those ' 4modern dialecticians"
who did not believe that universalisubstances were anythingbut a
flatumvocis.According to the HistoriaFranckathese dialecticians were
inspired by John, "who taught dialectic to be a vocal art". The
seminal author forany speculative discussion of vocesin the eleventh
was beginning to
centurywas Priscian, whose Institutiones
grammaticae
in
the
Ars
maior
of
so
beloved
of CarolDonatus,
outstrip popularity
ingian schoolmasters.Was Roscelin inspiredby contemporarydialectical discussion of Priscian's grammatical categories? Anselm refers
ratherdisparaginglyto such inquiryinto Priscian' s ideas at the end of
the De grammatico
when he complains to his disciple of "the extentto
which dialecticiansin our timesare at loggerheads about the question
which you put- whethergrammaticus
, classifiedby Priscian both as a
noun and an adjective, was a substance or a quality.26The De Grammaticowas his responseto such debate. Are these the same dialecticians
as he warns against in the De incarnatione
verbi?
In no other eleventh-centurycomposition is dialectical interestin
grammarmore evidentthan in theanonymous Glosuleon books I-XVI
of theInstitutiones
Grammaticae.
Its author is concerned throughoutwith
the causae inventionum
of the individual vocesdiscussed by Priscian.27
The earliestcompletewitnessis Cologne Cathedral MS 201, probably
dating fromthelate eleventhcentury.Its textcontains a recensiondifferentfrom,and possibly earlier than that found in fourother manuscripts, all from the early twelfthcentury: Metz, Bibi. mun. 1224,
ff. Ira-11Orbfr0m eastern France; Paris, BN nouv. acq. lat. 1623,
26De Grammatico
I 168;cf.D. P. Henry,TheDe Grammatico
, ed. Schmitt
,
ofStAnselm
Notre-Dame
1964,pp. 88-91.
27Theimportance
oftheGlosule
wasfirst
indicated
byHunt,1941-43.See too:Fredborg1977;id., SomeNotesontheGrammar
, in: CIMAGL, 37
ofWilliam
ofConches
Grammar
Philoso(1981),21-41;herchapter
, in:A History
Speculative
ofTwelfth-Century
, ed. PeterDronke,Cambridge
177-86.Forwhatfollows
on the
phy
1988,especially
and incunable
tradition
oftheGlosule
I am indebted
to thepioneering
manuscript
discoveries
ofMargaret
Works
thePrinted
Editions
Gibson,TheCollected
1470ofPriscian:
'
'Glosule
1859yin: StudiMedievali,
ser.3a 18(1977),249-60and TheEarlyScholastic
'
toPriscian
Grammaticae':
theText
anditsInfluence
in:
, Institutiones
29
235, ibid., (1979),
54. I am grateful
tooto C.H. Kneepkens
forcomment
on itstext.
13

09:07:18 AM

ff. lr-54v an abbreviated text fromSaint-Benot-surLoire; Brussels,


Bibi. roy. 3920, ff. 12ra-vb(the prologue). The now destroyedChartres MS, Bibl. mun. 202, ff.lr-68v,contained additional passages not
found in the otherMSS. None of these MSS identifyan author to the
'
Glosule.Our only attributionis to a Johannes de aingre" mentioned
in the colophon to the 1488 incunable edition of Arrivabenus, a
printerof Mantua who relied on a good manuscriptverylike thatnow
in Metz.28 An impossible form in Latin, de aingrecould well be a
printer's corruptionof dei gratia, the traditionalinterpretationof the
name John. The device "by him whose name means the grace of
God" is used to indicate the author of anothervery influentialglosule
on the Pauline epistles writtenin 1102 and closely related to those
attributed to Bruno of Rheims (also concerned with the causes of
words, in this case of St Paul).29 Whether these two glosuleare by the
same author still has to be investigated. There is a dry irony in the
author of a Priscian commentary so concerned with the causes of
words being identifiedas "John by the grace of God".
One word whose cause the Glosuleis much concerned with, is 'person', defined by Priscian in relation to a verb: the firstis one who
speaks about himself,eitheralone or withothers;the second is the one
28 1488unfoliated
e.g. 1492f.226; 1511f.204): "Iohannis
(resetin othereditions,
arcem[al. artem]possedit:
de aingre:summosqui interexpositores
grammaticae
' Cf.
finit.'
desideratissimum
uolumine
omnibus
commentum
supermagnoPrisciani
textoftheGlosule
253n. 14. The Arrivabenus
Works
Gibson,TheCollected
ofPriscian
Veniceedition
ofPrisofthe1496-97
a microfilm
is accessible
reproduction
through
theirseriesItalian
within
cian'sOpera
, published
Company
bytheGeneralMicrofilm
Mass. 1980-,Roll 463 item2. Subsequent
1601, Cambridge,
BooksPrinted
Before
heldin theRareBooksroomofRutgers
areto theVenice1511edition,
references
notalleditions
I ammostgrateful.
towhosestaff
Unfortunately
Library,
University
sharethesamefoliation.
29The information
toParis,BN lat.14442:"In nomine
theinitalrubric
comesfrom
sancti.Incipiuntur
epistolarum
pauliab iliovidelicet
glos[u]le
patrisetfiliietspiritus
de iherusolima
inannoquocons[u]lpictaviensis
cuiusnomengratiadeiinterpretatur
toWilliamVII ofPoitou,dukeof
rediit."A. Stoelennotesthatthiscouldonlyrefer
in
in 1101,butwaspresent
at Poitiers
wholeftforJerusalem
Aquitaine1086-1126,
leChartreux
attribues
Bruno
1102,Lescommentaires
, in: RTAM,25 (1958),
scripturaires
thisauthoron theeucharist
177-247at 186n. 11. Stoeleneditsa longpassagefrom
surl'eucharistie
etla *Lettre
deS. Anselme'
inBruno
leChartreux
, in:RTAM,
,JeanGratiadei
34 (1967),18-83.
30Instit.
tres,
VIII 101,ed. Keil II 448: "Suntigiturpersonaeverborum
Gramm.
ad
ut
'dico
se
sola
vel
cum
de
secunda,
dicimus',
aliis,
est,
quam
loquitur
prima quae
dequa extraseetillam,
deipsavelsolavelcumaliis,ut'dicisdicitis',
tertia,
loquitur,
ad quamdirigit
sermonem,
prima,ut'dicitdicun.etprimaquidem
positaloquitur
tertia
enimdemonstrantur,
et secundaverborum
sunt,praesentes
personaefinitae
utdefiniatur."
estitaqueegetplerumque
veroinfinita
pronomine,
14

09:07:18 AM

spoken to about himself,and the thirdis the one spoken about apart
fromoneselfand the person being addressed.30Applyingthe Boethian
res-vox
antithesisto the senses of 'person' as used by Priscian, the commentatorconsiders 'person' as both realis(the thingbeing referredto)
and vocalis(the word itself). He anticipates his explanation of Priscian's discussion in VIII 101, with a remark on VIII 66 about the
relativepriorityof the firstperson over the other two persons. Here,
he glosses a person as a thing.31Could this have been the point of
'
departureforRoscelin's trinitariantheology?In the TheologiaSummi
boni' Abaelard refutes Roscelin's definition of the Trinity as a
pluralityof thingsby explaining that Priscian' s definitionof 'person'
referredto threeproperties.32He is here criticisingan idea, not just
of Roscelin but one laid down in the Glosule.
The commentatorexplains himself more fully when expounding
Priscian's definitionof 'person' in VIII 101:
Thewordpersoncanbe takenindifferent
ways:foritmeansa certain
quality,
whichwe can callpersonality
and thisprothemselves,
adjacentto thethings
in thatqualitywhichwe call persons
perly;it designates
things
participating
thanksto thethingwhichtheyreceive;it [thewordperson]is also takenin
- a quality
ofanother
ofsignifying
designation
quality,
namely
personal
things
verbs:forwhenI say44 'I read'is a person"I do notsay
adjacenttopersonal
thatinthisverbis thatthing
rather
themeaning
ofthings
"personality",
subjacenttopersonality;
so saying" 41 read'is a person"is "signifying
a personal
thing."33
31I citetheGlosule
to the1502edition(e), corrected
wherenecessary
according
by
reference
to theCologneMS (K). K 35vae 114v:"Alia similitudo
de ordinepersimiliter
sonarum,
quod dicitsicutin dictisaliismodispraeponitur:
prima
persona
aliispersonis
hascausas:quiaperipsam
realem
, id estperprimam
praeponitur
propter
ab ipsaostenditur
secunda
realis:quia ad ipsamloquitur
significatam
primaet tertia
realis:quiade ipsaloquitur,
etuereperprimam
ostenditur
secundaet tertia:namnisi
sitprima
realisnoneritsecundaveltertia;
nondicitnonesseresquae dicuntur
(-unt
ea requaedicitur
etiamdestructa
e) secundaettertia
persona
prima;sedsubhacprononremanere
utdicantur
secundaettertia
siue(si nonsite) alia ressubhac
prietate
utdicatur
aliis,quiaomnis
proprietate
primaetideoetiampreponitur
primapersona
naturaliter
estantecausatiua
id estantesuoseffectus."
(propriis
K) causaefficiens
32TSumII 108,p. 153; TchrIII 175,p. 261.
33VIII 101K 40vbe 123v:
uerborum
<personae
[Sm/i
igitur
tres>]"Sciendumhanc
uocempersona
diuersisaccipimodis:significai
enimquandamqualitatem,
quam
uocarepersonalitatem
et hoc proprie;dsignt
possumus
ipsisrebusadiacentem,
etiamresiliaqualitate
participantes
quas solemusuocarepersonasgratiareiquam
etiamin designatione
alterius
scilicet
suscipiunt;
accipitur
qualitatis
significationis
rerum
namcumdico"lego
personaJium
quae qualitasadiacetuerbispersonalibus;
estpersona"nondicohuicuerboinessepersonalitatem
remillamimmosignificationemrerumpersonalitati
et estdicere"lego estpersona",id est
subiacentium,
rempersonalem.
Itemaccipitur
uerbasignificationem
significans
personasignificans
"
rerumpersonalium
participantia.
15

09:07:18 AM

In identifying'person' as both 'word' and 'thing', the commentator


was tryingto clarifythe reason behind the impositionof thisparticular
word. The firstperson was both "that thingwhich spoke about itself'
and, as a word, "that which signifieda thingspeaking about itself'.
One had always to ask whether'person' was being used as a thingor
as a word. "A thingis the cause of the vox",34 In this case the personthing was the cause of the word 'person'. The commentatorwanted
to distinguisha word fromthat which it signified.By twelfth-century
standards,thisterminologymightseem clumsy,but it was an attempt
all the same.
The commentatordid not accept some people's interpretationthat
"about oneself" in Priscian's definitionhad to enunciate an action or
a passion about oneself,distinctfromthe firstperson of the pronoun.35
He argued that the same person lay behind the pronoun as the verb.
The comentator then proferredas the opinion of "certain people"
(i.e. himself)the explanation he had already presentedas his own, that
Priscian was referringto 'person' both as a thing and as a word,
imposed to designate somethingreal. Expanding on Priscian's definition of the firstand second persons as finite,he noted that "I read"
representsthe speaker as "You read" representsthe one spoken to.
" or
This was true according to themselves"m/reales
according to their
" ut vocales". The third
infinite
needed to be
person, being
meaning
a
defined by a pronoun to be finitething in itself.
The commentator's concern to distinguish the cause of 'person'
(i.e. the thing) fromthe word itselfis only one example of his desire
to establish the causes of those vocesanalysed by Priscian. He was
particularlyinterestedin expanding upon those oftenbriefpassages in
which Priscian tried to establish philosophical principles to different
34Ibid.: "Cum igitur
hisquattuor
modisetsinedubioaequiuocepersona
accipiatur:
duas tantum
scilicet
Priscianus,
personehic tractat
significationes
agitde persona
secundum
rerumpersonalitati
subiectarum
et in
significationem
(K designationem)
uerborum
suntei secundarie:
cumdebetdifdesignatione
quae duae significationes
utsuperius
finire
earnperprimam,
diuidit
secundam
etterconiugationem
personam
tiam:in qua dicerem(K 41ra)satisinnuitur
diffinitio
personae.Nam personam
dicimusrealemquaeuel dese loquitur
deipsauel de qua
, uel ad quamprimaloquitur
uocalemuerouocemhancpersonam
loquiturprimaad secundam,
significantem.
Prima
est.Hie diffinit
et secundum
remet secundum
uocem:et
primampersonam
facit.Res enimestcausauoeis:etsicdicitresiliaestprima
competenter
quae
persona
sermonem
de quocumque
habitm
siuedesesiuede alio:
, id estquae profert
loquitur
eccerealis.Primauoealisestquae significai
remloquentem
dese,ethancnobisinnuit
cumdicitquaeloquitur
dese, id estprofert
uocemse significantem."
35VIII 101K 41ra 123v.
16

09:07:18 AM

4
partsof speech. Every noun had a thing' or resas its cause. This principle may help us understand the trinitarianargument St Anselm
foundso perplexing.While Priscian never explicitlyidentifieda noun
witha thing,he did say thatit was "a part of speech which distributes
a common or a proper (i.e. particular) quality of subject bodies or
things to each" (II 22). Priscian's definitionof a noun takes for
grantedthe primaryexistenceof subject bodies or things.A quality is
what thesebodies or thingsshare. When explaining that it was proper
to a noun to signifysubstance and quality [II 18], the commentator
observed that here Priscian was not using substance in its customary
sense of "a thingwith subsistingaccidents", but in a broader sense
of all essence. In his lengthygloss on the definition,he preferredto
use substance to referto the specific thing:
thatsubstance
forwhichitwasfoundtodesignate,
either
[A noun]... signifies
from
another
orsimilar< through
> thesharing
separate
through
anyproperty
ofanyproperty.
Forpropernamesarefoundand imposedso thattheyalways
somecertain
others
somecertain
signify
personseparatefrom
through
properties.Propernounsarefoundto designate
substances
in thattheyare separate
in theirproperties.
... Similarly
commonnames[appellativa
J are foundto
substances
similar
toothers
inanyquality,
as mansignifies
designate
manywith
one commonproperty,
and mortality,
becausesinceman
namelyrationality
thatoneas muchas thisone,itsignifies
a certain
common
to
signifies
property
be inall,inwhich
thatis properties,
aretheespecialcause
theyagree.Qualities,
ofthefinding
ofnouns.Forifnounswerefoundonlyto designate
substances,
so manydifferent
nounswouldbe superfluous,
sincethisname"substance"
wouldsuffice;
butsincesubstance
inas muchas theyareorexist
signifies
things
in themselves
iftakenstrictly,
itdetermines
inthesethings
neither
corporality,
whiteness
orblackness
oranything
elseofthis
animation,
sensibility,
rationality,
kind.Itwasnecessary
tofinddifferent
nameswhichdetermined
theseandother
different
themselves.36
qualitiesin things
36II 18K 13rae 24v: Proprium
estnominis
substantiam
[
significare
] "... scilicet
significai
illamsubstantiam
ad quamdesignandam
estinuentum,
ueldiscretam
ab aliaperaliuel similem
communionem
alicuiusproprietatis.
quamproprietatem
Propriaenim
nominasicsuntinuenta
etimposita
utsemper
signifcent
aliquamcertam
personam
ab aliisperaliquascertasproprietates;
discretam
nonenimsuntinuenta
difpropter
ferentiam
sed tantumad discernendas
in substantiis
substantiarum,
proprietates
utpotest
uideriin Socrate.Socrates
certam(K 13rb)personam
existentes,
significai
etdiscretam
ab aliisnoninsubstantia
essesedperhasproprietates
quodSophronisci
filius
cumenimeademsubstantia
sitin omnibus
est,quodpoetaet alia huiusmodi;
hominis
mortale
et nondiffrant
indiuiduis,
quia omnishomoestanimalrationale
nisiinqualitatibus,
inuentasuntpropria
nominaad designandas
substantias
in hoc
in suis proprietatibus.
Similiter
quod suntdiscretae
appellatiuasuntinuentaad
substantias
similes
aliisinaliquaqualitate,
uthomosignificai
designandas
plurescum
unacommuni
scilicet
cumrationalitate,
et mortalitate,
proprietate,
quia cumhomo
tambeneiliumquamistumsignificet,
significai
quandamcommunem
proprietatem
esse in omnibus,in qua conueniunt.
Sunt ergoqualitates,id est proprietates
17

09:07:18 AM

The commentatorinsists that substance and quality are not signified


in the same way, as if both substance and quality are nouns. Rather
a noun names a substance:
a qualitynot by
becauseit [thenoun] is imposedon it, whilesignifying
anddetermining
in relation
toa substance.
butbyrepresenting
nomenclature,
Forthisreasoneverynounhas twomeanings,
onethrough
on the
imposition
ofthequalityofthesubstance,
so
theotherthrough
substance,
representation
thething
orofothermen,bynaming
that'man'signifies
ofSocrates
it,deterand mortality
aboutit byrepresentation.37
mining
rationality
The commentator was aware that his interpretationdid not please
everybody.Some wanted nouns to name substance and qualityjoined
together,so that "Socrates" was the name both of the substance and
of the accidents which informedit: "which is proved not to be by
many and various arguments".38 The refutationof their argument
Namsi propter
causainuentionis
nominum.
solassubstantias
designandas
praecipua
inuenirentur
inuentaessenttotdiuersa,cumsolumhocnomen
nomina,superflue
in quantum
sed quia substantia
restantum
substantia
ad hocsuficeret;
significat,
in ipsisrebuscornec determinai
si proprieaccipitur,
sunt,uel per se existunt
rationalit
uelnigredinem
animationem,
sensibilitatem,
atem,albedinem
poreitatem,
necessefuitinueniri
nominadiuersaquae hasdiuersas
uelaliquidaliudhuiusmodi,
in ipsisrebusdeterminarent."
et aliashuiusmodi
qualitates,
37Ibid.[ = De Rijk,LM II. 1, p. 228 n.]: "Notandum
esttamenquodnomennon
etqualitatem
itaututriusque
consubstantiam
insimul
scilicet
nuncupatiue,
significat
nominat
iunctisitnomenuel utriusque
tantum,
perse nomensit,sed substantiam
uerosignificai
nonnuncupatiue,
immorepresenquia ei fuitimpositum,
qualitatem
substantiae
circasubstantiam;
tandoetdeterminando
propter
quamtamennotandam
unaperimpositionem
fuitimpositum.
Quareomnenomenduashabetsignificationes:
uthomo
in qualitate
in substantia,
alteram
ipsiussubstantiae,
perrepresentationem
id estnominando
remSocratiset ceterorum
hominum,
perimpositionem
significai
et mortalitatem
et hocrepresentando."
circailia rationalitatem
determinans
38Ibid.: "Similiter
albumperimpositionem
quia
corpusidestnuncupatiue,
significat
etalbedodicantur
alba", in
qui dixit"dicaturhaecresalba", nondixit"substantia
uerosignificat
ut prinalbedinem
per representationem,
quo notaturimpositio,
aequeplacet;uoluntenimquidamnomina
ciplemcausam.Sed istudnonomnibus
substantiam
etqualitatem.
Verbigratia,
hoc
nominare
scilicet
coniunctum
utrumque
et accidentium
nomen"Socrates"dicitnomenesse substantiae
quibusformatur
et cetera
substantia
filiationem,
albedinem,
lineam,Sophronisci
[/-antur-entie];
illam
accidentia
Socratem
dicuntesse partescomponentes
{e 25r)quae informant
etuariisnecessariis
substantiam
Socrates;
quodnonessemultis
quae dicitur
primam
reiSocratiscumipse
Si enimalbedoessetparsconstitutiua
probatur
argumentis.
albedoeritfundamentum,
et ita fundamentum,
Socratessitprimasubstantia
quod
uelperse uelcumaliisiunctum
estinconueniens.
Numquamenimaliquodaccidens,
substantiae
scilicetet
Itemsi Socratesestnomenutriusque
eritsustentamentum.
inconstituidestea accidentia
illudquodactualiter
illasformas,
accidentium,
suscipit
Namnequeestresperse existens
nihilesseprobatur.
tioneSocratis
[K subsistens],
Si dicatur
nonestaccidentalis.
Si dicaturesseresperse subsistens
necaccidentalis.
nonestaccidentalis,
esse resperse subsistens
quia homospeciesessenonpotest;
immo
necaliudhuiusmodi
actualiter
homoenimensspeciesnecalbedinem
suscipit
18

09:07:18 AM

formsan importantpart of his discussion of a noun. "For ifwhiteness


was a constitutivepart of the thing of Socrates, since Socrates is a
proper(or particular)substance, thuswhitenesswill be its foundation,
. For no accident can ever be a
which is inappropriate {inconueniens)
foundationeitherin itselfor joined with another. Renouncing thereforethisopinion, we say that Socrates designates a substance affected
with qualities, which 'I' and 'you' signify,but they do not represent
there qualities.,,
The distinctionbetween substance and quality distinguishesPriscian's approach to a pronoun fromthatof Donatus. Like most ancient
grammarians,Donatus had taughtthat pronouns stood fora noun in
general. Priscian on the otherhand had insistedthat a pronoun stood
for a proper noun.39 His commentatorunderstood Priscian to teach
that pronouns signifiedpure substance, unlike nouns which signified
substance with quality.40It was not only 'person' that the commentatoridentifiedas 'thing'; any pronoun came under a similar category
as it signifieda thing or a substance, devoid of any quality.41
The commentatorwas fascinated by the implication of Priscian's
distinctionbetween subject and quality in the definitionof a noun.
Roscelin of Compigne took thisdistinctionforgrantedwhen discussing the threeproper nouns 'Father', 'Son' and 'Holy Spirit' as three
subjects. He definedthemvariably as thingsor substances, not signifyingqualities because thiswould denote variabilityin God. While the
Glosuleis not concerned with theologicalissues, it does lay down very
precise rules about the meaning of a proper noun. Glossing Priscian's
tantum.Socratesiterumnon potestesse quia est pars substantiae
potentialiter
Socratis
secundum
hancsententiam.
Rursussi Socrates
et sicde
nominat
utrumque
ceteris
nominibus
nullaesseconuincitur.
Debentenimpropronominum
significatio
nominapuramsubstantiam
Sed cumdicamin designationem
Socratis
significare.
"Tu legis"etSocrates
substantiam
etqualitatem,
tuutrumque
dsignt
designabat;
Renunciandoergo huic sententiae
dicimusSocratem
quod est inconueniens.
substantiam
affectam;
designare
quamdamqualitatibus
quamipsamsignificant
ego
et tu,sed nonrepresentant
ibi qualitates;
quod facitSocrates.Hoc autemin hac
sententia
attendendum
quodSocratesipseetsiplureshabeatformas
quamhomoet
aliudsuperius,
noncrescit
tarnen
ab illisin quantitate."
quodlibet
39IrneRosierandJeanStefanini,
mdivales
dupronom
Thories
etdunom
, in:
gnral
De Ortu
Grammaticae.
Studies
inmedieval
andlinguistic
inmemory
grammar
theory
ofJanPinSten Ebbesenand KonradKoerner,Amsterdam, ed. G.L. Bursill-Hall,
borg
1990,285-303,esp. 288.
Philadelphia
40See n. 36 above;see tooGlosule
on XIII, 31.
41Glosule
on II 29: liQuihabeatsignificare
omnemillamremad quamproferatur.
Habetsignificare
eteasdemproprietates
uoxad quamrefertur";
cf.
quasdeterminai
Rosierand Stefanini,
295.
19

09:07:18 AM

comment about nouns applying to "subject bodies and things", the


commentator suggested that Priscian could here be referringto two
kinds of substance- corporeal and incorporeal.42One possibilitywas
thatincorporealsubstance were things,while bodies were visible to the
senses (alternativelybodieswere substantial things, while thingswere
accidental). When explaining Priscian's definition,the commentator
"
4
preferredto explain 'subject bodies and things" as corporeal and
42II 22 K 14rae 26r [passagesnot in K are in smalltype]:" Nomen
estpars
earum
a se inuicempartibusorationisper proprietates
> . Distinctis
< orationis
sufficienter
breuiterannotatasde singularum
tractat,
incipiensa
proprietatibus
deindeaccidenenimeiuspriusponitproprietates,
nominehocmodo.Substantiales
Tractat
tractatus
totusnominis
in quibustractandis
talesproprietates
peneuersatur.
exprima
habent
ftcationem
idestsecundum
secundum
denomine
autem
inuentionem,
quam
signi
primam
uocis.
formam
Conetsecundum
etsecundum
eius
diffinitione
estinprima
inuentione,
ethymologiam
quod
secundum
nominis
autemin nomineduo cumiliotertio
siderantur
quaetria
ipsius
ethymologia
etUOcis
scilicet
denomine
I significationem
tractatum
totum
ilium
compositionem,
dispont
ipsae
tamsubstantialis
nascitur
exquibusduobusomniseiusproprietas
quamaccidentalis.
illaproprietas
substantialis
eniminestnomini
Secundum
quae ineius
significationem
formam
Secundum
cumqualitate.
substantiam
scilicet
diffinitione
notatur,
significare
illud
nomen
innomine
sine
forma
etcompositio
ualet
secundum
tantum
UOcis
quod
ponet
compositionem,
estalbedo.
utabalbum
anderiuatiuum
idestansitprimitiuum
abaliquo,
uelnonsitsumptum
sumptum
Cumenimnomendiffiniens
distribuit.
subdiuisione
hancautemdiffinitionem
Nomen
in comdiuiditqualitatem
deberetdicerenomensignificai
substantiae,
qualitatem
istam.Nomenaliudproprium,
etacceditperhocad diuisionem
munemetpropriam
Res
etinincorpoream.
incorpoream
Diuiditetiamsubstantiam
aliudappellatiuum.
coretomnesresaliorum
substantiam;
uocatsubstantias
propter
predite
incorpreas
uocatomnes
uelcorpora
subiacent:
corporeis
porauocatistauisibiliaquae sensibus
Notaiterum
resomnesaccidentales.
ressubstantiales,
ponit
quia prosignificatone
modo
a tribuendo,
Nomenenimdicitur
distribuit
exequendouocisaetymologiam.
id estsignifcatiua
nonestparsorationis
diffinitionem,
prosingulauerbaprosequemur
utsignificando
nisisignificet,
antedebetappellari
uox. Nullaenimuoxparsorationis
nonquodsemper
uocatutsupraindictione
iuuarepossit.Etpartem
orationis
sensum
cumaliisiunctaeffici
sedquiaaptumestad hocutparsorationis
inoratione
consistt,
terminado
dicat;ab huiusdiffinitionis
possit.Cum ergonomenpartemorationis
id est
excludit.
etomnesuocesnonsignificatiuas
Sequitur
quodparsdistribuit
syllabas
uel id est uidelicet
uel propriam
diuersamscilicetcommunem
tribuit;
qualitatem
siuererum
tributam
uelpropriam
communem
unicuique
corporum
qualitatem
significationem
Sensusest: Nomen
siueincorporeae.
hoc estsiue ilia subiectasintrescorporeae
ueluthomo
aliisperaliquamcommunem
uelsimilem
remsubiectam
qualitatem
significat
et unitosin eiusdemconuenientia
qualitatis,scilicet
significat
pluresconsimiles
uel {K 14rb)dissimilem
ab omnibusaliisperpropriam
et mortalitatis
rationalitatis
accidentium
, utSocratesperproprietatem
quae nunquamerittotaeadem
qualitatem
ita tarnen
scilicetab omnibusaliis dissimilem;
illampropriam
in alio significat
sedperuerbumin quo
substantiae:
ut perse nondicatinessequalitatem
distribuit
in
sedperuerbum
substantiae:
a uerboetpartiquae dicuntinessequalitatem
differt
non
uerba
dicunt
inesse:
a
et
uerbo
differt
principaliter
quia
quae
particulo
quo
ut
uel ita distribuit
et illaminessesignificant
uel passionem:
corpussed actionem
a uerbis
circaearnperquoddiffert
substantiam
nomint
qualitatem
representando
quae nihilnominant."
20

09:07:18 AM

and arithmetica
, two of the examples
incorporeal things". Grammatica
cited by Priscian, the commentatoridentifiedas appellative nouns of
incorporeal things. He rephrased Priscian's definition: "a noun
signifiesa subject thingor somethingsimilar to othersthroughsome
common quality, as 'man' signifiesseveral similar [men] united in the
coming togetherof one quality, namely rationalityand mortality."
One question included in the printedversion of the Glosule, found
in all MSS except the Cologne recension, touches directlyon universais: ' 'whethercollectivenouns, words of universais accepted in their
universality,are appellative or proper." Its author concludes thatthey
were appellative according to their initial invention, because when
they were firstfound, they were found to signifyindividual things;
thereforeindividual substances are said to be firstsubstances because
words were firstimposed on them.43The insertedpassage elaborates
upon an existingtheme of the Glosule, that the original purpose of a
noun, as laid down by Priscian was to apply to individual things.
A sharp awareness of sensible reality informsthe commentator's
perspectiveon language. When 'man' signifiedthat human species as
a proper name, that universal nature which it designated was understood as a one and single man. This was quite separate from 'man'
as an appellative, its original sense:
buttothat
theword'man'referred
He whofound
nottothatunformed
species,
moras sensible,
tothesenseswhich
heconsidered
rational,
thing
(res)subjacent
in thisnature.
talandthushe imposed
thisname'man' on all others
agreeing
minded
Ifafterwards
a rational
Therefore
'man'byitsnatureis an appellative.
common
fromall mento one certain
someanalogywithotherthings
through
conceived
itin theintellect
initself,
notin thenatureofthings,
thingconstant
itwiththisname'man','man'oughtnotforthisreason
alone,anddesignated
a specialsubstance
nor
neither
be calleda proper[noun],sinceit designates
to many.44
specialquality,rather
[a quality]common
43Ibid.'[Textnotin K in smalltype]:"Et sciendum
dataest
quod haecdiffinitio
subiectorum
unicuique
quasiin collectione
quia nonsingula(e 26v)nominaattribuunt
uelpropriam'
communem
uel potestdicide singulisomnenomendistribuii
qualitatem
scilicetsi plurasubiectasunt
subiectorum
communem
uelpropriam
qualitatem
unicuique
de
Obicitur
si unumuniquamuisimproprie
hocmododistribuere
accipiatur.
pluribus,
de
decollectiuis
Item
nominibus
etqualitatem
nominibus,
significant.
plur<aJ>ibus
quaesubstantiate
sunt
sint
anpropria.
insuauniuersalitate
utrum
uocibus
uniuersalium
Appellatiua
appellatiua
acceptorum
inuenta
fuerunt
adsignificanda
indiuidua
inuenta
secundum
inuentionem,
primam
quiaquando
primm
fuerunt
eisimposita.
substantiae
ideosubstantalia
indiuidua
dicuntur
fuerunt,
prius
primae
quiauocabula
has
etproprium,
soluunt
Item
deomnibus
secundum
diuersas
sequentia
partim
queritur
quod
appcllatiuum
obiectiones."
44II 22 K 14rbe 26v:Et commune.
diffinitione
indeper
Positanominis
exemplicat
dicenscommunem
demonstrai
nomen,uthomo
partes
qualitatem
quidemcorporum
eademreperitur.
indiuiduis
Notaquia
etmortalitatem
rationalitatem
quaeindiuersis
21

09:07:18 AM

The commentator was interestedin the way universal names were


formedby the mind throughan analogical process.45The conclusions
he arrived at were quite differentfromthose of Boethius in his commentarieson the Isagogeof Porphyrybecause he took Priscian's definition of a noun as his point of departure. Such a distinctionbetween
proper and appellative nouns is incidentallyalso pivotal to the argument of a small essay on universais attributedto mag. R. in a Compigne MS which maintains that a species is a vox, as distinctfromthe
universal thing platonically contemplated by the mind.46
Adjectives, Priscian had noted, derive froma quality and were common to many (II 25). His commentatorunderstoodthis to mean that
theywere appellative because theysignifya common quality or quanThey derive froma
tity,as in a white (or black or short)grammaticus.
do
not come froma
he
because
grammaticallythey
explains
quality,
from
white
than vice versa.
Whiteness
comes
rather
noun.
qualitative
"If anyone asks what common propertywhitenessdesignates, we say
that it signifiesan incorporeal thing in that it is brightand contrary
to black/ ' 'White' signifiednot a substance, but a quality which could
be increased or diminished withoutconsuming the subject, "as when
we say Socrates is whiterthan Plato, we say thisbecause of the several
parts which he has occupied by whiteness,or when we say Socrates is
less white than Plato, it is to be said because of the fewer parts of
whiteness".
This account recalls St Anselm's rebuke that modern dialecticians
could not consider colour to be anything other than a body, or a
cumautem
ut proprium
nomenaccipitur,
quandohomospeciemillamsignificai
homoesseintelligatur;
uelutunusetsingularis
ilianaturaquamdsignt
uniuersalis
iudicandum
essede
arbitrantes
homoappellatiuum
affirmant,
semper
quidemtarnen
nominibussecundumnturminuentionis
ipsorumnominum;non secundum
ionis:qui auteminuenitpriushancuocem
modum(K 14va)significai
quemlibet
sed ad remsensibussubiacentem
ad illamspecieminformem,
homo,nonrespexit
mortalem
rationalem,
sensibilem,
sicque illi praesenticum
quam considerauit
hocnomenhomoimposuit.
omnibusaliisin hac naturaconuenientibus
Itaqueex
est. Si autemposteaanimusrationalis
naturahomoappellatiuum
per quandam
aliarumrerumductusremquandamunamex
similitudinem
[K quadam-dine]
nonquancommunem
hominibus
omnibus
quasiperse constantem
[#subsistentem]
solointellectu
in rerum
tum[K numquam]
natura,itase habentem
concepii,
eaque
deberediciprohochomouidetur
nontamenpropter
hocnomine
homodesignauit,
immocommunem
necpriuatam
substantiam
qualitatem,
prium,cumnecpriuatam
designet.
pluribus
46Editedby JudithDijs, Two Anonymous
Tractson Universais
12th
, in:
-Century
113-17.
28 (1990),85-117,especially
Vivarium,
22

09:07:18 AM

universal to be a flatumvocis.Such ideas, I suggest, were inspired by


the speculativeaspects of Priscian's thinkingabout voces
, in particular
as interpretedby the Glosule.Its author's definitionof a person or any
other noun as a 'thing' flowed from his desire to distinguish the
substance of any noun fromthe qualities with which it was informed.
He did not deny that a common substance like 'man' was shared by
differentindividuals, but he reserved the word 'thing' primarilyfor
whatever was differentiatedby some accident. He argued that if
whitenesswas a constitutivepart "of the thingof Socrates", it would
have to be part of the foundationof Socrates, an absurdity.47
Here I must voice disagreementwith the suggestionof Reilly and
Fredborg that the Glosule could be the work of William of
Champeaux.48 They suggestthat the Glosule'$ analysis of the substantive echoes William's understanding(according to Abaelard) that in
"Socrates is white", grammaticallythere was a conjunction of the
essence of Socrates and whiteness,even thoughthiswas different
from
the dialecticalsense.49The Glosuledoes not make a distinctionbetween
47See aboven. 38.
"
48Huntcommented
of a
, 219 n. 1) thattherefollows rejection
briefly
(Studies
view" in the sentenceon II 18: "Iterumquando diciturverbum
Nominalist
verbasic:velinherere
istamvocem,quod
significare
ipsuminherere,
perscrutentur
nichilesset,velsignificatum
nonpotestessepropter
illius,quoditerum
supradictas
rationes."
Therejection
herehowever
isofanyform
ofinherence,
notofnominalism.
TheGlosule
continues
itsrejection
ofanyideathatwitha verblikecurrit,
cursio
inheres
initssubject,
anopinion
heldby"magister
noster
V." andalsorejected
byAbaelard
in Dialctica
thatWilliammightbe its author,although
, 123. Hunt speculated
a passagein theHistoria
calamitatum
to indicate
thatWilliamlectured
on
misreading
Priscian
Helias'Summa
Priscianum
I-Ill: anEdi(art.cit., 209-10).L. Reilly,Petrus
super
tionandStudy
(D.Phil.Diss.,AnnArbor,Michigan1978),579-80arguedin favour
ofHunt'ssuggestion
onthegrounds
thatsum"has a two-fold
both
nature,
signifying
actionandsubstance".
Yetthepassagequotedin n. 49 indicates
thattheGlosule
did
notconsider
whiteness
to inhereinitssubjectin thissenseofest.Another
argument
raisedbyReillyisthatWilliam
isreported
as saying
that"humanity"
isnotthesame,
butissimilar
intwomen,ed.O. Lottin,
etMorale
1959,192,
, V, Gembloux
Psychologie
, (perhapsafterbeingbestedin debatebyAbaelard?).Fredborg
echoingtheGlosule
notesa connection
betweenthedoctrine
of Williamof Champeaux(according
to
Abaelard's
ofhismaster)
thatthereweretwosenses,dialectical
and
negative
critique
toa proposition
andthedistinction
between
andpredicative
grammatical,
copulative
functions
oftheverbesse
in: Twelfth-Century
Grammar
, inSpeculative
,
, 178-88.
Philosophy
49Abaelard,
diLogica
, ed. MarioDal Pra,Scritti
, Florence
Super
Topica
19692,272-3:
"Dicebantenimquodcumdicitur
Socrates
estalbus
rerum
, alia estconiunctio
quam
alia quamattendunt
... et hii [grammatici]
dialectici.
tantum
grammatici,
copulationemessentiaefundamenti
albedinisad Socratemattendunt.
... Hanc utique,
secundum
hancsententiam,
sensusduos,unumdialecticum
singulaepropositiones
estet quodammodo
secundum
alium
qui largior
inhaerentiam,
superior
simplicem
estcircacopulationem
... Nolumus
essentiae.
autem
grammaticum
quideterminatior
23

09:07:18 AM

two simultaneous senses, grammatical and dialectical, in a single


possiblefunctions(copulative and
proposition, only between different
predicative) of the substantive. It insists that one cannot interpret
'
"Socrates is white'' as 4' thisthing[Socrates] is thatthing[whiteness]'
4
in the same way as 'a dog is a barking animal". While William may
have accepted certain ideas of the Glosule, Abaelard's explicitcriticism
of William- justifiedor not- is a more elaborate formof an argument
already raised in the Glosule.It cannot be used to argue William was
its author.
A newly discovered draftof two chaptersof the De incarnatione
verbi
,
less polished than the final version, shows clearly how Anselm
countered Roscelin' s literalism by applying principles developed in
the De grammatico
to plural words used of God.50 One had to ask
whethera word signifiedperse or peraliud. In imagininghis adversary
looked at everythingas a collection of parts, Anselm was creatinga
straw man in order to demolish spurious arguments. The term resis
not the central concept of Roscelin's thought. His theme is that all
language, including that about the Trinity,had to obey grammatical
rules and that every word is distinctfromits meaning. Roscelin may
have borrowed the termresfromthe Glosuleon Priscian to referto the
meaning of that voxwhich was a proper noun, in this case 'Father',
'Son' and 'Holy Spirit'. Far fromquestioning the unity of God, he
was only pointing out that in so far as these are proper nouns of
human origin, they must referto separate things.
In the MonologionAnselm had argued that there were three nscio
quid in God that could be described as eithersubstances or persons.51
Afterthe work had been criticizedby Lanfranc (to whom he had submitted it for censure) Anselm included in its preface that passage of
which justified the equivalence of the Greek
Augustine's De trinitate
definitionwith the Latin formula, even though it was strictlydenied
by the so-called "Athanasian Creed". What had most irked
Roscelin's critic,John (then engaged in defendingFulco's recentand
hotlycontestedappointmentto the see of Beau vais), was thatRoscelin
was claiming Anselm' s support forhis argument.52The essay Est una
aliumattendant
aliumsensum
dialectici,
grammatici.
unquamutinconstructionibus
et dialectici
Sed idemex eademconstructione
et grammatici."
intelligant
50See myStAnselm
I (n. 1 above).
andRoscelin
51Monologion
I 85-86.
c. 79, ed. Schmitt
52According
of Beauvais
to an entryaddedto an eleventh-century
martyrology
at hisdeath(9 Julyofan
tothechapter
cathedral
a Roscelinus
bequeathed
grammaticus
textsstudiedgrammar,
unknown
books,mostly
logicand rhetoric,
year)fourteen
24

09:07:18 AM

reads as a deliberate attempt to demonstrate superficial continuity


withthe argumentof theMonologion
, withthe addition of resto thepersona!substantiaidentification.We know that Ivo of Chartres asked
Roscelin to write such a palinode to clear his name.53 Its
unacknowledged authorityis Priscian, as interpretedby the Glosule.
Roscelin followed the commentary in emphasising the radical
discretenessof every proper noun as a separate thing.
Anselm criticizedexcessive literalismin understandingthe Trinity.
While Anselm thoughtthat the meaning of a word could change by
being used per aliud., Roscelin rejected the notion that a word could
change its meaning. His strictattitudeto individual vocesalso earned
the ire of Abaelard, who emphasised that Priscian' s definitionof the
threepersons as "he who talks", "he who is spoken to" and "he who
is spoken about" related to properties and not things. Roscelin' s
thinkingabout resas what was signifiedby vocesderived fromapplication of the Glosule's Boethian categories to Priscian. In engaging in
withsometheology:
"Roscelinusgrammaticus
deditlibrossuos Sancto
although
Petro:Augustinum
de doctrinaChristiana,
PrissuperJohannem,
Augustinum
Rethoricam
de inventione,
Boetium
sianum,
Arismeticam,
Macrobium,
Dialecticam,
de consolatone,Virgilium,Oratium,Juvenalem,Ovidiummetamorphoseon,
Statium
ettroparium."
ThisRoscelinalsobequeathed
hishousein the
Thebados,
cathedral
cloisterand eightarpenni
of vinesat Hosdenc,eightkilometres
from
Beauvais.LopoldDelisle,Notice
surunmanuscrit
del'abbaye
deLuxeuil
en625, in:
copi
Notices
etExtraits
dela bibliothque
desmanuscrits
nationale
, XXXI.2, Paris1886,149-64,
at 160;seetooHenriOmont,Recherches
surla bibliothque
del'glise
cathdrale
deBeauvais
,
Paris1914,2-3.A Roscelinus
ofSaint-Pierre,
is mentioned
in
, cantorofthecathedral
a charter
of17May 1072as having
a canonofComNevelon,
joinedwitha certain
a smallcompigne,in requesting
bishopGuyofBeauvais(1063-85)to establish
ofcanonsinthechurch
ofSaint-Vaast,
Beauvais,ofwhichtheyhadthecare;
munity
cf.PierreLouvet,Histoire
dela villeetcitdeBeauuais
, Rouen1613;repr.Marseille
etantiquitez
dupasdeBeauvaisis
I 694, Beauvais1631-35,
1977),III 480-2andHistoire
5; GalliaChristiana
IX, Paris1751,709.Theoriginal
(Beauvais,Archives
municipales
GG 251) is citedand commented
on byAnnieHenwood-Reverdot,
SaintL'glise
Etienne
deBeauvais.
Histoire
etArchitecture
their
, Paris 1982,9. UrbanII confirmed
theapparent
ordeathofFulco.There
privileges
onlyinAugust1095,after
deposition
was alonghistory
ofrivalry
between
bishopGuy,patronofthisRoscelin,and the
ofbishopFulco,Anselm's
Muchis explained
aboutthepolitical
cirfamily
protg.
cumstances
behind
thedesiretosilenceRoscelin
ifhewasoneofthose
ofCompigne,
clericsofBeauvaisopposedto Fulco'ssimoniaca]
appointment
(cf.Anselm'sEpist.
124).
53Letter7 in Yvesde Chartres.
, I ed. JeanLeclercq,Paris1949,26:
Correspondence
"Resttigiturut palinodiam
scribaset recantatis
vestemDominitui,
opprobriis
fuisti
quampublicescindebas,
publiceresarcias,
quatenus,sicutmultisexemplum
sicde caeterofiasexemplum
Sic enimbonoodorepraecedente
correctionis.
erroris,
etpristinum
fetorem
et a nobiset ab aliisdiligiet colligi,et beneficiis
consmente,
poteris
ampliari."
25

09:07:18 AM

argument with Roscelin on the Trinity, Abaelard drew on the


underlying concerns of the Glosule, while being impatient with its
excessive use of the term res.
Roscelin's debt to the Glosuleapplies not just to his definitionof
'person', but to his understandingof language as a whole. The commentator's explanation that 'person' was both voxand resis only one
example of the way in which he expanded upon the tentativedialectical speculations in Priscian. He was particularlyinterestedin the
precedentPriscian had set of tryingto re-establishthe rules of correct
Latin, freefromcorruption,on the patternof the ancientGreek grammarians. Priscian' s comment that younger grammarians were the
more perspicacious prompted the commentator to reflect that
linguisticknowledge had been expanding fromits earliest days. The
first" inventor" of words may only have establishedfourlettersin his
life(presumablyof the name of God). The next generationcould learn
them in one day and so findthe otherlettersof the alphabet.54Not all
subsequent changes were necessarilygood, being done to please rather
than forany rationalreason.55One had to imitatethe best the ancients
could offer.Language was acquired graduallyand thus had to be subject to rules of human origin.
The commentator wanted to understand the reasons behind the
invention of words. The philosophical definition of a vox as the
smallest unit of air sensible to the ear which opened Book I enabled
him to launch into a long discussion of the nature of vox as distinct
from res,56 4'Philosophers deal with the definitionsof things, gram54I 2 K lrh-lva
. Arguitur
e 2V:" Cuiusauctores
iuniores
perspicaciores]
quanto
[quanto
Et benea iunioribus
quia sunt
potuerunt
redargu,
inquamsciliceta iunioribus.
etdiligentia,
etueresuntperspicatiores,
florent
id est
quia etingenio
perspicatiores,
sic ex ingenioscientia.Ideo post
ex floreprocedit,
arteualent,quia sicutfructus
studiiualet
additdiligentia
nisi
, quia nihilprodestper ingenium
florere,
floruisse
eos esse
uenire.Et hoc,id estperspicatiores
ad maturitatem
faciatflorem
studium
uiderisi iuniores
Nondebetmirum
auctoritate.
omnium
grammaticae
comprobatur
cumprimusinuentor
in inuentione:
artisdicuntur
pertotamuitam
perspicatiores
insolodiepoterunt
iuniores
inueniendis:
litteris
elaborasset
forsitan
suaminquattuor
ad
successorum
Ita peradditionem
etpostex sua partealiasreperire.
eas addiscere,
iuniores
estnonarbitror
sed postquam
consummata
istaarsincreuit,
perfectionem
esseperspicatiores."
55k jvbe 2V:"Suntenimqui corrigunt
prosoloplacitoet nonproaliquacausa
rationabiliter
prospecta."
56K lvbe 3V:"Philosophi
de littera
Priscianus
uocem
tractaturus,
definiunt
[esseaerem].
ne perignotum
uocemut genussuumpositurus:
litterae
et in descriptione
genus
a philosophis
datamconuenienter
uocisdiffinitionem
ignotamspeciemdiffiniret,
uero
diffinitiones
Est autemphilosophorum
rerum;grammaticorum
praemittit.
26

09:07:18 AM

"
marians with formingthe etymologies of voces
. Opinions differed
among philosophersas to thenature of thissmall quantityof air. Some
said that animals lived fromthis air which they breathe in and out;
otherphysicisaid that animals got life not fromthis small quantityof
air, but from that air which stretchesup to heaven and which by
uocumaethimologias
formare.
Vel ad maioremauctoritatem
diffinitionis
dicit
diffiniunt
uocem:ut auctores
diffinitionis
nominati
et
commendabilem
philosophi
autenticam
reddant
dicentes
uocem
esseaerem
tenuissimum.
Ideo
ipsamdiffinitionem,
dicittenuissimum
tenuisestrespectu
quia aernaturaliter
aquae et terrae;qui dumab
animalihauritur
collatoria
aditus,etperillainteriora
perarteriarum
angustos
usque
ad pulmonem
fittenuior,
inattractione
si quamsordem
sibiab
attrahitur,
deponens
exterioribus
ut sicutuinumpostcolationem
contraxerat,
liquidiusquam priusin
emissioneuero per easdem arteriarum
si quid adhuc
angustiasregrediens
illamexuit,et tuncdemumfittenuissimus.
retinebat
Sed quia homo
spissitudinis
ueldormiens
sinealicuiusuocisinformatione
emittit
additictum
id
cogitans
spiritum,
estpercussum;
et quia possetpercuti
essetuox,
digitoin orepositoet nontarnen
estnaturalibus
instrumentis
ad uocemformandam,
uidelicet
intelligendum
lingua
De istoaerequemitaattrahunt
etemittunt
palatolabiisdentibus.
animalia,diuersa
philosophorum
opinioest.Aliienimdicuntanimaliauiuereexistocorrupto
aere,qui
nosundiquecircumscribit
etemissionem.
Phisicitamenalitersenperattractionem
animalia
exnostro
aerequi adeospissusestuitamsuamcontinuare
tiunt,
quiadicunt
(K 2ra)nonposse,sedex iliosuperiori
qui estextraglobolunaeusquead firmamentmquinostri
aerisconsideratione
tenuissimus
illumdiuinadispositione
est,etdicunt
uias et quosdamporosad nos descendere,
et animaliaper
perquasdamlatentes
arterias
ad pulmonem
illumattrahere.
In primis
estan uoxsicdiffinita
quaerendum
speciessit aeris,id est significet
aliquamremuniuersalem
quae sit speciesin
substantiae:
praedicamento
quoddicimusnonesse.Vox enimaeresin essentia
sui,
scilicet
inhocquodsuntaeresnonsignificai,
setpotiusex quadamaccidentali
causa
in hoc scilicetquod percussisuntnaturalibus
instrumentis.
Dicimusergohoc
uocabulum
uoxaccidentale
a quadamqualitate,
uel
esse,idestsumptum
percussione
alianonsecundum
Nonestergosubstantialis
uocem,sedsecundum
significationem.
diffinitio
si uoxaeremnonsignificet.
Hancdiffinitionem
praemissa
aJiqui
putantse
hanchypoteticam
in suaerationis
exordioponentes:
si uoxestaeret est
infringere
'
duasregulas
unamAugustini
corpus.Huicprobationi
supponunt:
qui dicit 'nullum
in eodemtempore
totumin diuersislocisreperitur";
alteram
corpusindiuiduale
Boetiiquaeest,"idemsermototusetinteger,
cumomnibus
scilicet
suiselementis
ad
auresdiuersorum
in eodemtempore,
peruenit
quasi in diuersislocisest." Inde
inferunt:
auctoritate
uox poterit
igituruox nonestcorpus.Salua autemutriusque
si quodBoetiusdicitrecteintelligatur.
Estenimuerumquoduox
corpusremanere
formaliter
eademet nonmaterialiter
in eodemtempore
diuersorum
repletauditum
utputaiactolapideinaqua fitorbis.Hicueroorbisisteuicinasundasimpellens
alium
orbemfacit,et illealiumet sic multiorbesmateriaquidemet locodiuersi:sed in
formaidem a primoilio orbe formantur.
Eodem modo aer in ore loquentis
naturalibus
instrumentis
formtus
uicinosimpellit
aeres,et in sua conficitur
forma,
etitafitutuoxeademsecundum
formam
sitinorationibus
diuersorum.
Sedquantum
ad materiam
utitadicam,aerumdiuersa.Potestigitur
esseut nullum
diuersorum,
totum
indiuersis
locishabeatur,
eterituoxcorpus,
etipsa
corpusineodemtempore
secundum
id estsonisimilitudinem,
eademin eodemtempore
in diuersis
formam,
auditur
locis.Ethancsimilitudinem
de aqua ponitBoetius
inprologo
quempraemittit
in musica."
27

09:07:18 AM

divine dispositiondescends into our lungs. The second interpretation


fittedin with the bigger argumenthe soughtto present,that a voxdid
not signifya universal substance, but was rathersomethingaccidental, so called fromits percussive quality. While some argued thatrules
established by Augustine ("no individual body could be found in differentplaces at the same times") and Boethius ("the same word comes
complete to the ears of differentpeople at the same time in different
places'') that a voxcould not be a body (as distinctfroma universal
substance), these rules had to be interpretedcorrectly.When a word
reached differentpeople, it was a similar sound ratherthan the same
sound which all heard.
The commentator'sdiscussion of vocesprovides an excellentillustration of his thinkingabout parts and wholes. Voceswere all quite distinct
fromeach other. No individual thing could be the same in different
places. Only God, who was truly incorporeal and underwent no
change, remained the same in all places.
whiteness
ofa wallwhichrestson different
Justas thecontinuous
things
[i.e.
walls]is said to be one, notbecausethatwhiteness
adjacentto thispartis
thesameas thatofanother
andjudged
individually
partbutbecauseitis similar
tobe calledthesamein thesamespecies,likewise
'man'once
whenI articulate
and I pronounce
thesamevox'man' at another
time,although
theyareessenandmaterially
thatitisas ifI havearticulated
voces
one
, I affirm
tiallydifferent,
vox
We say as if informed
, becauseof [their]similitude.
by one becauseof
and therefore
one vox.bl
similitude,
There is a striking similarity here to the arguments Abaelard
attributed to Roscelin about parts and wholes. The commentator
insisted that the words of Boethius and Aristotleabout voxand oratio
had to be rightlyconstrued:
57Ibid.: "Nulla enimres indiuidualiter
(e 4r) totain diuersislocisesseaffirmari
nisisolusdeusqui uerumincorporeum
utunaessentialiter
remaneat,
est,et
potest,
qui nullammutabilitatem
recipere
potest.Ad hoc respondeo
quod sicutcontinua
unadicitur
albedoparietis
nonquia iliaalbedoquae huic
fundatur,
quae in diuersis
sedquia similis
estet
partiadiacetsitiliaindiuidualiter
quae in alia partefundatur,
eademspecieiudicatur
uocarieadem;itacumprofero
homosemeletaliauiceeandem
et quamuisdiuersaesintessentialiter,
etmaterialiter
uocem,id esthomopronuncio,
similitudinem
affirmo.
eandemuocemprotulisse
uoces,tarnenpropter
quasiunam
aerisunaforma
cumindiuersis
uocisa diuersis
audientibus
Similiter
partibus
suscipi
uideatur,tarnenilla qualitatiuaforma,quae huic parti aeris copulataest
esse illamundealia parsaeriseffecta
estnonpotestprobari.Nos
indiuidualiter,
tarnen
similitudinem
uocamusetpropterea
unam
quasiunaminformationem
propter
uocem."
28

09:07:18 AM

of Aristotle,
definea voxas a quantity...
Others,armedby theauthority
Deceivedbytheambiguity
oforatio
, theydo notrealisethatthewordsignifies
one thingas a quantity,
as a substance.58
another
An issue raised very brieflyby Priscian allowed the commentatorto
bring ideas of Boethius and Aristotleto bear on the physical nature of
the words which grammarians analysed.
His keythemeis thatno voxsignifiesnaturally.It is a physicalobject
on whichmeaning is bestowed by the one who formsit by strikingair.
Priscian distinguishedarticulate sounds, in other words sounds "apt
to be spoken to show the sense of the speaker'' fromthose "natural"
sounds which were inarticulateand not utteredfromany intentionto
signify. The commentator recognised that Boethius approached
in evaluating meaning by what was generated in
language differently,
the mind of the listener. Priscian' s physical analysis of sound attracts
the commentator'ssympathy.Meaning is defined by what a speaker
wishes to say ratherthan any quality discerned in the language itself.
Roscelin extended the Glosule*
s insightinto language as an artefact
to words used of God. The message of Est una, Notandumestand the
letterto Abaelard is that the only underlyingunity is that of God.
Roscelin's refusalto accept that the threepersons of the Trinity constituteda common 'thing' was the result of applying litterallythe
Glosule's grammatical definitions to trinitarian doctrine. He was
inspiredby itsperceptionof individuadwords as physicalobjects, each
with its own dimension, each radically differentfrom the other.
58Ibid.: "Est alia sententia dicitomnesillosaeressimul
quae
acceptossimulunam
uocemetnullum
eorumperse,sedhocparumualorishabet.Aliterquidamrespondentobiectionibus
dicentes
tantum
uocemesseaeremplectro
praemissis
linguaeformtmetnullumalium.Affirmant
enimeandemuocemperuenire
eodemtempore
ad auresplurium
in diuersislocisexistentium,
nonsecundum
sui essentiam,
sed
secundum
uelalicuiusdicitur
auditum,
esse,
quemadmodum
lapisinoculisplurium
nonsecundum
sui substantiam
sed secundum
tantum,
uisum,et in hac sententia
cumpraedictis
iterum
oppositiones,
quaesequentur
quiescunt.
Opponitur
praemissae
diffinitioni,
quae dicituocemesse aeremquod Boetiusin secundocommentario
Periermeneias
dicituocemesseaerispercussionem
perlinguam,
quod si aerispercussioqualitati
uocemeidemsupponinecesseest.Sed si quisdiligenter
supponitur,
dictaBoetiiconsideret,
inuenietuocemqualitatinon supponi.Non enimdicit
uocemesse percussionem,
sed aerispercussionem,
id est aerempersimpliciter
Alii ueroAristotelica
auctoritate
muniti
cussum,et est dictumad expressionem.
uoceminquantitate
dicitenimAristoteles
inquantitate
orationem
esse.Sed
ponunt;
inquopraedicamento
estspecies,ibidemoportet
etiamessegenusilliusspeciei.Huic
obiectioni
sic respondeo,
orationis
illam
quia istiaequiuocatione
deceptinesciunt
uocemquaeestoratio,aliudsignificare
inquantitate,
aliudquandosubiicitur
uociin
substantia.
Vocesenimeaedemsaepeetsignificant
et
substantiam
quodamrespectu,
aliorespectu,
utcorpusistauox."
quantitatem
29

09:07:18 AM

Anselm found this teaching, that a universal substances was nothing


but a "puff of air", reprehensible.Rarely in the historyof logic, has
such weight been given to a single derisoryand misleading remark.
Like the commentator, Roscelin might have considered genus and
species as voces.The Glosuleauthor did not deny that a universal was
a res, but insisted that the words we used of that universal were voces
and had to be analysed as such. The accusation that "modern dialecticians' ' did not believe in the real existenceof universais is a red herring distractingus fromtheirconcern with the nature and meaning of
voces.
The res-vox
distinctionRoscelin used was too crude forAnselm and
Abaelard when applied to the Trinity. Nonetheless, Roscelin shared
with Anselm and passed on to Abaelard, a desire to uncover the
"causes" of language about the Trinity. Whether one spoke of person, like the Latins, or substance, like the Greeks to referto thatwhich
was plural in God, one was dealing with human attemptsto define
what was ultimately ineffable. While Anselm and Roscelin both
accepted that such language was always subject to rules of signification, theydisagreed on what these rules were. Anselm was perhaps the
more original when it came to the interpretationof Priscian.
The Glosuleilluminates the comment of the HistoriaFrancicaabout
Roscelin learning from the mysteriousJohn that dialectic is an ars
vocalis, a discipline founded on voces. To call this John "an early
nominalist" is to fall into the same trap as Aventinus- reading into
the past a school of thought which never had such a clear-cut
existence. While the application to dialectic and theologyof Priscian's
reflectionon nouns was taken for granted in the mid twelfthcentury
by people like Gilbert of Poitiers and John of Salisbury, there was
inevitablymuch disagreement as to the implicationsof this process.
Polarisation between masterswas an inevitableconsequence of a fluid
intellectualenvironment.The distinctionHermann of Tournai drew
between those who taughtdialectic in voceas against in rewas between
"empty talkers" unlike "real philosophers". We should be wary of
interpretingsuch groupings as distinct philosophical schools with a
"real" existencebeforethe mid twelfthcentury.There is no evidence
that Roscelin denied the reality of universal substances as Anselm
claimed.
The interrelationshipbetween study of vocesand philosophy as a
whole is explained within the prologue to the Glosule. Priscian's
primary intentionis teach people to speak grammatically:
30

09:07:18 AM

I saygrammatically
from
which
as different
teaches
dialectic,
speaking
according
totruth
andfalsehood
andfromrhetoric,
whichteachesspeaking
to
according
thedecoration
comesfirst,
ofwordsandphrases.
Oftheseartsgrammar
because
one oughttoknowhowto makeappropriate
or
joiningofwordsbeforetruth
ofeloquenceis learnt."59
or thedecoration
falsehood
Grammar was a part of logic, a subject which could be divided into
what was sermocinalis
(to do with language) and what was disertiua(to
do with findingarguments). Through this "linguistic"' ( sermocinalis
)
part, grammarwas led back to logic as ifto its genus.60The threearts
of logic, with those of ethics and physics, derived fromthe "Greek
springs" of which Priscian spoke at the outsetof his work.61This idea
had been expressed in similar termsin an eleventh-centurypoem on
the seven liberal arts found in a manuscript of Saint-Evroul.62
The tradition
of theGlosule
Not all previous thinkershad agreed that grammar was an integral
part of logic.63 Alcuin and others who followed Isidore of Seville
divided logic into the arts of analysing and findingarguments,dialectic and rhetoric.(ConfusinglyIsidore had also suggestedthatlogic was
another name for dialectic.)64 By contrast Clement, teacher in the
59Glosule
dicoad dif, ed. Gibson,StudiMedievali,20 (1979),249: "Grammatice
ferentiam
et rethorice,
ueritatem
et falsitatem,
dialectice,
que docetloquisecundum
ornatum
uerborum
etsententiarum.
que docetloquisecundum
Quibusartibus
prior
est grammatica,
facereconuenientem
coniunctionem
dicquia priusscireoportet
tionum
uel ornatus
addiscatur."
quamueritasuel falsitas
eloquentie
60Ibid.249-50:"Nec dubitandum
, cuiusestipsagrammatica
quinlogice
supponatur
terciapars.Logicealia parsestsermocinalis,
alia disertiua.
Disertiuaparteshabet
inuentionem
etiudicium,
et rethoricis
conueniunt.
Sermocinalis
que solisdialecticis
uerogrammaticorum
ac perearnad logicamuelutad suumgenusgrammatica
est;
"
reducitur.
61Ibid.251: "Celebrasse
rum
dicoderiuatam
aJonte
Greco
etorigo
' Grecienimfuerunt/onj
omniumartium,quia earuminuentores
fuerunt.Cum dicitderiuatam
alludit
latineenimartesquasiriuisuntgreceinuentionis.
Et
metafore,
quiadixerat
jontibus'
etiamcelebrasse
omne
, per hoc uocatstudiaquia in naturisrerum
genusstudiorum
uehementior
animiapplicatio
exhibenda
studiorum
est;etneinomni
inuestigandis
genere
et sutoriam
artemet alia seruiliaofficiaadditgenusdico
acciperemus
pictoriam
lucesapientie
sicut
, quia seruilesartesmentisoculos non illuminant
prefulgens
philosophia."
62Printed
in PL 151,729-32fromAlenon,Bibl.mun.10.
63On earlymedieval
classification
oftheartes
Eineverschollene
, seeBernhard
Bischoff,
derWissenschaften
in:AHDLMA,25 (1958),5-20,reprinted
in
, first
Einteilung
printed
hisMittelalterliche
Studien
, I, Stuttgart
1966,273-88.
64Isidore,
PL
Etymologiae
(ed. Lindsay)II.xxiv.7,butcf.I.ii.l; Alcuin,De dialctica,
101,952C.
31

09:07:18 AM

court of Louis the Pious and author of an Ars grammatica


included
a
of
as
subdivision
a
itself
with
dialectic
of
rhetoric,
grammar
species
An
.65
into
De
mundi
constitutione
interpolation
pseudo-Bede's
logica
explained that there were two definitionsof logica, one strictthat it
comprised dialectic and rhetoricanotherloose, thatit was a sermocinalis
scientiaembracing dialectic, rhetoricand grammar.66
The Glosule, like the didactic poem, adhered to the view that
included grammar within logic.67 Roscelin of Compigne likewise
absorbed fromthe mysteriousJohn the idea thatdialecticwas "a vocal
ar' Abaelard reacted against Roscelin' s literalisticinterpretationof
definitionsof Priscian. For him logic and dialectic were synonymous.
Grammatical issues he dealt with in the firsttractof the Dialctica, the
"book of parts". I have suggested elsewhere that his lost Grammatica
or "reconsideration of the predicaments", to which he alludes in his
, was a reworkingof the firsttract of the Dialctica
TheologiaChristiana
and that it contained new ideas about the relationship between
substance and quality.68While Abaelard tended to presenthimselfas
a great innovator in dialectic and to be silent about his debt to past
masters, he was in fact developing a speculative traditionrooted in
grammatical reflectionof the late eleventh century.
Further manuscript discoveries may well illuminate the extent of
Roscelin's influenceon thistraditionfurtherthan I have been able to
do here. I have not had time to discuss the fascinatingcommentary
on Psalms 1-25, attributedto Roscelin (with good reason I would
argue) by Stegmller. This work, surviving in six twelfth-century
manuscripts,suggestthatRoscelin was one of themost philosophically
65Clementis
arsgrammatica
20.3
15, ed. JoannesTolkiehn,
Supplementband
Philologus.
(Leipzig1928),p. 10.
66PL 90,908B:''Logicaestdiligens
ratiodisserendi,
etmagistra
iudicii;sicdefinita
stricteaccipitur,comprehendens
tamenrhetoricam
dialctica.Large vero sic
describitur:
in tria,in dialecticam,
scientia,et dividitur
Logicaest sermocinalis
See also CharlesJones,BedaePseudepigrapha
rhetoricam,
, Ithaca
grammaticam."
notesthattheseinterpolations
donotoccurinthesurviving
1939,39. CharlesBurnett
MSS ofPseudo-Bede,
thanthe12thcentury,
noneearlier
De Mundicelestis
terrestrisque
constitutione
Institute
andTexts10,London1985,11.
, Warburg
Surveys
67Ibid.ed. Gibson251: 14Celebrasse
dicodoctrinam
omnis
eloquen
tie,id est scientiam
totiuslogice;ethicincludit
doctoseteloquentes
reddit.
Doctriuium,
quodhomines
trinam
dicoderiuatum
afonte
Grecienimfuerunt
Grecorum;
artium,
fonsetorigoomnium
latineenimartesquasi riuisuntgreceinuentionis.
Et etiam
quia dixerat
fontibus'
omne
celebrasse
studiorum
ethicamet physicam,
in qua
, perhoc comprehendit
genus
quadriuium."
physicacontinetur
68Mews1987.
32

09:07:18 AM

minded scripturalexegetes of his generation.69Much remains to be


explained about his precise contributionto the study of dialectic. I
hope however to have suggestedthat he is not a thinkerwho springs
out of nowhere. Roscelin studied at Rheims, a citywitha proud tradition of classical scholarship since at least the time of Gerbert of
Aurillac.70There is no betterwitness to this classical revival in the
eleventh centurythan the Glosuleon Priscian. Its author, I suggest,
was theJohn who taught Roscelin that dialectic was an art that dealt
withvoces.It mightbe worthinvestigatingwhetherits author could be
who came to Saint-Evroul in
John of Rheims, the famousgrammaticus
a
monk
there
until
his death in 1125 and who,
1076/77, remaining
to
according Orderic Vitalis, was continuouslyengaged in the study
of the ancients.71The Chartres MS of the Glosulecontained a list of
twenty-eightbooks borrowed from Saint-Evroul.72 Bee was not the
only centre of philosophic discussion in late eleventh-century
Normandy.
The Glosuleindirectlyexerted an enormous influence on twelfthcenturythought,not least throughits impact on William of Conches
and Petrus Helias. It may be worthstudyingits influenceon Gilbert
of Poitiers and the whole Chartrian tradition. Otto of Freising may
have exaggerated Roscelin' s originalityin initiating interestin the
sententia
. John of Salisburyconsidered him to be someone whose
vocum
had
opinions
long since been overtakenby the achievementsof Gilbert
and Abaelard. Nonetheless, Roscelin did play a significantrole in
emphasizing thatboth dialectic and theologyhad to be based on clear
understandingof the meaning of individual voces.St Anselm was not
wrong in recognizingthe intellectualchallenge which he presented.
Clayton, Victoria
Monash University
69Stegmller,
Biblicum
no. 7516. He is certainly
mistaken
however
in
Repertorium
to Roscelinthecommentary
on Psalms26-150in theTroyesMS, Bibl.
attributing
mun.1750(inwhichtheentire
collection
is attributed
to "magister
Bruno".Forfull
discussion
ofthiscommentary,
seemyforthcoming
StAnselm
andRoscelin
: Some
study,
NewTexts
andTheir
II (see n. 1 above).
Implications
70Epist.adAbaelardum,
ed. Reiners
65.JohnR. Williams
documents
theimportance
oftheschoolat Rheims,perhapswithout
sufficient
on itsrolepriorto
importance
TheCathedral
School
intheEleventh
29 (1954),
Gerbert,
, in: Speculum,
ofRheims
Century
661-77.
71OnJohnofRheimsandintellectual
lifeat St Evroulinthisperiod,seetheeulogy
ofOrdericVitalis,Ecclesiastical
, ed. MarjorieChibnall6 vols.,Oxford1972History
comments
ofChibnallin I 11-23.
80, III 166-70,andtheintroductory
72TheChartres
MS contained
on a flyleaf
a listofbooksborrowed
from
thisabbey
toanother,
toH. Omont,Catalogue
desmanuscrits
desbibliothques
according
gnral
publiXI Chartres
, Paris1890,108.
quesdeFrance
33

09:07:18 AM

Vivarium
XXX, 1 (1992)
Nominalism and GrammaticalTheory
in theLate Eleventhand Early TwelfthCenturies
An ExplorativeStudy
C.H. KNEEPKENS

Up to the present, we know of only two explicit referencesto a


nominalist statementand one explicit referenceto a realist statement
in late eleventh- and twelfth-century
grammatical treatises (List of
In
&
cf.
no
no
12
addition, we findthe phrases sententia
Texts,
13;
25i).
Realium!Nominaliummentioned as examples in a description of the
' in an
term 4sententia
anonymous gloss commentaryon Priscian, the
so-called Glose 'Promisimus'(Hunt 1950; List of Texts, no 25h). However, since the glossator does not add any doctrinal material, this
referenceonly indicates the currentinterestin theiropposition. This
does not imply that we do not find any further mention of
vocalist/nominalistor realist positions in grammatical works. When
the grammarians explained their interpretationof Priscian's description of the meaning functionof the noun {Inst. gram.II, 18) or commented on Priscian's answer to the question "quid estanimalrationale
mortale?"{op.cit. XVII, 35), theysometimesrevealed theirontological
commitments.Nearly all of them appear to have adhered to a nonnominalist position, whereas typicallyvocalist or nominalistviews as
portrayedin other sources are seldom referredto. From this we may
conclude that even in the dominating realist atmosphere of the late
eleventh and early twelfthcenturiesgrammarwas not liable to realist
or nominalist positions. However, this did not prevent some grammarians, while discussing particular semantic aspects, to show their
preferencesfor one position or the other'.1
1 Sometimes
onewhichis suitable
forthe
weevenfinda doublesetofobservations:
Priscian
fortheNominalists,
in an anonymous
comRealistand another
e.g.
gloss
"
"
mentary LicetMultiin Arte (MS Oxford,Bodl.Lib., canon,misc. 281; cf.
35. Priscian
1976,13-5& 19871,47-53)adPriscian,
saysthatwhen
Kneepkens
" is XVII,the
rationale
mortale
intends
to be
thequestion" quidestanimal
asked, questioner
homo
statesthatitis "common
aboutthespecies,namely
informed
, ofwhichPriscian
in thefollowing
comments
to all people".The glossator
way:(f. 16v)"thatspecies
is theLatinverb)all people;or,the
toall people,thatis: itfits(convenit
is common
itcan alsobe explained
in another
continues,
way:thatspecieswhichis a
glossator
34

09:07:25 AM

So a directlink between a particulargrammarian and 12th-century


logical nominalismor non-realism(Jolivet1981; cf. Courtenay 1991a,
14) cannot be shown on doctrinalgrounds.2Nor can it be proven that
the grammaticalthoughtof the Priscian traditionwas particularlypromotingnominalism. Yet it has been claimed that grammaticalthought
paved the way fornominalism,especially forwhat is called theological
nominalism3 which recently has been claimed even to have been
"primary" with regard to "logical nominalism'' (Courtenay 1991a,
13, 28; cf. Normore 1987).
Theological nominalism is immediatelyconnected with the discussions of the identityof God's knowledge and the identityof the belief
of the People of God.4 There are different
ways in which an object of
God's knowledge or an article of faithwas formulateddepending on
where on the time-scale God's knowledge is referredto, or when an
article was believed. Some theologians tried to explain these differencesby claiming only one enuntiabile
which was behind the several
formulationsof the same object of knowledgeor articleof faithdiffering only withrespectto the tense of the infinitiveverb. In theirview,
this enuntiabilewas realized in enuntiabiliain several tenses which
. To use two
appear as inflectedforms of "the original enuntiabile"
famous examples: Abraham believed that Christ would be born, we
believe that Christ has been born: Abraham's and our belief is the
same belief, although the way in which it is expressed has changed
because of the movement of time, which is expressed by a change of
tense. In the same way is illustrated the tension between God's
is common
toall people,thatis: itfitsall peopleby
specialword{speciale
vocabulum),
a nominalist
Themovetowards
madebythis
appellation
position
{perappellationern)".
in thisalternative
becomesclearwhenwe compareit withthe
glossator
exposition
madeinthecommentary
remark
onPriscian'
whichbelongs
s De constructionibus
tothe
Glosulae
tradition
1978,114-6).Herethenoun
(MS Orlans,B.m.90; cf.Kneepkens
homo
is saidtobe thecommon
nameofall men,whereas
thespeciesis "in all men"
(p. 373a).
2 ExceptforthecaseofRalphofBeauvais(cf.Listoftexts,no. 25i).Unfortunately,
thetwoworks
havecomedowntous,areofa rather
level
byRalphwhich
elementary
oftheNominales
and do nothavemuchinformation
aboutthedoctrine
(cf.Listof
texts,no. 13).
3 Fortheso-called
seeChenu1935-36,
Chenu1957,90nominalism",
"theological
107, Landgraf1943,Nuchelmans
1973, 177-89,Normore1987and Courtenay
1991a.
4 For an in depthdiscussion
of the far-reaching
of "theological"
consequences
nominalism
fortheothertheological
of language,see
aspectsand thephilosophy
1991a,20 and Normore
1987,206-10.
Courtenay
35

09:07:25 AM

knowledgethatthe world would be created, whichwas trueknowledge


beforethe creation of the world, and the statusof thisknowledge after
the creation of the world.
On the face of it, this solution must have sounded odd to mediaeval
ears, and some of these theologiansdefendedtheirtheoryby referring
to the adjective albus, which though having a masculine formalbus, a
feminine form alba and a neutral form album, remains one and the
same adjective albus.5 Later on, by authors of the middle of the thirteenth century, this phenomenon was called the unity of the noun
), and the theologianswho supportedthis in this debate
(unitasnominis
nominales.
called
were
The notion of the unityof the noun is clearlygrammaticallybased.
'
'
Chenu (1935-36/1957) saw the rootsof this 'theological' nominalism
hidden in early twelfth-century
grammatical thought,especially in a
the
denominatives
on
which, according to John of Salisbury
theory
{Metal. Ill, 2), was maintained by Bernard of Chartres. This famous
scolaeof Chartres (/Z. 1120; Southern 1970, 61-85) maintained
magister
that the denominatives principally signifiedthe same as the words
which theywere derived fromand only differedin consignification.So
the principal significationof albedo, albumand albetis the same, but
their consignificationsdiffer.Chenu's surmise is clear. In Bernard's
grammatical theorywe also find the principal meaning preserved on
the one hand, and the differencesbetween the several parts of speech
which were only caused by the differencesin consignificationon the
other. And ifnot this theory,what other grammaticaltheorycould be
the cradle of the notion of the unity of the noun?
Recently, the introductionof Bernard of Chartres and his semantic
theoryinto the doctrine of the unity of the noun has been criticized
(Courtenay 1991a, 22). It has been argued that in the writingsof
Aristotle,Augustine and Anselm of Canterbury the importantingredients were already present, viz. consignification,the oneness of the
noun and verb based on an underlyingmeaning and the secondary
status of tense. Furthermore,Bernard's theorywas said not to be a
theoryof the unity of the noun, but a Platonizing interpretationof
Aristotle's section on the denominatives. This criticismis, to a great
extent, correct. There is no compelling reason to accept Bernard's
teaching as the root of theological nominalism. On the other hand,
5 Forthesimilar
inthedoctrine
ofthe
ofthisgrammatical
phenomenon
application
see Valente1990,73.
Trinity,
36

09:07:25 AM

saying that the theorymentioned by John was only Bernard's interpretationof a small section of Aristotle'sCategories, does not do full
justice to the Old Master of Chartres. Furthermore, it has been
argued that in the discussions of the universais the transition of
vocalism to nominalism was only possible, after a process of delingualizationof the noun, which was closely connected to the notion
of the unity of noun, had come about (Courtenay 1991a, 25).
At present,one of the firsttasks will be to investigatewhetherthere
existed some sort of theoryof the unity of the noun in late eleventhand early twelfth-century
grammar, and if so, what was its impact on
the linguistic status of the noun. As has been rightly observed
(Courtenay 1991a, 22), the ingredientsmay have been present, but
they needed to be brought togetherin order to obtain an operative
theoryor notion. In a firstinvestigationI foundtwo domains in which
such a unity of the noun could have been developed.
2. The theory
of theunityof thenoun
2. 1 The doctrine
of denomination
The firstdomain in which one can look forthe origin of the notion
of the unityof the noun is the doctrineof the denominativeswhich we
have already met in the discussion of Bernard's theory.Here we must
bear in mind that therewere two doctrinesof denomination operative
in thisperiod. One belongs to logic and has its roots in Aristotle'sfirst
chapter on the categories. According to the glossing master of one of
the Priscian commentariesin the NotaeDunelmenses
(Hunt 1943, 196" causae rerum'
the
Aristotelian
concentrated
on
the
8),
approach
Accordingto the glossing master, the otherdoctrineof denomination
is to be found in Priscian and has a purely grammatical character
are
verborum
focusingon word derivation: the originesand formationes
said to be its subject. The grammariansof the period under discussion
were acquainted with both theories,6but Aristotle's conception of
6 Cf. NotaeDunelm
. , f. 77ra: "Notandumetiamaliteraccipidenominatiuum
ab
Aristotile
et alitera Prisciano.
ab albedine
Aristotiles
enimdicitalbumdenominan
ad causasrerum,
Priscianus
ueroalbedinem
ab albo respiciens
respiciens
quasiad
et informaciones
uocabulorum."
origines
Fora similar
seetheso-called
Tractatus
opinion
(Vat.lat. 1486;cf.Fredborg
1977),
f.29ra: "Nota Priscianumacciperedenominatiuum
contrariomodo quam
Aristotilem.
uocisrespicit
Quodindeprocedit
quodquia istead formationem
que fit
mutatione
ueladditione
littere
uelliterarum,
utiusticia
fita iustus,
iusti
, additaeia,ille
ueroad sensummaximerespiciens,
quod requirit
priusesse remin aliquoquam
tarnen
nomenrecipiat,
iustus
et similiauocauitdenominatiua.
37

09:07:25 AM

denomination was by far the most influentialforthe developmentof


grammatical thought(Jolivet 1974 & 1975).
Another aspect, which we have to bear in mind, is that in the
Aristoteliandiscussion only nominal derivationis considered. Aristoand fortis.The
tle considers relationshipssuch as thatbetweenfortitudo
same tendency we find in Boethius' commentaryon the Categories.
and the
Here Boethius identifiesthe protagonistsas the nomen
principale
nomentransfiguratum
(which only differsfrom the nomenprincipaleby
means of a casus). According to Boethius, who introducesthe Platonic
notion of participation into the doctrine of denomination (Jolivet
1975, 225), three conditions must be met before one can speak of
denomination: the formal participation on the level of the res
{albedo!albus), the material participationon the level of the noun, and
finally transfiguration,for there must be an "external" difference
between both nouns.
In the grammatical commentariesof the late eleventh centurythe
Aristotelian-Boethiantraditionof denominationwas enlarged withthe
doctrine of a semantic affinitybetween verb and adjective. A central
notion of the verb-adjectiverelationshipis the resverbi
, about which
the Mediaevals found material in Priscian. Basically, every verb
signifiesits resverbiin a special, viz. verbal, manner as inhering.What
exactly the resverbiwas and what its ontological status was, was not
made clear, but there was a common agreement based on Priscian
(XVIII, 43) thatyou could findthe resverbiby looking at the meaning
of the respectiveinfinitives,since the infinitivewas considered to be
the name of the resverbi
, which generallycould also be representedby
cursus
a verbal noun: legeremeans lectio
, alberealbedoand so on.
} currere
of the cognate
the
function
to
be
This was also considered
denominative adjective albus and the participle currens.It turned out
that legitsignifiedlectioas inhering, legensdid the same, whereas a
also signifiedlectioin an inheringposi(substantive) noun such as lector
tion. The resultwas that the grammariansbuilt up a sortof Platonizing semantic web based on Boethius' interpretationof Aristotle'sdoctrine of denomination, enlarged with Priscian's doctrine of the res
verbi
, which could be reduced to the principal significationof the nomen
principale.
It appears from the texts that the outlines of this approach were
commonly accepted in the early twelfthcentury(Jolivet1975, 232-3).
We meet it forinstance in Abaelard's writings(Jolivet 1975, 233-4).
There was less consensus, however, about the ways in which the parts
38

09:07:25 AM

of speech agreed and differed.Bernard of Chartres accepted an agreewhich he regarded


ment on the level of the principalissignificatio
to the level of
res
and
the
differences
the
to
verbi,
assigned
equivalent
the consignificatio
.7 We find this view also mentioned in the Notae
Dunelmenses
(f. 93ra-b) and the Tractatus.In these texts, however, we
8 or
alio modo
do not find the term "consignificare"
, but only significare
the observationthatthe differencesmust be looked fornot in the prin, since verbs signifywith tenses and
cipal meaning, but in the accidentia
Other grammarians
moods and nouns do so withoutthese accidentia.9
the criterionfor the
considered for instance the principalissignificatio
categorizationof the parts of speech, or made a distinctionin theprinsubstantialis
between significatio
, which in the case of a
cipalissignificatio
accidentalis
verb indicated the verbal signification,and the significatio
,
which stood forthe resverbi.10
We have to admit, the doctrine of the significativeidentityof the
denominativestaken in a wider sense was too non-specificto be the
directsource of the notion of the unityof the noun and we do not find
it mentionedin this context. On the otherhand, those theorieswhich
claimed a differencebetween noun and verb which was only based on
the accidentia
as the glossatorof
and spoke of the significationis
identitas
7 Incidentally,
we mustbearin mindthatconsignificatio
is thetermwhichwasused
wholivedaboutforty
byJohnofSalisbury,
yearslaterthanBernard
(cf.J. Pinborg,
DieEntwicklung
derSprachtheorie
imMittelalter
, 1967,32 & 34).
8 NoteDunelm.
f.93rb:"Et beneconcedunt
albedo
et album
idemsignifiquodalbet,
modis."
cant,seddiuersis
9 Tractatus
nullam
(Vat. lat. 1486),f.43vb:"Nota in hac principali
significatione
essedifferentiam
interquedamnominaet uerba,ut interalbumet albet
, et sedens
nomenet sedet.
Et ut plusdicamintersignificationem
et uerborum
supradictorum
nullasecundum
hancsignificationem
Namquemadmodum
uerinuenitur
differentia.
bumactum[actiuum
quod [hocMS]
[passiuum
MS] uel passionem
MS] secundum
insuntsignificant,
sicutet supradicta
resquas primonotantnonsimpliciter,
sed
Sed licetin hoc nullasit differentia,
tarnenin
inherent,
inquantum
significant.
accidentibus
in temporibus
et modis.Verbaenimcummodiset
magnaest,scilicet
actumuel passionem
inesse,nominauerosineillissignificant."
temporibus
10Notae
Dunelm.
itaqueillamprimam
(DurhamMS), f.35ra:"Secundum
generlem
etprinciplem
ac substantialem
uerbisignificationem
hicagitde uerbo.
Obicitur
autemadiectiua
lector
nominainhocnondifferre
a uerbo,utab albusalbet,
a legit.
Concedimus
quodhocet uolumus.Cum enimomneuerbumex naturasua
sitadiectiuum,
nondebetdifferre
immoconuenire
cumadiectiuis
siue
quibuslibet
nominibus
siuealiisin modosignificando
Non estinconueniens
bis
[inconueniens
cumquibus[analiisMS] nominibus
in significatone
sua
MS] si uerbumconuenit
dumtarnen
aliomodoconueniat
aliouerboetalionomini,
uerboscilicet
principali,
utsignificatio
nominiuerout accidentalis,
cumlicetin hoc
substantialis,
presertim
in multistamenaliisdiffrant."
quoquomodoconueniant,
39

09:07:25 AM

the oldest version of the Glosulae already had done,11 must


undoubtedlyhave contributedto an atmospherewhich stimulatedthe
developmentof such a notion based, forthe most part, on a combination of the absolute predominance of principal significationover
secondary significationand common origin.
words
2. 2 The domainof inflected
The otherdomain in which a unityof the noun could be spoken of,
is farmore restricted.It can be recognisedforinstancein observations
such as those by Godfreyof Poitiers and Saint Bonaventure about the
words albus!-bal-bumwhich being three voces
, are neverthelessone
noun, or which being three nouns, are nevertheless not different
nouns (Chenu 1935-36; Courtenay 1991a, 16-7). It is obvious thatthis
is the direct domain of the inflectedformsand that the unity of the
declinables is at stake, as was also recognisedby the Mediaevals themselves.
Here too, the approaches of grammar and logic turn out to be
diametricallyopposed. In Aristotle'sDe interpretatione
(c. 2, 16bl; c. 3,
16bl 7-8) and in Boethius' commentarieson thiswork,the Mediaevals
found the view that the casus of a noun and the casus of a verb were
not a noun and a verb respectively.This view opposed the position
maintained by the grammarians, who believed that case, mood and
tense were accidentia
, and did not affectthe categorical status of the
declinata.On thelevel of semanticsit was the grammarians' view which
was not only generallyadhered to by the grammarians,but also by the
logicians. Abaelard's position is evident in this respect {Dial 125, 23): the casus rectusand the oblique cases are of the same signification,
and the
althoughtheirconstructionalbehaviour is absolutelydifferent,
same holds true for the adjectives albus, alba and album: the same
meaning, but of a differentgender.12The author of the Introductiones
MontanaeMaiores,13who was doctrinallycognate withAlberic of Paris,
11Glosulae
nullam
significations
(MS Kln,201), f.28ra:"Nota in hac principali
essedifferentiam
internominaquedamet uerba,utinteralbum
etalbet... Sed licet
in accidentibus
tarnen
in temporibus
nullasitin hocdifferentia,
magnaest,scilicet
hancsignifications
uolentes
deuitare
identitatem
et modis.... Quidamtarnen
12A similarviewis heldin theTractatus
(Vat.lat.1486, f.48va).The verbalforms
in themodeofsignifying,
sincethe
thesamelectio
andlegisignify
, butdiffer
legebam
it as beingimperfect,
thelatteras perfect.
former
signifies
13Preserved
cf.E.P. Bos,La thorie
dela
in MS Paris,BN, lat. 15141,47r-104rb;
' ' danslesIntroductiones
in:
dela "uoxsignificatiua
adplacitum
Montanae
Maiores,
signification
73-90.
Gilbert,
40

09:07:25 AM

said (f. 49r) thatthereare two definitionsof the noun: A strictdefinition which removes oblique cases, infinitenouns etc. from being a
noun, viz. the Aristoteliandefinition,and a large definitionwhich
includes all the nouns, oblique nouns, adverbs etc., at least iftheyare
"of a certainsignification7
' 14So essecertaesignificationis
was a criterion
for being classifiedas a noun.
An interestingpoint of the Montanist's discussion of the noun is
that he is strugglingwith a problem which put anachronisticlyshows
some resemblance to the distinctionbetween the lexeme and wordforms(cf. Lyons 1981, 101). It is asked whetherthe oblique cases of
the proper noun Socrates'are separate nouns. The author admits that
the noun Socratis
is the proper noun of the man
, Socratiand Socratem
but
he
refuses
to
call
Socrates
forthat reason binomial. This
Socrates,
noun Socratis
the
he
,
continues, is not thisnoun Socratem
,
genitivecase,
the accusative case, (that is: the word-formsare not the same) nor is
it another noun (that is: it does not belong to another lexeme), but it
"
is the same noun: " idemcumilio nomen
(that is: both are word-forms
of the same lexeme):15albus!alba!albumare formsof the same lexeme,
which in modern notation would be writtenas 'albus'.
In my view, the Alberican approach is not only a fine example of
the way in which the notion of the unityof the noun was operative in
order to cope with the linguisticproblem of the relationshipbetween
14MS Paris,BN lat.15141.f49ra:"Ad quoddicimus
quodduesuntnominis
[modi
et uerbi,una laxa secundum
quemadmodum
exp.MSC]diflnitiones
quam omnia
aduerbia
certesignificationis
etobliquinominum
etnominainfinita
nominasunt,hec
scilicetuox significatiua
ad placitumsine tempore
cuius nullaparsseparataest
omnibus
Estalia difinitio
istispotestassignari.
nominis
significatiua,
que diffinitio
strictior
secundum
etobliquietnominainfinita
a nomine
remouenquametaduerbia
tur. Vnde Aristotiles
ait: "Catonis et Catoni non sunt nomina,sed casus
nominum...."
15 MS Paris,BN lat. 15141,f.49ra:"Rursus
"Socratesestnomen;ergo
opponitur:
est proprium
uel appellatiuum.
Et cumnonsitappellatiuum,
undeestproprium
cumnonsitalterius.
Et si estSocrates
nomenSocratis,
Socrates
habethoc
Socratis,
nomenSocratiset eademrationeSocrate<m>,
Socrate.Et ita uocaturhocnomine
concedere.
Nos nonconSocratis,
Socrati,Socratem,
Socrate,quodestabsurdum
cedimusquod uoceturaliquis [f.49rb]Socratisuel uocationemfierinisi per
nominatiuum
etuocatiuum,
uthicuocetur
Socrates
uelo Socrata.Adquod
[Socrates]
dicimusesse concedendum
quod hoc nomenSocratisSocrati,-temest proprium
nomenSocratis.Et Socrates[-tisMS] habethocnomenSocratiset Socratem.
Non
tarnen
habetpluranomina,
Et hocnomenSocratis
nonest
quia iamessetbinomius.
hoc nomenSocratem
nec aliudnomen,sed idemcumilio nomine.Sed quamuis
habeatSocrateshoc nomenSocratem,
non potestuocariistonomine,sed potest
nomineistoet uocarinominequodestidemcumisto."
appellari
41

09:07:25 AM

several forms of one word (the lexeme/word-formaspect), it also


paved the way forthe acceptance of a lexeme status of a noun which
is not equivalent to the status of being a mental noun.
Another interestingsource fora theoryof a noun at the level of the
lexeme in connection with the unity of the noun does not date back
to early decades of the twelfthcentury, but to the 1160s, viz. the
Summa"Brevesit" by Robert of Paris (ed. Kneepkens 1987II). But it,
in turn, has an earlier predecessor.
Near the end of the firstbook (97-103) Robert of Paris quite comprehensivelydiscusses the semantic and taxonomie relationshipof the
nominato theirdiminutiva
, e.g. Antoniusand its diminutiveAntoniaster.
One of the problemswhich these nouns give rise to is whethertheyare
two different' 'nouns' ' or one "noun". To illustratethe problem in
more depth, Robert appends the question whetherthe Latin formand
and Hubert,are one name or
the French formof a name, e.g. Robertus
whetherthe person who can be called by both names is binomial. His
conclusion is that they are the same noun. He supports this view by
These
pointingto the Latin noun homoand the Greek noun anthroopos.
nouns are the same noun, not, however, the same Greek noun or the
same Latin noun, but just as eo and is are the same verb, but not the
same monosyllabic or disyllabic verb. This identityof the noun is
based by Robert on the identityof theirdefinition.For the Greek definitionof man and the Latin definitionof man are the same definition,
because according to Boethius the definitionsare the same for all
people. Thus the words which are definedby means of the same definition must be the same word.
"
What is meant by " idemnomen in this context?At firstglance, it
seems that we are at the crossroads of two traditions of mental
language. One has its rootsin Augustine's observationson the interior
word.16This interiorword is not the word thatcan be pronounced nor
the mental counterpartof an utterable word conceived of in a vocal
sequence in the mind. It is that word of the rational animated being,
which precedes all the signs by means of which it can be expressed,
and findsits origin in the knowledge which remains in a man's mind.
It cannot be pronounced nor conceived of in any vocal sequence,
which is a condition necessary for its being a word of any human
16Cf.G. Nuchelmans,
entaal,
HetMentaals,
detaalvanhetdenken
, in: id., Wijsbegeerte
'
desMitcordisZurSprachphilosophie
Meppel1976,153-72and H. Arens, Verbum
7 (1980),13-27.
telalters
, in: Historiographia
Linguistica,
42

09:07:25 AM

language, as Augustine argues {Trin. XV, xi, 20). So it is the word


whichdoes not belong to any spoken language (e.g. Trin.XV, x, 19).
We find these three ways of "speaking" repeated in Anselm's
Monologion
(c. 10). Anselm argues thatwe can use our tongue and say
for instance "man", and we can tacitlyconceive of the same name
'man'. Thus farAnselm is in absolute conformity
withAugustine. But
Augustine's third way of speaking, the real interior word, is subdivided into two kinds by Anselm. One happens by means of a picture, the other by means of reason. The latter takes place when one
considers for instance man's universal nature: " animal rationalemortale1' . The words of the thirdway of speech as Anselm emphasizes in
Aristotelian-Boethianwords, are naturaliaand the same forall nations
(.Monol. c. 10).
The other traditionstems from Boethius' commentaryon Aristotle's Perihermeneias.
Boethius, working in the tradition of the Greek
Aristotlecommentators,distinguishesbetween a writtensentence, a
vocal sentenceand a sentenceon the level of the intellectus
or concepts
We
find
this
triad
mentioned
(Nuchelmans 1976, 157).
by Robert in
his section on the diminutives,where he explicitlyrefersto Boethius'
threekinds ofwords withthe terms:nomen
and
, nomen
scriptum
prolatum
nomenintellectum
(ed. Kneepkens 1987II, 101, 21-2).
It is undoubtedly tempting to accept that the notion of the
'

"unspoken word" underlies Robert's statement that homo and


4
' are the same
noun, but such an interpretationdoes not
anthroopos
to
be
correct.
Anselm'
s interpretationof Augustine shows that
appear
the Mediaevals of the late eleventh centuryrecognised two formsof
mentallanguage in Augustine's words. One is based on psychological
imagination,and the otheris based on reason. The latterindisputably
. Robert joins both
approaches the Aristotelian-Boethian"intellectus"
traditions by attributingto the definitiothe role of the Boethian
intellectus.
He is able to do so because Anselm had already explained
the universal essence of man with the help of the definitionof man.
Furthermore,Anselm himselfhad already made a directlink between
these two traditions.The problem is, however, that the AugustinianAnselmian "interior word", and Boethius' intellectus
or definitionare
exactlythat which this "idem nomen" should be the noun of. Moreover, in my opinion it is not correctto postulate "a thirdnomen": the
nouns homoand anthroopos
are said to be the same noun, but otherwise
as in the case of the definitions,Robert does not say that these nouns
"- a
are the same noun " apud omnes
condition necessary for being a
43

09:07:25 AM

mentadnoun- but they are said to be the name of somethingwhich


is the same for all people, and thereforethey are the same noun.
We find an earlier version of Robert's discussion in Abaelard' s
bus1
in his Logica 'Ingredienti
commentaryon Aristotle'sDe interpretatione
But
Abaelard
still
of
voces
and
not
of
speaks
(ed. Geyer, 323, 17).
nomina(Jolivet1981, 176; Courtenay 1991a, 25). CriticizingAristotle
in this respect,Abaelard argues that it happens that the voces(Jolivet
1981, 184) of various languages are the same according to the same
way of signifyingthe same thing. For, Abaelard continues, anthroopos
"
signifiesthe same thingin the same way as homo, viz. thatit is animal
'
'
rationalemortale. In modern terminologyAbaelard and Robert would
have said: The Greek lexeme 'anthroopos' and the Latin lexeme
'homo' are the same lexeme, that is theyhave the same meaning and
significativefunctionin their respectivelanguages.
Concluding this part of my article, I would argue that in the
linguisticthoughtof the firsthalf of the twelfthcenturythe unity of
the noun (or verb) or rather the identitywas an operative notion.
When we compare the approaches of the generation of Bernard of
Chartres and the Alberic/Robertperiod, we see that in addition to the
interestin the identityof meaning on the level of denominativeaffinity
(denomination taken here in a wider sense) the grammariansand logicians of the later period paid increasing attentionto the identityof
words which differedonly by inflection,and to the related semantic
problems.
Furthermore,the followingthreeaspects undoubtedlycorroborated
the position of the noun as an appropriate successor of the transient
flatusvocisin the theoryof the logicians who adhered to a vocalist position (Courtenay 1991a, 25): first(1) the tendencyto detach the noun
from its spoken language forms,giving rise to the development of a
mediaeval counterpart to the modern lexeme, second (2) the claim
that the diversityof the languages was no impedimentto the identity
of correspondinglexemes, and third(3) the yet remaining languagebound character of the noun. This happened not only on the level of
predication theories, but also in semantics as the substitution of
Abaelard' s voxwith Robert's nomenshows.
Anotherpoint which deserves our attentionin thiscontextis thatin
their commentaries on Priscian grammarians comprehensivelydealt
with the verbal infinitive.They discussed the phenomenon of the res
verbi
, and considered the constructionaland semantic aspects of the
infinitive.Furthermore,we find extensive discussions of the several
44

09:07:25 AM

tenses of the verb and of the distinctionbetween time and tense. But
it is surprisingthat the grammarians did not mention the problem
which will occupy the nominalisttheologian: the semantic differences
betweenthe different
tensesof the infinitives.This is the more striking
since Abaelard had already manifestlydealt with the problem of the
dictumpropositionis
. In his discussion of Abaelard's view on the
status
of the denotatum of the dictumpropositionis
,
ontological
Nuchelmans (1973, 156) has referredto Abaelard's inclinationto considerthe whole dictumas a sortof name or noun ("quasi nomen
") of that
which is expressedby the propositionitself.We findseveral analogies
between Abaelard's conception of this "quasi-nomen" and the "real
noun". Abaelard speaks of its "impositio"; the vocal sequence
" in the
" Socrates
" '
currit
curriestverum"functions
proposition Socrates
as subject and is not a proposition itself,but it is the noun of that
"
which is given the attribute"true": " nomeneius cui uerumattribuitur
(Dial. 150,20). It must be noted thatAbaelard, who in his theological
works dealt with theological and epistemological problems caused by
enuntiabiliawhich differ only in tense (ed. Mews, TS, 61 sqq.;
Courtenay 1991a, 23-4), in his Dialecta did not even touch upon the
differencebetween ilSocratem
currere"and " Socratemcucurrisse"
. Even
the grammarians of the second part of the twelfthcentury, who
devoted separate quaestiones
to the several aspects of the substantivated
infinitive and entered upon the constructional status of object
language sentences within a metalinguistic context avoided
elaborating on this topic. Petrus Hispanus, the author of the Absoluta
cuiuslibet
defended a nominalisticview on the de dictoand de re interpretation(ed. Kneepkens 1987, IV, 71; cf. List of texts,no 50c), but
one looks in vain in his workforthe problem of the infinitivesor rather
dictawith a view to theirdifferenttenses. The only conclusion I dare
to draw at thispoint is thatthiswas material which was not dealt with
in grammar, but remained reserved for the theologians. The grammarians were only interestedin congruencyand constructionanalysis.
" and
In this respect the propositions " Christumnatumesse est verum
" Christum
"
nasciturum
esseestverum do not differ.God's knowledge,the
status
of
the
ontological
object of epistemicverbs and truthand falsity
are not the grammarian's concern. But as soon as de dictoand de re
problems arise, the grammarian is present in order to distinguish
between the various constructionalrelationships.

45

09:07:25 AM

and thediscussionof theuniversais


3. A noteon grammatical
theory
Finally, I would like to make some observationson the role which
grammatical theory played in the nominalist discussions on the
universais. In my view the relationshipbetween noun and definition
which we have met in the discussion on the identityof the noun might
have played an importantrole in the move fromthe focus on the vox
to the nomenwithin this theory.
The famous codex Orleans 266 has preserved in the pages 276a to
281a a treatisewhich is called in the manuscript" Positiovocumsententiae". 17The text startswith Porphyry'sdescriptionof the genusin the
translationof Boethius (II, 4, ed. S. Brandt, 179-80): " quoddepluribus
'
etdifferentibus
speciein eoquodquidsitpraedicatur(cf. 181, 14-5), whereas
the speciesis described in the same words the only differencebeing
1.
"
ilnumero
"
After some
differentibusinstead of specie differentibus1
proposes to startwith
general remarksthe author of the /W/zo-treatise
4
an inquiry into the universal, universale
, which he defines as 'that
which is aptumnatumpraedicaride pluribus". Next, threedefinitionsof
are given, the second of which is of special interest
the termpraedicatum
to the author. In it he defines the term praedicatumas ilquodlibet
vi substantivipresents
vocabulumalii coniugibileveraciteraffirmative
to
the
in
this
author,
praedicatum
interpretationis applied in
According
,18Next, the definitionof the universale
the definitionof the universale
given in the beginningof the treatiseis rephrasedwiththe help of this
estquodui substantiui
: li Universale
uerbipresents
definitionof praedicatum
estpluribus".
etprorsusconiungibile
ueraciter
Obviously it is of great importanceto the vocalist or nominalistto
'
remain on the ' 'linguistic' level. On the other hand, he needs to be
in contact withthe extra-linguisticworld which in his view consistsof
individuals only. Furthermore,there is on the level of language a
pluralitywhich he must avoid, viz. a pluralitywhich could be caused
by signification,which taken here in a strictersense opposes nominatio.
For when Socrates is sittingand reading and is being pointed at by the
speaker, the followingtwo propositionsare true:
(x) this sittingbeing is Socrates
and
(x) this reading being is Socrates,
17An editionbyDr. Y. Iwakumais forthcoming.
18Incidentally,
: a linguistic
is a vocabulum
thisimpliesthattheuniversale
entity.
46

09:07:25 AM

which would lead to the admission of the proper noun Socratesinto the
category of universais. For legensand sedensare not only different
(spoken) words, theyare also differentin theirprincipal signification,
'
'
since 'sitting' represents sessio and 'reading' 'lectio', and therefore
plura,19
To get around this difficultythe author introduces the semantic
: plura in the definition of the universal must
notion of nominatio
indicate a pluralitybased on nominatio.That is why he inserts:plura
nominatione.
Nominatiois a technical term which belongs to the doctrine of
nominal signification.Although in detail some of the texts show a
was commonly used to
divergenceas we shall see, the term nominatio
indicate the denotative or rather 4'naming" functionof the noun.
in the strictsense, which in its turn was
Nominatioopposes significatio
said to indicate the relation between the name and a quality or a
nature with referenceto the thing denoted. We find this theoryheld
in both camps: the vocalists/nominalistsand the realists. William of
Conches, a realist, explicitly argued that the noun homo names
, i.e. the individual men, and not the quality
{nominat)ipsos homines
which it signifies: " significai communem qualitatem omnium
hominum"
{LogicaModern., II, 1, 224). The nominalistAbaelard maintained a similar position. He claimed that the noun homodenotes
{nominat)Socrates, that is the individual man, but signifiesman's
mortale
nature: animalrationale
{Dial. 562-3), of course conceived of by
Abaelard only as a concept.
It appears thatthe author of the Positioalso adhered to thiscommon
and nominare
of nominatio
, but he neverthelessconsidered
interpretation
it appropriateto eliminate another,deviatingapplication of nominatio.
19MS Orlans266,p. 276b:"Quia uniuersale
estquodui [scr.qui MS] substantiui
et prorsus
estpluribus.
ueraciter
[scr.subiectum
coniungibile
MS] uerbipresents
Pluraautemoportet
uthec'<hoc> sedens'et 'hoclegens'
accipiin nominatione,
nonsunt,quiaeandempersonam
de quibusSocrates
multainnominatione
predicatur
habent.
significare
ex partesubiectiponitur,
est
Opponitur
quia cum etiamSocrates
coniungibile
et[inMS] animali,
pluribus,
quiahomini
que plurasuntinnominatione,
quiaanimal
talequidsignificat,
ab homine.
quodnonsignificatur
Ad quoddicimusquodeis quidemconiungi
non
potest,
apponiueroeis prorsus
Predicati
autemapponi[potest
uero
subiecti
MS,sedexp.]est,idestsuperponi,
potest.
etquasisubiectum.
Etilludetiamdicipotest,
etanimal
diuersain
subponi
quia homo
nominatione
nonsunt,quiaaliquidab aliquocontentum
ab alteroetiampersonaliter
contineri
habet."
47

09:07:25 AM

He felthimselfchallenged to meet the objection that the noun Socrates


put in subject position is also able to be joined to liplura' since it can
be joined to the nouns homoand animalin predicate position:
(x) Socratesesthomo
and
(x) Socratesestanimal
"
"
which are " plura in nominatione"
, for animal signifiesa tale quid
which is not signifiedby the noun homo.Our author points to the difference between a noun in subject position and predicate position,
, and
whereby incidentally he uses the verbs supponereand apponere
of
we
are speaking
words in
argues that in regard to universais
predicate position only. But he also denies that these nouns, animal
in nomination,since the thingwhichis denoted
and homo, are different
one
of
the
can
also personally be denoted by the other one.
two
by
" becomes clear
What is meant by the adverb " personaliter
e.g. from
Ralph of Beauvais' observation on persona( Gl.s. Donatum,21,2 sqq).:
it is the individual essence of a rational creature. The emphasis, howessencia,which
ever, is on 'individual'; personais not said of a communis
is signifiedby a universal noun but not denoted. This means that our
vocalist author as well as Abaelard and William of Conches use
in regard to individuals only. On the otherhand it turnsout
nominatio
that the position which he attacks was not invented 4pour besoin de
la cause", but a view really maintained in the early twelfthcentury.
The anonymous glossator
We find it referredto in the Tractatus.20
20MS Vat.lat. 1486,f. 17ra:"Huic sententie
opponitur
quod qualitasnominis
notetMS' animal
nomint
uidetur
esse,utcumhomo
[MSfinmarg.
parsnominat[iu]i
iliatalitasparsessenominati.
uidetur
ei illamtalitatem,
taleattribuendo
licetconstet
iliaspecialis
Sicutanimaltale,scilicet
Adquodrespondendum.
natura,
ex animaliperillamqualitatem
, tamennonestiliaduoconiuncta,
quamponithomo
utsedensnonestpersonaet
animaletqualitas,sedestanimalsicformtm,
scilicet
itacumdicimus
homo
animaitale,idestspecialem
nominare
sessiosedaffecta
sessione,
idestanimaiet qualitatem
coniunctam,sed
naturam,non nominamus
utrumque,
homo.
actuillaproprietate
animaiformtm
quamei attribuit
uel aliamsubstantiam
ad primamredeamus
Demissaergohac sententia
nominum
enimtriplicem
nominidemusquam et pleriqueponunt.Considrant
unam in substantia,
secundamin qualitate,terciamid quod
significationem:
hocnomen
et adiectiuis
discrete
uideamus.
Socrates
nominatur,
quodin substantiuis
habetspecialem
naturam
eandemquamsuperius
substantiam
hominis,
qualitatem
homo
substantiam
ueroindiuiduam
remcuipositum
est.Similiter
nominat
diximus,
remcui et
uerospecialem
habetanimalipsum,qualitatem
quam prius,nominat
reiquamnominant
substantiam
habentmateriam
datumest.Ita etalia substantiua
in id quodnominatur."
id quod redigit
materiam
uel quasimateriam,
qualitatem
48

09:07:25 AM

argues thatthe "common view" maintains that nominal signification


has three aspects: the significationof the substance, the signification
of the quality, and the nomination. In practice, this theorysays that
the proper noun Socrates
has as its substance the special nature of man,
viz. homo, as its quality socratitas,
and it signifiesboth of these, but it
nominates the individual thingon which it was imposed. In the same
way the common noun homohas as substance animal also called
"materia", and as quality humanitas,
but it nominatesthe " specialisres"
to which it has been given: homo, which is not an individual. The
glossatorsummarizeshis positionby sayingthatthe substantivenouns
have as substance the matterof the res, which theynominate (e.g. in
thecase ofhomo
: animal), as quality thatwhichreduces ( redigit
) the matter to that which is nominated, homo{resspecialis).
So it turnsout thatthe notion of nominatio
was of paramount importance to the nominalistpositionin the debate on the universais. It kept
the whole predicationon the level of language; not only the predicate
but also the subject of the predication was a term or rather a noun.
This fact was even referredto in the grammatical treatises, as the
observationby Robert of Paris shows (List of texts no 12). Furtherintroducedthe noun as a product of imposition, not
more, nominatio
as a mere voice which existed only during the time of its pronunciation, the challengedflatus vocis. Besides, nominatioas taken by the
author guaranteed a direct link between the outer world and the
predication: forthe subject term of the predication always names an
individual being.
4. Final remarks
Summing up my investigationsI would like to make the following
final remarks:
1. The Aristotelian-Boethiantheoryof denomination, enlarged by
the grammatical theoryof the resverbiand the logical theoryof the
affinityof verb and adjective, created a semantic atmosphere which
was appropriate forthe development of the notion of the unityof the
noun. It must be stressed,however, that we do not findit mentioned
in this context.
2. The confrontationof the grammaticaldoctrineof the identityof
the principal significationof the forms of the declinabiliawith the
Aristoteliantheory of a fundamental differencebetween noun and
verb and theirrespectiveoblique cases, in connection with the doc49

09:07:25 AM

trineof binomyand the Boethian traditionof the identityof the definition, compelled the twelfthcenturyscholarsto elaborate a sortof "lexeme' ' notion, the unitas(identitas)nominis
, with the result that they
could speak about a noun not directly bound to any individual
language without, however, leaving the level of vocal language.
It must be noted that in the grammatical texts one does not find
referencesto the problem of tensed infinitivesnor the question of what
is called the identityof the enuntiabile
(Courtenay 1991a, 17). These
of
the
of the logician and the
domains
were
apparentlypart
problems
not
concern.
were
the
grammarian's
theologian; they
3. I have not found a specific grammatical theory which was
exclusively related to (logical or theological) nominalismjust as Porconstruiand the
retan linguistics, for instance with its substantive
related
was
to Porretan
status
of
the
predicate noun,
significative
thought. On the contrary,grammatical doctrine turned out to have
been neutralto realism and vocalism or nominalism,and could inspire
both theories.
4. If the introductionof the grammaticalor rathersemantic notion
into the theoryof predicationof the vocaleswas not responof nominatio
sible for the shiftfromvoxto nomen
, it undoubtedly supported it.21
Katholieke UniversiteitNijmegen
InstituutOudeLetteren
21Thanksare due to Drs. Th. Harmsenforhishelpwiththetranslation
ofthis
article.

50

09:07:25 AM

Vivarium
XXX, 1 (1992)
Vocalista,Nominalism and the Commentarieson
theCategories from theEarlier TwelfthCentury
JOHN MARENBON

Commentaries on Aristotle's Categoriesare a rich, and hardly


logic.1 The
explored, source of informationabout twelfth-century
evidence theyofferabout nominalism supportsthe traditionalview of
its originsagainst those historianswho have argued that the nominales
were so called, not because they were said to describe genera and
, but because they adhered to a theoryof the 'unity
species as nomina
of the noun.'2 This paper will explore three main aspects of this
evidence: the use of the word nomenin logic; the controversybetween
Abelard and Alberic over universais; and the originsof the thesisquod
semelestuerum,semperestuerum.
and theCategories
1. Nomina, nominanominum
Those who argue against the traditionalaccount of the origins of
nominalism point out that, whilst a number of thinkersin the early
twelfthcentury held that genera and species are uoces, and whilst
Abelard subsequentlymodifiedthis view, and described universais as
sermones
, thereis much less evidence that Abelard or anyone else described theirpositionas being thatgenera and species are nomina
.3 And
so the nominales
can hardlyhave acquired theirname because of their
views about universais. But the linguistic usage of Abelard and his
contemporaries was less fixed than this argument allows. Even
William Courtenay, the most eloquent proponentof the view, admits
that in both of his long PorphyrycommentariesAbelard did referto
universaisfromtime to time as nomina
.4 The background to thisusage
is provided by Boethius's commentaryon the Categories.
1 SeeMarenbon,
Medieval
latin
commentaries
fora catalogue
andgeneral
discussion
ofthe
- ee. (C 8).
material.
tothiscatalogue
aremadeinbrackets
References
inboldprint
2 Firstsuggested
in Chenu1934and 1935-36(1957),theviewis presented
in detail
in Courtenay
1987.
1991a;cf.also Normore
3 Courtenay
1991a,p. 15.
4 Courtenay
1991a,n. 23.
51

09:07:37 AM

Boethius explains that, in discussing the ten categories (which are


the most general genera), Aristotlewas concerned with words, rather
than directlywith things: words, however, considered not as the sub5
jects of grammaticalinvestigation,but in that theysignify(160 A). In
his introductionhe describes the ten categories interchangeablyas
.6 and he begins by making a distinctionbetween
uocesand as nomina
nominaof the firstimposition(which signifythings,such as the words
forthe categories) and nominaof the second imposition(termsof grammatical description,which signifyjust otherwords) (159 A-C). Nomen
was thus established as a useful alternative to vox when a term is
needed which means 4word' not in the sense of a physical sound, but
commenas that which signifies.The early twelfth-century
Categories
taries show clearly how this usage was absorbed. In C 8, probably
fromc. 1110-1120, nomenis used oftenin passages taken directlyfrom
Boethius; otherwise it occurs in phrases where the commentatoris
contrastingtheuse of a word in the firstor second imposition a nomen
rerum
, as he puts it, or a nomenuocum.7But once it is used as a direct
alternative to uox;8 and this tendency becomes marked in the interpolations to C 8 probably dating from the 1120s9 and in Abelardo
.10
long commentaryon the Categories
5 References
are to thecolumnsof Patrologia
s Categories
to Boethius'
commentary
Latina64.
6 Forexample:4In hocigitur
et
nominibus,
est,de primisrerum
operehaecintentio
nomen
ressignificantibus
de vocibus
disputare (159C); 'Haec ... unumsubstantiae
... unumtamennomen
concludens
nomine
continentur
includit... uno quantitatis
omniaqualitatis. ..' (160C-161A);'... de primisvocibus
, primarerumgenera
nomina
nam
...' (161A): '... ad multitudinem
ipsadispertit;
generum
significantibus
sedsecundum
rerum
rerum
orationem,
generasuntnonsecundum
quoniamdecern
dividit...' (163AB); 'Quoniamhicde
indecern
voces
praedicamenta
significationem
tractatus
habetur...Y184A).
nominibus
7 This commentary
is foundin ParisBN lat. 13368,ff.195r-214v;
Munichelm
14458, ff.95r-102r(incomplete);London BL Royal 7.D.XXV, ff.55r-63r
version:VaticanReg. lat. 230,ff.41r-71r.
(See Mareninterpolated
(incomplete);
0
ofthe
treatment
andcommentaries
bon,Glosses
, 6 forthisdating,where( 7) a fuller
nomen
enimsubstantia
willbe found.)Eg. 'Accipitur
introduction
tothiscommentary
nomen
uocum
...' (VaticanReg. lat.230,f.44v).
substantia
rerum... Itemaccipitur
note,are foundalso in theother,
(This passage,and thatquotedin thefollowing
manuscripts).
uninterpolated
8 'Quandoautemsubstantia
Substan... tunchabethancdescriptionem.
nomen
uocum
fundamentum
est. ..' (ibid.)
tiaestuoxiliaque aliarumuocum
9 'Sed quia Aristoteles
est
de rebussubstantialibus
perhocnomen
quodestsubstantia
modisaccipitur,
diuersis
hecuoxqueestsubstantia
etindiuersis
tractaturus,
preceptis
huiusuocissignificatio
perfundamentum
aperiendauidetur'(ibid.); '... substantia
... Vnde funuoces
earum,ponensin eis sustentationem
, scilicetnomina
significai
ad reset ad uoces.
estequiuocum
damentum
(ibid.,ff.44v-45r)
10All references
are to Geyer'
s editions
s logicalcommentaries
to Abelard'
(191952

09:07:37 AM

Voxremained the standard termto contrastwith res,and those who


.n
rejected the position that universais are things were called uocales
But thinkerswere troubled by the physical connotations of uox. Both
the writer of C 8 and Abelard try to avoid these problems by
distinguishingcarefullybetween uocesin essence, regarded as physical
things,and uocesregarded as bearers of signification.12Eventually, in
his later long commentaryon the Isagoge,13Abelard decided to solve
the problem by defininganother term, sermones
, to mean words as
institutedby humans to signify,and lettinguocesstand for words as
physical entities. By this terminologyuniversais, are, of course, sermones
, not uoces(522: 10-524:20). Abelard chose sermoratherthan nomen
as his term, partlyperhaps because he wanted to insist on his own,
precise technical definition, and partly because he thought that
- could be uniververbs- which it would sound strangeto call nomina
sais (18:1-2). He was aware, however, that he risked bewilderinghis
readers by the use of a termin a new, technical sense, and so he was
, to gloss it withthe
careful,almost immediatelyafterhe firstuses sermo
4
sermonm
sive nominum
familiarnomen
: Quid enim aliud est nativitas
,
, ex
quam hominum institutio?Hoc enim quod est nomensive sermo
hominum institutionecontrahi (522:17-19). It would be surprising
if, afterhis criticismof uoxtheories,Abelard and those who followed
his views on universaisshould have continued to be called uocales; but
not at all implausible that theyshould have been called, not afterthe
termsermo
, but afterthe more familiar,if less accurate, nomen.
One passage in Boethius's commentaryon the Categories
provides
another reason why the title nominaleswould have been thought
appropriate. In order to explain why it does not followfrom'Socrates
haecdecern
nomina
multis
de
vocavit,
1933):Eg. 112:8-12:'Quod igitur
primasvoces
causisaccipipotest.
Possunt
secunnamqueprimaediciineo quodde eisintenditur
dumprimamnominum
... Est namqueduplexvocum
...;'
impositionem
impositio
116:35-117:3:
'Arbitror
autemhancdisiunctionem
magisconpraedicamentorum
sideratam
secundum
vocum
naturasrerum... Sed
significationem
quamsecundum
secundum
nominum
haecratiovisaest
profecto
significationem
11See Iwakuma1992b.
12C 8: 'Videndum
illamsententiam
unaquodsecundum
quoduoxestinsubstantia,
esseconsiderata
est.... Secundum
quequeuoxsecundum
proprium
primasubstantia
hocueroquoduoxesttantum
inquantitate
nullauoxin proprio
essesuoprimauel
secundasubstantia
est.' VaticanReg. lat. 230,f. 45rb;Abelard(earlierlongcomon Porphyry)
37:40-38:40.
mentary
13Known,from
itsopening
sociorum.
Constant
words,as theLogicanostrorum
petitioni
Mews(1985,77-8)has suggested
a datebetween1120and 1124,butan evenlater
datingis notimpossible.
53

09:07:37 AM

is a man' and 4Man is a species' that 'Socrates is a species', Boethius


explains (176D) that species and genera sunt quodammodonominum
nomina.He probably intends merelyto say that theword'species' and
theword 'genus' are words which describe other words rather than
logicians, such as the writerof C 8
things.14But early twelfth-century
took the passage as supportingthe position that universais are words,
not things.15Abelard takes Boethius's remark in the same way and
extends it, so as to make it support even more clearly his theoryof
universais. In the sophism 'Socrates is a man, 'Man is a species',
'Socrates is a species', it is not merely (as Boethius had noted)
'species' which is not predicated in substance. The middle term,
'man', Abelard adds, changes its meaning fromthe major premise,
where it is the name of a thing,to the minor premise, where it refers
to itself(133:24-31). And Abelard may have used this passage more
prominentlyon another occasion, if credence can be given to a
twelfth-century
gloss on Priscian which attributesto Abelard a work
entitledIncipiuntnominanominum.16
2. Abelardand Albericon universais
One of the earliestreferencesto the nominalistsis John of Salisbury's
remarkthatAlberic was 'a verykeen opponent of the nominalistsect'
(List no. 5). Does this mean that he was an opponent of Abelard and
his followers? Courtenay thinks this conclusion is not proven,
although he does trace an opposition between Abelard and Alberic
over the 'unity of the noun' and over parts and wholes.17From their
, however, it can be shown both that Alberic
exegeses of the Categories
attacked Abelard over the nature of the universais, and that this differencemarksa fundamentaldivision between theirunderstandingsof
the place of language withinlogic.
14As Reiners1910,6-8rightly
explains.
15'Confirmt
... uoces
in eodemcommento
etiamBoethius
[sc.superCathegorias]
nominanominum
essegeneraet species,dicenset generaet species'quodammodo
of thenominalist
sunt",VaticanReg. lat. 230, f. 41v. A 'realistrepresentation
someas
2486
in
Vienna
in
an
found
represents
(P
20)
commentary
Isagoge
theory'
nominum'
are'nominatantum
fivepredicables
thatPorphyry's
by
(discussed
holding
see below,p. 101).
Iwakumain hisarticlein thiscollection:
16Cf. Barrow,Burnett,
to theglossPromisimus
Luscombe1984-85,269 (referring
,
OxfordLaud. lat.67, f. 22r)
17Courtenay
1991a,16, 25-6.
54

09:07:37 AM

Abelard' s long commentary on the Categoriesis well known.


Alberici exegesis of the work can be reconstructedfroma varietyof
sources. In Paris Arsenal 910 (Ar), an importantlogical collection,
thereis a fragmentof a commentaryon the Categories
(C 21: ff. 143rintroduction
and
the
very firstglosses.
144r) which includes only the
By its polished styleand its lack of referencesto a master or masters,
it appears to be a particular master's own exposition of his views.
Since a number of the comments it contains correspond exactly to
what in C 15 and C 17 are recounted as Alberic's views, there is a
strongprobabilitythat this fragmentcomes from a commentaryby
Alberic himself,or is veryclosely related to such a work. Ar contains
another commentary(C 20: ff. 147r-162v) which covers about the
firsthalf of Aristotle's text. It too puts forwardmany of the views
known to be Alberic's, but is less full and less polished than C 21.
Close to the beginning it attributesa view which is very probably
Alberic's to 'the master'.18There seems everyreason to take thiscommentaryas the work of a pupil, based on Alberic's teaching. Then
thereare the two commentariesC 15 and C 17, whichgive an impression of the debates about the Categories which took place on the Mont
Saint Genevive in the 1130s.19 Finally, there is another, very
incompleteCategories commentaryalso in Ar (C 16: ff. 145r-147r),
which consists just of the discussion on most of the chapter on
substance. This commentatorremarksabout a certain view which he
has just mentioned: 'In Alberic's time, this was the opinion of
everyone, which Alberic himselfcondemned, in the followingway'
and he proceeds to give Alberic's argument (f. 145v). From this it is
clear that C 16 was writtensome time afterAlberic lectured on the
Categories, but by someone who thought Alberic's views still
valuable.
The opposition between Abelard and Alberic over the nature of
universais is clearest in their treatmentof the categoryof substance.
Abelard argues thatAristotle'sdivision of substances intoprimaryand
secondary is hard to understand if it is supposed to be a division of
things,ratherthan words. If it is taken as a division of things,Aristotle
will be 'saying that, of the things which are substances, some are
universal, some singular, as if one were to say: of man, that is the
18See n. 24 below.
19See De Rijk 1966,31-9.
55

09:07:37 AM

thing which is man, one is universal, another particular' (141:2-4).


Abelard objects that this statementwould have the unacceptable consequence of making what is universal exactly the same as what is
singular. He admits that Boethius took the division to be one of a
genus into species. But on this view primarysubstance would be a
species of substance, which it cannot be, since everysubstance- 'that
is, every individual of substance'- is primarysubstance. Moreover,
one of the species, secondary substance, would contain universal
substance, which is what is being divided. These difficultiesare
avoided, he concludes, if the division is taken as one of words (in
which case it is of an accident into accidents) (141:16-24).
Alberic's views are very different.He is willing to recognize that
'substance' is a word with many differentmeanings. But the sense in
which 'substance' means 'the name which signifiessubstance' is not,
he says, a significatio
but rathera trans
latio- a metaphoricalratherthan
a literal sense of the term.20The division of substance into primary
and secondary substances is, he claims (citing the authority of
Boethius's commentaryon the De interpretatione
which Abelard mentions but rejects),one of a genus into species. The commentaryprobably writtenby a pupil of Alberic's (C 20) adds a referenceto 'obstinate
people who say thatthe division is of an accident into accidents.' They
say that Aristotle's division means: 'of the words which signify
substance some are discrete in their signification, some nondiscrete...'. This view is emphatically rejected. According to it, the
commentator says, neither primary nor secondary substance is
substance or is contained in any of the Categories.21The commentator
recognizes as a possible argument against seeing the division as one
of genera into species the factthatthisimpliesrealism about universais
'which is regarded as an objection by them.' But the commentator
happily accepts that 'primaryand secondarysubstance are substances
20C 16: 'Accipitur
etiamsubstantia
substantiam.
Sed non
pronominesignificante
estsignificatio,
immotranslado'(f. 145r);C 20: 'Dicituretiam< substantia
> pro
nominesignificante
ut hic: 'omnissubstantia
uideturhoc aliquid
substantiam,
- quodpotiusesttranslatio'
significare'
(f. 150r)
21 'Quidamtarnenobstinati
dicuntearn[sc. hancdiuisionem]
esse accidentis
in
accidentia,et dicunthanc diuisionemtalemesse: 'substantiaalia prima,alia
substantiam
alia estdiscreta
secunda',id estuox significans
, alia est
significations
uel alia estsignificans
substantiam
uthocaliquid,alia ut qualequid ...
indiscreta,
hocnecsubstantia
Sed secundum
necin aliquo
primanecsecundasuntsubstantia,
continentur.'
ParisArsenal910,f. 150r.
predicamento
56

09:07:37 AM

'
and things existing in themselves and calls on the authority of
Boethius's commentaryon Porphyryin his support.22
than merely
Abelard had done more in his reading of the Categories
in
he
advocated
to repeat and reinforcethe position
commentingPorphyry. The approach to significationwhich underlies his view of
universaisaffectsthe veryway in whichhe elucidates Aristotle'sintention in the work. Certainly, Abelard wishes to stay within the main
lines of Boethius's interpretation.He allows that one of the reasons
4
why the categoriesare called firstwords' is that theyare words of the
firstimposition. 'Although "substance" and "quality" are in a certain way the names of words', he remarks,'they are not treated here
in thatsense', but ratheras names forthings(1 12:23-5). Yet, by a few
subtle changes to otherwiseBoethian phrases, Abelard insinuates his
own views. He cites with approval Boethius's statementof Aristotle's
intention- 'to discuss the firstwords signifyingthe firstgenera of
thingsin thattheysignifythings' but he immediatelyadds the gloss:
'that is, to reveal their significationaccording to the natures of the
thingssubjectto them' (111:18-21); and, in the passage which follows,
instead of followingBoethius (161 A) in mentioning the ten genera
referredto by the ten category-words, he prefers to speak of ten
'natures' of all things (111:26). The expression is carefullychosen,
since in Abelard's terms'natures' are not themselvesthings. And, at
the end of the introductorysection, Abelard strikesout more boldly,
withthejudgement that 'this distinctioninto categoriesis based rather
on the meanings of words than the natures of things. For, as regards
the naturesofthings,thereis no reason why Aristotleshould not have
set out fewer or more categories than he did' (1 16:35-117:2). 23
Abelard's view is, then, that whilst a study of the Categories does
reveal somethingabout how thingsare (in this sense it is, as Boethius
said, concerned with words signifyingthings, not words signifying
otherwords), the ten Categories themselvesare not things, and their
organization does not even reflecta fundamental patterningin the
order of things,but merelya featureof how language signifiesthem.
22 si hecestdiuisiogenerisin speciestunc... generaquaedamesseresperse
habeturapud eos ... Ad hec autemomniaque
existentes
quod proinconuenienti
et
substantiam
in primisdicentes
breuemsolutionem,
obiectasuntfacimus
primam
in
Boethius
et resperse existentes,
essesubstantias
secundam
quodetiamtestatur
tractat.'ibid.
et speciebus
de generibus
ubiquestiones
commento
superPorfirium
23The sameviewis putin theearlierofAbelard's
on Porphyry:
longcommentaries
54:32-4.
57

09:07:37 AM

Alberic rejectsthiswhole line of approach. Not only does Abelars


talk about the 'natures' of things(as opposed to theirgenera) vanish;
he also attacks Abelard's fundamental idea that the scheme of ten
some, instead of
categories is based on language. He mentions that
'
first
words' for the
saying that Aristotle's intentionis to discuss the
4
firstgenera of things,say the ten firstwords'. Alberic objects to the
insertionof ten': it is foundnowhere,he says, in Boethius's commentary. And anyway is not the case, he believed, thatthereare ten words
which signifythe ten genera of things.24
Alberic's differenceswith Abelard covered many areas.25 But the
evidence here, along withthat in Part II, makes it most plausible that,
when John of Salisbury described Alberic as an opponent of the
nominalists, he was referringto his attacks on the followers of
Abelard, and that one of the central issues he had in mind was the
nature of universais.
'
3. Abelardand ' Quod semelestuerum
, semperest uerum
is that
One of the positionsmost commonlyattributedto the nominales
in
.26
This
est/erit
uerum
uerum
est
semel
appears
apophthegm
, semper
quod
none of Abelard's survivingworks,but it has been recognized that, in
withoutparallels in the Theologia
a passage of the Theologiascholarium
a similaridea is proposed in connecSummiBoni or TheologiaChristiana
tion withGod's knowledgeofAbelard's birth.27In C 17, however,the
thesis quod semelest uerum
, semperest uerumis explicitlymentioned as
'Master Peter's', by which the commentator doubtless means
Abelard's.28 One of Abelard's argumentsfor this position, the com- dicunt
24C 21: 'Sic igitur
de primisuocibus
estAristotelem
dicendum
disputare
in
hoc
commento,
uocibus';sednusquam
(f. 143r);
reperitur
primis
quidam'de decern
non.Sed
habetur4decern
uocibus',in quibusdam
C 20: 'In quibusdamcommentis
'decern'utsitdoctrina
meliusest,utdicitMagister,
generalior
quodibinonhabetur
et quia etiamnonsuntdecernuocesque decernrerumgenera[rerum]
significant'
(f. 147r).
25See n. 32 below,andcf.De Rijk 1966and Martin1986and 1987.
areaisomaae
tothisdoctrine
26List
oftextsnos.46; 50a,b; 51a;52d;bzd.Keerences
wordsin nos.64a; cf.44a,e; 52e; 64c; 65a.
in different
27TS, 526: 821-837;cf.Normore
1991a,23 (& cf.27).
1987,207 andCourtenay
28(Thepassageisunfortunately
>
mcertain
places). < secundum
corrupt
obviously
> P<etrus> quodsemelestuerum,semperest
dicitM < agister
hancauctoritatem
uerumet semperfuituerum,et sempererituerum,et quod < semel> fuit
< uerum
>, semper erit uerum, semper est
>, semper fuit < uerum
quam
uerum:ut 'Socratessede hoc uerumsemperfuitquia opiniosecundum
hoc uerumest immobilis;
ergoilluduerumsemperest. Set [etiam]
concipitur
58

09:07:37 AM

mentatorsays, concerns the object of faith.Abelard wishes to say that


the prophecy'A virginshall give birth' means thata virginwill (in the
future) give birth and, since this is not (now) the case, what the
prophetsaid was untrue. And so he argues that what the prophetsaid
(the dictum
) is always true and never false,but it is signified(now) not
by the proposition 'a virgin shall give birth' but 'a virgin has given
birth.' But quod semelest uerum
, semperest uerumis also linked to the
of
Aristotle's
passage
Categories
being discussed at thispoint. The relation might seem puzzling, since Aristotle seems to be proposing
exactlytheopposite position- thatthe same statement( oratio
) or belief
{opinio) varies between being true and false depending on the circumstancesin the world ('Socrates is sitting'is true when he is sitting
and becomes falsewhen he stands up).29 It becomes clearer, however,
in the lightof Abelard' s discussion of this passage fromthe Categories
in his Logica ingredientibus
and Dialctica, and in the light of another
thesis which C 15 also attributesto Abelard at this point.
Aristotle has identified the capacity to receive contraries whilst
remainingnumericallyone as distinctiveof substance (4al0). He then
considersthehypotheticalobjection thatstatementsand beliefstoo can
receive contraries,since theyare trueat one time, false at another. He
begins his answer to it by explaining that substances, unlike
statementsand beliefs, receive contrariesby a change in themselves.
<non> semper
eadempropositione,
significatur
quia quandoquesignificatur
prode futuroquando res non
positionede futuro:tunc significatur
propositione
ad<h>uc est,ut antequamSocratesesset,hocuerumsignifcabatur
hac propositione'Socratessedebitin tali instantiin quo modo sede; et, Socratestante,
hac propositione
'Socratessedit'(ms. sedet),et ita idem uerum
signifcabitur
a diuersis
significatur
propositionibus
perdiuersatempora.
Quod etiamprobatper
dietaprofetarum
etsacramenta
hocmodo.Dicitprofeta
'uirgopariet'.Hec propositio
setuirginem
estfalsum;
dixit
significat
uirginem
parituram,
parituram
ergoprofeta
falsum.
Etnehocinconueniens
ideodicendum
estdictum
estuerumet
concedamus,
setnonsignificatur
hacpropositione
falsum,
numquam
'uirgopariet',setista'uirgo
SocratesiurauitPlatonidaturum
in die
nummum
peperi.Similiter
(ms.spniliter)
transacto
diedominico,
hocestfalsum,
iurauit
falsum.
Etne
dominico;
ergoSocrates
hoc inconueniens
sequatur,dicendumest quod hoc- SocratemPlatonidaturum
- estuerum,setnonsignificai
in die dominico
nummum
< ur> hac propositione,
'Socratesdabitnummum
in diedominico'
setista,'Socratesdeditnummum
in die
dominico.'
latfol.624,f.83v).It islikely
thatthepreposition
before
hanc
auc(Berlin
toritatem
at thebeginning
of thepassagewhichthegrammar
requiresis secundum
becausetheprevious
sentence
reads'Oratioetopinioomnino
immobilia
perseueran
toAristotle's
viewthatstatements
andbeliefs
do notthemselves
(a reference
change,
butrather
Forreferences
in C 15 toMasterP. ( = Abelard),cf.De
circumstances).
Rijk1966,33-4.
29
4a20-4bl5;Arist.lat. I, 53:13-54:10.
59

09:07:37 AM

In his commentaryon the Categories


and in the Dialctica.Abelard asks
bothers
Aristotle
to
add
his
explanation, since the objection is
why
obviously inapposite forvarious reasons.30In particular,he explains,
statements and beliefs are excluded by the requirement that what
receives contraries is numerically one. The objection supposes that
'Socrates is sitting'is numericallythe same statementevery time it is
uttered. This is indeed, Abelard admits, a common way of talking,
but not an accurate one.31What he seems to have in mind is a distinction between sentences and the statementstheyare used to make. He
bringsthisout farmore clearlyby anotherpositionwhich is attributed
to him at the same point in C 15 (and also in C 17). According to the
commentator, Master Peter says that 'the verb refersto the instant
before it is spoken.32As the objections the commentator goes on to
rehearse confirm,Abelard was arguing that, if I say, 'Socrates is sitting*, the statementI express is that Socrates is sittingat t, where t
is the moment before I begin to make the remark. By doing this, he
brings out in terms of time the differencebetween sentences and
statements.A temporally-indefinite
sentence such as 'Socrates is sitwill
a
statement
different
ting'
express
every time it is uttered. The
to Abelard just before: that
of
this
is
the
attributed
position
corollary
the same statementwill need to be made, at differentpoints of time,
by differentsentences. And since even sentenceswhich are temporally
indefinitein formexpress statementswhich are temporallydefinedby
referenceto the time of theirutterance,what is once true will be true
always.
The passage from C 15, is then, shows that the nominalist thesis
estuerumwas explicitlyproposed by Abelard
, semper
quodsemelestuerum
30Categories
161:5ff.;Dialctica
, ed. de Rijk,53:11ff.
commentary,
31 quippeoratio
sedenteSocrateet quae profetur
eo stante,nonest
quae profetur
eademnumero... sed magissecundumhominum
acceptionem'
(161:20-24);cf.
Dialctica
on Porphyry,
, ed. cit., 54:14-18;cf. also theearlierlongcommentary
38:11-15.
32'Dicit M < agister
ad illudinstansquod
> P<e trus> quod uerbumrefertur
antecedit
prolationem.'
(Berlinlat.fol.624,f.83v);and', forC 17, De Rijk1966,
error
Petridicentis
sedeestaliaoratio
p. 45: 'Hie confunditur
Magisti
quod Socrates
...' Thesameposition
prolataa Socrateetaliaprolataab eodeminalioinstanti
(not
in C 20, thecommentary
attributed
to anynamedmaster)
is attacked
by
probably
a pupilofAlberic's(ParisArsenal910,f. 153v);andC 17 shareswithC 20 oneof
- thatitwouldmakeitimpossible
themainarguments
to
againstthisthesis
directly
It seemsprobable,then,thatthiswas anotherarea on
contradict
anystatement.
whichAlbericattacked
Abelard.
60

09:07:37 AM

himselfand it also suggeststhat the background to the view lies, not


in theories about the 'unity of the noun', but in speculation about
statements and beliefs in the context of Aristotle's views about
substance and contraries.
Cambridge
TrinityCollege

61

09:07:37 AM

Vivarium
XXX, 1 (1992)
What Must One Have an Opinion About
STEN EBBESEN

In this paper I want to give an impressionof the sort of issues that


interested, united and divided philosophical schools (sectae) in the
second half of the twelfthcentury. Insider- and outsider-testimonies
combine to suggest that membership of a secta was defined by
adherence to a " creed" (professio
) constitutedby a numberoftheorems
(positiones
), virtuallyall connected with the Old Logic. I shall argue
that Nominales formed a school in this sense, named after the
trademarkslogan genusestnomen
, whereas Realesdid not not: any nonnominalist1group could be thus called. I shall produce new evidence
suggestingthat Nominaleswere the spiritual children of master Peter
(Ablard?).
Several outsider sources ascribe certain theses to Nominalists, Porretans etc. In three texts insiders list theorems of their respective
school and then provide a rationale for each item on the list.
2
The biggest of the three is the Compendium
LogicmPorretanum
(henceforwardComp.Porr.)withsome 116 theoremslisted and proved.
The firstperson plural is used in a way that clearly identifiesthe
author's group as followersof Gilbert of Poitiers, and the theorems
confirmthat he representswhat outsiders called Porretani.He occa'
sionallyadmits dissentin the group, sayingthat "some of our people'
have another opinion than the rest.
SectaMeludina(henceforwardS.Mel.) lists 53 theorems. In our sole
copy (Ms London, B.L., Royal 2.D.XXX) the ensuing discussion
3
only covers theorems1-3 and partly4. The author explicitlyidentifies
his sectaas that of Melun. Like his Porretancolleague he admits occasional dissent in the group:
1 I use 'nominalist'
and 'realist'as translations
ofthesources'nominalis,
realis
; no
connotations
to follow
are intended
thetwowordsas usedin thispaper.
modern
2 Ebbesen,Fredborg
& Nielsen,1983.I quotebytheorem
number.
Whenquoting
textsI do notrespect
thisandothermedieval
theorthography
ofeither
manuscripts
butclassicizeall waythrough.
or editors,
3 See De Rijk1967,at 11.1:283-286.
I refer
to thethesesbythenumbers
assigned
to thembyDe Rijk.
62

09:07:50 AM

nondicerenisicontentum
nostrorum
individuum
Consueverunt
tarnen
quidam
est
secundum
loco sub speciespecialissima
quod omneindividuum
proximo
et noneconverso.
(Ms cit.,f.97vB)
primasubstantia
S.Mel, discusses each theoremat lengthwithdigressionson mattersof
similar interest, instead of focussing sharply the reason for the
theoremas does Comp.Porr..
Nominalium(henceforwardPos.Nom.).*
Finally, we have a Positiones
This
nostrae.5
The titleis my invention,inspiredby the incipit:Positiones
work lists some 17 theorems; the subsequent proofs, forno apparent
reason, stop afterN 4. The firstperson plural is used in a way that
but probably indicatesthatthe author speaks
could be pluralismaiestatis
on behalf of a group which he contrastswith that of the realists(Text
60).
Many school theoremsare at firstblush as outrageous as the Stoic
paradoxes ("Only the sage is rich etc."); they were meant to attract
attention.In the competitionforpupils a list of a school's paradoxical
opinions may have had an advertisingfunctionsimilar to that of a
restaurantmenu displayed in the window. The Porretansclaimed that
Omnenomensignificaiduo (Comp.Porr. 1.8)' yet Omnenomenaequivocum
una sui prolatione
unumsolumsignificat
(1.10). The Melun people held
that Nullum nomenest aequivocum(S.Mel. 13);6 and Nulla species
praedicatur
(S.Mel. 8). The nominalists insisted that nothing grows
(Texts 26, 37, 40b, 53), and Pos.Nom. enhances the provocation by
loudly advertisingthat "we" hold that opinion in the teethof no less
an authoritythan Aristotle.The paradoxical nature of school theses
is expresslymentioned in Text 26 (they are inopinabiliato outsiders;
cf. Text 37), and anothercontemporarynoticesthe surprisingfactthat
obviously false propositions have reputable thinkers for their proponents:
falsaquae tamennondicuntur
multasuntmanifeste
inopinabilia,
quia a viris
< thusMeludinenses
suntposita,utnullum
nomenesseaequivocum
authenticis
,
cf.above>, nomenessegenus<thus Nominales
>?
What, then, must one have an opinion about? First and foremost,
controversial points relating to Logica Vetus. Some texts attribute
4 Editedin Ebbesen1991.Editio
in Pelster1944-46,rp.Amsterdam
1971.
princeps
5 References
ofthetype"Text8", "Text60" etc.aretothelistoftextspublished
in thisissueof Vivarium.
byY. Iwakumaand myself
6 Cf. theextracts
from
ArsMeliduna
in De Rijk1967II. 1, 297.
7 S. Ebbesen,Anonymi
Aurelianensis
I Commentarium
in Sophisticos
Elenchos
, in:
CIMAGL 34 (1979),68.
63

09:07:50 AM

overtlytheological propositionsto certain schools, but none occur in


the listsproduced by insiders, not even in S.Mel, whose author claims
to deal exhaustivelywith the tenets of his school.:
dicta
Meludinaeprofessionis
quae ratiodisserendi
(quamea parsphilosophiae
consummatur
inhuiusoperisvolumine
etintegra
estsibiducemelegit)perfecta
(Ms London,B.L., Royal2.D.XXX, f.95rA).
cognitio
Admittedly, the parenthesis may not have been so parenthetically
meant; if it wasn't, the author only claims that his treatiseprovides
fullinformationabout the sect's dialectics,not about all of its doctrine;
but Jacques de Vitry's story about the bishop who had been a
nominalist when teaching the arts (Text 53) supports the notion that
the school-definingtenets all belonged to logic.
I shall now treatof some selected theorems,firstsome with a clear
, inclusive of Boethius' logical
background in the exegesis of Ars Vetus
opuscula, then some which could be suspected of having no such connection; I will tryto find one even in their case.
Such are the many that conlinkedto Isagogeor Categories.
(I) Theorems
cern universais and singulars,equivocity,categories,and predication.
In several instances one school's thesis was obviously formed as an
answer to another's (though we cannot always tell which came first).
de aliThe very firsttheoremof S.Mel, is Nullumsingulare
praedicatur
quo and we are told that there is a good reason to startthus:
estnullumsingulare
de aliquo.De quo
veroprimm
praedicari
Propositorum
dissensio
maximasoletfieri
ad utramque
contradica controversantibus
partem
de singulari
rationibus.
sentiat
nostrae
inductis
tionsmultis
Quidigitur
professionisopinioprimoestpertranseundum.
(mscit.95vA)
There was indeed disagreementon the point. The Porretansheld that
In omni propositionein qua aliquid praedicatur,praedicatursingulare
(Comp.Porr. 2.8). But if Porretans and Melun people sometimesheld
opposing opinions, they also shared some. S.Mel, asks utrumomne
eteconverso
sit individuum
(ms cit., f. 97vB), and we are told of
singulare
a minor disagreement in the sect, but also that they agree that omne
estsingulareet noneconverso
individuum
(e.g. "this animal" is a singular
but no individual), which is identical to Comp.Porr, theorem 3.28.
Similarly, S.Mel. 53 is partially identical with Comp.Porr. 2.3.
The question about singulars and individuals arises naturallyfrom
a discussion of Porphyry's universais. As with other mereological
problems, its relevance to Trinitarian and C histological discussions
(cf. Text 10) indubitably contributedto the interestit attracted,but
64

09:07:50 AM

'
'
as the conceptsof "par and ' 'whole' were routinelyused in a great
variety of philosophical contexts one should not overstress the
theologicalbackground. There were lots of reasons to talk about such
mattersin dialectic class.
Of all questions relating to the Old Logic the most famous is and
was "What sortof entitiesare universais?" Godfreyof St Victor (Text
18) uses the differentviews about what a genus is to distinguish
between realists and nominalists,and also makes special mention of
the collectivistaspect of Porretan lore on what a genus is.
I know of no self-styledrealis, and the theses attributedto realesby
othersmake it clear, I think,(a) thatit is a collectivetermdesignating
all non-nominalists,and (b) that the distinctionbetween realists and
nominalistsis primarilyused in connectionwith the subject of universais and the significatesof general termsand propositions. Only four
basic theses are attributedto realists, viz.:
Realistthesis/7/. A genus is a thing(genusestres), and not a name
of some sort. (Text 43. In Text 18 [1] is stated indirectlyby contrastingthe excusable errors committed by realists with the inexcusable madness of those who believe that a genus is a name.)
The case of the genus is clearly meant to be paradigmatic for
universais(cf. Text 5), and withthesis[1] come the corollaries "What
is signifiedby a common noun like 'man' is a universal not a status"
(Text 13), "In predication a thing is predicated of a thing" (Text
22a), "An individual is not a predicable because it does not signifya
natural thing" (Text 48d), and "There is somethingbesides the particular" (Text 60).
Realist thesis[2]. The truths signified by true (and, of course,
tensed) propositions,and objects of belief, knowledge and power are
not tenseless.8(Not stated in exactly these terms; see Texts 29, 44a,
52d; cf. 70).
8 I hereassumethatthenominalist
viewrejected
theobjects
construed
bytherealists
ofbelief,
andpoweralikeas dicta.CalvinNormore
has pointed
outthat
knowledge
4
thismight
notbe trueandthattheirreasonforacceptingQuicquid
deuspotuit
potes
*
be altogether
different
from
theirreasonforaccepting
deusscivit
sci
might
Quicquid
andforclaiming
thatthepatriarchs
offaith
believed
inthesamearticles
as Christians.
thatnominalists
heldthatGod can whatever
he could
However,theinformation
whereas
realists
wereuncertain
aboutthematter,
occursas a noteonPeterLombard,
Sentences
I d.44c.2,andis meanttoinform
us thattheviewPeterdefends
thereis that
ofthenominalists;
butwhatPeteractually
saysis thatjustas God alwayswillsand
knows
whatever
He willedorknewatsometime,so He alwayscanwhatever
He could
at sometime.Lestanydoubtshouldlingeraboutwhatsortofthings
be submay
' Peterillustrates
sumedunder'quicquid
hispoints
withthethreepairsofpropositions,
65

09:07:50 AM

Realistthesis[3]. Nothing followsfromthe impossible (Text 59).


Realistthesis[4]. Something grows (Text 70).
Notice that all four theses are just the common-sense answers to
startlingnominalistclaims. They owe theirexplicitformulationto the
nominalist theses which they deny.
At least one man presentshimselfas a nominalist(the Anonymous
of Text 22b), and two more seem to do so (Godfrey of Poitiers and
Peter of Capua, but Godfrey's case hangs on a sim in Text 48c which
may, for all I know, be a private reading of one manuscript; and in
Peter's case we are in a disputational contextin which a firstperson
need, perhaps, not referto the master or his sect).
This is a satisfactory overlap between what the self-styled
nominalist(s) consider(s) nominalistdoctrine, what the anti-realistof
Pos.Nom. presentsas 'our theorems', and what outsiders attributeto
"
nominalists. A well-attestedtheorem is Universals, such as genera
and species are nouns/names" ( nomina
; see
, but in Text 4 vocabula
Texts 4, 44c, 60) withvariants,such as "Some names are universais"
(Text 5), and the handygenusestnomen(Text 18 [wherenominalistsare
contrastedwith realists and the latter exempted fromthis madness];
nisi
40a, 44d [whereit is added thatperhocnomen"genus" nonsupponitur
"There
is
the
come
corollaries
central
thesis
With
the
nothing
vox].)
besides the particular" (Text 60), and "In predication a term is
"
predicated of a term, not a thing of a thing (Text 22a), as well as
"What is signifiedby a common noun is a specificor generic status"
(Text 13).
Apparentlytherewas less diversityamong nominaliststhan among
realists on the question of universais. Perhaps not so strange if we
think of how the question was conceived by, e.g. the author of Ars
Meludina:
estquodest
universale
dfinit:
inlibroPerihermeneias
sicAristoteles
Universale
de
i.e. praedicabile
de pluribus,
natumpraedicari
aptumnatumpraedicari
sit
res
an
terminus
utrum
sc.
illud
Sed
sit,
contingit
quid
praedicabile
pluribus.
aliiresi.e. teressepraedicabilia,
solosterminos
dubitare.
Quidamenimponunt
minorum
Bodleian,Digby174,f.218vB)
significata.
(Ms Oxford,
That is, the question is conceived in the form"is it common terms
or things signifiedby such terms that are universal?" The common
'Deusscivit
1Deus
V'Deusseitse
se resurrecturum
Deuspotest
resurrexisse',
resurgere
potuit
'/'
resurrexisse
and tellsus thattheyare
Deus
vult
and 'Deusvoluit
resurrexisse7
resurgere
on thesamePeterLombard
commentator
parallel.Cf. also theanonymous
strictly
passagein Text50a-b.
66

09:07:50 AM

termsare taken forgiven, the universais are sought. The realist who
identifiesuniversaiswithsignificatesought to tellus what sortof thing
he thinkscommon termssignify.The nominalistdoes not have to do
that to answer the question about universais since he identifiesthem
with what was given. This opens the possibilitythat the 'nominalist'
label was applicable to people with very differentviews on, e.g., the
significationof general terms, but just sharing the creed that only
words are universais. The lone source thatsays theythoughtcommon
nouns signifystatus(Text 13) could be thinkingof a typicalnominalist
view ratherthan the only one.
9
'
'
'
Nevertheless,I doubt that nominalesresembled reales in being a
blankettermforseveral groups withno institutionaland fewdoctrinal
bonds to join them. As we have seen, at least one man identifies
are often
himselfas a nominalis.Second, and most important,nominales
not just contrastedwith realists but treated as parallel to, and conand Adamitae(Texts 11,
trastedto, such groups as Montani,Porretani
a
can
of
and
47, 53),
they
exemplify group people with special tenets
or Adamitae(Text 21). Third, the
(Text 37) just as can Meludinenses
nominalistsare said to have held several theses with no obvious connection to the question whetheruniversalityis a propertyof words or
of things(see, e.g., Text 48a); and at least one theoryof considerable
complexity is ascribed to them, namely the one which by
distinguishingbetween a person and the substance/essencewhich is
that person (Texts 33a, 40b), allows the substance to cease to exist
withoutendangeringthe person. The "Nothing grows" thesispresupposes the distinction (persons grow, substances do not, they are
destroyedand yield their place to new ones if someting is added to
them; cf. below). Such a complex theorywas scarcely the common
propertyof several schools with otherwise differentviews. Finally,
Godfreyof St Victor (Text 18) expresslyoperates with severedschools
of realists without subdividing nominalists. This fits well with the
testimonyofJacques de Vitrywho identifiestwo groups of people first
as nominalistsand Adamites, then refersto them as nominalistsand
realists(Text 53); apparently, ' realists' in his generic name forthose
whose specificname is 'Adamites', whereas nominalists cannot be
divided into species.
The Adamites were considered realists, and so were the Melunpeople. Both rose to the nominalistchallenge, but theydid not present
a united front. The Adamites accepted the proposition Hoc genus
"ammalia" estgenushuic speciei "homo" (Text 21, cf. 55-56); S. Mel.
67

09:07:50 AM

denies it in theorem39, Nullumnomen


universale
pluralisnumeri
significai
vel singulare
; - though the author of Ars Meliduna(ms. cit., 221vB) is
less strict,holding that both the nominative plural and the oblique
formssignifythe same universal as the nominative singular.
or Boethianopuscula. Several
(II). Theoremslinkedto Peri hermeneias
theoremsmay derive fromthe study of Perihermeneias
, and this is the
obvious background forS.Mel. 40 about the requirementsa proposition must fulfilif somethingis to be predicated of something.De differenti topicisclearly lies behind theoremsconcerning inferencesand
the notions of argumentatio
and argumentum
{S.Mel. 22, 23, 26, 43;
Comp.Porr. 2.17, 2.19, 2.20, 3.40, 3.41). Many theorems in
Comp.Porr, derive from Gilbert of Poitiers' commentaries on the
OpusculaSacra, but also belong in purely logical contexts.
aboutmolecular
are many, but often dif(III). Theorems
propositions
ficultto link to the exegesis of some particulartext,as both the Organon
and several Boethian opusculahave contributedto the developmentof
this branch of logic, which attractedso much attentionin the twelfth
centurythatGodfreyof St. Victor saw fitto characterizethe followers
of Alberic with a crypticremark that probably alludes to their views
about the proposition 'Socrates is well or ill* or 'if Socrates is well,
Socrates is not ill'. An Albrican is one
cuiusSortesaegersit,sed nonmanetsanus.
Sed quia velociter
transit
homovanus
etiamdummoritur
maneatinsanus.(Text18)
According to Text 25b the Albricans thoughtthat the inference'X is
a man, thereforeX is a man or an ass' is invalid. The Porretans
disagreed: Omnis disiunctaest vera cuius altera pars tantumest vera
{Comp.Porr.2.27); i.e. theywould not proscribepropositionswithdisjoined predicates which are such that no subject that at any time
satisfiesone of the predicatescan ever satisfytheother. The same matter is debated in Introductiones
Montanae Maiores (henceforward
I. Mont.Mai. ; ms Paris B.N. lat. 15141, about ff.65v-67r),9 and one
of the standard examples is Socratesestaegervelsanus, which ought to
be acceptable even to those who do not allow just any pair of disjoined
predicates. I. Mont.Mai. accepts such propositions because 'ill' and
'weir may apply in turn to a given subject (they permutantur)
. This
9 ApartfromthemsI havehadaccessto a partial
byProf.E.P. Bos,
transcription
whomI wouldliketo thank.
68

09:07:50 AM

mightbe the sort of view Godfreyalludes to, and he may also have
in mind a thoughtexpressedin I. Mont.Mai. to the effectthat 'Socrates
is ill or weir is no categoricalproposition: it performsno predication
but indicatesthateither'ill' or "well" is a predicate of Socrates. I.e.,
in the propositionin which illness is actually predicated of him (. est
aeger)no trace remains of his potential health ( sed non manetsanus).
Thus we may have an interpretationof Godfrey's firstline, the sequel
however remains undeciphered.
Alternatively,Godfreycould be alluding to the debate about locus
ab immediatis.It appears from Introductiones
Montanae Minores
("I. Mont.Min. '^10 and I. Mont.Mai, ms cit. f. 77rB-vA, that the
,
group to which these authors belong accept Si Socratesnon est aeger
Socratesestsanus and reject the claim that this legitimatesthe proof
(1) Si nulla res est, nullus asinus est
(2) si nullus asinus est, nullus asinus est sanus
(3) si nullus asinus est sanus, omnis asinus est aeger
(4) si omnis asinus est aeger, omnis asinus est
(5) si omnis asinus est, quaedam res est
(6) ergo si nulla res est, quaedam res est.
I. Mont.Mai. accepts (2) but rejects(3); the consequence, he says, holds
is asserted (i.e. if thereis an existentialpresupposionly ifa constantia
thus:
si
nullus
asinusestsanus, cumsitanimal,omnisasinusestaeger.
tion),
Perhaps, then, we should emend Godfrey and read Cuius Sortesaeger
sit, si nonmanetsanus, and take the followingverses as a referenceto
a claim that Si Socratesnonest,Socratesnonestsanus is true. We could
then paraphrase Godfrey's satire thus:
TheAlbrican's
Socrates
Yet,
maybe ill,butthenhehasshedhishealth/sanity.
heloosestheproperty
ofbeingillbydying,
thishappensso fastthathe
though
has no timeto exchange
it forhealth/sanity:
in deathhe can stayin-sane.
Or, perhaps the Albrican claim was that while health and illness cannot be propertiesof the same subject, illness and death (in the sense
of dying) can; hence, paradoxically, the minor calamity, illness,
destroyshealth, whereas the major calamity, death, does not destroy
the propertythat succeeded health. This interpretationwas suggested
to me by an anonymous commentatoron the Categories
:
Soletquaeride morte
etvitautrum
sintprivatio
ethabitus,
sedquandofittalis
an quaeratde illamorte
unde
quaestiodebemus
ipsumquaerentem
interrogare
10Ed. De Rijk1967II. 2, 67.
69

09:07:50 AM

an de illaundedicitur
mortuum."
dicitur
moriens
(Ms Paris,BN, lat. 17813,
f. 50rA)
Or, finally,the Albrican view may have been that the Socrates who
was healthyis in some sense replaced withanother one on the advent
of disease, while the passage frombeingjust ill to dyingdoes not affect
his self-identity.Anyhow, whatever the thesis really was, it surely
belongs in a debate which drew at least part of its original inspiration
The example of
from chapters 10-11 (on opposites) of the Categories.
the sick and healthy Socrates sufficesto show that much.
The same chaptersmakes a commentatorwithnominalistleanings,
Anonymus D'Orvillensis,11 introduce the "Nothing grows" thesis.
Firsthe relatesan argumentpurportingto show thatwithhis view that
variaiessenomnisdemptio
partisetomnisadditioetomnispartiumtranspositio
tiam totiushe cannot make sense of the proposition sanumpotestesse
, for what is ill cannot cease to be so withoutloss, acquisition
aegrum
or transpositionof some part; so, if it ceases to be ill it ceases to be,
and consequently it cannot be well. To this he answers that quicquid
sanum <and thus cannot be ill>, etquicquidest
estsanumestnaturaliter
idemhomoqui estsanuspotestesseaeger.The
, tarnen
aegrum
aegrumnaturaliter
answer exploits the essence/person distinction.12 The man's
' 'essence' ' ceases to be when
parts are added, lost or rearranged,but
the person, "this man", persists.
ch. 15, the same author spends much
In his commentson Categories
deminutio
time on generatio,corruptio,argumentation
, and ends by
tamenquod
Concedimus
nominalism
from
standard
by saying
deviating
than
is
more
the
deviation
crescit.
real, for
However,
apparent
aliquid
the
fewer
essentia
with
he denies the identitybetween the thing(
parts
)
and its successor. The smallerthingceases to be, the biggercomes into
being out of its predecessor plus some additional parts. 'Grows'
describes the genesis of the successor thing, its predecessor does not
grow.
11See Ebbesen1991,at 438ff.
12Cf. Ms Oxford,
in my
Bodl.L., D'Orville207,f.3rA,on Cat.ch. 2 (notprinted
1991paper):Itemnobis,quidicimus
quodmodositsialiqua
quodnihileritSocrates
nihilest
estinhochomine,
sicobicitur:
"Risibilitas
velsubtrahatur,
parsei addatur
eraserit,ergoin nulloeritin
hiehomoquoderaserithiehomo,et haecrisibilitas
utin subiecto."Ad hocdicipotest
quodhaec
quo modosit,ergononestin homine
licet
sedin persona,
hominis
nonin essentia
estin homineutin subiecto,
risibilitas
etaliudessentiae.
tamenaliquidconvenit
idemsitpersonaquodessentia,
personae
nonhaec
confuse
estin homineut in subiecto,
Vel dicaturmeliusquod risibilitas
sedquaedam,et erasquaedameritin hochomineut in subiecto.
risibilitas,
70

09:07:50 AM

Theorems 3.9-12 of Comp.Porr,all concern wholes


(IV) Mereology.
and parts. 3.12 (cf. Text 11) mentionsan inter-schooldebate concern, but also that most schools agreed that a collective
ing totacontigua
whole is several things(plura); the Melun school appears to have been
the exception, for S.Mel. 31 says Nullus populusest plura. The two
schools agreed that no part of an integralwhole is a differentthing
fromthe whole {Comp.Porr.3.11, S.Mel. 20), but Comp.Porr.3.10 adds
that every whole is a differentthing fromits part.
If these mereologicaldebates have an origin in the exegesis of auctores
topicisand
, Boethius' section on locus a totoin De differentiis
Categoriesch. 6 (on quantity) might be the places. Anonymus
D'Orvillensis on Cat. 6 says:
estsubqua invenitur(?)
omnisresquamcitoipsa
Itemaliquaspeciesquantitatis
ut numerus.
est,et nullatalisestqualitatis,
Quam citoenimaliquidest,est
sub hac forma
unumvel plurasecundum
quod dicitBoethiusin commento
vocis:4'Quamcitoaliquaresest,estunumvelplures".Quidamab hisverbis
estplures
eliciebant:
talemsensum
"Quam citoresest,estunum,ut simplex;
etitaaliquidestpluresres,etsicaliquidestsuaepartes.Nos
res,utcomposita",
unumsolumhabet
sic dicimus:"Aliqua resestunum,i.e. aliquisterminus
ut
uthocnomen'Socrates';aliquisterminus
plurahabetappellata,
appellatum,
Bodleian,D'Orville207,f. 7rA)
'populus'.(Ms Oxford,
Comp.Porr,theorems3.20-23 are about the "successive congregative"
whole called time. We learn that each concretethinghas its own time
{mora),which is concomitant with its formin the same way that its
truthand unity are. A thing's temporal location is the collection of
other moraeco-existingwith its own. The moradoes not count as an
item of the ontology since it just adiacet(like the relation of being to
the right),whereas real forms44are in" theirsubject. This account of
time is a tidierversion of thoughtsfound in Gilbert of Poitiers, who
also sketchedhow an analogue of this time-theorycould be applied to
in a late 12th-centurySentences
divine eternity;13
commentarywe find
an epigrammaticformulationof his thoughts:
esse
aeternitatem
dicentium
Hie breviter
estquorundam
opinioannotanda
Patr.136:
dieshominis
moramquae adiacetdeo. (SummaBreves
, msBamberg,
3vA)
Quite elegant. The Porretan principle that the structuresof natural
language must be preservedin theological discourse is respected; and
no inconveniententityis introducedsince eternityjust adiacet.Notice,
13De frinitale,
onBoethius
1.4.82,in NikolausM. Hring,TheCommentaries
byGilbert
, StudiesandTexts13,Toronto1966,at 131f.
ofPoitiers
71

09:07:50 AM

however, that in Comp.Porr,there is no mention of eternity,only of


time.
Boethius' theological opuscula played an undeniable role in the
development of Porretan time theory,but thereare other sources too.
Comp.Porr,theorems3.20-23 all show a concern about the unity and
multiplicityof time, and so do S.Mel. 4 and 45. The same concern
sitan plurain ms.
found expression in a question An unumsolumtempus
Wien NB lat. 2459 ff. 104vA-105rA,14and underlies the Albrican
sunt(Text 24), and this establishes a link to
thesis that Omniatempora
ch. 6. I quote two anonymous commentators:
the exegesis of Categories
Ms BerlinStaatsbibl.
2 624,f.84vA-B:Quidamdicuntquodnullumtempus
northepresent
est [... Neither
thepast northefuture
is, theyargue
] Dicit
etfuturum
suntpartes
quodpraeteritum
tempus
magister
A(lbericus)
principales
ex quibuspraesenstempusconstat;ut Augustus
estpars
temporis
praesentis
succedit
in anno,sicpraeteritum
et futurum
anni,id estparticulariter
tempus
non tarnensuntsi tantum
succeduntin praesentitempore,
particulariter
ex hisquae nonsunt,quia ex praeterito
est,quodconstituitur
praesens
tempus
Si verodicatur
nonexistit
etfuturo.
"Nonexistente
totum",hoc
parteprincipali
existentiam
de illistotisquaehabent
moram
estintelligendum
secundum(?)
paruttempus
etvox
successionem,
tium,et nonde hisquae existunt
perpartium
et cursus.Potesttarnenprobaripraeteritum
tempusesse, quia praeteritum
[est]
tempusest id secundumquod aliquiddiciturprius,ergopraeteritum
> tempus
estidsecundum
est;< futurum
quodaliquiddicitur
posterius,
tempus
'Omnepraeteritum
est.[...] Si autemopponatur
tempus
tempus
ergofuturum
nonsequitur,
esta carnibus',
est,ergoabstinendum
est,ergoquadragesima
quia
nonquicquidestnuncest.
Ms Padova,Bibi.Univ. 2087,f.28rA:Vidimusquid sittempusperdefiniexquibuspartibus
Hicdiversae
suntsententiae;
nuncvideamus
constet.
tionem,
et futuriet
Quidam enim dicuntquod tempusnon est totumpraeteriti
inqua sententia
suntsibilatores.
Aliidicuntquodtempus
esttotum
praesentis,
in qua sententia
fuitAristoteles
et Boethius,
et
et futuri
temporis,
praeteriti
sie opponitur:
"Praeteritum
etiamest Alb(ericus)[...]. Nostraesententiae
sedpraeteritum
nonest,ettempusest,ergo
tempus
tempusestparstemporis,
Simili
aliquidquodnonest <est> parseiusquodest". Fallosimilietratione.
inaestate,sedrosanonest,ergoaliquidquodnonest
sic:rosaestherbaflorens
4est' dissimiliter
in aestate.Rationesic, quia hic terminus
est herbaflorens
'<
id est
dicitur
>
est
cum
praeteritumtempus parstemporis*
quia
aeeipitur,
fuisse
cumcontingit
"conti<n>git praeteritum
tempus
ipsum
partem
temporis
fuisse",sedcumdico'praeteritum
tempusnonest' id est"non existit",ideo
nonsequitur.
S. Mel. 19 states that Nullius hominispars estanima and the same thesis
is defended in Ars Meliduna. 15It is the resultof a debate anchored in
would
. Arborporphyriana
commentarieson Porphyry'schapterDe specie
14EditionbyY. Iwakumain preparation.
15Ms Oxford,
inDe Rijk,1967II.l, 315.
Extracts
Bodl.L., Digby174,f. 223rB-vB.
72

09:07:50 AM

seem to make rationalitya propertyof bodies (man is a rational corporeal substance, i.e. a rational body). But doesn't rationalitybelong
to the soul ratherthan to the body? Are body and soul parts of man?
And if so, can the whole man and one of his parts share a predicate
withoutsharingit with the other? Two twelfth-century
commentaries
on theIsagogereportmasterP(eter),s views on thismatter.16According
to theone in ms Wien, ONB, lat. 2486, he held thatproperlyspeaking
'man' is a name of the body only, and this is also the sense when we
say thatman is rational, forthatjust means thathe is a body animated
by a rational soul. Then it is objected that on Peter's view man is a
thingthat neitherunderstandsnor discerns nor sees nor uses reason,
since man is a body, and by Peter's own avowal all these activities
necdiscerbelong to the soul alone: sedquodhomositresquae nequeintelligit
nitnecvidetnecrationeutitur,ille <i.e. Petrus> concedit
necpro inconvenientihabet.Which is exactly the paradoxical thesis that Text 26
ascribes to the nominalists!
The nominalistview was not shared by the author of Comp.Porr.His
theorem 3.5 is Solus spiritusest rationalis,and he explains that some
aberrant members of his school accept 3.6, Omnishomoest corpuset
, because in normal usage both bodily and spiritualpredicates
spiritus
are said of the whole man ('Socrates is white' 'Socrates is rational').
Himself,he rejects3.6, forstrictlyspeaking spiritualpropertiesbelong
to the spiritonly, corporal ones to the body only, and properlyspeaking Socrates in his soul ratherthan his body. The author wants us to
believe that he is in accord with Gilbert, but it more looks as if the
' 4aberrant"
group was so.17
(V) Enunciables.Several theorems in S.Mel. (15, 37f.) and Comp.Porr.
(2.10, 4.2-16) deal withenunciables (enuntiabilia!
dicta).This is a typical
12th-centurysubject of interest.The nominalist view that truthsare
sempiternal is of theological relevance, but it may have been formulated in the exegesis of Categories
5, 4a34ff.,where Aristotleclaims
thatpropositionsand opinions may change truthvalue. The commentatorin ms. Padova, B. Univ. 2087 says that master Peter denied the
identityof 'Socrates is sitting' uttered at tj with 'Socrates is sitting'
utteredat t2, on the ground that theydo not signifythe same, forthe
tense of verb makes a location in absolute time, viz. the moment of
16See De Rijk1966,at 24-29.
See Gilbert,
De Trinitate
1.2.73-85,ed Hring,94-97.
73

09:07:50 AM

utterance, part of the proposition's meaning.18There is but a short


tensed propositionswhich are
step fromthisto holding thatdifferently
true respectivelybefore, during and aftersome event signifyone and
the same dictum/truth.
And, in fact,commentingon the same passage
of the Categories
, the anonymous of ms. Berlin, Staatsbibl. 2 624,
f.83vA says:
"oratioetopinioimmobilia
< Propter
> hancauctoritatem
dicit
persvrant".
M(agister)P(etrus):Quod semelestverum,semperestverumet semperfuit
verumet sempereritverum;et quod fuit<verum>, sempereritverum,
semperest verum,ut Socratemsedere,hoc verumsemperfuit,quia opinio
secundum
hocverumestimmobilis,
quamconcipitur
ergoilludverumsemper
est. Sed non [non:etiamcod.] sempersignificatur
eadempropositione,
quia
de futuro;
tuncsignificatur
de
quandoquesignificatur
propositione
propositione
futuro
quandores non acihucest,ut antequam Socratesesset,hoc verum
hac propositione
'Socratessedebitin taliinstanti'
in quo modo
significabatur
hac propositione
'Socratessede et ita
sedet;et Socratestantesignificabitur
idemverumsignificatur
a diversis
propositionibus
perdiversatempora.
Quod
etiamprobatperdictaprophetarum
et sacramenta,
hocmodo:Dicitpropheta
sed virginem
"Virgopariet",haecpropositio
significat
virginem
parituram,
estfalsum,
dixitfalsum.
Et ne hocinconveniens
conparituram
ergopropheta
estdictumesse[esta.c.] verumetnumquam
cedamus,ideodicendum
falsum,
sed <nunc> non significatur
hac propositione
'virgopariet'sed ista'virgo
peperi.
occasionedby theSophisticiElenchi?Some Melun people
(VI) Theorems
held that Nulla quinqusuntduo et trianecduo et triasuntquinqu{S. Mel.
4
28; also Text 16a). The sophism Five are two and three' derives from
Aristotle'sSophistici
Elenchi4, 166a33, and we may wonder, as did one
did not join Aristotlein
12th-centuryscholar,19why the Meludinenses
saying that thereis a fallacyof composition and division (i.e., that in
one sense we are dealing with one proposition with a compound
predicate, viz. 'five are two-and-three', in another sense with a conjunction of propositions, viz. 'five are two, and five are three').
The theorem is discussed in Ars Meliduna,20and according to
Fallaciae Melidunaeit fell under a more general Melun theorem, viz.
Nulla coniuncta
estveranisi verasit disiuncta
, necdisiunctanisi verasit coniuncta(Text 16a). The firstpart of thisrule seems to statethata proposition depraedicato
copulatoshould always be treatedas a conjunctionof
18Ms. cit.,20rB:cumprofero
inhocinstanti
significat
ipsumsedereinhocinstanti,
et cumprofero
in alio instanti
eumsederein alio instanti,
significat
ergosignificat
aliud,ergononesteadem.Morecontext
quotedbyDe Rijk1966,45.
19See Ebbesen& Iwakuma1991,47-112,
at 83.
20See De Rijk 1967II. 1, 334f.
74

09:07:50 AM

propositions.This is strangeenough, but when the second part of the


rule is added, the effectis even stranger,since disjunctivepropositions
turnout to be equivalent to conjunctiveones. One mightthinkthe formulation is just sloppy and that the rule about disjunction should be
understoodto mean 'no disjunctivepropositionis true unless eitherof
its parts could be true' so that the purpose was to avoid declaring
Socrates is a man or a
pearl' a true proposition and yet be able to
sunt
rationaliavel irrationalia
Omnia
animalia
(= S.Mel. 27). But
accept
FallaciaeMelidunae'srule about dis- and conjunctionlooks suspiciously
like the same source's rule about conditionals viz. Nulla hypothetica
'e ex quitus constatsint verae.
<i.e. conditional> est veranisi categorico
amount
to
two
rules
the
saying that no molecular proposiTogether
tion is true unless all its constituentpropositionsare so. Now, a wellknown Melun thesis is Ex falso nihilsequitur(Texts 18, 21, 38; S.Mel.
11). If you add what a later age expressed by saying Ex falso nonnisi
falsum,you have the formulationEx falso nonsequiturverumnecex vero
falsumwhich Text 23 ascribes to the Melun people, and which is for
all practical purposes equivalent to the thesis that no conditional is
true unless its constituentcategoricals are so. It looks as if a rule that
was invented to deal with conditionals was extended to conjunction
and disjunction and thus was overstretched.
The proposition'Five is two and three' comes fromthe Elenchi, but
we can now see that the Melun theorem belongs in a debate about
molecular propositions that moves within a universe of problems
establishedbeforemen startedto studythe Elenchi.All that book contributedwas an example.
S.Mel. 24, Omniselenchus
estnecessarius
may depend more
sophisticus
importantlyon studyof the Elenchi, but its ultimateorigin could conceivably be exegesis of a Boethian passage, such as the end of De differentiis
topicisI.
The best candidate for an origin in Elenchiexegesis in Pos.Nom. 6,
"Being is predicated univocally of all things", because it is accompanied by a referenceto Zeno that presupposes acquaintance with
Elenchich. 10, though the thesis itselfdoes not: the standard
Sophistici
doctrinewhich it rejects, viz. that 'being' is not univocally related to
all things,was available fromPorphyry'sIsagoge.
or Topics? Not a single school theoremseems
(VII) Aristotle's
Analytics
to presuppose acquaintance with Topicsor PriorAnalytics
, though the
author of Comp.Porr,had some familiaritywith both. Similarly,with
one possible exception (see later), there is no trace of influencefrom
75

09:07:50 AM

the Posterior
Analytics,
though several masters fromthe later 12th century must have studied that work even if they did not teach it.21
(VIII) Grammar.A few grammatical propositionsoccur in our corpus
of theses. There are four in Pos.Nom., all criticadof Priscian, viz.
(11) Syllaba potest habere infinitatempora in metro.
(12) Interiectiosub adverbio collocanda est.
(13) Priscianus est insufficiens,quia species troporumnon erudivit.
(14) Nulla constructioest vitiosa.
Of these at least N 11 may have its origin not in the exegesis of Prician but of Categories
ch. 6, where Anonymus D'Orvillensis says:
Nos dicimusquod productioet correptio
vocis sed
non suntquantitates
essetquantitasvocis,ergo si
qualitates.Si enim productiovel correptio
minueretur
vocisminueretur
est
quantitas
ipsavox,sedeademvocaliscorrepta
et tarnen
nondecrescit.22
et producta,
Two theorems in Comp.Porr, apparently undercut the grammatical
distinctionbetween noun and verb, between participleand noun, and
between the active and the passive voice: 1.5 Eadem dictioestnomenet
verbum
, 1.21 Omneactivumetsuumpassivumidemsignificant
quomodoetiam
et
suum
nomen
verbale
but
are
,
appearances
participium
deceptive. The
for
those
theses show they were not meant to change
proofs offered
grammar.
An anonymous grammarian makes the Porretans hold that Nomen
in appositonulliusestpersonae(Text 25d). But he makes it clear that this
thesis, though genuinely grammatical, is a by-productof the sect's
views on predication. According to Text 25e they considered a
genitiveending in -tusas a criterionforbelonging to the word-classof
pronouns ratherthan adjectives. This sounds like pure grammar,but
once again it may well be a by-productof somethingelse, possibly
Trinitarian theology, in which such words as unus and solus play a
crucial role. We do have a fragmentof a grammarcomposed by a Porretan.23But neitherin- nor outsidersseem to have thoughtspecifically
grammatical theses were an importantpart of what distinguisheda
Porretan fromthe rest of mankind.
21See, e.g., thetextsin S. Ebbesen,Anonymus
Aurelianensis
//,in: CIMAGL 16
Aurelianensis
I Commentarium
inSophisticos
Elenchos
, in: CIMAGL
(1976); id. Anonymi
34 (1979).
22QuotedfromEbbesen1991,435.
23See K.M. Fredborg
& C.H. Kneepkens,
Porretana
Grammatica
, in: CIMAGL 57
(1988), 11-67.
76

09:07:50 AM

The same applies to the Meludinenses, whose Nulla oratioest


imperfecta
(S.Mel. 33) of course operates with the grammatical notion
of perfection,but probably was a by-productof theirlogico-semantic
views. Similar considerationsapply to the view attributedto Montani,
that demonstrativepronouns are not parts of speech (Text 25a); and
to a Parvipontanean thesisabout the functionof relativepronouns and
attributiveadjectives (Text 49); it probably originated in investigations of the truth-conditionsof propositions with embedded predicates.
Conclusions
The temporal distributionof referencesto the schools show that
theirgreat time was the mid-late 12th centurywith at most a feeble
after-lifein the 13th c. Anonymus D'Orvillensis just may and the
authorofPos.Nom. probablydoes belong to the early 13thcentury.He
may have been the last nominalist.
All non-theologicaltheses attributedto schools by in- or outsiders
fall within the fields of enquiry defined by the old logic withjust a
Elenchiand a tinylittledose of Priscian. The only
sprinkleof Sophistici
possible exceptions are some theorems of Pos.Nom. that may owe a
debt to books that became available only in the second half of the
twelfthcentury.The prime suspects are theorems3-5, 10 and 15, viz.
(3) Nihil augmentatur
(4) Non contingitaliquid moveri
(5) Non est actio nisi per poros.
(10) Grammatica, dialctica et rhetoricasunt scientia una
(15) Omnis scientia est demonstrativaet nulle topica.
etcorruptione
(3) is statedin explicitdefianceofDe generatione
, and (4)
of the Physics
, but this may just be an attemptto make old goods look
modern. (3) reallyis just theold " Nothinggrows", as is stronglysuggested by Anonymus D'Orvillensis:
Concedimus
tamenquodaliquidcrescit
enimnilaliudestquam
[...], crescere
augmentan
(Ebbesen,1991,440)24
"
'
Nothingmoves' has a betterclaim to an origin in discussions of the
new Aristotle,but perhaps it is just an extensionof 4'Nothing grows";
24Noticethatat
15al3 "TranslatioBoethi"has crementum
Categories
, whereas
"Translatio
hasaugmentum.
composita"
77

09:07:50 AM

a slightly less radical extension is actually found in Anonymus


D'Orvillensis:
dicimusquod omnisdemptiopartiset omnisadditioet omnis partium
variatessentiam
totius(Ebbesen,1991,438).
transpositio
As it stands, Pos.Nom.'s proof of (4) employs terminologyfrom the
, but it is easily rephrasable in termsthat were available prior
Physics
to any acquaintance with the Physics.
Theorem 10 is stated to be contradivisionem
Alpharabii, but does not
for its formulationrequire acquaintance with his work. Theorem 15
was probably inspiredby the Posterior
, but could be a revampAnalytics
a
discussion
the end of Boethius' De
of
one
of
originatingin, e.g.,
ing
I.
differentiis
The one proposition that surely presupposes acquaintance with a
new book is "There is no action except via pores", for it is only
etcorruptione
intelligiblewhen seen on the background of De generatione
1.8.
With these exceptions the non-theologicaltheoremsreflecta stage
of development reached already about 1150, as far as spheres of
interestare concerned, though some may have received their final
shape somewhat later. Thus many of the theorems of Comp.Por. are
recognizable in Gilbert of Poitiers' works, but he did not formulate
them as neatly as his pupils. Perhaps we can go furtherback in time
than 1150. For all I know, virtuallyall the theses could have sprung
fromthe debates of the predecing decades. We have to except one or
more of the Pos.Nom. theoremsalready discussed and perhaps a couple
that seem to presuppose acquaintance with SophisticiElenchi(section
VII above).
Perhaps not all the theological theses that later sources attributeto
schools could be older than 1140/50,but many of them do have roots
that far back. More than is generallyrecognized may have startedas
theorems of secular logic. None occurs in any of the lists.
I will tentativelyconclude that the school division was created by
masters of arts who were pupils of the great masters of the meriod
1120-40. Like members of religious groups, members of the
philosophical sects identifiedthemselvesby theiradherence to a creed
formulatedin the early days of the sect, consideringwhateverviews
theymighthold in new fieldsirrelevantto theirsectarian affiliationas
long as these new views did not interferewith the creed, which contained (almost) solely propositions pertaining to the logic that had
developed fromexegesis of Logic Vetus.
78

09:07:50 AM

Theologians issued fromthe same logic school could not help sharing many theologicalpositions,and someone steeped in Porretanlogic
is easily recognizable whateverhe writesabout. A pervading Porretan
smell clings to the " somebodies' ' criticizedforwrong opinions in the
Sentences-c
ommentaryBrevesdieshominis(ms Bamberg, Patr. 136) and
Humbertus names them as proponents of many (wrong) theological
views (Text 36). Did the school distinctionscarry over fromthe arts
to theology?Perhaps only in the sense thatoutsiderscould reasonably
label as Porretan or Nominalist such theological theses as were
(characteristically)held by adherentsof one or the othercreed in logic.
Perhaps not in the sense that any theologymaster advertised himself
as Porretan or Nominalist. It mightbe all rightto belong to a sectain
logic, but though Alain of Lille dared write Regulae CaelestisIuris,
wouldn't a list of positionesnostraein theology look like settingup a
haeresis?
Copenhagen
Institute
of Greekand Latin

79

09:07:50 AM

Vivarium
XXX, 1 (1992)
Abelard and theSchool of theNominales1
C G. NORMORE

Philosophical confusion is often a sign of historical confusion. A


position or an argument grows up withina particularhistoricalcontextas a solution to a particularset of problems,and when the context
and the problems change and the original context and problems are
forgotten,the argument is oftenleftorphaned, ripe for exploitation
and misunderstanding.At this point philosophersmay put it to new
and ratherawkward uses under the illusionthatthesewere the original
uses. Differentphilosophers tryto twistthe terminologyand concepand incompatibledirections
tual resourcesin what are really different
while intending to use them as their teachers did. The result is
muddle.
This seems to be the situation with Nominalism. Even a cursory
glance at the current philosophical scene will reveal that the term is
now applied to a motley of views about universais, about abstract
objects, about whether there are natural necessities and even about
principles of parsominy and plenitude. Most of these views seem
logically quite independent of one another and seem to be even about
very differentsubjects, and yet philosophersare, on the whole, quite
unaware of this and often,just because the terminologyis common,
seek to fitthe views into a common framework.
So much confusion is a likely sign of a fairlydeep and fairlyold
misunderstanding about what Nominalism was. To uncover such
misunderstandingis a task best undertakenfroma position of methodological innocence. Let us suppose thatwe do not know at all what
Nominalism is and tryout to seek out its origins in the earliest texts
we have. What do we find?
A plausible startingpoint is the supposition that 'nominalism' is a
position (or cluster of positions) having to do with nomina.Equally
plausible is the suggestionthatthese positionsare conncectedwiththe
1 Thispaperwascompletely
inthePhilosoProfessor
rewritten
whileI wasa Visiting
Irvine.I wouldliketothankU.C.I,
oftheUniversity
ofCalifornia,
phyDepartment
suchan hospitable
environment.
thereforcreating
and mycolleagues
working
80

09:07:56 AM

twelfth-century
group referredto as the Nominalesand the fourteenthto in the fifteenth-century
referred
as Nominalistae.
But
centuryfigures
who were thesegroups, whywere theyso-called and what do theyhave
to do with one another?
1. Abelardand theNominales
There seems to have been no one before Abelard who is explicitly
linked with the Nominales in the texts we have. On the other hand,
Abelard is linked with them threetimes in early texts. First, the Gesta
Fridericiof Otto of Freising speaks of him as someone who held the
'sententia vocum seu nominum'.2 Second, the Metalogicon
of John of
Salisbury speaks of Alberic as a bitterenemy of the 'secta Nominalis'
in the same breathas he speaks of Abelard' s leaving Paris, and in such
a way that it would be natural to read the text as suggestingthat he
was thereforea bitter enemy of Abelard too.3 Third, the De Nugis
Curaliumof Walter Map speaks of him as 'princeps nominalium'4
These are all early and reliable witnessesleaving littleroom fordoubt
that Abelard was at least a significantfigureamong the Nominales.
Was he the founderof the group? The best evidence to the contrary
seems to be the text fromOtto of Freising mentioned above. There
Otto explicitlyclaims that it is Roscelin who 'firstin our time established the sententiavocumin logic'. Otto then goes on to speak of
Abelard as 'holding the sententiavocumseu nominumin the natural
faculty'and as 'incautiously introducingit into theology'.5If we can
safelyidentifythe 'sententia vocum' and the 'sententia nominum' as
Otto seems inclined to do, then we have good reason to think that
whoever founded the group it was certainlynot Abelard.
But, despite Otto's apparent identificationof them, there is reason
to doubt that the sententia
vocumis the sententia
nominum.First, there is
of
remark
in
the
John
Salisbury's
Metalogiconthat the opinion that
'voces themselvesare genera and species' has 'vanished readily with
its author' at the very moment that textsabout the Nominates begin
to appear.6 Second there are several texts,all admittedlyratherlate,
which explicitlydistinguish 'nomen' and 'voces' and ascribe to the
2 Listoftexts,6.
3 Ibid.,8.
4 Ibid., 19.
5 Ibid.,6.
6 Metalog.
II, 17 (ed. Webb,93).
81

09:07:56 AM

Nominales the thesis that 'unum nomen est plures voces' or its
equivalent.7 While it is possible that someone might carefully
distinguishvocesand nominaat the same time thatothersidentifytheir
vocumor sententia
nominum
as the sententia
views indifferently
, it is not
in
there
are
the
reasons
advanced
particularly plausible. Third,
an
that
the
vocales
were
earlier
for
Iwakuma ([1992b])
thinking
group
(perhaps associated with a certainJohn, Roscelin's teacher) who were
supplanted by the Nominales around the middle of the twelfthcentury.8From thisperspective,as Iwakuma pointsout, Otto's identification can be seen as a sign that he saw historicaland doctrinal continuitybetween the two 'sententiae', but not as evidence thatthe term
'Nominales' was used of anyone before Abelard.
What of the positive evidence that the Nominales were in any sense
Abelard' s followers.Otto says that Abelard held the 'sententiavocum
seu nominum' in natural philosophyand introducedit into theology,
and Walter Map says that he was 'princeps' among the Nominales.
We know thatAbelard was a charismaticand popular teacher,and we
have no evidence at all of his followers(who must have been many)
being called by any other name. We must conclude, then, that either
he did not found a distinctiveschool or that the Nominales are that
school.
On the other hand I know of no text which both identifies
itselfas
and
no
text
which
'our
master'
and
calls
Abelard
Nominales
fromthe
in thetextas Abelard's to the Nominales. The
attributesviews identified
identificationof the Nominales as Abelard's followerswould, then,
have to rest squarely on finding them characterized by distinctive
theses which we have independent reasons to thinkof as in some way
peculiar to Abelard.9
2. OpinioNominalium
If we examine the textswhich we can date more or less securelyto
before 1230 and which mention the Nominales we finda fairlylarge
and disparate collection of theses attributedto them. These include:
7 Listoftexts,52c,52f,54a.
8 The keytexthereis theHistoria
desGaules
etdela
deshistoriens
Francica
in Recueil
France
1991,p. 14.
, vol. 12 (Paris1877)3; cf.Courtenay
9 The needto finddistinctive
theseswhichAbelardand the
thesesand notmerely
in Courtenay
bothheldis emphasized
Nominales
[1992a].
82

09:07:56 AM

) are universais10
1) Some names ( nomina
est
nomen'11
'Genus
(two attributions)
2)
12
3) Genera and species are vocabulaor voces
4) Nothing save a vox is supposited forby this name 'genus'13
5) No complex sermois a genus or species14
6) Almost every whole is its parts15
7) 'Nulla res (or nihil) cresci16 (Four attributions)
8) 'Aliquid' is not properlyspeaking superior to 'homo'17
)
9) There is a differencebetween suppositionforthe person {persona
and supposition for the thing ( essentia
) so that 'Socrates' and 'that
which is Socrates' supposit differently18
19
10) To be Peter is essequernand not essequid
11) Terms are predicated of terms not things of things20(two
attributions)
12) Topical loci are not required (apt) for syllogisms21
13) One may not infernegative claim from an affirmative22
14) It is not the case that "Posito falso possibili, potest concedi et
probari quodque contingens"23
15) 'Quidquid potuit potest'24
16) The same belief can be expressed by a futuretensed claim at
one time (e.g. that the Messiah will come) and a past tensed claim
(e.g. that the Messiah has come) at another25(four attributions)
17) 'Unum nomen est plures voces'26
18) That the act and the concomitantvoluntas are the same sin.27
10Listoftexts,5.
11Ibid.,40a, 44c.
12Ibid.,4.
13Ibid.,44d.
14Ibid.,22b.
15Ibid., 11.
16Ibid.,26 cf.also37, 40b,48c,48d,and 53.
17Ibid..33b.
18Ibid.,33a, 33b,48d.
19Ibid.,40b.
20Ibid.,22a; cf.also 12.
21Ibid.,20.
22Ibid.,23.
23Ibid.,58.
24Ibid.,29.
25Ibid.,44e,46, 48b,52d+ f.
26Ibid..52c.
27Ibid.,48a.
83

09:07:56 AM

In this list the these most frequentlyand most widely attributedto


the Nominales are number 7, the claim that nothing grows, and
number 16, the claim that the same articlesof faithcan be expressed
using differenttenses. There is another clusterof very closely related
theses (8-10) above which could all be characterizedrathervaguely as
claiming that there is a significantdifferencebetween picking out X
and pickingout thatwhich is X. Then thereare the linkings(in theses
1-5) between genera and species and nominaor vocabula.One way of
testingthe connection between Abelard and the Nominales is to see
whether these widely attributed theses are indeed Abelardian and
whetherthey are distinctivelyAbelardian.
But firstwe must get as clear as we can about the views the
Nominales held. Since we do not have any extensive treatisewhich is
both uncontroversiallyfrom the Nominales and which discusses the
views of the school in detail this can at most be done tentatively.First
then about predication. In his early Summa BreveSit Robert of Paris
attributes to the Nominales a distinctionbetween the subject of a
predication which they say is a term and the subject of a locution
which theysay is a thing.28If we suppose thatthe Nominales held that
predicationis fundamentallya linguisticaffairbut thatwhat language
is about in the sense of what is picked out by linguisticexpressionsare
thingsin the world, then thisfallsinto place. It also suggestsa connection withone of the most characteristicthesesof the Nominales- that
the same thingcan be picked out by expressions in one tense at one
time and in another tense at another. Perhaps the simplest way to
make sense of this is to suppose that an accusative infinitivesignifies
and
what withoutontological prejudice we may call a state-of-affairs
consignifiesthe time of that state of affairsfromthe point of view of
the speaker. Thus two accusative infinitiveconstructionswhich differ
only in tense will signifythe same state of affairs. In the extended
sense suggested by Robert of Paris we can regard that state of affairs
as the subject of a locution like 'That the Messiah would come was
what Abraham believed' This picture connects in a natural way as
well withthe thesisabout the unityof names throughvariation of case
and of gender. Such variation would be thought of as producing
changes of consignification(changes, if you like, in how things are
signifiedbut not in whatis signified).If we suppose thatthe Nominales
28Ibid., 12.
84

09:07:56 AM

thought that only a change in what was signifiedcould produce a


change in which expression (e.g. which name) was under consideration, then we have the 'unity of names' doctrine.
If we turn to the views of the Nominales about 'universais' one of
the thingswhich leaps to mind is that most of these ascribed to them
in this area are not about just any universais in the sense which
everyone in the period understood the term 'universal' - i.e. what is
fitto be predicated of many- but about genera and species. We are
told thatthe Nominales thinkthat genera are nomina
, thatsomenomina
are universais, and that the Nominales feignthat genera and species
are vocabula.We are also told that 'genus' itselfstands fora voxon their
view. Perhaps most importanthere is to get clear about what is not
being claimed. It is not being claimed that all universais- i.e.
, only that
everything fit to be predicated of many- are nomina
some- the genera and species- are. Second we are told that at least
'genus' standsfora vox.This last point, I think,fitswell withthe much
repeatedclaim thatthe Nominales draw a distinctionbetween predications of (say) 'Socrates' and predicationsof 'that which is Socrates'.
The differenceseems to be that a term like 'Socrates' could on differentoccasions pick out differentsubstantia.Perhaps on any given
occasion Socrates is one such substantia
, but Socrates mightbe different
on differentoccasions. If we ask then what the term 'genus'
substantia
picks out on a given occasion the answer mightbe 'that vox' pointing,
forexample, to a token of 'homo'. We could then correctlysay (pointing to the vox) 'That is a genus'. This does not mean that we would
have to say thata genus is a vox.A genus is a nomenand differentvoces
may be the same nomen.Still a voxmay be a nomenand some vocesare
genera.
This also suggestsa way of understandingthe thesis 'nihil crescit'.
In what is probablyour earliestreferenceto this thesisthe anonymous
Parisian author of the Commentary
on theSophisticiElenchiputs this as
'nulla res crescit'. If we take this as a perspicuous renderingand put
it togetherwiththe suggestionthat 'aliquid' is not superior to 'homo'
(Thesis 8 in the above list of theses of the Nominales) it suggeststhat
the Nominales could well admit that (say) 'Socrates grows' while
or reswhich is Socrates grows. Two of our
denyingthat the substantia
textsmake veryclear thatthe thesisthatnothinggrowsdoes not entail
thatPeter does not grow or that a man does not grow. Thus the thesis
is specificallyabout the behavior of certain expressions- 'aliquid',
'res' and 'nihil' it seems.
85

09:07:56 AM

There are a large number of logical theses attributed to the


Nominales. Among these is the rejection of the (derived) rule of
Obligatiothat any contingent sentence follows from a false positum
(Thesis 14 above). By itselfthishas littleconnectionwithany debates
we know of in the logic of the time, but the reasoning attributedto the
Nominales as the basis for rejectingthe rule provides a strongbasis
forattributingto them also the rejectionof the principlethat fromthe
Parisienses
impossible anything follows. According to the Obligationes
the Nominales rejectthe reasoningwhichleads to the derived rule that
any contingentsentence followsfroma falsepositumbecause theyhold
that ifthat reasoningwere valid, thenwe could by the same reasoning
conclude froma falsepositumto an impossibility.The reasoningwhich
supports the derived rule can be illustratedas follows:
Suppose thatas a matterof factSocrates is black and thatthepositum
of our Obligatiois 44Socrates is white"
1)
2)
3)
4)
5)
6)

Socrates is white
Socrates is white and you are not a bishop
Not (Socrates is white and you are not a bishop)
Socrates is white
Not (You are not a bishop)
You are a bishop

(the positum)
(rejected)
(conceded)
(conceded)
(conceded)

6 has to be conceded
The argumenthere is relativelystraightforward.
because it is the negation of 5. 5 is conceded because it followsby disjunctive syllogism(or the third Stoic indemonstrable)from3 and 4.
4 is just the positum.3 is conceded because it is the negation of 2. 2
is rejected because it is false and it doesnotfollowfrom1.
The Nominales hold, according to the text,that ifwe replace "you
are not a bishop" in 2 by the opposite of somethingimpossible, the
For example if we replace it by "God
argument will stillgo through.
exists" and so get
2') Socrates is white and God exists
we will be able, by the same reasoning as before, to conclude
6') God does not exist
This is obviously unacceptable and so they reject the procedure.
Why, we mightask, are the Nominales the ones to point this out?
Why doesn't everyone reject the procedure? The answer is that ifwe
replace "You are not a bishop" by a necessarytruth(the opposite of
an impossible) in 2, most would regard the resultingsentenceasfollow86

09:07:56 AM

, and so not irrelevant,and thus to be conceded


ingfromthepositum
ratherthan rejectedas 2 was. This is because ifyou accept a) that the
necessary followsfromanything,and you accept b) that the positum
followsfromitselfand you accept c) that if B followsfromA and C
followsfromA, thenB&C followsfromA, thenyou have to accept that
T followsfrom 1. Thus if you deny that T follows from 1, as the
Parisienses
Nominales did according to the Obligationes
, you must give
that
the
Nominales
To
of
or
c.
one
a,
b,
gave up b or c
suppose
up
would be to ascribe to thema verystrangelogic indeed and one which
commentsfromthe author of the Obligawould suggestratherdifferent
The only plausible conclusion then is that theyreject
tionesParisienses.
a - that the necessary follows fromanything. But if you accept that
fromthe impossible anythingfollowsand accept contrapositionyou
are committedto a. There is certainlyno reason to think that the
Nominales gave up contrapositionand so the only plausible conclusion is that they also rejected the rule that from the impossible
anythingfollows.
This is a rather lengthy chain of reasoning but it is a chain of
reasoningwhichwould immediatelysuggestitselfto a logician reflecting on the argumentin Text 58 and certainlyto anyone trained in the
involves. I suggest that
Parisienses
kind of dialectic that the Obligationes
it provides very strong reason to think that the Nominales did not
accept either that from the impossible anything follows or that the
necessary followsfromanything.
If, indeed we have good reason to thinkthat the Nominales were
committedto rejectingthese 4paradoxes of strictimplication' then we
have another problem. In the anonymous De CommunibusDistinctionibusin Vat. lat. 7678, it is claimed that according to the opinion
of some Nominales 4'fromthe impossible anythingfollows". It would
seem thenthateitherwe must discard one of these sources or suppose
that they reflecta differenceof opinion among the Nominales. I will
returnto this below.
The briefdiscussion above leaves several thesesof the Nominales in
logic and grammar to be explained as well as the strikingviews that
almost every whole is its parts and that the act and the voluntas are
the same sin. Our texts tell us so littleabout these claims that there
is no way to test a theoryabout why the Nominales hold them unless
we anchor it elsewhere. As we shall see in a moment if we allow
ourselvesto treatAbelard as a characteristicNominalis these textstoo
become intelligible.
87

09:07:56 AM

3. OpinioAbaelardi
Abelard was a master of may subjects- among themlogic, philosophy of language, ethics and theology.In each of these areas he carved
out a distinctivereputation and distinctivepositions. The definitive
study of Abelard' s philosophyis far frombeing writtenand too little
is known to try to identifya small body of central intuitionswhich
would connect his many views. Her I can hope only to point some of
his more strikingphilosophical theories which may be connected to
what we know of the Nominales.
Abelard's logic is distinctive.As ChristopherJ. Martin has argued,
while he was among the very firstto discover and employ propositional logic in the Middle Ages, he mixed thisdiscoverywitha conservatism about inference.29The core of his account of inferencewas a
division of inferencesinto perfectones which needed no topical locus
as a justificationand imperfectones whichhad to be reduced to perfect
ones by a topical rule.30Aristotle's syllogisticprovided a paradigm
case of perfectinference.In advocating this picture Abelard was taking a stand on a controversialissue in twelfthcenturylogic namely
the relative positions of syllogisticand topical inference.He was also
accepting thesis 12.
Abelard's relationto topical inferenceis, on the whole, unusual. He
, and because he rejects this locushe rejects
rejects the locusab oppositis
the claim thata negative followsfroman affirmativeor vice versa. He
rejects all of these because he has a batteryof argumentsdesigned to
show that if theyare accepted one will be able to derive froma given
claim the negation of that claim. It is (as Christopher Martin has
shown) a basic principle of Abelard's logic that one cannot derive a
claim from its negation. From this basic principle also follows
Abelard's rejection of the Parvipontanean thesis that "from the
impossible anythingfollows". There are other grounds on which one
might reject the Parvipontanean thesis (Robert of Melun's followers
seem to have done so because of a view that entailmentis a real relation among things, for example), but it is not easy to conceive a
coherentposition differentfromAbelard's and plausible in the twelfth
centurywhich would have one give up exactly the logical principles
Abelard abandons. It is strikingthatthe Nominales too abandoned the
29Cf. C .J.Martin,TheLogicoftheNominales
in thisissue.
30Cf. Dialctica
III, 256 11.30-35.
88

09:07:56 AM

view that one can infera negative from an affirmative.Unlike the


froma negative which many later logicians
inferenceof an affirmative
rejected on the ground that affirmativeshave existentialimport and
negatives do not, the rejectionof the inferencefromnegative to affirmative seems hard to motivate forother than Abelardian reasons. If
we take it togetherwiththe commitmentof the Nominales to denying
that anythingfollowsfromthe impossible, it suggests a close connection with Master Peter.
If we turn fromLogic to Metaphysics we find Abelard advancing
an interconnectedset of theses in ontologywhich have some startling
consequences. Abelard holds that the only resthere are are individual
forms and individual essentiae.Like many of his contemporarieshe
seems to have been an atomistabout matter.Abelard has an extremely
sophisticatedaccount of identityand differenceand he seems to have
had a deep interestin what is reallythe Chrysippean growingparadox
(though it is unlikelythathe knew of the ancient discussion of it). The
growing paradox has several formsbut one simple one is just this.
Suppose thatSocrates is identicalat a given time witha particularcollection of matterand forms.Call the collection A. Since A is a particularcollectionof matterand forms,adding more matterwould yield
somethinga littlebigger than A; call it B. B is not identical with A
(for one thingit is bigger). But if Socrates is identical with A, then B
is not identical with Socrates either. Abelard worries about various
formsof this problem in several places including his Dialcticaand his
.31 In his TheologiaChristianaBk. Ill Abelard faces
TheologiaChristiana
and differenceamong the members of the
of
sameness
the problems
Trinitywitha theoryof identityformulatedwiththe growingparadox
in mind. Abelard workshere withtwo distinctrelations: thingscan be
the same (or not) and can be diverse (or not). It is possible to have a
non-diversitywithout having sameness. For example a thing is not
numericallythe same as one of its parts but is not numericallydiverse
from it either. Abelard distinguishes numerical sameness and differencefromessential sameness and difference.A thingand its proper
part are essentially diverse even though not numerically diverse.
Again sameness of essentiadoes not guarantee the next level of
, and thissameness does not guarantee
sameness, sameness ofproprietas
sameness of definition.Individuals have definitions.32The notion of
31Op. cit.p. 42Iff.
32Theseclaimsareworked
in Theologia
inOpera
outanddefended
Christiana
theol.
Ill,
147-157.I owemuchhereto MonikaAsztalos,PeterKingand MartinTweedale.
89

09:07:56 AM

essentiaat work here has littlein common with the notion as we find
in Aquinas, forexample. An essentiais typicallywhat is picked out by
a bare demonstrative- that, pointing towards Socrates. Abelard
insists that any change of parts creates diversityof essentia.Hence if
Socrates loses a fingerwe no longerhave the same essentia
, thoughsuch
a loss does not create numerical diversityand we do not have a differentSocrates before and after. Abelard applies his account to the
Trinity (where we have sameness of essentiabut not sameness of proprietas)and to the analysis of augmentation where an essentiacannot
be said to grow, thougha person can. This seems to be preciselythesis
7.
Abelard is probably most famous as a semantic theoristand forhis
account of the behavior of general terms- especiallyspecies and genus
terms. On occasion he seems to accept Aristotle's suggestion that a
and nominates
and
sentenceconsistsminimallyof a name whichsignifies
time. On other occasions he
a verb which signifies and consignifies
claims that names too consignifytime and change their nomination
with time. Abelard seems to claim consistentlythat names nominate
things, express propertiesand have statuses. A status for Abelard is
constructionspick out statuses, and
not a thing. Accusative-infinitive
definitions.In his
Abelard claims thatdifferentstatusesyield different
mature work,at least, Abelard claims thata genus or species is a name
sermo(Thesis 5) and he carefullydistinguishesbetween a
or incomplex
name or sermoand a vox.33A voxand a sermohe claims to be wholly
the same in essentiabut to be differentin institution(and so we might
and definition).34Because a sermoand the correspondadd in proprietas
ing voxare identicalin essence, we can assertboth 'Genus est vox' and
'
'Genus est sermo' (Theses 2 and 4). Because he uses 4sermo and
in his discussions of genera and species,
'nomen' quite indifferently
we can also commit him to 'Genus est nomen' (Thesis 2). Because
theyare not the same in propertyor definition,we can assert 'sermo
est genus' and 'all sermones are voces' withoutbeing committedto
'Vox est genus'. On the more general question of which expressions
are universais Abelard claims that verb and infinitenames as well as
finite names count, but he does not suggest that verbs of infinite
names could be genus or species terms.35It seems thenthathe accepts
every one of thesis 1-5.
33AbelardLI p. 16 1.19-22fortheviewthatonlyincomplex
sermones
areuniversais.
34AbelardLNPS p. 522 110-32.
35AbelardLI p. 17.
90

09:07:56 AM

In Ethics Abelard is famed forhis view that value lies not in acts
but in what in his Scito Te Ipsumhe calls 'consents' to acts. Abelard
insiststhat whetheror not the external act is performedand whether
or not one has a voluntasto performthe act are both ethicallyirrelevant. What mattersis the consentalone. Such a view requires only the
shiftfromthe vocabulary of consent to that of voluntas(in some ways
a more traditionalterminologyforthis notion anyway) to yield thesis
18.
Finally, in modal theoryAbelard was famed forthe view that God
could only do what he did in factdo. This position Abelard founded
on a more general position- that what is possible for X is just what
is compatible with the nature of X. In formulatingthis position
Abelard seems to have had in mind Boethius' discussion in his Second
of the differencebetween
Commentaryon Aristotle'sDe Interpretatione
Stoic and peripateticviews of modality. The Stoics, Boethius says,
regard as possible forX whateveris compatible with X and the attendant circumstances. The Peripatetics, on the other hand, regard as
possible for X whatever is compatible with the nature of X alone.
Abelard seems to have endorsed the peripatetic view and to have
understood 'nature' in such a way that thingsof the same kind have
the same nature. In God's case Abelard' s view entailed that since perfectgoodness was part of God's nature, God could do only what was
forthebest, i.e. what he did do. In any case though, since the natures
of thingsdo not change with time, Abelard is committedto the view
that what is possible forX at one time is always possible for X, i.e.
to thesis 15.
4. Is theopinioNominaliumtheOpinioAbaelardi?
The thumbnailsketchI have just given of some of Abelard' s views
will no doubt sound familiar.There is not a single thesisin the above
list of theses attributedto the Nominales which conflictswith a view
of Abelard' s. Nearly all of them are explicitlyasserted somewhere by
Abelard and those which are not can be easily defended fromothers
of Abelard' s known views. Even if we look at theses attributedto the
Nominales in the thirteenth
centuryonly one, the attributionto 'some
nominales' of the view that everythingfollows froma contradiction,
raises any difficulties.Even these difficultiesare not very serious
because even if we omit the (non-negligible) risk of scribal error or a
misunderstandingon the author's part, we could explain the conflict
91

09:07:56 AM

between this and the rejection of the thesis I argued above to be


Parisiensesas the result of confusionamong
implicitin the Obligationes
Abelard' s followersabout how to respond to the devastatingattack on
Abelard' s theoryof inferencemounted by Alberic of Paris.36
Thus there seems to be an uncanny similaritybetween Abelard's
views and those attributedto the Nominales in our early texts. Is the
similarityenough to fatherthe Nominales on Abelard. I thinkthat it
is. The only other alternative would be to see Abelard as basically
reflecting,refining,and elaboratinga complex set of views whichwere
already held by others(by the mysteriousvocalesperhaps). This is not
impossible, but it does seem unlikely. Abelard is the only figure
securely linked by name with the Nominales, attributionsto the
Nominales are not found during his lifetimeor before but are found
within twentyyears of his death, and there is an uncanny similarity
of complex and frequentlyunusual doctrine over a wide range of
subjects.
5. WhyweretheNominalesso-called?
There are, so far as I know, three plausible accounts of where the
Nominales get their name. The traditionalaccount is that theywere
so called because they held the view that genera and species were
names. The second view (which Stephen Menn has proposed to me
in conversation), is that the name comes from their characteristic
account of predication. The thirdview, which both W.J. Courtenay
and I have defended, is that the sobriquet comes froma set of theses
which they held about the unity of the name.37 Are we in a position
to evaluate these proposals?
Let us firstconsider the traditional view. There can be no doubt
that the traditionalview is a medieval view; Zenon Kaluza has shown
that Jean de Maisonneuve, Jean Gerson and others associated with
them around 1400 explicitly identify the Nominales as so-called
because of their views on universais.38 What is not clear is how
authoritativethat identificationis. De Maisonneuve et al. seem to be
36I pursued
thislineofthought
in TheTradition
In thatpaper
Nominalism.
ofMedieval
incallingtheAlberic
I persisted
wholaunched
thisattack*Alberic
ofRheims'.I owe
to W.J. Courtenay
and C.J. Martin.On theauthenticity
thecorrection
of the
Nominalist
21 impossible
1992aand Iwakuma1992a.
rule,see underCourtenay
37Cf. Normore
(1991a).
38Kaluza 1988.(1985),Courtenay
92

09:07:56 AM

relyingalmost exclusivelyon remarksAlbertus Magnus made about


the Nominales and perhaps especially on a passage fromAlbert's Liber
de Praedicabilibus
(Text 61). Here it is explicitlyclaimed that "those
who are called Nominales say that commonness exists only in the
intellect.Moreover theyclaim that the intellectis bare of preexisting
dispositions,'39
Two thingsare worthnotingabout thistext. The firstis thatAlbert
does not say that the Nominales are so-calledbecause they held this
claim about communitybeing found only in the intellect.Indeed it is
not easy to see how such a view could give rise to the name
' Nominales' unless it were
accompanied by a very strong theoryof
mental language. The second is that Albert is almost among our
witnessesin suggestingthatthe Nominales make a claim about intellectualcommonness. Several early textssuggestthat the Nominales think
that genera and species are linguisticitems in some sense, but none
suggestthattheyare in any way mental items. The only independent
connection between the Nominales and the idea that genera and
species are in some way mentalis found in a note which K.H. Tachau
foundin a manuscriptof William of Auxerre's SummaAurea.40Tachau
suggests that the note is in a thirteenthof fourteenthcenturyhand,
and the author in a list of three differencesbetween Nominales and
Reales puts firstthat " Reales say genera and species to be something
in re, Nominalessay themto be nothingin re but to be certainconceptiones
animae."41 It is difficultto assess thiswitnessand at this point it seems
mostplausible thatwhat both Albertand the anonymous author of the
note have done is take the connection among the Nominales between
genera and species and vocabula and turnit into a connectionbetween
genera and species and intellectusor conceptiones. Within a midthirteenthcenturymilieu the slide is understandable enough.
Outside of the fifteenthcentury Albertine tradition there do not
seem to be texts claiming that the Nominales take their name from
theirviews about universais. Even the anonymous author of the note
just mentioned simply includes the position about universais in a list
of significantdifferencesbetween Nominales and Reales which also
includes the notoriousarticlesof faithand 'nihil cresci theses. There
are however several texts which distinguishthe Nominales and the
39Kaluza 1981,19.
40Listoftexts,70.
41Ibid.
93

09:07:56 AM

Resiles in termsoftheirpositions about universais. Besides those mentioned above both the Archpoet and Godfrey of Fontaines rely for
theirdramatic effecton theirreaders knowingthatthe Nominales and
Reales had different
views of universais.42There can be no doubt then
that a position about universais was associated with the Nominales
both early and often.Associating a group with a position is not, however, the same thing as claiming that theywere named forthat position and the factremains thatthereis no hard evidence connectingthe
appearance of the term'Nominales' withtheirviews about universais.
The second view- connecting the term 'Nominales' with their
views about predication- has not been sufficiently
explored. The root
intuitionhere- thatNominalism is theview thatnames and not things
are involved in predication- receivesdirectsupportfromText 12 and
is suggested by Text 22a. Although I cannot explore it furtherhere,
it deserves, I think, serious attention.
The thirdview, that the Nominales were so-called because of their
view that a name was invariantunder changes of case and of gender,
and more metaphoricallythat the significationof an expression was
invariant under changes of tense as well, is the only view to receive
direct support before the last few years of the fourteenthcentury. In
Bk.l d.41 a. 2 q.2 of this Commentary
on theSentences
of PeterLombard
Bonaventure expressly endorses the view. He opens the passage by
alluding to the view of those who say that 'albus', 'alba' and 'album',
althoughtheyare threevocesand have threemodes of signifying,carry
the same significationand so are one name.He continues by drawing
the analogy withenuntiabilia
which differin tense yet signifythe same
thing, and he concludes by saying that "this was the opinion of the
Nominales whoare calledNominalesbecausethey
foundtheirpositionon the
the
name
."43
unityof
Bonaventure is not in this passage claiming that the distinctive
thesis of the Nominales was that variation in gender did not vary the
name. He is rather claiming that that was a special case of a more
general thesis which is also alluded to by William of Auxerre (Text
52c), namely the thesis that sameness of significationmakes for
sameness of a nomen.
The texts linking the Nominales with the thesis that sameness of
42ForthepassagefromtheArchpoet
see thepaperofC.J. Martinin thisvolume;
forGodfrey
ofFontaines
see listoftexts,18.
43Listoftexts,64a.
94

09:07:56 AM

significationentails sameness of nomenare not quite as old as those


linkingthem with problems about universais, but they are nearly as
frequentand the differencein their age is at most one generation.
Although Bonaventure does not display any extensive knowledge of
Nominalist views, what he says in the few passages in which he
discusses themis otherwiseconfirmedby othersources. It seems then
thatwe have no good reason to discount his testimonyabout how the
name arose. Thus while none of the three theoriesmentioned above
has been eitherproved or disprovedbeyond reasonable doubt, it is the
thirdview which the preponderance of evidence slightlyfavors.
6. Nominalesand Nominalistae
Even as recentlyas fiveyears ago thereseemed to be no way of connectingup the ascriptionof the term 'Nominales' in the twelfthcenSince the modern
turywiththe term 'Nominalistae' in the fifteenth.44
term 'Nominalism' seems as connected to the fifteenth
centuryas to
the twelfth,thislack of continuitymade it veryunclearjust what is was
that the modern usage was supposed to go back to. With the publication of Zenon Kaluza' s Les QuerellesDoctrinales Paris all that has
changed. Kaluza has, I think,cleared up one of the more important
historicalquestions about medieval nominalism by showing that at
least one strand of the fifteenth
centuryuse of the term 'Nominales'
can be traced back to Albert the Great's remarks about the twelfth
century Nominales. Kaluza has done more; he has shown that
century
preciselybecause it is parasiticupon Albert's use, the fifteenth
use of 'Nominalistae' is, at least in the mouths of some, to pick out
a position (or a range of positions) about the problem of universais.
Kaluza' s workmarksa significantstep in our understandingof how
the twelfthcenturyNominales and the fifteenth
centuryNominalistae
came to be connectedhistorically,but it raises a number of new questions. The Albertine tradition seems to have thought of the labels
'Nominales' and 'Nominalistae' as pejorative. Yet by the time of the
Royal Edict of 1473 which bans the teaching of nominalism at Paris
therewere clearlydoctors who identifiedthemselveswith these labels
and who seem not to have regarded the Albertineaccount of what the
labels signifyas definitive.If the letterrespondingto the Royal Edict
44This was thesituation
whenI wroteTheTradition
Nominalism
, for
ofMedieval
example.
95

09:07:56 AM

is to be taken seriously,the problems of universaisdid not loom large


in the minds of these doctors as what united them.45
7. A Fable
Very littleabout the Nominales is beyond reasonable doubt. For the
moment we are like Timaeus, in the realm of the likely story. Here
is the one I would tell:
Once upon a time a number of thinkersincludingperhaps Roscelin
and the Garlandus of the Dialctica, began to think that many differences among words- especially genus and category words and
tense and gender indicators- did not reflectany differencesin things.
They began to claim thingslike "Vox est genus". They had a brilliant
studentin Peter Abelard who saw thatthe views theywere advancing,
though on the righttrack, were far too crude and invited refutation.
Abelard significantlychanged the views while preserving much of
their spirit. He began to claim that semantics was the province, not
of the bare word (the vox) but of the significantword (the nomen)and
the significantexpression (the sermo)and to utterclaims like "Nomen
est genus" and "Albus et alba idem nomen sunt". He attracted
studentsnot merelybecause of theseviews but because of his brilliance
and his original and articulated work in a variety of fields. People
began to talk about Abelard and his group as Nominales. Abelard in
due course died but the movement, unified by reverence for his
memory and close adherence to his teaching, survived into the end of
the twelfthcenturyand the memory of it never quite faded away.
This is a likely story. It fitsthe evidence adduced and it fitsother
things too like the DialcticaArs which William, bishop of Lucca,
donated to the Church of St. Martin in that city and which refersto
Abelard as 'the Philosopher'- a sobriquet later reserved forAristode
alone. Perhaps most important it suggests a line of philosophical
research. By thinkingof Abelard and the Nominales and figureslike
the author of the DialcticaArs as parts of a single if loosely defined
movement we can hope to get new insightinto the position each held.
Universityof Toronto
Ezindale College

The Ohio State University

Department
of Philosophy

45Forthisepisodecf.L. Thorndyke
Records
andLifeintheMiddle
University
AgesNew
York(1944),355ff.
96

09:07:56 AM

Vivarium
XXX, 1 (1992)
Nominales
Twelfth-Century
The PosthumousSchool of PeterAbelard
IWAKUMAY.

*was
The label 'nominales
originallyattached to those who belonged
to the logic-schoolof Peter Abelard. It is one of several schools active
in the second halfof the 12th-century.In thispaper I shall discuss why
nominales
were so called (1-2), when theyappeared (3) and disap'
'
peared (4), and what was understood by nominalesin the 13thcentury(5).
and nominales
1. The unitasnoministheory
were called so because of
Bonaventure (#64a)! says that nominales
44
their holding the unitas-noministheory, or the thesis 'albus' '-a'
'-um' sunt unum nomen". Two more 13th-centurysources attribute
the theoryto nominales
(# 52c, 54a). Supported by these sources, M.D. Chenu and W.J. Courtenay argue thatthe basis of the nominalism
was in the unitas-nominis
theory,and they search under this presupof
the nominalism into teachings of masters
for
the
position
origin
other than Abelard.2 It is true that nominalesactually held the unitasnoministheory.3 But still the testimonies on which Chenu and
Courtenay rely turn out to be unreliable, if we study 12th-century
sources.
1 The numbers
with
arethosein IwakumaY. & S. Ebbesen,Logico-theological
volume
A ListofSources
theSecond
Schools
, in thepresent
Century:
from
Halfofthe12thofthisjournal.
2 Chenu1935-36;Chenu1957;Courtenay
1991a.
3 A 12th-century
treatisein ms Vienna,VPL 2459, ff.107v-lllra,discusses,
withotherthesesof nominales
theory
(cf. n. 20 below),theunitas-nominis
together
(109va-b)as follows:
"Quaeritursi 'albus,-a, -um' sitidemnomenvel diversa.
Quidamdicuntquoddiversa;quidamquodidemnomen;aliidicunt<quod> hoc
nomen'albus'estpluranomina,nontampluraasserentes
(] asserentibus
ms)quod
sitnominadiversa.< Primis
> sicopponitur Contranos: 'albus,-a, -u<m>
estidemnomen,<ergo> nullamterminatione<m>
habethocnomen<'albus'>
contraillosqui dicuntquod
quamnonhabeathocnomen'alba'. Fallacia Item
"
pluranomina,nontarnen
plura,sie opponitur
97

09:11:17 AM

The unitas-nominis
theorywas firstproposed in somewhata different
formula,viz. "oblique cases are the same noun as theirnominative".
This theoryis against what Aristotlesays in his De interpretatione
(2,
"
16a32-bl, transi.Boethii): 'Catonis' autem vel 'Catoni' et quaecumque talia sunt non sunt nomina, sed casus nominis". In his Dialctica
Peter Abelard gives commentsto thisAristotle'sidea to the effectthat
cases or gender; and
significationremains the same throughdifferent
that
'Cato'
and 'Catonis' are
in his Logica Ingredientibus
explicitlysays
the same noun in so far as one pays attentionto the identityof their
signification.4It is almost certain that Abelard was the firstperson to
theory in these forms,since none of the
propound the unitas-nominis
commentaries gives similar comments to
extant earlier PerihermeniasAristotle's phrase.5
By Abelard' s last days thisissue became a matterof discussion. The
Introductiones
Montanae maioressays as follows (Ms Paris, BN, lat.
15141, f. 49ra-b):
'Socrates'estnomen,ergoproprium
velappellativum;
et
Rursumopponitur.
cumnonsitalterius;
etsi est
cumnonsitappellativum,
estproprium;
Socratis,
'Socrates'nomenSocratis,Socrateshabethoc nomen'Socratis',et eadem
ratione<'Socrati'> 'Socrate<m>' 'Socrate';et ita vocaturhoc nomine
concedere.
'Socratis''Socrati''Socratem''Socrate',quodestabsurdum
'Socratis'velvocatioestfieri
Nosnonconcedimus
quodvocetur
aliquis/49rb/
et vocativum,
ut hicvocetur
Socrates'Socrates'vel 'o
nisipernominativm
esseconcedendum
Socrates
quodhocnomen
(] socrataMr)'. Ad quoddicimus
nomenSocratis,
et Socrates(] socratis
'Socratis''Socrati''-em' estproprium
nontarnen
habet
, quia
pluranomina
Ms) habethocnomen'Socratis'et'Socratem',
nam(] inMs) hocnomen'Socratis'nonest
non(] tamMs) essetbinomius(!);
cumilionomen.
Sed quamvis
hocnomen'Socratem'necaliudnomen,sedidem
nonpotest
vocariistonomine,
sedpotest
hocnomen'Socratem',
habeatSocrates
cumisto.
nomineisto,et vocarinominequodestidem
appellari
This work reportsthe teachings of Alberic of Paris in the mid-12thcentury,and oftencontraststhem with those of Peter Abelard. In the
4 See Dial., 124.36-125.15,
and LI , 344.14-17.
5 FortheextantPerihermeneiascommentaries
and thebriefdating,seeJ. Marenbon
All ofearliercommentaries
thatAristotle
intends
interprete
bythe
[forthcoming].
noun.Onlytwoofthe
phrasetoexcluseobliquecases(as wellas infinite
nouns)from
listedtheresay thatAristotle
17 extantcommentaries
definition
to
givestwo-fold
infinite
nounsandobliquecasesas nouns,anda
noun,a looseonewhichincludes
strict
onewhichexcludes
them.Theyare H15 (msParis,BN lat. 15015,f. 183va),
datedto mid-1
130's,and H10 (ms Paris,Bibl.Arsenal910, f. 166va),datedby
Marenbon
after1120,butI aminclined
todateitlater.Bothofthemwerelaterthan
Abelard'sworks,
mostpresumably
and therefore
undertheinflutheywerewritten
enceofAbelard'sunitas-nominis
theory.
98

09:11:17 AM

passage quoted above the name of Abelard is not mentioned. However, it is highlyprobable that in his last days Abelard taught the
unitas-nominis
theory,whichhe had arrivedat in his youngerdays; and
Alberic followed him in this issue, though otherwise being a bitter
opponent of Abelard.
Montanae maioresprovides evidence that the
The Introductiones
Albricani
, followersof Alberic, asserted the unitas-nominis
theoryas well
as nominales.Moreover, Porretaniaccepted the unitas-nominis
theory,
that
asserts
Porretanum
too. Thesis 1.2 of the Compendium
plures
logicae
vocesesse unumterminm
, or oblique cases are the same noun as the
suntunumnomen
,
nominative; and Thesis 1.3 assertsthatpluresdictiones
'
9
or 'albus*'-a '-um are the same noun.6
These two questions are dealt with as the same one in another
source, a treatise in Ms Munich elm 29520(2) (an unfoliated fragment). The treatiseis a product of the Petit-Pontschool, as I argue
elsewhere.7Unfortunatelyonly the beginning part is extant. It tells
s view on the issue:
nothingof Parvipontani
cumsuisobliquis,et diversi
soletessequaestio:utrumnominativus
Generalis
ab altero,sintidemnomenvel diversa
nominativi
quorumunus formatur
est
nomina,ut 'albus' 'alba' '-bum','Socrates''-ti'. Circa quod multiplex
hos(] hi(us)ms)nonsolumesseidemnomen,sed
qui dicerent
opinio.Fuerunt
Contraquossic.
etveritati.
obvitrationi
etiameandemvocem.Quodprorsus
Aliquidestparshuiusvocis'albus',quodnonestparshuiusvocis'alba', et e
... (thereis one line
converso;
ergohaecvoxnonestilla. Et hocab Aristotile
more,butitis damagedto be illegible)....
ArsMelidunareportsvarious opinions to thisissue propounded in the
second half of the century(Ms Oxford, Bodl. libr., Digby 174, ff.
21 lvb-213ra):
utrum
obliquuscumsuorectodicendussit idem
Consequenter
ergoquaeritur
nomenvelnon.
invenitur
opinio.Dicuntenimquidam obliTriplexsuperhocmodernorum
alii
eo quodaliasiteiusterminatio;
quumessealiudnomenquamsuumrectum,
etinstitutio
dicunt
obliqui
quodsitidemnomen,eo quodeademsitsignificatio
etrecti;alii quodnecidemnecaliud;nonidem,quia noneademestvocistervel
minatiorecticumobliquo;nonaliud,quia nonalia est eius significatio
institutio
quamrecti.
et usui,et ex
auctoritati
Et primaquidemopiniorpugnt
grammaticorum
.../212ra/....
inconvenientia.
ipsamultasequuntur
dicentium
Secundam
diximusesseopinionem
obliquoscumsuisrectisesse
identitatem
etinstitutionis.
Sed haeciterum
idemnomenpropter
signifcationis
Dicuntenimquidam eorumobliquoscumrectoesseet idem
opiniovariatur.
6 Ebbesen/Fredborg/Nielsen
1983,3.
7 IwakumaY. [1992a],3. (ed.)
99

09:11:17 AM

nomenet eandemvocem;et sicutidemnomenita et eandemvocemplures


habereterminationes,
voxet institutio;
quia ad essenominisduo exiguntur,
undecumdicitur
"hoc nomen'homo'esthocnomen'hominis' sensusest,
i.e. haecvoxesthaecvox,ethabeteandeminstitutionem.
Alii verodicuntrectumcumobliquisesseidemnomen,sedessediversas
vocespropter
diversas
teret sicpluresvocesesseidemnomen.
minationes;
Sed hisposterioribus
multipliciter
potestobici
Notandum
dictionibus
declinabilibus
ergoquoniameorumquae conveniunt
Etquae
quaedamsibiinomniterminatione,
quaedamnoninomniconveniunt.
omnemterminationem
attribu
insunt,
(] quodMs) secundum
possunt
qualibet
terminatione
dictionis
uthocnomen'albus'estadiectivum
nominata,
mobile,
est alicuiuscasus,generis,numeri;similiter
hocverbum'curri
declinatur,
esttertiae
estalicuiusmodi,personae,
temactionem,
signifcat
coniugationis,
suntvera.Quae veronon
poris,et huiusmodi;
quae peromnesterminationes
secundumomnemterminationem
insunt,possuntattribuinon <nisi>
nominando
ut nomenquod profertur
ab istoest masculini
terminationem,
estfeminini,
estneutri,
tantum
hocnomen'albus'
generis,
positoquodprofrt
in hac terminatione;
similiter
in '-us', in '-a', in '-um', est
terminatur
nominativi
eodemmodoverbum
ab istoest
casus,estgenitivi;
quodprofertur
indicativi
futuri,
praesentis
temporis,
modi,imperativi,
praeteriti,
optativi,
infinitivi.
Sed si velimusnominareterminationem
dictionis,ilia sola erit
nominanda
secundum
illi convenit,
ut hoc nomen
quam istudpraedicatum
'albus'estmasculini
et hocverbum
'curro'primaepersonae;
sednon
generis,
similiter
dices:hocnomen'albus'estfeminini
velhocverbum
'curro'
generis,
estsecundaepersonae,
nonconvenit
alteriistarum
dicquia talepraedicatum
tionumin hac terminatione
velin illa. Itaquenominata
terminatione
dictionis
nonerit,utdiximus,
sivecopulandum
non
aliquidattribuendum
quodei/212rb/
conveniat
in illaterminatione.
Similiter
nominando
non
pluresterminationes
eritaliquidattribuendum
illasterminationes.
Unde
quod noninsitsecundum
nonestverumquodhocnomen'albus,-a, -um'sitalicuiusgeneris,
quia non
estalicuiusgeneris
secundum
omnesillasterminationes,
sedmagisaliquorum;
nechocnomen'dominus,
domini,domino'"estalicuiuscasus,sedaliquorum.
Fortassis
autemnechocipsumbenedicitur
domini'estnomen",
'dominus,
vel " 'curro,curris,-it' estverbum",sicutnec istud"haec species'homo,
homini'praedicatur
de aliquo".
hominis,
Nec tarnen
solutioquamdiximuspotestinfirmari
hocmodo..../213ra/....
Nunc tertiaeopinioniobviandum,
quae scilicetasserit'homo' 'hominis'
essevoces,sed necidemnomennequediversa
diversas
Suntetiamal ii qui nonrecipiunt
hancvocemesseillamnecaliamab ea, sicut
necnomen.Atverohancopinionem
multaeex supradictis
rationibus
videntur
interimere,
ideoquenihilaliudnunccontraearndicemus
quamquaedictasunt
prius.
It is evident thatMeludinenses
, too, held the unitas-noministheory,but
in a differentform,viz. according to them oblique cases are not only
the same noun but also the same voice as the nominative.
These pieces of evidence8 prove that in the second half of the 12th-noministheory was held by rather many logic
century the unitas
8 Thereis another
textdiscussing
theissuefromthestand-point
that
12th-century
nounsfrom
thenominative.
See Ms Oxford,
Bodl.Libr.,
obliquecasesaredifferent
Digby174,f.242vb.
100

09:11:17 AM

formula.It cannot be exclusively


schools, each witha slightlydifferent
attributedto nominales
, as the 13th-centurysources say. And if so, the
'
'
label nominalescannot stem from their holding that theory as is
asserted by Bonaventure.
2. Whywerenominales
calledso?
As is well-known,Peter Abelard developed the theorythat universais are sermones
, not vocesas had traditionallybeen formulated.J.
Reiners argues that Abelard took sermoto be identical to nomen
, and
laterhis theoryof universais came to be formulatedas ' 'universais are
9
nomina".9Thus J. Reiners suggeststhatthelabel 'nominalesoriginated
fromtheir theoryon universais in this formulation.
" is
The formula 4'universais are nomina
frequentin 12th-century
VII- 12 ; cf.
sources (#5, 18, 40a, and John of Salisbury's Polycraticus
etiam 25i, 43). It is thereforeverylikelythatthe label comes fromthat
formulation.It is highly improbable, however, that nominalesthemselves adopted the formula. Abelard would never agree with the formulation, since forhim not only nouns but also verbs and participles

are universais. And a text writtenby a nominalis10


says 'universalia
termini sunt, et ... quaedam sunt nomina, quaedam sunt alii
termini".
' when
Even realists were cautious of using the term 'nomen
they
I
know
on
universais.
intend
their
rival's
to
discuss
theory
sincerely
threerealistrepresentationsof the nominalisttheory.(1) A treatiseon
universais (#4), where the nominalist theoryis formulatedin terms
of vocabula.(2) Porphyry-commentaryin Ms Vienna VPL 248611;
there the term 'nomina3 is used togetherwith 'vocabula' and 'termini*
,
but 'nomina' does not play a central role. (3) Ars Meliduna II (Ms
Oxford, Bodl. Libr., Digby 175, f. 218vb):
sicAristoteles
Universale
in libroPerihermenias
(De Int.I, 17a39-40)dfinit:
universale
estquod estnatumpraedicari
de pluribus,
i.e. praedicabile
aptum
9 Reiners1910,46: "So stellt
Ablarddiesermones
gleichmitdenNamen",58: "So
istdie LehreAblards
mitdemLosungswort
nomen
in denVordergrund
getreten".
10Ms Paris,Bibl.Arsenal910,ff.141va-142vb,
at f. 141va.
11M. Grabmann,
inhisEin Tractatus
deUniversalibus
undandere
Inedita
ausdem
logische
12.Jahrhundert
imCod.lat.2486derNationalbibliothek
in Wien
, in: MediaevalStudies,
9 (1947),65-70,editedthetexton ff.lr-4ras an independent
treatise
on universais.
LaterDe Rijk1966,24, discovered
thatthesametextis included
in thePorphyryon ff.45r-60v
ofthesamemanuscript.
commentary
101

09:11:17 AM

de pluribus.
Sed illudpraedicabile
natumpraedicari
seil,sitres
quidsit,utrum
aut terminus,
dubitari.Quidam enimponuntsolos terminos
esse
contingit
aliires,i.e. terminorum
solosterminos
praedicabilia;
significata Ponentibus
vel singularia,
... (therefollow
esse universalia
manifeste
obvitAristoteles
'
fromAuthorities
quotations
againstthenominales
thesis).
' is used.
Here only the term 'termini
'
1
The term vocabula appears in (1) and (2) above. The latter(2) was
writtenin the mid-12th-century12;
and the former(1) is dated around
the same period, since it sometimesstilluses the term 'voces',the keytermof the nominalisttheoryin the earlierstage. The ArsMeliduna(3),
where the key-termis 'termini
' is dated to 1170/1180. 13Presumably
nominalesadopted in the mid-12th-centurythe term 'vocabula' instead
of Abelard' s 'sermones'as the key-termto express their theory,and
then gradually shiftedto the term 'termini'.The term 'termini'would
be betterthan 'sermones'
or 'vocabula'to express what Abelard means,
since for Abelard the universais are only those words which can be
terms, predicate terms in particular.
"
One can conclude, then, that the formula " universais are nomina
was originallycoined by realistsas a rough and inexact one. Realists
would have mocked their adversaries, attaching them the label
'nominales
'. Nominalists gradually accepted the label to referto themas
the case in a nominalisttext,14but theynever accepted the
is
selves,
formulationitself.
3. Whendid nominales
appear?
I have elsewhere shown that earlier nominalistswere called vocales
,
15The label 'vocales' was later
and theirtheorysententia
vocum.
replaced
by 'nominales'.When did it happen?
The label 'vocales' must have been derived from the early
nominalists' theorythat universais are voces,not res.And the replacement of the label into 'nominales'must have had somethingto do with
the transformationof the nominalists' view fromthe pox-theory
to the
sermois firstrecorded in
theory. As is well-known, the rmo-theory
Abelard' s Logica ('Nostrorumpetitioni sociorum" written in ca.
1120/24(?). 16This is the terminus
post quemof the appearance of the
nominales.
12See De Riik1966,30.
13See Hunt1975,18,n. 8.
14A treatise
on predication
(#22b),wheretheauthorsays"nos nominales".
15IwakumaY. [1992b],
1.
16I tollowthedatingbyC. Mews1985.
102

09:11:17 AM

antequemis suggestedbyJohn of Salisbury's Metalogicon


The terminus
11-10 (#8), the earliest source with definite date where the word
'
'nominales
appears. John describes therehis apprenticeshipin France
'
'
between ca. 1136 and 1146/7. Was the term nominalesalready currentin the period ofJohn's apprenticeship,or should we thinkof 1159
was completed?
when the Metalogicon
The latter is more probable. For in a Porphyry-commentarya
vocalisis attacked as holding the sermotheory (Ms
theory, not voxf.
lat.
Bodl.
Laud.
libr.,
Oxford,
67,
7rb-va):
aucethocpluribus
Dicuntquidamgeneraetspeciesessesermones
incomplexos,
.../7va/....Ad eiusdem(= huiusopinionis)
confirmare
conantur.
toritatibus
utamur.Ut enimdicimus,aucinfirmationem
propriisargumentationibus
toritates
adducerealienoest uti testimonio.
Itaque quod et per hoc genus
circaomne
monstratum
etpropriis
rationibus
'animal'idoneis
testimoniis
fuerit,
: hocgenus
nemomortalium
constare
ambigat.Vocalis
genusetomnemspeciem
'animal*
esthocnomen'animal'.Cantaber:
ergohocgenus'animal'estaliquid
longcounter-arguments
quodesthocnomen'animal'velnon... (therefollow
'
ofCambridge,
or Guarinus
againstthevocalisthesis)....
byCantaber,
I date this commentaryto 1140's. For, first,this commentaryadopts
the rather elaborated heads which R. Hunt calls 44type D + type
C"17; it was hardly before ca. 1140, and indeed all the Porphyrycommentaries written before the 1130' s adopt heads of type C.
Secondly, this commentary reports a lecture of Guarinus of Cambridge, who later became abbot of St Albans between 1183 and 1195;
thereforehis mastershipwas hardlyearlier than 1140's. Thirdly, it is
improbable thatthiscommentaryis dated afterthe mid-12th-century,
because the logicanovaliteratureis never mentioned. If my dating is
, not
correct,thenold Abelard and his followerswere stillcalled vocales
nominales.
'
'
Other earliest sources referring to nominales are the Summa
elenchorum
( #addendum).
sophisticorum
( #5) and De figurissyllogismorum
18
The formeris dated to 1155/60. The latter,a collectionof instantiae
17See R. W. Hunt,TheIntroductions
in: Studia
in theTwelfthtothe'Artes'
Century,
inhonorem
Martin
mediaevalia
admodum
Patris
Reverendi
, Bruges1948,
Raymundi
Josephi
85-112(repr.inhisTheory
ofthiscommentary
, 117-44).Forthebeginning
ofGrammar
whichenumerates
those
headsof typeD, see De Rijk 1967,80. After
discussing
todiscusstheheadoftypeC (f.6rb):"Assignatis
heads,thecommentary
proceeds
illisquae circaartemextrinsecus
de eis quae circahunclibrum
erantconsideranda,
Ea sunthaec:quaesitauctoris
suntinquirenda
restt
dicendum.
materia,
quae intencui partiphilosophiae
tio,quismodus,quis ordotractandi,
quis finis,quistitulus,
supponatur,
quae sitcausacompositionis".
18De Rijk1962,
89.
103

09:11:17 AM

against the valid modes of syllogism,is fromaround the same period,


exclude the date before the
too. For, on the one hand, the instantiae
it
would
the
mid-12th-century.On
other,
hardly be dated after the
'
'
mid-12th-century,since it still calls followersof Abelard vocales as
19Otto of
well as 'nominales'.
Freising suggests, too, that even in the
'
'
late 1150' s the word nominaleswas still feltas new-fangled. In his
Gesta Friderici(#6) written in 1156/58 he refers once to "sententia
'
vocum
M, the name attached to the vocales theory, and he calls it at
. It suggeststhat Otto had
vocumseu nominum"
another time " sententia
. All these sources
some hesitation to say simply "sententianominum"
'
'
was
label
'vocales'
the
indicate that
graduallyreplaced by nominalesin
the 1150's.
Several logic-schoolsrivaled nominales
, presumably in Paris, in the
second half of the 12th-century.The earliest record of the rivalryis
(ft7a), where John mocks followersof
John of Salisbury's Entheticus
Adam of the Petit-Pont,Robert of Melun, Alberic of Paris, and Peter
Abelard (John does not referthere to Porretani
, or followersof Gilbert
was writtenin 1154/62. By the
of Poitiers, but why?). The Entheticus
period the school-founders,including Abelard, are known to have
died or retiredfromlogic-teaching. It means that their schools were
'
*
succeeded by theirdisciples. The label nominaleswas coined in place
'
'
for vocales in the rivalryof those schools.
was characterizednot only by holding (1) the
The school of nominales
nominalisticview on universais (#4), but also many othertheses: (2)
nonsequiturnegativa( #23), (3) ex negativanonsequitur
ex affirmativa
afirtotum
est
omne
nisi
est
nullum
,
plures
fere
mativa,(4)
praesens (5)
tempus
estargumentum
, (7) locinonsuntaptisyllogismi
( #20),
( #11), (6) propositio
nihil
crescit
and
est
verum
verum
,
, semper
(#26,
(9)
(8) quicquidsemelest
40b). All of these theses originate fromAbelard's teaching.20And the
rival schools did not usually share the theses.21The 12th-century
19Ms Wolfenbttel,
Guelf.56.20Aug.8, f.81v:"Secundus
HerzogAugust-Bibl.,
... Vel sic: omnesvocalessunt
sicfalsificatur.
moduseiusdem( = secundae)figurae
suntlitterae,
sed nulliclericim(agistri)
litterae,
ergonulliclericim(agistri)
P(etri)
' ' . The sametreatise
sententiam
tenentes
alsocallsclerici
< sunt> vocales
magisti
P(etri)
*is not
'
*
#
see
addendum.
Petri
Petri'nominales
abbreviated);
(here magisti
20As fortheorigin,see Abelard'sDial., 395.7-400.6and 547.27-555.19,
forthe
222.35-38
Abelard'sSuperTopica
theses(2)/(3)and(4)/(5)respectively;
,
glossae
(ed.
for(5) and(6). As for(7) and(8), seen. 32/33and37 below.
Dal Pra)and319.30-31
inn. 3 abovediscusses
TheViennatextmentioned
affirmatively
(2), (3), (6) and(8).
21Thereis littlespaceto provethisclaim.
104

09:11:17 AM

nominales
developed a systemof whole logic consistingof these theses
and of otherscommon to rival schools like the unitas-nominis
theory.
4. Whendid nominales
disappear?
It is without doubt that nominalescompletely disappeared by the
mid-13th-century.Albert the Great, Bonaventure, and Thomas
9
Aquinas all referto nominalesopinions in past tense ( #61, 62d, 64a-c,
65a, cf. etiam 50c-d, 71).
It is highlyprobable, however, thatnominales
ceased to be active far
earlier. As is shown in 1 above, the unitas-nominis
theorywas held not
Porr
and
but
Meludinenses
nominales
etani,
, each
,
Albricani,
by
only by
witha slightlydifferenttone. William of Auxerre leftthe earliest false
theorywas to be exclusivelyascribed
testimonythat the unitas-nominis
to nominales
( #52c). William's Summaaureais dated between 1215 and
1229.22Assuming that he wrote his Summain his thirties,his apprenticeshipat Paris would have been around 1200 at the earliest. If so,
thenaround the turnof the centurytheyhad lost the exact knowledge
9doctrine.
schools and ofthe nominales
of therivalryofthe 12th-century
It means that the schools disappeared ten or more years earlier.
It is certain that the other 12th-centuryschools rivaling nominales
, Montani,
disappeared by the end of the century.As for the Albricani
and Meludinenses
, no 13th-centurysources referto them at all. Faint
or Adamitaeare sometimes discovered in 13thechos of Parvipontani
but
Gervase of Melkley's Ars versificatoria
sources;23
, dated to
century
121624and the earliestsource fromthe 13th-century,says ' 4Parvipontani olim...censuerunt..."
is
(#49, cf. etiam 56). The name of Porretani
very often mentioned in the 13th-centurysources; but Humbert of
Balesma's Summa, which is dated to 1194/1200,25already refersto Porretani9
s doctrinesin past tense (#36c-d).
Among the 12th-centuryschools, the Petit-Pontschool was without
doubt active when Alexander Nequam studied there between ca.
1175-82.26The Meludinenses
, too, were certainlyactive in 1170's, if,
and it is verylikely,Hunt's dating oftheArsmelidunato 1170/80is cor22J. Ribaillier,
Guillelmi
Summa
Altissiodorensis
aurea
; Introduction
Magisti
gnrale
(=
Bonaventurianum
1987,16.
Spicilegium
XX), Paris/Roma
23See Lewry1983.The sourceshe collects
thereare #39b,42, and 55-57.
24Farai1924,37.
25Heinzmann
1974,20-24.
26ForthedateofAlexander
s studyin Paris,see Hunt1984,4.
105

09:11:17 AM

rect.27And the Compendium


logicaePorretanum
mightpossiblyhave been
writtenaround the same period, maybe slightlyearlier.28It is concluded, then,thatthose schools disappeared verysoon afterproducing
those fruitsof theirdoctrine, if my previous conclusion is correctand
the memoryof the rivalryof the schools was already forgottenaround
1200. This swiftdisappearence of the schools would need explanation.
I am inclined to consider that it had something to do with the
reorganizationof education at Paris promotedby Pope Alexander III
in 1170's. But thisis a major problem beyond the scope of thispresent
study.
and
A source appears to contradictmy claim above, viz. nominales
other rival schools disappeard around the 1180's. It is a 13th-century
99 #
nostrae
treatise*' Positiones
( 60), whichenumeratesand proves theses
"contra opinionem realium". But was the anonymous author a real
nominalist?
Most of the positionesenumerated there are completelyalien from
those of 12th-centurynominales.Some similarityis found only in the
firstpositio, viz. universais are nomina
; and in the third,viz. nothing
But the formulationof the positionesare spurious. The
augmentatur.
formeris formulatedin terms of 'nomina', which 12th-centuryreal
nominales
would not have accepted as is argued in 2 above; the latter
9 but the
is formulated"nothing augmentatur9
,
genuine formulationis
. Moreover, the rationes
to prove them are completely
"nothing crescit99
differentfrom 12th-centuryones. There is another question on the
anonymous author. He sometimes disagrees with Aristotleand sides
withZeno (positiones
3, 4, 6, & 15); he also challengesPriscian in favour
11 & 12). But it is highlyunlikelythatthere
of a Stoic theory{positiones
were people who sincerelytried to attack such authoritiesas Aristotle
or Priscian in favour of Zero or Stoicism.
99is not a work
For these reasons I consider the " Positiones
nostrae
by
a real nominalist, but a record of a school exercise in which one was
demanded to prove nonsenses, including those which were supposed
to be of the notoriousnominales.
The term 'positio3does not mean there
a positive assertion,but an assumption to be taken as true only in the
course of the exercise. The termis used in such sense in 13th-century
'
3
J
literature.
writings,thus positiofalsi or 'positioimpossibilisin obligatio27See n. 13 above.
28See theintroduction
to theedition(cf.n. 6 above),vii.
106

09:11:17 AM

5. The 13th-century
nominalesin theology
Among the 12th-centurylogic-schoolsthe names of 'nominales'and
'Porretani'
survived the next century.But it is in theologyratherthan
in logic that sources fromthe centurymention their names.
In the sphere of logic, neithernominales
nor Porretani
are known to
have been active in the 13th-century,unless the anonymous author of
the {(Positionesnostrae"(#60) had been a real nominalis.Two more
'
logic textsmentionnominalestheories( #58-59). But none of them are
supportedby 12th-centuryreliable sources. Or rathertheyare simply
false. For instance,the source #59 attributesto nominales
the thesis"ex
not
", but this is a theoryof Parvipontani,29
impossibili
quidlibetsequitur
of nominales.One may say that 13th-centurypeople were ready to
attributeany such eccentrictheories to nominales.
In the sphere of theologysources began to mention nominalesand
Porretaniin the last decades of the 12th-century(seil, sources after
#29), that is to say after the disappearance of the logic-schools.
Abelard and Gilbert of Poitiers, the foundersof those schools, were
influentialbut notorious theologians. They were known to have been
condemned at councils.
Very few 13th-centurymanuscripts are extant for Abelard' s
works,30while rathermany forGilbert's. It suggeststhat 13th-century
people had littleinterestin Abelard' s works,while Gilbert's continued
to be copied and read. It was possible to referto Porretani'
s doctrine,
3
'
directlyaddressing Gilbert's works. Porretanusin singular came to
referby itselfto Gilbert of Poitiers (#54b, 62a, 63, 66d); and 'Por' in
retani
plural simplymeant thosewho followedGilbert in thisor that
'
'
theory.31But the relation between nominalesand Abelard's doctrine
was not so straightforward.His teachings were transmittedthrough
several channels, more or less inexactly.
Abelard asserts that God always knows, wills, or can do what he
once knows, wills, or can do.32 His successors in logic, the 12th, reformulatedthis idea into a formirrelevantto the
centurynominales

29See Iwakuma[1992a],1.
30SeeJ. Barrow/Ch.
Burnett/D.
Luscombe1984-1985.
31Albert
theGreatreports
thatsomeofhiscontemporaries
Gilbert
hadnot
thought
*and 'Porretani
' in #62b.
erred(#62c).Cf. alsoAlbert'susageof 'Porretanus
32See hisIntroductio
adtheologiam,
orthelongerversion
oftheTheologia
"Scholarium",
PL 191,col. 1103Aand 1104A.
107

09:11:17 AM

divine nature, viz. 'quicquid semelest verum


, semperest verum'.33In
Peter
Lombard
adopted Abelard' s theory
theology,on the otherhand,
in his Sentences (I, dist. 41, c. 3 and dist. 44, c. 2); and in his solution
he touched on the immutabilityof the object of faithacross time (I,
"
dist. 41, c. 3). This was one of the roots of theologicalnominalism".
NeitherAbelard nor Peter Lombard explicitlysay what are the objects
of the immutable divine knowledge,will, and volition,or what are the
articlesof faithcommon to Christiansand the Patriarchs.Theologians
in the thirdquarter of the 12th-centurydeveloped several theoriesto
explain the immutabilityof the divine knowledge, etc., or the com.34It was after
monness of the faith;but theynever referredto nominales
the last decades of the centurythat theologians began to associate a
thesis,or to remark
semper
type of the theorieswiththe nominales'semelin these respects( #29, 44a,
thatPeter Lombard speaks as ifa nominalis
44e, 4635, 48b, 50a-b, 51a, 52d, 51f).
Another root of the theological nominalism is in the question
whethervoluntasand actusare the same sin or not, which Peter Lombard does not definitelyanswer in his Sentences (II, dist. 42, c. 1). As
is well-known, Abelard argues in his Ethica that the sin is par
excellence in voluntasratherthan in actus. In the thirdquarter of the
12th-centurysome theologiansassertedthattheyare the same sin, and
used to referto the unitas-nominis
theoryas an analogy, viz. according
to them, voluntasand actus, though differentin themselves, are the
same sin, just as 'albus' 'alba' 'album',though differentin themselves,
are the same noun.36 They would not have mentioned the unitasnoministheoryif it had not been widely accepted by logic-schools in
their day. In the early 13th-century,however, theologians began to
ascribe the same-sin theoryfalselyto Abelard,37and consequentlythe
33Salisbury,
and Neckm,
Nat.rerum
to
III-32,200.22-201.3
, c. 173,refer
Metalog.
thosewhoheldthethesis.
nominales
Theyareundoubtedly
(see #46a,50a-b,51a,52d,
62d,70).
34See relevant
andBandinus,
passagesofUdo,SimonofTournai,PeterofPoitiers,
all citedin A. Landgraf
1943,199-204.
35In ourlist,we date #46to 1206/10,
G. Lacombe,La vieetlesoeuvres
de
following
Prvostin
to Landgraf
, Kain 1927,181.Butitshouldbe datedto 1188/94,
according
1973,154.
36SeeJ. Varichez(ed.), LesDisputationes
deSimon
deTournai
, Louvain1932,Disp.
II c. 14(PL 211,
59,Q.4 (169),andDisp.93,Q.3 (270);PeterofPoitiers,
Sententiae,
col. 989C7).Bandinusin hisSententiae
col. 1068D),mentions
, II Dist.42
192,
(PL
the"unitas-verbi",
of 'amo'and 'amas' Cf. alsoa passageofUdo's
or thesameness
on PeterLombard'sSententiae
, citedin Landgraf
1943,201f.
commentary
37See thepassageofPeterofCapua's Summa
citedin Landgraf
1943,202,n. 81.
108

09:11:17 AM

same-sin theory togetherwith the unitas-nominis


theory to nominales
that
the
unitas-nominis
#
It
is
also
noticeable
theorywas
( 48a, 52c, 54a).
thesis until
never mentioned in the same contextsas the semel-semper
Bonaventuredid so ( #64a). The formertheorywas never taken as the
basis of the latteruntil the mid-13th-century.
The thirdroot of the theological nominalism is in the 12th-century
9 thesis "nihil cresci' The thesis
nominales
played a role in Trinityin
and
after
decades
before
1200
theory
(#40b, 48c, cf. etiam 33a-b,
' retained the
'nominales
38
And
the
label
48d, 53, 70).
very
lastly,
memoryof the nominalisti view on universalis,though in the inexact
"
formula"universais are nomina
(#40a, 44c-d, 60, 70, cf. etiam 61).
These are all that 13th-century people understood as
thesis associated with a type
"nominalism", viz. (1) the semel-semper
of theoryto explain the immutabilityof God's knowledge, etc. (2) the
unitas-nominis
theoryassociated withthe same-sin theory,(3) the thesis
"nihil cresci', and (4) the nominalistic view on universais. Some of
them are genuine theses of the 12th-centurynominales
, but some are
not. And the other aspects of the whole systemof logic developed by
the 12th-century nominaleswere forgotten. Some 13th-century
theologians tried to defend the nominalisticviews, particularlythose
Some even professedto be
Sententiarum.
supposed to be of the magister
as Peter of Capua did ( #44c). But theirnominalismwas connominales
siderably differentfrom that of the 12th-centuryoriginal one. The
nominalism was taken as such during the 13th-century,and became
the basis of the furtherdevelopment in the next century.
Fukui, Japan
Fukui Prefectural
University
38According
likesubstantia
doesnot
nature
to #40b,thethesis
meansthata universal
areinterrogated
a persona
likePeterdoes;andnatures
by 'quid',while
grow,although
between'quid'and 'quis'can be tracedbackto
by 'quis'."Thisdistinction
personae
" and "Nostrorum
sociorum"
Abelard'
s Logica Ingredientibus
(36.23-26and
petitioni
between'aliud'and 'alius'
ed. Geyer).Cf.alsothesametypeofdistinction
537.26-33
in hisDial. 549.16-18.

109

09:11:17 AM

Vivarium
XXX, 1 (1992)
The Logic of the Nominales,
or, The Rise and Fall of ImpossiblePositio
CHRISTOPHER J. MARTIN

1
Introduction
The twelfthcenturyNominaleswere withoutdoubt the followersof
Peter Abaelard and they were probably so called on account of their
theoryof universais. As my witnessI call the Archpoetwho on a Sabbath nightprobably in 1164 or 1165 had a vision of heaven where, he
tells us:
vidinecHomerum,
Hie necAristotilem
et rerum,
nominum
tarnen
de sententiis
de naturis
atquespecierum
generum
verum.
Augustinus
magnusmihiprotulit
Posthecad archan
gelmloquensMichaelem,
qui regitperangelospopulumfidelem,
ut secretaceiem,
ab eo summonitus,
neminirevelem.2
et celiConsilia
Though Bonaventure's account of how theNominalesgot theirname
is surelya red herring,3the Nominalesdo seem to have maintained the
unityof propositionalcontentsin the face of variationsin tense. What
we know of their views suggests, indeed, a simpler reason for their
name than that offeredby Bonaventure. They apparently held that
accusative infinitiveconstructionsmay serve as names for what is
signified by the corresponding propositional tokens. These
nominalizations are called 'quasi-names' by Abaelard.
I thinkthat we are safest,however, ifwe followthe Archpoet since
as far as we know he had no philosophical axe to grind. Chenu' s
association of the Nominaleswith the realist Bernard of Chartres is
entirelyuntenable.
1 Thisisanextract
a muchlonger
from
paperofthesametitle.In ordertosavespace
inPart2, and
withPart1,condensed
theargument
I havedoneawayalmostentirely
I hopeat sometime
inthefootnotes.
references
allbutthebaresttextual
suppressed
to publishthepaperin itsentirety.
2 Heinrich
desArchipoeta
Die Gedichte
1958,TextV, p. 62.
, Heidelberg
Krefeld,
3 Listoftexts,64a.
110

09:11:24 AM

Just like today's anti-realistsAbaelard derived conclusions about


entailmentand argumentfromontologyand philosophical semantics.
Where today's anti-realistsare intuitionists,however, Abaelard and
the Nominaleswere connexivists. Connexive logic has as its leading
idea that 4no propositionshould implyor be implied by its own negaand is
tion'.4 Since halfof this principle is found in the PriorAnalytics
, it was bound to be acknowledged
Hypothetico
reportedin de Syllogismo
in some form by all dialecticians. Abaelard held that the most
peculiarlyproperprincipleof Nominalist logic followedfromthe basic
connexive principle.This is the claim thatconditionalswhose antecedent and consequent differin quality are false. To understand the
character of Nominalist logic it is thus necessary to understand the
nature of Abaelard' s support for connexivism and in particular why
he advocates this account of the conditional.
Abaelard' s connexivism ultimately rests upon an ontology of
individual formsand I so will begin with a very brief survey of this
and its relationshipto his theoryof language. The main part of the
paper explores Abaelard' s theoryof logical relations and its application by the Nominales.In particularI propose that theywere probably
the inventorsofpositioand thattheyrediscoveredthe Liar. I conclude
witha discussion of two paradoxical claims made by his followersbut
not by Abaelard and some suggestions about the later historyof the
logic of the Nominales.
A VeryBriefSummary
1. Abaelard'
s Ontology:
The mediaeval problem of genus and species is not the same as the
modern problem of universais. Mediaeval discussions concern a very
limited range of predicates and have three distinct aspects,
, on the other
ontological,epistomologicaland semantical. We moderni
hand, tend to be generous with respect to candidate predicates but to
limitourselvesmainly to questions of ontology.A crucial differenceis
that two mediaevals might both have radically individualistic
ontologies, or even the same ontology, but yet offerquite different
resolutionsof the problem of universais. Their differentaccounts of
predicationcould easily allow each to abuse the other as a proponent
rerum.
of the sententia
or sententia
nominum
4 See A.R. Anderson
& N. Belnap,Entailment
, vol.1,29.8,'Connexive
implication',
p. 438.
Ill

09:11:24 AM

That said, it is Abaelars ontologyto which we must look ifwe are


to understand his account of the conditional. I propose that he may
be characterisedin contemporaryterms as a transferabletrope antirealist. Abaelard as I read him thus offersan account of substance and
nature like that recentlyfound in Metaphysics
Zeta by Frede and Pat, however, Abaelard is
zig. Perhaps unlike Aristotlein the Metaphysics
also committedto individual accidental forms.To Socrates*individual
whiteness, for example and Sophroniscus' individual paternitywith
respect to Socrates. These forms cannot exist apart from the
substances to which theynow adhere but beforetheirattachmentthey
mighthave gone elsewhere. Unlike Ockham, Abaelars anti-realism
does not extend to a radical or even moderate reductionof thevarieties
of forms.
For Abaelard' s theoryof the conditional what is cruciallyimportant
is the differencebetween what I will call external
and internal
relationships
structure.External relationships hold between distinct existents.
Between substances, for example or between a substance and its
accidents. The strongestconnection that can hold in this case is that
A is strictlyinseparable fromB if it
of what I call strictinseparability.
is impossible forA to exist and B not to exist at the same time. The
internalstructureof an existenton the otherhand consistsof the relations which hold in virtue of its being the kind of thingthat it is. The
relations, forexample, between a kind of substance and its material
essence, or between the various substantial formsthat constitutethis
essence. According to Abaelard the connectioncharacteristicof internal structureis that of what I call conceptual
: A is concepinseparability
tually inseparable fromB just in case being A requires being B in the
sense that being B is part of the meaning of 'A'
Abaelard insists that in imposing the name 'man' on a particular
existentthe original impositormay have no notion at all of its internal
structure. In doing so, however, he is in effect stipulating that
speakersof his language will call a man whateverhas an internalstructure exactly resemblingthat of the sample. It is assumed, of course,
that we can recogniseothermen as exactlyresemblingeven ifwe cannot give an account of theirinternalstructure.According to Abaelard
the act of original impositiongives the word 'man' its sense. Justwhat
the sense is is something which the philosophical logician must
discover and which he does, according to Abaelard, by cooperating
with the natural scientist.It is crucial fora dialectician to discover the
sense of words since otherwisehe will be at a loss to distinguishtruth
112

09:11:24 AM

fromfalsehood and so a sound argument from an unsound one. In


particularhe will not be able to recognise a true conditional when he
sees it or to prove that it is true, since what is required for the truth
of a conditional,according to Abaelard, is thatthe sense of the antecedent contain the sense of the consequent.
Furthermore,and importantly,Abaelard maintains that proper
names have a sense. When Sophroniscus chose a name forhis son, the
child still had to acquire most of those featureswhich we know and
love. The baby was neitherbald nor pot-belliedand thoughhe probably had a snub nose, he mightnot have had one. The name 'Socrates'
was introducedby Sophroniscus solely to designate a particular man,
and it has forits sense just the sense of 'man'. 'If Socrates is Socrates,
then Socrates is a man' is thus a true conditional.
The late antique theoryof consequences as it appears in the account
of the conditionaland the topics presentedby Boethius is an attempt
to characterise the various internal and external relations of
substances. Abaelard' s reconstructionof it is absolutely remarkable.
The ancienttheory,however,was a theoryof the relationshipbetween
of simple predicates,which Boethius characterisesas res,
the significata
rerum.Its concern
or sometimes,like Priscian, as essentiaor existentia
rerum
was to establish consequentiae
, the relationships between the
predicatesor the formsin virtueofwhichsomethingis, say, a man and
able to laugh. There is no notion of propositionalcontentavailable for
the theory and so no suggestion that the relationships in virtue of
which conditionals are true are relationships between contents, or
affairs.The logic of such a theoryis quite properlyconnexstates-ofive: it followsimmediatelyfromthe principle of non-contrarietythat
a contrarycannot be a consequence of its contrary.Abaelard on the
other hand insists that conditionals are true in virtue of relations
between propositionalcontents.
2. Abaelardand theLogic of Propositions
Abaelard is famous for his insistence that the ultimate bearers of
truthand falsityare not propositional tokens nor the understandings
constitutedin our minds when we hear themutteredbut rathera quite
different
kind of item. It seems to me that these items, what it is that
propositionssignifyin virtueof theirbeing used to assert something,
are what we would now call states-of-affairs.
On this account of propositional meaning a non-quantifiedaffir113

09:11:24 AM

mative categorical proposition and the correspondingmental token


and are true if that state-of-affairs
is
signifya positive state-of-affairs
a nonthe case, that is iftheworld is as it is said to be. Mutatismutandis
In
quantifiednegative propositionsignifiesa negative state-of-affairs.
theDialcticaAbaelard preemptsBoethius' terminologyand uses ' essen' to
rei as well as ' essentiaand existentia
tia rei and ' existentia
rerum
designate what is signifiedby affirmativepropositions.He introduces
' non-existentia
rei!rerum1
for as it were' the things subject to negative
In
the
and the glosses on de TopicisDifferen
Ingredientibus
propositions.
tiis he calls the same items dicta.
rei!rerumor dicta as the bearers of truth and
To referto existentia
it
if
misleads
implies any suggestionof a furtheritem in virtue
falsity
of some relationshipto which theybear the truth-valuesthat theydo.
are ratherwhat we would now call truth-makers,and
These existentiae
when he is discussing Cat. 10 on what ' underlies' affirmationand
negation it is clear thatthisis how Abaelard thinksof them. He follows
rei!rerum
and nonexistentia
not as true
Aristotleand speaks of existentia
or false but as being or not being.5
This is all well and good and as transferabletrope anti-realist
Abaelard seems bound to introduce states-of-affairs
in addition to
substances and their accidental forms. It just will not do to
characterisethe world as consistingof this man and that man, of this
whiteness and that whiteness. It remains to be said where the
whitenessesbelong since it is not of their nature to be attached to a
particularsubstance. The moral of the argumentis generallytaken to
be that states-of-affairs
have to be introduced into the ontology.
Abaelard famouslyargues forjust the opposite conclusion. For him
existentiae
are not res since they are neither substances or
rei/rerum
forms.They are, however, what it is that have logical propertiesand
stand in logical relations; they are necessary, possible, logically
opposed to one another, entail one another and so on. The need to
ground logical relations is, indeed, a major argumentforintroducing
of propositions.The othercandidates are
them as one of the significata
for the most part transitoryand certainlydo not have the necessary
connection required for the truthof conditionals.
What Abaelard has hitupon is the concept of propositionalcontent.
At the same time he seems to be the firstmediaeval to give clear
account of the concept of a propositional operation. That is of an
5 LI, 275; compareDial, p. 293.
114

09:11:24 AM

operation forformingpropositionalcontentsfrompropositionalcontents. For example forformingfromthe contentsof the propositions


'Socrates is a man' and of 'Socrates is an ass* each of which says one
thing about the world the content of 'if Socrates is a man, then
Socrates is an ass' and of 'Socrates is a man and Socrates is not an ass',
each of which,Abaelard maintains, also says only one thingabout the
world.
In one sense there are exactly as many truthsas there are truth
as thereare states-ofmakers, since thereare as many states-of-affairs
as
of
these
as
there
are
nominalized
and
affairs,
proposimany
just
tions. But in another sense we may ask a question which Abaelard
would presumably have rejected as ill-formed:How many kinds of
are there?Abaelard himselfexplicitlyrecognisesaffirstates-of-affairs
and also consequences. Disjuncmative and negative states-of-affairs
to the former.
tions reduce to the latterand particularstates-of-affairs
Beyond thishe is perhaps committedto modal and temporal states-ofaffairsbut not, I think,to general states-of-affairs.
Abaelard shows great care in settingout the theory of existentiae
or dictaand, in particular, in discussing sameness of content
rei!rerum
in the face of differencein tense when dealing with divine knowledge
in the Theologia'Scholarium'.6We must thus treat with caution the
reportsfromSt. Bonaventure and St Thomas that the Nominalesdealt
with this problem by claiming that differentenuntiabiliasignifythe
same res.
Abaelard insiststhatfora conditionalto be truethe antecedentmust
be inseparable fromthe consequent in the sense that it is impossible
forthe antecedentto be truewhen the consequent is false. This condition of strictinseparabilityis not sufficient,however, to capture the
relation of consequence, or entailment, between states-of-affairs.
Indeed Abaelard claims that it does not even express a genuinely
hypotheticalconnection but is rather entirelycategorical. He notes
that if it were accepted as necessary and sufficient,then anything
would followfroman impossibility.
The conditionthatAbaelard proposes as necessaryand sufficient
for
the truthof a conditionalis that the antecedentrequires
the consequent
in that the sense of the antecedentcontainsthat of the consequent, the
antecedent is thus conceptually inseparable from the consequent.
Abaelard maintainsthatthisconditionis satisfiedparadigmaticallyby
6 TSch
, III.61.
115

09:11:24 AM

the conditionalisations of the moods of the categorical and


entailment
in the sense
hypotheticalsyllogism.Each of these is a perfect
that in virtue of its complexio,
or form,it is clear that fromthe truth
of the antecedentthe truthof the consequence follows.Like Aristotle,
Abaelard has nothing mor to say on this point. There can be no
appeal to reason against someone who will not concede the truthof
such conditionals. As an alternative characterisation of perfect
entailmentsAbaelard proposes they obey the principle that uniform
substitutionpreserves consecution.
Abaelard claims that the connectionbetween antecedentand consequent is the same forall the figuresof both varietiesof syllogism.The
differencebetween the firstand the otherfiguresis one of evidentness.
The less evident secondary figuresmay be shown to be valid by conversion to the firstfigure.
In satisfying the condition of uniform substitutabilityperfect
entailmentsdifferfrom imperfect
In these the sense of the
entailments.
antecedent does indeed contain that of the consequent, but it does so
in virtue of a topical relationship. Consecution is preserved in such
cases only by the substitutionof terms the subject things of which
stand in the appropriate topical relationship.
More to the point, Abaelard claims that conditionals true in virtue
of a topical connection may be proved to someone who is in doubt
about them. Indeed in the Dialctica the theory of the topics is
presentedalmost entirelyas an apparatus forproving conditionals. It
seems to followthat conditionals true on the basis of a topical connection have the status of what we would now call analytic a posteriori
truths.Thus to prove 'if something is a man, then it is an animal':
1. Of whatever a species is predicated so is its genus, 2. man' is a
species of 'animal'; therefore3. if somethingis a man, then it is an
animal. 1. is the maximal proposition of the argument and so an a
prioritruth. 2. is a truthabout a relationshipbetween words established by the original impositor, although he may well not have
realised that it holds- suppose a man was not one of his paradigms for
'animal' . The cooperation ofphysiciand dialectici
would thenhave been
that
to
discover
the
necessary
topical relationshipholds and what they
if
would have discovered is, anythingis, an analytic truth.
Though Abaelard maintains thatthe paradigms of trueconditionals
are conditionalised syllogisms,he refusesin general to allow that an
argument is good if and only if the correspondingconditional is true.
He realises that all that is needed for a good argument is that its
116

09:11:24 AM

premissesare true and that it is impossible forthem to be so without


the conclusion also being true. Thus the strictinseparabilityrejected
forthe truthof a conditional is just what is wanted for
as insufficient
thevalidityofan argument.It followsthatAbaelard cannot allow conditionalisation as a means for generating true conditionals. Many
topics, for example, will warrant a truth-preservingmove from
premissesto conclusionbut will not provide an entailment.Abaelard' s
refusalto grantconditionalisationamazed John of Salisbury but was
accepted at least by implicationby the author of the SummaDialctica
Artis1and ought to be a characteristicfeatureof Nominalist logic.
Another and related characteristic is recorded as an error
.8 Abaelard insists that no locus is needed to support a
Nominalium'
or
syllogism to guarantee the correspondingconditional. A syllogistic
inferencemay be set out in a general rule but such a rule is not a maximal proposition. The principle that uniform substitutionpreserves
consecutionrequires no particularrelationshipbetween substituands,
but that it mention such a topical relationshipis one of the defining
featuresof a maximal proposition. The problem here forAbaelard is
thatBoethius characterisesde TopicisDifferentiisas an investigationof
whichloci are suited to syllogisms.The best thatAbaelard can do with
thisis to propose that Boethius had in mind that one of the premisses
of a syllogism might be construed as assigning a locus for the
enthymeme formed from the other and the conclusion. But as he
points out the maximal propositionsappealed to in this case will not
in general support containmentof sense.
Abaelard insists that entailment, or consequence, holds between
states-of-affairs.
In an extremelyimportantbut dense and rathercorrupt section of the Dialcticahe presentsa series of argumentsagainst
those who would construelogical relations as holding between things
signifiedby the termsappearing in true conditionals. The occasion for
the discussion is the need to clarifythe rules for the manipulation of
conditionals. In particular Abaelard proposes that it does not follow
from the fact that a conditional expresses a consequence that if its
antecedent is destroyed,then its consequent is destroyed. In opposition he brings forwardsomeone who I will cadi a termist.
The termist
points to examples such as sickness and health which are related by
7 Guglielmo
VescovaDi Lucca,Summa
Artis
Dialecta
, LorenzoPozzi(ed.), Padua
1975.
8 Listoftexts,20.
117

09:11:24 AM

immediate opposition. They are exclusive and exhaustive alternatives


forthe class of subjects of which theyhold. Boethius maintains that a
conditional of the form 'if it's not A, then it's B' holds only if A and
B are immediate opposites. For such conditionals,then, it is true that
ifthe antecedentdestroyed,the consequent is also destroyed,i.e. ifit's
A, then it's not B'.
In response Abaelard claims that this featureof immediate opposition is not relevant to the concepts of antecedent and consequent
deployed in the rules forthe manipulationof conditionals. The termist
wants to account forthe relationshipof consequence by appealing only
to the nature and properties of things as set out canonically in
Boethius' account of the topics. Abaelard insistsagainst him that the
connection should be understood less narrowlyin terms of the relaIf he is rightto claim thatthereare contionsbetween states-of-affairs.
states-of-affairs
which cannot be reduced to a relabetween
sequences
this
not merely be a matter of
between
will
tionship
things,
In
Abaelard
maintains
thatthetermistwill be
redescription. particular
embarrassinglyat a loss to give an account of certain consequences
with impossible antecedents. To account for conditionals with such
antecedentsis one of the major problemsoflater twelfthcenturylogic.
They are not, however, the only problem for the termist.Abaelard
challenges him to find a connection between the termsof the antecedent and consequent to account for the truthof the followingconditionals: (CI) if every animal is a stone, then some stone is a stone;
(C2) if Socrates is Brunellus (i.e. Brunellus the ass), then Socrates is
a man; (C3) if Socrates is an animal, then Socrates is a man.
Let us consider C2. It is embarrassing to the termist,since:
ofBrunellus
andmaninthesecondconsequence
... ifweattend
totheopposition
ofonerequires
thepredication
ofother.9
howcanwegrantthatthepredication
Indeed the termist,followingBoethius' account of the dialectical
loci, ought, if anything, to maintain its contrary: 'if Socrates is
Brunellus, then Socrates is not a man'. Appealing to the maximal
propositionforopposites thatifone of a pair of opposites is predicated
of something,its opposite is removed.
Abaelards proof of C2:
C2.1
C2.2

If Socrates is Brunellus, then Socrates is Brunellus,


if Socrates is Brunellus, then Brunellus is Socrates,

9 Dial., 293.
118

09:11:24 AM

C2.3 . ' if Socrates is Brunellus, then Socrates is Brunellus and


Brunellus is Socrates.
if Socrates is Brunellus and Brunellus is Socrates, then
C2.4
Socrates is Socrates,
if Socrates is Socrates, then Socrates is a man,
C2.5
if Socrates is Brunellus, then Socrates is a man.
C2.6
According to Abaelard, termiststry to avoid embarrassment in
three ways the firsttwo of which present themselves as complaints
about the 'dissimilarityof the middle' and so the improprietyof the
appeal to the transitivityof entailment.10
Is Unsound
[A] TheArgument
Those objecting in this way insist, in effect, that considered
independentlyof the argument, C2.5 is true in virtue of Socrates
being essentiallya man. Abaelard agrees with them. They go on to
claim, however, that since the supposition made in the antecedent of
C2.1 is incompatiblewith Socrates' being a man, C2.5 as it appears
in the argument is false. Abaelard argues to the contrary that
'Socrates', 'Brunellus', and 'man' have the same sense throughout
and that C2.5 would only be threatenedby a categorical assumption
thatSocrates is Brunellus. He furtherargues thatthe position adopted
by thesetermistsis incoherentsince theyclaim that fromthe supposition thatSocrates is Brunellus it followsnot that Socrates is a man but
that he is an ass. But as Abaelard points out this entailmentis on aill
fourswith the one which they reject. He generalises the ad hominem:
opponents of this sort offerno coherent account of conditionals with
impossibleantecedents.Abaelard insiststhatsome must be rejectedas
false and others accepted as true but the termisthas no way of nonarbitrarilydistinguishingone sort fromthe other.
Is Valid
[B] The Argument
A second group of termistscontinue to claim thatthe argumentfails
because of the differencein meaning of the putative middle but they
concede thateach of the conditionals is true as it appears in the argument. They maintainthatthe argumentdoes not in factinstantiatethe
10Dial 288-305.
119

09:11:24 AM

proper formulationof the transitivityof entailment, since this must


include a proviso that the terms are construed in the same way.
Against them Abaelard insiststhat (i) the satisfactionof such a clause
can never be read offthe termsof an argument and (ii), once again,
the senses of the termsin theseargumentsdo not vary fromone occurrence to the next. His point is, I think,that the sense of expressions
are constructed4by addition' fromthose of theircomponentsand not
vice versa.
Abaelard goes on to offera number of otherargumentsin the most
importantof which he proves by contraposingthe premissesand conclusion of an argumentwhich theyaccept the soundness of one which
he claims they must reject.
Isn't Embarrassing
[C] The Argument
The last group of termistsclaim to accept the premissesof the argument and its validitybut to findnothingat all embarrassingabout the
conclusion. They maintain thatthe antecedentof C2.1 amounts to the
supposition that being Brunellus is not opposed to being a man.
Abaelard insists that this is not so, and if it were so the argument
would be quite a differentone in which the antecedentof C2.1 would
express an identity.The intentionhere is quite otherwise. Brunellus
is an ass and Socrates is a man and being a man is opposed to being
an ass. Abaelard claims that the only way to avoid embarrassmentis
to adopt his own account of consequence as a relationshipbetween
what it is thatpropositionsassert. In particularhe connectsthe consequent of C2. 1 to the antecedentby appealing not to a topical connection but ratherto a basic principlesof his ontologyand philosophical
semantics:
Forhowcouldthesubstance
ofSocrates
either
as Socrates
be something
elseor
holdofitas Socrates,
ifititself
shouldnotbe whatitis saidtobe and
something
remainunderoneessence.Butifititself
shouldremain
thepeculiar
of
property
Socrates
it is necessary
justas it is locatedwiththename'Socrates',certainly
thatit havethenatureofman.11
The firsttwo responses of the termistshave them maintainingthat
in a union withBrunellus Socrates would not remain a man. Abaelard
has argued thattheycannot have him becoming an ass either.Though
Abaelard thinksit incoherent,a natural thesis for a termistto adopt
11Dial., 302.
120

09:11:24 AM

would thus be that nothingfollowsfroman impossible combination.


Strikinglythis is just the theoryattributesto the Reales in one discussion of the Parvipontanian principle that everythingfollowsfroman
Montane
impossibility.12Furthermore,according to the Introductiones
the
bitter
most
Minores
at
least
,
opponent of
by implication,Alberic,
in
the
combination
Socrates
the Nominales
,13argued that
impossible
would not retain his nature. Here, then, is another, and perhaps the
deepest, reason why the Reales and Nominalesmight have been so
named. In calculatingconsequences the Realesinsistthatone attendto
the res. Abaelard maintains to the contrary,as presumably did the
Nominales
, that what is crucial is names and their imposition.
BeforeI move on to Alberic and the schools, however, let me mention a quite remarkable and previously unnoticed use to which
Abaelard puts his theoryof the conditional. A conditional, he claims,
is true if and only if the sense of the antecedent propositioncontains
that of the consequent. Thus Aristotle's argument for fatalismfrom
division and Boethius' argument from divine foreknowledgefail.
Abaelard' s solutionis thatof Chrysippusthoughwith a quite different
distinctionbetween conditionals. Indeed Abaelard seems to require
for the truthof a conditional what the Peripatetics did, rejectingas
only categorical inseparability the criterion for truth proposed by
Chrysippus. We cannot inferthe necessityof the futurefromdivine
foreknowledgesince:
tobe equalsand
... although
theeventandGod'sprovidence
ofitareconceded
associates< comitantia
> , thereis no necessary
between
themsince
entailment
is understood
in theassertion
neither
oftheother.14
Abaelard' s solution to the argument from division, on the other
hand, is to appeal to a corollaryof the requirementof containment,
the most characteristiclogical thesisof theNominales
, thatconditionals
with antecedent and consequent of differentquality are false. The
premissthatifeverythingis necessary,then nothingoccurs by chance
is just such a conditional.
This is all quite wonderful but trouble is very close at hand.
Abaelard does not prove directlythat opposites cannot be related by
containmentbut rather taking the basic connexive principle as his
12Listoftexts,59.
13Listoftexts,8.
14Dial., 219.
121

09:11:24 AM

axiom forcontainmenthe argues that the contradictoryof thatprinciple followsif we accept a conditional connecting opposites.
The flaw in Abaelard' s marvellous constructionwas eventually
noticed by Alberic. He argued that Abaelard must accept that if
Socrates is a man and not an animal, then Socrates is not an animal,
but if Socrates is not an animal, then Socrates is not a man, and if
Socrates is not a man, then it is not the case that Socrates is a man
and not an animal, so if Socrates is man and not an animal, then it
is not the case that Socrates is a man and not an animal. Alberic's
argumentasks forverylittlein order to obtain its conclusion. A conditional which Abaelard agrees is true, simplification,contraposition
and transitivity.
Another source tells us that 4pressed with this argument Master
Peter conceded it to be necessary' 15And indeed he might since he
himselfhad shown how to block most of the plausible ways of avoiding
it. He is committedto simplification,since he explicitlyaccepts repetition and strengtheningthe antecedent. He also insists, as we have
seen, on transitivityespecially in the face of impossible antecedents.
The obvious principleto give up would be contraposition.Abaelard
holds that the consequence expressed in an imperfectentailment
instantiatesan explanatoryconnectionbetween antecedentand consequent as a law of nature. It is certainlynot unreasonable to maintain
that explanitorinessdoes not survive contraposition.But Abaelard is
in a difficultposition here since, although his support for the contrapositive of a true conditional turns on a proof by reductiowhich
guarantees only strict inseparability, he employs exactly the same
device to derive the secondary from the primary figures of the
syllogism. Lower the status of the contrapositiveand there seems no
reason to accept that any but the primaryfiguressatisfythe containment condition. All well and good, you may say, perhaps we can
finallymake sense of Aristotle'sclaim thatthe primaryfiguresare evident in a way that the others are not. For Abaelard, however, as for
us, all syllogismshold equally in virtue of their form,and he surely
would not have bought the primaryfiguresat the expense of the rest.
MontaneMinores16and the ArsMelidunatell us that
The Introductiones
15In thecommentary
on Boethius'desyll.hyp.in BerlinLat. Fol. 624 quotedby
L.M. de Rijk 1966,1-57esp. 54.
16'Introductiones
Minores1
Montane
, in: L.M.4de Rijk1967II. 2, 9-71,p. 66,correcting
thetextin theobviously
, OxfordDigby174,ff.211necessary
ways;ArsMeliduna'
241,ff.235ra-vb,
quotedin L.M. de Rijk 1967II. 1, 352-3.
122

09:11:24 AM

some people, presumablytheNominales


, responded to the argumentby
in
that
effect,
claiming,
simplificationto the negative conjunct fails
when the conjunctsare of mixed quality, since in such a combination
the negation is 'not so strong' as when it occurs adone. This is a possible response, and it recalls a recentdistinctionbetween negation plus
conjunctionas a cancellationof contentand negation plus conjunction
as explosion of content. It would be difficultfor Abaelard to accept,
however,since he must regard the copulative combination of affirmation and negation as negative if he is to save as paradigms of entailmentthe syllogismsof the firstfigurewithnegative consequents. Furthermore nothing in the argument for simplificationsuggests any
independentreason fordisallowing strengtheningof the antecedentof
a repeated affirmativewith a negative proposition. The cancellation
view of negation would also, of course, require us to give up
simplificationto the affirmativeconjunct, but unfortunatelywe seem
to have been leftwith no record of the view of the Nominaleson this
point.
Had they insistedon it theywould have been well on theirway to
the development of something more like modern connexive logics.
These typicallysave simplificationas a rule of inferenceat the expense
of conditionalsimplificationand the deduction theorem. We do know
that in the face of Alberici argument something like this was
who seem to have rejected simplificationin
advocated by the Porretani
any form. The Montani, followingAlberic, adopted the termistposition criticisedby Abaelard and maintained that what grounds transitivityis a connectionbetween predicates,and that the conditions for
the application of the rule are not satisfiedhere. Two extreme alterand the Parvipontani
. The
natives are representedby the Melidunenses
first maintained that not only does nothing follow from an
impossibility but indeed nothing follows from a falsehood. The
followersof Adam Parvipontanus, on the otherhand, and temporarily
the victorsin the debate, seem to have given up the containmentcondition and embraced the ' paradoxes' of strictimplication.
These alternative accounts of the conditional became available
around about the middle of the twelfthcentury. Not long afterwards
the earliestsurvivingaccount of obligationes
must have been written.It
between
and
distinguishes
possible
impossiblepositio and explicitly
the
of
the
Adamitorum
in thelatter. It was
rejects
application
consequentia
not
a
written
of
Robert
follower
of
Melun and probapresumably
by
bly not by one of Gilbert of Poitiers or Alberic, since there seems to
123

09:11:24 AM

be no restrictionof simplificationnor any suggestionthat transitivity


rests upon a connection between predicates.
That leaves the Nominales
, and one of themis surelythe most plausible candidate forauthor of the TractatiEmmerani,For though theyare
rathergarbled, both the semantical and syntacticalconstraintsplaced
thereupon the notion of followingunder an impossible
positioare those
of Abaelard' s containment conditional.
If the Nominaleswere the inventors of positio, they must also be
leading candidates forthe honour of having rediscoveredthe Liar and
its solution by cassatio.Note, however, that the majorityof evidence
on the early Liar and on cassatioin particularcomes fromthe ObligationesParisienses
, which in view of a referenceto the inapplicabilityof
the consequentia
Nominaliumin a particular argument was presumably
not writtenby one of them.17
There is furtherevidence that at least the TractatusEmmeranusde
was writtenby a Nominalis
. We know froma couple
ImpossibiliPositione
of sources that the Nominalespropounded the paradoxical thesis that
nothinggrowsand fromone source thattheyalso assertedthatnothing
moves. Normore has argued that Abaelard is committedto both of
thesethesesbut ifwe examine his workswe findthathe accepts neither
of them. He certainlyconsiders both claims, but in each case offers
accounts of movement and change to save the appearance.
we finda quite differentstory.The
Turning to the TractatiEmmerani
treatise on impossiblepositiois much occupied with the varieties of
union. It distinguishesas did Abaelard but in an un-Abaelardian way
between essence and person and proposes that there may be a union
of one or of both of these. Obviously the questions of the characterof
the Trinity and the Incarnation are in the background here:
It is to be notedthatsometimes
thereis a unionofessenceonly,sometimes
of
of bothessenceand person.And grantedthat
personsonlyand sometimes
essenceandpersonare thesameand thatonecannotexistwithout
theother,
nevertheless
one of themmayindeedbe understood
without
theother.And
becauseit maybe understood
it maybe positedsinceimpossible
comes
positio
aboutwithrespect
to understanding.
The essenceis thesuppositum
understood
without
formandthepersonis thesuppositum
understood
withform.
Andnote
thatthoseterms
arecalledessential
whichareso predicated
ofa wholeas tobe
ofeachofitsparts,forexample'body','wood'andthelike.Those
predicated
termsarecalledpersonal
whichareso predicated
ofa wholethattheyarenot
of each partof it, forexamplethe term'man' and the term
predicated
'animal'.18
17Martin1992.
18Tractatus
Emmeranus
deimpossibili
, in L.M. de Rijk,SomeThirteenth
positione
Century
Tracts
ontheGame
12 (1974),94-123,120.
, Vivarium,
ofObligation
124

09:11:24 AM

The Tractatusgoes on to note that neuter adjectives are essential


terms, a point earlier made by Abaelard, though he has it that they
denote a nature ratherthan a person. We are then given some rules
for predication. If a union is of essences, then an essential term
predicatedof one of the members must also be predicated of the other
but not so a personal term. Posit the essential union of Socrates and
' must be conceded but not
estidemquodBrunellus
Brunellusand ' Socrates
4SocratesestBrunellus'
. So also, presumably,as Abaelard argues, 1Pater
9
estidemquodFilius but not ' PaterestFilius' For personal union it is just
9but concede
estidemquodBrunellus
the opposite, we must deny ' Socrates
9
'
9
4
' Socrates
estBrunellusand so, presumably, Deus estHomo but not Deus
estidemquod Homo9.
The Tractatus
claims thatamongst formsthereare some, like blackness
and whiteness, which belong to both essences and persons. Others
such as growthand decrease belong only to persons. Though we are
not told so it seems reasonable that we should deny the predicationof
the correspondingpredicates of essences, that is we should deny 'this
body grows' and 'something <aliquid> grows'. But if we deny that
something grows we must grant its opposite: 'nothing grows'. If
'movement' is a formbelongingonly to persons then we will have the
second paradoxical thesis too.
The TractatusEmmeranusis the last text that I know to mention
Abaelard' s logic for the conditional. Towards the end of the twelfth
century a new theory and classification of the conditional was
developed perhaps based on a reading of Book V of the Topics. The
containmentrelationis stillmentionedas characteristicof natural conbesides formaland
ditionals,but theseoftenappear as an afterthought
simple conditionals. They are importantfor Scotus, however, since
just the conceptual separabilitycaptured by the distinctionbetween
the two kinds of necessityacknowledged by Abaelard is required to
locate a formal distinction. Not surprisinglyScotus makes use of
positio.What is curious, however, is that while Ockham has
impossible
nothingto say about natural conditionals beyond claiming that they
are evident to everyone, he does nevertheless recognise impossible
positio.In factthe SummaLogicaeseems to provide the last account of
this obligatioin the middle ages.
Ockham obviouslyhas his doubts about impossible
positioand in conif
there
is
his
of
it
he
use
for the device.
discussion
asks
any
cluding
He grants that there is and claims surprisinglythat it is sometimes
useful for investigatingthe distinctionof things. Perhaps the reason
125

09:11:24 AM

that impossible
positiodisappears afterOckham and so the last trace of
the twelfthcenturyNominalesin the fourteenthwas the realisationthat
talk of evidence to everyone is much too vague to ground the use of
the device. On the otherhand any attemptto provide a special conditional foruse under impossible hypothesesruns the riskof providing
a tool for making the sort of distinctionsthat Abaelard and Scotus
were so fond of but which the great fourteenthcentury Nominalist
abhorred.
Auckland
The University
ofAuckland

126

09:11:24 AM

Vivarium
XXX, 1 (1992)
The School of PeterAbelard Revisited
DAVID LUSCOMBE

My concern in this paper is not withworks of logic associated with


Peter Abelard but withwritingsof a theologicalkind containingmaterial which is similar to that also found in Abelard' s own writings.1
To theseworksof theology,largelycollectionsof sentencesbut also
including some works of biblical commentary,I gave attentionin a
book whichI published in 1969 under the titleTheSchoolofPeterAbelard
and with the sub-title The Influenceof AbelardosTheologyin theEarly
ScholasticPeriod.2After the passage of more than twenty years I
welcome Professor Courtenay's mandatumto me to revisit what I
called, followinga well-establishedconvention,the school. Whetheror
not this school looks any differentnow than it did two decades ago is
one legitimateconcern of this colloquium which seeks to raise new
questions and to explore differentpossibilitiesthan I have previously
made
done. When John of Salisbury, as he tells us in his Metalogicon,
a returnvisitto the Mont Sainte-Genevive afteran absence of twelve
years to see again the contemporariesand pupils of Abelard, he was
disappointed to find that they had not progressed one bit; John's
enquiries revealed nothingthat had not been known earlier.3Perhaps
not in the case of John and the logicians from 1136 to 1148, but my
1 SeeJuliaBarrow,
Part3 ofthis
DavidLuscombe
CharlesBurnett,
1984-5,183-302.
doctrine
abouta fewworkswhichputforward
Checklist
(259-261)givesinformation
ownwritings
aboutAbelard's
Part2 givesinformation
identifiable
as Abelard's;
(240ofAbelardian
3 ('The Diffusion
Writings',
258). See alsoLuscombe1969:chapter
on logicand theology
somedetailsofwritings
byAbelard
inspired
60-102)includes
5 and 10 (143-172,224-260)examine
as wellas ofthosewritten
byhim;chapters
fromAbelard'sschool.
worksoftheology
2 See n. 1 above.
3 'Iucundumitaqueuisumest,ueteresquos reliqueram
et quos adhucdialctica
in montereuisere
cumeis superambiguitatibus
detinebat
socios,conferre
pristinis,
Inuentisuntqui
mutuacommetiremur
utnostrum
invicem
ex collatione
profectum.
Adquaestiones
fuerant
uisisuntprocessisse.
etubi.equeenimad palmum
prstinas
nec propositiunculam
unam adiecerant.
dirimendas,
Quibus urgebantstimulis,
in uno dumtaxat,dedicerant
eisdemet ipsi urgebantur.
Profecerant
modum,
nesciebant.
modestiam
Adeoquidem,ut de reparatione
eorumpossetdesperari',
of K.S.B.
, 11.10,ed. J.B. Hall withtheassistance
Johnof Salisbury,
Metalogicon
CCCM 98, Turnhout
1991,li 83-93.
Keats-Rohan,
127

09:11:34 AM

hope is that a freshreturnvisit to Abelars followersin theologywill


reveal some freshconsiderations.
When consideringthe theologicalliteratureof the twelfthcenturyin
all its diversityand quality, we should remember that the writings
which are either ascribed to Abelard or which contain features
characteristicof his teaching are not especially numerous or very
much copied but theywere remarkablein theircontentsand character
and caused considerable controversy.
We have knowledge, in the firstplace, of Abelard's own books,
in its many successive versions4and his Ethics.5
especially his Theology
Then there are the various collections of sentences. Of prime importance here are the Sentences
called the Sentences
of MasterPeterAbelard
From
time
to
time
been
have
called
the Sentences
(SPA).6
they
ofHermannbecause a certain Hermann names himselfin one version of the
work. But Peter Abelard names himselfin another version.7Clearly
this collection of sentences representsthe teaching given by Abelard
to studentsas reportedor copied, perhaps by some of those students.
This is a well writtenwork; it is far frombeing a set of loose reporta
tiones.
Other collectionsof sentencesalso summarise Abelard's theological
teaching in more or less similar ways to that found in SPA : the short
Sentences
Parisiensesedited
ofSt. Florian( SF) forexample,8 the Sententie
which
I
and
cadi
SPI.9
In thisway we may distinguishthe
by Landgraf
firstcollectionof the Paris Sentences
fromSP2 which is a second collection of Sentences
also reportingAbelard's teaching and found in the
same MS of the Bibliothque nationale, latin 18108. 10
4 TSum
, TSch,Tchr,Tsch.
5 Peter
Abelard's
Ethics
. AnEdition
with
Translation
andNotes
Introduction,
English
byD.E.
OxfordMedievalTexts,Oxford1971.
Luscombe,
6 Mostrecently
editedby S. Buzzetti,
Sententie
Petri
Abelardi
Hermaistri
(Sententie
manni
dellaFacoltdi Letteree Filosofia
dell'Universit
di Milano
), Pubblicazioni
101. Sezionea curadell'Istituto
di StoriadellaFilosofia
3, Florence1983.AlsoPL
178,1695-1758.
7 Buzzetti,
ofauthorship
and suggests
thatone
op. cit.,4-6 explainstheproblem
Hermannus
revisedthetextoftheSentences
ofAbelardandthat,in so doing,
magister
hisnamewherethenameofPetrus
hesubstituted
appearsinonegroupofmanuscript
Constant
Abelard
, in:
copiesofthework.See further
J. Mews,TheSententie
ofPeter
RTAM, 53 (1986),130-84.
8 Sententie
Florianenses
Patristicum
, ed. Heinrich
Ostlender,
XIX, Bonn
Florilegium
1929.
Ed. Arthur
Ecrits
d Abelard.
deI ecole
Textes
indits
, Spicilegium
Landgraf,
theologiques
sacrumLovaniense.
Etudeset documents
14, Louvain1934.
10Ed.J. Trimborn,
DieSententiae,
mis
so,ausderAbaelardschule,
Quoniam
Cologne1962.
128

09:11:34 AM

All the featuresthat are common to these sentence works derive


from Abelard and from Abelard alone. Of especial concern to
Abelardo criticstowards the end of his career was a lost work which
was simplycalled Libersententiarum
Petri(LS). Abelard denied
magisti
was
written
it.
It
taken
into
account
by Bernard of Clairvaux,
having
William of St. Thierry and Thomas of Morigny as theyprepared for
the condemnationof Abelard. Some of the work can be reconstructed
on thebasis of the quotations made fromit by Abelard' s accusers, and
an edition of as much of the textas survivesin thisway was published
11
by Constant Mews in 1986.
Some additional textshave also come to light.In the BritishLibrary
MS, Cotton, Faustina A.X (saec. XII1) there are lengthyloose notes,
written in the margins of an Anglo-Saxon work, which report
Abelardo ethical teachings.12This is not a structuredsentence collection like thoseI have just mentioned,merelya set of reportationes
or jottings. They show an especial interestin the notion that sin is not act
or deed, that forgivenessis not obtained by anythingthat man or the
church does. This writerusefullyamplifies,although in small ways,
what we otherwiseknow mainly fromAbelard' s littlework on Ethics,
the Scitote ipsum.
I showed in my book on The Schoolthat in addition to the narrow
but consistentstream of sentence works which contain neat doses of
Abelard' s own teachings, there also developed another narrow and
less consistent stream of hybrid sentence collections which mixed
togethersentencesof Abelard and teachingsfromthe school of Hugh
of St. Victor.13Leading examples of this currentof writingare the
of Omnebene (SO)15 As
of Roland (SR)1* and the Sentences
Sentences
to
recentlyas 1988 Charles Burnettbrought lightanother such collection, a Summasententiarium
by a certainAlberic who was a monk in the
Veneto.16 His collection is sometimes long-winded. It cites magister
Petrusexplicitlyon seven occasions, and incorporates passages from
11Mews,TheSententie
168-83.
12N.R. Ker,Catalogue
Oxford1957,194-6.
ofManuscripts
containing
Anplo-Saxon,
13TheSchool
Abelard
s Disciples
10('Abelard'
andtheSchool
, especially
ofPeter
chapter
ofSt. Victor',224-60).
14Ed. A.M. Gietl,DieSentenzen
1891.
Rolands
, Freiburg
15Theseareinedited
extracts
wereprinted
inthenotestoGietl's edition
of
although
SR andDr.JuliaBarrow
ofNottingham)
hasprepared
formea fulledi(University
basedon all theknownmanuscripts.
tion,as yetunpublished,
16Ch.S.F.Burnett,
A newtext
Abelard"
Dossier?
, in:AHDL 1988,
forthe"School
ofPeter
7-21.
129

09:11:34 AM

Abelars Theologiaas well as fromSPA. Alberic also includes passages


that correspondto a version of SPA that has not so far come to light.
This means, incidentally,that Alberic's Summahas now to be taken
into account in constructingthe new edition of SPA. Like ill the
writersof all the other sentence works fromAbelard' s school, Alberic
distinguishes sins from acts and from will; and like all the other
followersof Abelard he attaches the propertiesof power, wisdom and
love to the threepersons of the Trinity, Father, Son and Holy Ghost
respectively.
These, then,are some of the textsthathave to be taken into account
both collectivelyand singlywhen, as historiansof medieval thought,
we tryto evaluate the trendsor the tendenciesforwhichAbelard may
be held to have been responsible. We have a recognisable body of
material, large enough to enable comparison and cross-checkingof
contents to take place.
There is a second preliminaryconsiderationthat I wish to propose.
This owes everythingto the work ofJean Jolivetand especially to the
closing pages of his justly celebrated book on the Artsdu langageet
17
thologie.Jolivetargued that Abelard is betterrepresentedas a nonrealist ratherthan as a nominalist, as a dereifier,especially in logic.
However, at the end of his book Jolivet widened the scope of his
enquiry beyond grammar and logic. He suggested that in all his
thought, including his theology and his ethics, Abelard was always
dereifying, always evading res, always evacuating terms of the
thingness which people tended to put into them, always seeing in
words the power to convey meaning flexiblyand variably. This is as
much part of Abelard's effortin the Prologue to his Sic et non, in his
Theologiaand Ethics as it was in his commentaries on the logic of
Boethius. One identical method, one unifiedphilosophyof language,
was employed throughoutAbelard's oeuvre.To this momentJolivet's
is the most dominant and convincing general interpretationof
Abelard' s thought. It still occupies a uniquely importantposition. It
does contain some troublesome spots, as when Joliveton p. 362 goes
beyond his demonstrationof the unityof Abelard' s method and style
to speak of "un systmebien articul". In factAbelard tended to fire
away at almost every possible target. Opportunism and consistency
marched together,but he had diverse inclinationsto try to keep in
17Arts
dulangage
etthologie
chezAblard
mdivale
, Etudesde philosophie
LVII, Paris
to thesecondedition.
1969;secondedition1982.I refer
130

09:11:34 AM

step. On earlier pages (p. 353, p. 354 n. 59) Jolivet described


Abelard' s thoughtas a curious amalgam which preserves,along with
the dereifyingimpulse, elements of Platonism and which recognises
that are real, although beyond time and
relationshipsor habitudines
left
behind
a
number of unresolved issues.
He
language.
With these two preliminariesstated, I would like in the main part
of thispaper to bring togethersome illustrations,taken fromthe various sentencecollectionsassociated with the school of Abelard, of how
Abelardian 'non-realism' was applied withinhis school to a range of
issues belonging to the realm of Christian belief and doctrine. The
common featuresand the common structureas well as contentsof the
sentence collectionsof the school should be kept in mind.
Christian belief, what is needed for salvation, consists of three
things- faith,charityand sacrament.18The sentence collections are
accordingly divided into three parts: first,a section on God, the
Trinityand Christ; then sectionson sacramentsand on ethics. Of the
greatest interest,and also among the best preserved in the manuscripts,are the discussions of God and Trinity,and I shall delay commenting on these until I have considered some other matters more
briefly.These mattersrelateto the redemption,charity,merit,virtue,
vice, sin and the remission of sin. On these mattersAbelard' s main
viewpointsare shared by his school, though oftenwith some loss of
nuance.
Firstthe redemptionand the attackmade by Abelard, as previously
also by Anselm of Canterbury,on the theoryof the devil's right.The
devil had no ius wherebyto hold captive fallenmankind. This view is
: the devil held
prominentin the thirdfragmentof the Libersententiarum
fallenmankindcaptive until the death of Christ but only because God
had permittedhim to do so.19 As Roland writes, ius has its propria
18Tria sunt,ut arbitror,
in quibushumanesalutissummaconsistit,
scilicetfides,
caritaset sacramentum,
S/Mc.l, ed. Buzzetti25; PL 178,1695A.Cf. SF c.l, ed.
Ostlender
146;SR, ed. Gietl1; SO, ed.
1; SPI, ed. Landgraf
3; SP2, ed. Trimborn
Barrow(MunichStaatsbibliothek
Cod. sim.168(= M) p. 151; Naples,Biblioteca
and Mews1.1,//.
NazionaleMS VII C 43 ( = N) io. 1). Also,TSch,ed. Buytaert
11.
ed. Buytaert
1-2;tsch,
19LS Fragment
3, ed. Mews177-8.SPAc. XXIII, ed. Buzzetti
102-3,//.14-37;PL
SF c.30,ed. Osdender14. Also,Abelard,Commentary
onSt.Paul,
178,1730C-31A:
totheRomans,
ed. E.M. Buytaert,
Petri
Abaelardi
1, CCCM II,
opera
Epistle
theologica
Turnhout
henceforth
as Comm.
1969,114-15
(thisworkisabbreviated
Rom.).Likewise
intheologiam
theanonymous
Ecrits
Ysagoge
( = YT) II, ed. Arthur
Landgraf,
thologiques
lard, 156.
Ab
del'cole
131

09:11:34 AM

and the term is not used properly in this context of the


significatio,
power exercised by Satan. Dominiumis the correctterm, the fact of
domination over fallen man, not a rightfullordship.20What ratio,
therefore,needs to be discovered for Christ's incarnation, life and
or opusforeitherthe incarnationor the
death? Was thereany necessitas
crucifixionas a means of redeeming mankind? For God could have
In factGod chose to take
redeemed mankind sola iussioneor soloverbo.21
on a human nature in order to display divine love and wisdom to
mankind tamverboquamexemplo
, the example being an example of obedience even unto death, the verbumbeing preaching and spoken
teaching.22
Moving on to ethics, R. Wielockx has drawn attentionrecentlyto
23These
certain interestingaspects of the Abelardian notion of caritas.
are picked up in the sentencecollectionsin the school. The Ciceronian
and utilewas familiarenough to moralists
distinctionbetween honestum
in the Middle Ages; in definingcaritasas amorhonestus
, and not as
the
utilitatem
sentence
collections
were
caritaspursued propter
,
aliquam
in
a
was set
Christian
followingin the stoic tradition.But amorhonestus
contextas well: caritasis love of God forGod's sake and love of one's
neighbour also but forGod's sake. We should do nothing,whetherit
be eating food, going to sleep or gettingmarried, forany otherreason
than for God's sake. Augustine had writtenof charitythat it has its
climax in and ultimatelyconsists in the enjoyment or fruitioof God
himself.But theAbelardian school distillsout all notion of recompense
or reward. Charityis love of God forGod's sake; it is thereforedefined
simply and strictlyfor what it is, not forwhat it entails.24
A similar comment may be made about Abelardian perspectives
concerning merit and blame. Merit and blame are not conditional
upon human achievement. Merit, forexample, is not attached to the
20SR, ed. Gietl161-2.
21LS fragment
Rom.116.
4, ed. Mews178; Comm.
22LS fragments
6-9,ed. Mews 178-9;SPA c.XXIII, ed. Buzzetti103-5,PL 178.
ed. Osdender15. Cf. Abelard,Comm.
SF
Rom.117-8.
1731A-1732A;
23R. Wielockx,La sentence
De caritate
et la discussion
surl'amour
, in:
scolastique
58 (1982),50-86,334-56;59 (1988),26-45.
Lovanienses,
Ephemerides
Theologicae
24SPAc.I, XXXI, ed. Buzzetti
SF
25-6,139-40,PL 178,1695B-D,1747C-1748A;
C.2,ed. Ostlender
1-2;SPI , ed. Landgraf
5, 48-51;SR ed. Gietl314-22.See also
Abelard,TchrV.51-2,ed. Buytaert
369-70;tsch13-15ed. Buytaert
405; TSchI, 3-8
ed. Buytaert
andMews319-21.Wielockx
note)showsthatAbelardand
(seeprevious
hisfollowers
wereinfluenced
morerecent
thanAugustine,
Dedoctrina
Chrisbywritings
tianaIII. 10.16,CCSL 32, 87. See also YT I, ed. Landgraf
85-91.
132

09:11:34 AM

act of martyrdomor the practiseof fasting.Rather, as SPA say, it consists in the will alone: a good will brings its own reward; merit and
blame are not created by external conduct. This is not only because
meritand blame are independentof the sphere of behaviour external
to the human will- the sphere of acts- but also because the fragility
of creation is such that meritand blame are functionsof divine grace
which enable or disable the human will. But man can himself- using
freewill and reason (with which to choose between good and evil)accept or not accept God's grace.25
The decoupling effectedby Abelard (especially in his Ethics) of the
notion of sin from res is well enough known. Abelard's followers
similarlyremove the notion of sin fromthe sphere of acts and locate
it inwardlyin the mind which knowledgeablyopts forcontemptof the
creator. Sin is distinguishedfromvice, fromall external materiasuch
as temptationor concupiscence. Like Abelard, the school workedhard
to purifythe concept of sin of all non-essential ingredients.26
Likewise the economy of forgivenessis separated fromthe external
spectrumof requirementscomprisingconfession,ecclesiasticalabsolution and satisfaction. Forgiveness by God and the human sigh of
remorse are simultaneous and coincident and inside the mind; an
external frame of requirements is needed but to serve wider
purposes.27
These examples show how Abelard and his school scraped away all
superficialities that may obscure the thinking mind of the
knowledgeable believer. A clear, knowing choice or consent or even
contemptthat is exercised in response to the grace proferred,and to
the perfectionof the goodness displayed, by God is all that ultimately
counts. The place of externalitiesin relationto the workingsof reason,
conscience and understandingwas sharply circumscribed.
Finally I must turnto God about whom it was always necessaryfor
the Abelardians to say at once that God is beyond language. As SPI
, the rules of the arts,
explain, the art of division, the use of vocabula
25LS fragments
15-16,21,ed. Mews180-2,183;SPAc.XXXIV,ed. Buzzetti
153-5;
PL. 178,1754-6;
SF c.27,ed.Ostlender
13;SPI ed. Landgraf
57-60;YTed. Landgraf
91-2.Cf. Abelard,Ethics
on Romans
, ed. Luscombe26-9,48-51;Commentary
, ed.
240-2.
Buytaert
26LS fragment
24-5,ed. Mews183;SPAc.XXXIII, ed. Buzzetti150-1;PL. 178.
106-9.
1753A-D;SPI , ed. Landgraf
55-6; YT, ed. Landgraf
27SPAc.XXXV-XXXVII,ed. Buzzetti
156-63;PL. 178. 1756A-8D;YT, ed. Laned. Luscombe98-127.
dgraf207-16;SR, ed. Gietl243-9.Cf. Abelard,Ethics,
133

09:11:34 AM

are of no help to philosopherswho tryto learn about God.28 This was


in fact like an 'official health warning': the Abelardians did not in
practise prohibit the use of uocabula. The school, like Abelard,
defendeda theoryof transferenceor translationof meaning. Thus, we
continue to use personal names- father,son and spirit- to designate
three persons in the Trinity. Nonetheless, the names of Father, Son
and Spiritsunttranslata
a propriissignificationibus
in order to signifypersons in the Trinity.29Yet the dissimilitudines
that are therebycreated
are not total; the names reflectlimited likenesses: resille, as both the
author ofSP2 and SO write,quarumnominasumuntur
debent
habere
aliquam
cum re ilia ad quam significandam
,30 Thus the
sumuntur
similitudinem
Father is like a fatherwho begets a son fromown being; the Spirit is
like the breathwith which a mothershows her feelingsto her creature.
of God. By the
Nonetheless, such personal names are used improprie
- ifindeed theydid not themtime Abelardo censors had highlighted
in 1139 to 1140 it
selves provide- that adverb in the Libersententiarum
was easy, although wrong, for William of St. Thierry to allege that
Abelard and his supportershad denied three divine persons.31
Several of the compilersof the sentencecollectionsgo to some trouble to reproduce Abelard' s summaries of differingnotions of persona.
In grammar, a person is one who speaks to another, is spoken to by
another, is spoken about. In rhetoric, a person is someone about
whose actions or speech someone else argues or speaks. In Boethius,
a person is substantiarationalis individua.32For all their many
resemblances, it is here on God and the Trinity that Abelardian
sentence collectionsmost display characteristicdifferencesof selection
and emphasis. The SPA , which have a good claim to representthe
actual teaching of Abelard, are in fact the closest of all to being an
28SPI , ed. Landgraf
6-7.CfTSum11.64-74,
andMewsII.546-678;Tchr
ed. Buytaert
IL 1338-1570;TSch11.75-93,
ed. Buytaert
III. 115-30,ed. Buytaert
and MewsIL
1138-1399.
29SP2, ed. Trimborn
176,IL 22-4.Cf. SPAc.XV, ed. Buzzetti73, /.4; PL. 178.
1716D.SO is verysimilartoSP2, ed. Barrow(M p. 163,N fo.27v).
30SP2, ed. Trimborn
creaturae
ilhusinsteadofcumre
176,//.25-7(Trimborn
prints
ilia).SO, loc. cit.
31LS fragment
1, ed. Mews177.
32SPA c.XIII, ed. Buzzetti70-1;PL. 178. 1715D-16C;SFc.lO, ed. Ostlender
5;
SPI , ed. Landgraf
182;SO, ed. Barrow(M pp. 164-5,N
30; SP2, ed. Trimborn
and Mews,II. 1003-59;Tchr
ed. Buytaert
fo.29).Cf. Abelard,TSum11.106-12,
III. 174-81,ed. Buytaert
and MewsII.
II. 2153-2231;TSchII. 104-9,ed. Buytaert
1520-1612.
134

09:11:34 AM

anthologyof quotations fromthe Bible and the Fathers. SP2 , on the


other hand, boldly eschew quotations from the authorities and are
seriously philosophical. What, they ask, does individuamean in
Boethius' definition of a person as substantiarationalisindividua?
Individuummeans that which nonpotestdividi. An atom is individuum
because it is too small to be divided. Steel which is too adamantine to
be fracturedis individuum.Anythingthat is predicable of one thing
only is an individual.33SP2 painstakinglyexamine, in the light of
Boethius' definition,the question of persons in the Trinity: a divine
, because God the Son was joined to man in unam
person is not individua
personamthrough the Incarnation; yet there had not been two
separable persons, God and man, before the Incarnation occurred.
That was one reason forquestioning the use of the noun, person, in
the Trinity.A second reason is that,on Boethius' definitionof person,
there would be not one but three rational substances in one God.34
Why, then, if the word person raises problems when used of the
Trinity, do Christians use it? The sentence collections, even where
theyblend Abelardian with Victorine teachings, are reasonably consistentand persistentin their answer. Person, in the Trinity, means
not substance but property. The distinctionswithin God are not
distinctionsinto threeindividual, rational substances, but distinctions
into threepropertieswhich are power, wisdom and charity.Together
these threepropertiesof power, wisdom and charityconstituteperfec35
tion of being; they constitutethe summumbonum.
Still, the writersof the sentencecollectionsare not contentto let the
matter rest there, having challenged the notion of person in the
Trinity and having reproduced Abelard' s idea that three properties
togetherconstitutethe summumbonum.They also raise, like Abelard,
the question whythereis a Trinity,notjust one undivided permanent
substance. The propertiesof power, wisdom and charityconstitutea
supreme goodness, but why cannot onedivine person be this power,
wisdom and charity?Why threepersons? The answer given is that in
order to persuade men to worshipGod a display of a diversityof pro33SP2, ed. Trimborn
182.Cf. SO, ed. Barrow(M p. 165,N fo.29-29v).
34SP2, ed. Trimborn
182-6;SO, ed. Barrow(M p. 165,N os. 29v-30).
" LS fragment
1,ed. Mews177;SPAc.V, ed. Buzzetti
34-6;PL. 178.1699C-1700D;
SPI , ed. Landgraf
SR, ed. Gietl21-5,46; SO, ed.
7-13;SP2,ed. Trimborn
188-204;
Barrow
Nfos.12-13).Cf.Abelard,
TSum1.2-9,ed. Buytaert
andMews
(A/pp.158-9,
II. 20-97;Tchr
IL 49-101;TSchI. 30-5,ed. Buytaert
andMews
I, 4-7,ed. Buytaert
Ii 336-89.
135

09:11:34 AM

perties is helpful:people will fearGod iftheyperceive his power, they


will love him iftheylearn of his wisdom and experiencehis love. And,
although the sentence collections are not fullyexplicit on this point,
an appreciation of God's propertieswill be easier if each of the three
propertiesis speciallyand properlyassociated withone of threedivine
persons, power withthe Father, wisdom withthe Son and charitywith
the Spirit.36
The problems associated with use of names forGod are verydominant in the sentence collections. They distinguishtwo principal types
of name. On the one hand thereare personal names whichare the particular names of each of threedivine persons: Father, Son and Spirit.
On the other hand, there are natural or substantialnames which are
common names of the essence of God.37 These latterare of two kinds.
One of these is of names secundum
se or ex se: thus when we say God
is immense or omnipotentor just or wise or eternal we apply names
to God's substance. The second kind of natural names of God is of
names which arise in respect of the relationship between God and
creation: examples are just, merciful, creator etc.38 In SPA these
names secundumnos or respectu
creaturarum
are either temporal names
such as creator or lord, or they are eternal names such as provident
or prescient.39However, SP2 are not so easily satisfied.To say that
God is immense and just and eternal is certainlyto use names secundum
se because iftherewas no creation God would stillbe eternal,just and
immense. But these same names are also names secundum
nos: God is
immense respectu
rerumque nonsuntimmense
he
is
eternal
tem,
respectu
40And thisleads SP2 to take the furtherunusual
.
porum
step of qualifying Abelard' s argument that the distinctionsin God are distinctions
between complementary properties. The distinctions between (for
example) God's wisdom, justice and mercy are not distinctions
between differentproperties but distinctions between the diverse
36SPAc.V, ed. Buzzetti
SP2, ed. Trimborn
35-8;PL.178, 1699D-1702A;
188-94;
SO, ed. Barrow(M pp. 158-9,Affos.12-13).Cf.Abelard,TSum1.2-4,ed. Buytaert
andMewsli 21-49;TChr1.4-6,ed. Buytaert,
II. 49-87;TSch.1.28-35,ed. Buytaert
and Mews,II. 324-89.
37SPAc.XIV, XVII, ed. Buzzetti
72, 79-80;PL.178. 1716CD,1720A-B;SP2, ed.
Trimborn
174;YT, ed. Landgraf
258,260,263-4;SR, ed. Gietl43-8;SO,ed. Barrow
(M pp. 163-4,Nos. 27-28v).
38SF C.9,ed. Ostlender
4 ('Quaedamnominacompetunt
Deo ex se, quaedamex
176.
SP2>ed. Trimborn
nobis');
39SP2ted. Trimborn
176.
40SP2, ed. Trimborn
176.
136

09:11:34 AM

intellectus
whichmen formin the lightof theirdiverse reactionsto God
acting wisely,judging justly and forgivingmercifully.41Once again
we see, as in Abelard' s Ethics, the switchfromnouns to adverbs, from
what to how. An effortis made in the school of Abelard to definethe
names of God from both an intrinsicand an extrinsic viewpoint.
Moreover, SP2 find the pluralityof the non-personal names of God
somewhat unnecessary.
Beforeleaving this matterof names, one final point must be made
about the Incarnation. The Incarnation for the Abelardians is not a
union of two persons. Abelard's followersdeny that two natures or
two substances are fused in one person. Divinityjoined to humanity
remains divinityjust as bones joined to flesh remain bones. So it is
improperor figurativeto say, propos of Christ, that God was made
man or was made flesh.42Out of this objection was born the doctrine
usually known as Christological nihilism.43
Nowhere in the Abelardian sentence collections need we expect to
find brand names such as nominalesor Abelardiani. But the
resemblances between the texts of the school and Abelard' s own
writingsspeak louder than any label in favour of the existence of a
distinctiveschool of thoughtwhich was inspired by Abelard himself.
For a while in the twelfthcenturyconsiderable interestwas shown in
Abelard's teachings. This interestdwindled afterthe 1170s or so. The
Victorines and Peter Lombard had by then provided a counterbalance; the condemnation of Abelard in 1140 had identified
troublesome spots. This does not mean that Abelard' s followers
achieved little.To be overtakenis not necessarilyto fail; Abelard and
his school had radically changed the agenda of theological discourse.
Their new agenda was largely about names, as I have tried to show.
As Otto of Freising wrote in his GestaFriderici(I, 47) Abelard had at
the time of his firstcondemnation at Soissons in 1121 appeared to
- whereas the
reduce the persons of the Trinityto vacuanominatantum
churchfaithfully
suisque
taughtthatthe threepersons were resdistinctae
as
Otto
And
Abelard
discretae.
wrote,
had,
incautiously
proprietatibus
41SP2, ed. Trimborn
180.
42SPAc.XXIV ed. Buzzetti106-9;PL 178. 1732-4;SF c.34 ed. Ostlender
16-17;
SPIyed. Landgraf
31-2;SR ed.Gietl172-9;SO,ed. Barrow
(M p. 187-9,C( = Monte
dellaBadiaMS 386) pp. 69B-70B).Cf. Abelard,TSchIII. 74-81,
Cassino,Archivio
ed. Buytaert
andMewsII. 991-1112. YTdoesnotfollow
Abelardinthis,ed. Landgraf
164.
43See Luscombe1969,250-2,272-3.
137

09:11:34 AM

applied the sententiavocumseu nominumto theology.44In 1139-40,


William of St. Thierry complained that Abelard was stillattenuating
the realityof thedivine persons by speakingof theirnominaas impropria
and by focussingon what is significativam
potiusquam realem
Here was a powerful current of theological thought. It was not
called nominalist but it was much concerned with nominal issues.
Sheffield
The University
of Sheffield
44GestaFriderici
1.47,ed. MGH, Scriptores
XX, Hanover1868,376.
imperatoris
thequestionofwhether
Abelardcertainly
theTrinity
consisted
ofa real
regarded
ofpersonas ofgreatconcern
to hiscontemporaries:
'Autenim,inquiunt,
diversity
in solisuocabulisconsistit,
hecdiversitas
nonin re ... autin resolaet
personarum
non in uocabulis,aut simulin re et in uocabulis1,
TSum11.44('primaobiectio
aduersustrinitatem'),
ed. Buytaert
and Mews //.397-401.Cf. TchrIII.90, ed.
II. 1148-51.
Buytaert
45Disputatio
Petrum
PL 180,532A,256D.
adversus
Abaelardum,

138

09:11:34 AM

Vivarium
XXX, 1 (1992)
PeterLombard and Abelard:
The Opinio Nominalium and Divine Transcendence
MARCIA L. COLISH

This paper has a double inspiration. One is my own investigation


of Peter Lombard's doctrine of God, as part of a larger study of his
theology. The second is the discovery, on the part of William J.
Courtenay, following Artur Michael Landgraf, Marie-Dominique
Chenu, and Johannes Schneider, of the factthatthe Lombard appeals
to an argument derived fromthe Nominalesof the early twelfthcentury. Citing this argument, whose earliest expression he traces to
Peter Abelard, Courtenay describes it as "the principal opinio
Nominalium
, namely, that whateverGod at one time knew, willed, or
was able to do, He always knows, wills, or is able to do. By the third
quarter of the twelfthcentury, this theoryhad been reduced to the
axiom: once it is true, it is always true {semelest verum
, semperest
in
Abelardo
stated
As
this
out,
principle,
verum)."1 Courtenay points
a unitary
have
rests
on
the
nouns
idea
that
Theologia"scholarium",
signification,although they also have other consignificationswhen
they are used in propositions that include verbs in differenttenses,
voices, or moods. In the Theologia"scholarium",Abelard uses this
notion to supportone of his most notorious ideas, the claim that God
cannot do better,or other, than He does.2
There is another argument of the Nominales
, mentioned in passing
and Schneider called
to
which
Chenu,
Landgraf,
by Courtenay,3
attentionearlier, a parallel analysis of verbs. According to this view,
a verb signifiestwo things, an action and the time when the action
takes place. A single action is signified,irrespectiveof the time. The
time is only a passing circumstance.It is a consignificationwhich does
not alter the proper significationof the verb. Thus, the nominalist
estverum
maxim, semelestverum
, can be applied just as easily to
, semper
1 Courtenay
"He" inreferring
tothedeityinthisquota1990,46. I havecapitalized
tionforthesakeofconsistency.
2 Ibid.,46-50.
3 Ibid.,46, 56 nn. 8, 12.
139

09:11:47 AM

propositions stating actions as to propositions making statements


about the thingssignifiedby nouns. As these earlier scholars note, the
Lombard makes express referenceto this nominalist argument concerning verbs in his treatment of God's power.4 For his part,
Courtenay adds as well that the Lombard reprises Abelard' s
nominalist argument in his treatmentof God's knowledge. As with
Abelard, Courtenay observes, he uses it to defend God's
immutability.At the same time, the Lombard turns the self-same
argument against Abelard, in attackinghis claim that God cannot do
better or other than He does.5
It is preciselythe Lombard's appeal to this nominalistprinciple of
the semantic unity of nouns and verbs and his concurrent antiAbelardian application of it that I want to address in this paper. At
firstglance this looks like a paradox or inconsistency. But, I will
argue, the Lombard's tacticsare perfectlycomprehensiblein the light
of the doctrine of God which he defends more generally,in the light
of his views on what we can know about the divine nature, and in the
lightof how he sees the functionof the artesin helping us to clarifyour
ideas in so doing. In this connection, what is at issue is not only the
nominalistic understandingof nouns and verbs but also the type of
logic which thisunderstandingaccompanies. As forthe firstpoint, the
Lombard seeks to reclaim forwesternChristian thoughta theologyof
divine transcendence.6In this theology the deity is seen as absolute
being, being as such, the supreme metaphysicalreality.Man, according to Peter, can gain an understanding of this reality through
metaphysicalreasoning. He views the deityas utterlyinexhaustiblein
Himself and as totallyunconditionedand unbounded by His workings
in the creation and man. At the same time, Peter's goal is to dePlatonize the nature of God. For him, God's actions are always free.
They are never constrained,eitherby anythingexternalto Him or by
4 Landgraf
DieLehre
1943,192-4,199;Chenu,1957,93,96,99;Johannes
Schneider,
vomdreieinigen
inderSchule
Gott
desPetrus
Lombardus
, Mnchen1961,43-4,53.
5 Courtenay
1990,53-5.
6 To
oftheLombard's
doctrine
ofGodareErmenegildo
Berdate,thebestaccounts
diDioinPierLombardo
48 (1956),
tola,Il problema
, in:Rivistadifilosofia
neo-scolastica,
followed
diePierLombardo
nelQuattro
135-50;closely
byGuiseppeLorenzi,Lafilosofia
libridelle
Sentenze
4 (1960),24-8.Alsoimportant,
for
, in: PierLombardo,
particularly
hisemphasis
onGodas essence,
areCornelio
deinomi
divini
Fabro,Teologia
accenting
nelLombardo
e inS. Tommaso
4 (1960),79-81;EtienneGilson,
, in: PierLombardo,
Pierre
Lombard
etlesthologies
d'essence
, in: Revuedu moyenge latin,1 (1949),61-4;
Die Lehre
, 25-30,224-6.
Schneider,
140

09:11:47 AM

any internal necessity of His own being. In considering God's


manifestationsof Himself ad extra
, Peter views them as God's effects,
not as emanations or as participationsof the divine being. For this
reason, the Lombard takes sharp exceptionto the theologyof Abelard,
because he sees it as too economic, treating God as knowable
primarilyor exclusivelyin the lightof His action in the cosmological
and charismaticorders. By preciselythe same token, he objects with
equal forceto other economic theologies of the day, be they those of
Hugh of St. Victor, the Chartrains, or Rupert of Deutz.
But, Peter singles out Abelard in particular as his target for two
otherreasons. First,in his own estimation,what Abelard has done has
been to take the eternityof God, which ought to be seen as transcendent, and to collapse it into God's created and time-boundordinance.
And second, the nominalist analysis of nouns, by means of which
Abelard buttresseshis own economic inversionof the Lombard's own
theologicalpriorities,is also articulatedin the contextof a logic that,
in the Lombard's view, is ill adapted to the scrutinyof metaphysical
objects of knowledge, and above adi,the deity. In clarifyingthe Lombard's objections to Abelard' s use of the opinio Nominaliumand in
showinghow he makes his own countervailingapplication of thatsame
principle,it will help to examine the wider frameworkin which both
Abelard and the Lombard develop their arguments.
It was Abelard who made the initial sally here, and he did so in
treating the question of divine providence, foreknowledge, and
predestinationand theirrelationshipto futurecontingents,or, alternatively stated, the relationship between necessity and possibility.
This alternativeis not a matterof mere, idle phraseology.For, the first
and most importantpoint to be made is that Abelard viewed this
whole issue primarilyas a logical, not as a theological, one. He takes
it up, initially,in his early logical works,writtenbeforehe decided to
move on to theology.When he did make that transition,he retained
the logical mode of handling it. This fact is worth noting, in and of
itself.Equally importantis the kind of logic that Abelard draws out
of, or applies to, the Boethian-Aristotelianmaterials which he makes
his point of departure. In this connection, his understandingof the
scope of logic itselfneeds to be recalled, since it affectspowerfullyhis
overall methodand also the kinds of claims he will be able to make for
his logical argumentson thissubject when he transposesthem into his
theological works. Notwithstandingthe fact that he begins by commentingon the Aristoteliantexts available in the Latin school tradi141

09:11:47 AM

tion, Abelard takes from Boethius and sharpens a Stoic-Megaritic


approach to logic bound by its own rules. In his earliestworks,he confirms that, for him, logic is a science of discourse, not a mode of
analysis whose goal is to seek verificationof its conclusions in the
world of nature or in the ontological order. Concepts may, initially,
derive from things. But, once in the mind, they are usable, comprehensible,and meaningfulin propositionalformapart fromthings.
It is the internal structureand relations of the propositionsand the
termsthat comprise them that determinethe truthclaims theymake.
Asserted initially in his commentaries,7these same principles are
developed by Abelard in his own logical treatises,both in his express
statements defining the nature and scope of logic as such8 and,
implicitly,in his reformulationsof syllogisticargumentsdrawn from
his authorities, in which arguments that involve priority and
posteriorityin time, or conditions that are verifiableempirically,are
converted into propositions and syllogisms that display exclusively
logical relations.9The fact that Abelardo logic is not envisioned by
him as capable of establishing any truthbut the intrapropositional
truth of logic itself has received general recognition from modern
students of his philosophy.10The fact that a logic understood as a
science of discourse, not as a science of things,a logic understood as
having jurisdiction only within its own realm and as unable to
establishtruthanywhereelse, would make an imperfectinstrumentof
theological analysis was also noted, in the early 1140s, by disciples of
Gilbert of Poitiers, and held against Abelardo theologicaluse of logic
7 See, forexample,
inCategorias
Editto
PeterAbelard,
; Editio
; Glossae
super
Porphyrum
dilogica
in: PeterAbelard,
Scritti
Aristotelem
deInterpretation,
, 2nded., ed. Mario
super
dal Pra,Firenze1969,3, 61, 84-5,105-6,110-3.
8 LI 17,20-1,28-9,60-1;112-5;307-10,320-2;LNPS,585;Dialctica
, 2.1.1.4,2.28,
153-60,163-4,210-3.
9 Dial. 3.1.4, 4.1.2 ff.,270-309,469-532.
10Dal Pra, intro.to his ed. of PeterAbelard,Scritti
Beoniodi logica
, xxii-xxiii;
tr.SimonPleasance,DorBrocchieri
1974,153-63;TheLogicofAbelard,
Fumagalli,
Philos.
drecht
,
Schriften
1969,13-23,28-36;Geyer,comm.onhised.ofPeterAbelard,
etthologie
chezAbelard
Heft4, 621-33;Jolivet,
, 2nded.,
1977,312-8;Artsdulangage
Paris,1982,19-22,44-5,67-72,74-7,96-104,229-335;Tweedale,1976,93-5,130-7,
: A Critical
TheLogicofDivineLove
185-8,210; RichardE. Weingart,
Analysis
ofthe
areDe Rijk,
dissenters
Oxford1970,11-31.The principal
Abailard,
ofPeter
Soteriologe
xcv-xcviii
andLucia
Dialctica
intro.tohised. ofPeterAbelard,
xl,lv-lix,
, xxiii-xxviii,
" Roma
deintellectibus
deAbelardo
e il "Tractatus
UrbaniUlivi,Lapsicologia
,
1976,85-93,
ofa purely
formal
De Rijkinholding
thattheachievement
95-100,whofollows
logic
arriveat thatdestination.
s goalbutthathe didnotactually
was Abelard'
142

09:11:47 AM

on just that account.11It does inspire Abelard at times to argue that


theological language is metaphorical, or to invoke arguments from
theological appropriateness. But it does not dampen his enthusiasm
for the claim that dialectic, "to which the judgment of all truthor
'
itasubiecta
seufalsitatisdiscretio
falsityis subject' (cui quidemomnisveritatis
of
the
Catholic
faith
used
to
demonstrate
the
should
be
teachings
est)
and to refuteheretics.12
The firsttheological topic to which Abelard gives logic this somewhat ambiguous assignment, on his own accounting of it, is God's
providence and futurecontingents.Abelard takes up this issue forthe
where he indicates, by his very
firsttime in his Logica ((ingredientibus'
address to it, his desire to treatit as a technicaltopic in logic. He urges
that the subject of future contingents be taken out of a temporal
frameworkaltogether.Past, present,and future,to be sure, are conditions that occur in nature. But the problem, he argues, should be
treatedon a purelyconceptual and not on a natural level.13Our concepts, whatevertheir content,exist as if in the present. This report,
fromthe precinctsof logic, is used by Abelard to reinforcethe analogy
between the soul's present memory,
made in Augustine's Confessions
as
attention,and expectation reducible to the soul's presentaction and
the eternityof God, dwelling in the eternal present. But Abelard' s
analysis, unlikeAugustine's, is based on the workingsof logic, not on
those of human psychology.One can, he notes, argue against those
who think that God's providence is undermined by natural contingencyand human freewill, equating God's providencewithuniversal divine determinism.This can be done, he shows, as Augustine had
done it, by distinguishingbetween providence and predestination.As
he reads this distinction, providence is understood as God's
foreknowledgeof what will happen, whether good or bad, whether
caused by God Himself or by the actions of men or other secondary
causes. On the otherhand, predestinationis confinedto God's determination of those thingsHe wills to occur by His own directagency,
specifically the granting of grace to the elect. As with the late
Augustine, Abelard holds that this grace has two aspects. It prepares
11NikolausM. Hring,ed., DieSententie
Gisleberti
Pictavensis
/,2.38magisti
episcopi
Gisleberti
Pictavensis
39, in: AHDL, 45 (1978), 119; idem,ed., Die Sententie
magisti
II: Die Version
derflorentiner
episcopi
Handschrift
, 2.38-39,in: AHDL, 46 (1979),54.
12Dial., 4.1 prologus,
470.
13LI , 26-7.
143

09:11:47 AM

the elect to respond to God's call and it helps them to perseverein it.
Strictlyspeaking, predestinationis the grace of preparation,and it can
be distinguishedfromthe giftthat makes salvation possible once that
initial grace has been received. Since predestinationhas this consequence, we can say that its causative effectis always good. Now God
knows fromall eternitywhich men He will endow with grace. He also
knows which sins men will commit, althoughHe does not cause them.
This Augustinin attack on the question is in no sense the whole
story,forAbelard; nor, in his estimation,is it the most interestingway
to address it. He next introducesBoethius's repriseof the key chapter
where a more strictlyphysical and
in Aristotle's De Interpretationen
of
account
necessity,possibility,and contingencyis provided.
logical
9
of
that
In chapter
work, Aristotleframesthe issue in termsof a sea
battle that may or may not be foughttomorrow.There is always the
possibilitythat the captains may cancel the battle because the rulers
they representhave settledtheir differences.Or, hostilitiesmay still
prevail, but bad weather may prevent the battle from taking place.
The natural or human contingenciesinvolved in these possibilitieslie
within the structureof natural laws and the nature of man. But
whetheror not they will be activated so as to prevent or call offthe
battle is a matterof chance or contingency.With thisanalysis in mind,
Abelard now distinguishesprovidence fromfate. Fate he sees as the
natural necessitiesbuilt into the physical order. Fate is ineluctable in
the sense that, once the relevantphysical laws of cause and effectare
set in motion, the outcomes flowingfromthemwill necessarilyfollow.
God knows that these consequences will occur if these physical laws
are activated, since He created the universe with the natural laws in
question. At the same time, agreeing with Aristotle and Boethius,
Abelard observes that there are areas of contingency and human
choice here which determine whetheror not these natural laws, and
theirconsequences, will be activated in a particularinstance. He adds
that there are also physical events which God permits to happenmiracles, for instance- even though theyoccur outside of the causal
nexus of thelaws of physics.This observationaside, along withAristotle and Boethius, he accents the idea that creatures, as they are
created, possess certain built-in capacities to do or to refrainfrom
doing what theychoose. Giving an Aristotelianexample here, he notes
that a man, by nature, is capable of sittingdown, but whetherhe will
do so at a particular moment is a matterof choice, not necessity,on
his part. The same analysis applies to a man's capacity to sin. The fact
144

09:11:47 AM

thatGod knowshow the man will exercise thiscapacity does not mean
thatGod causes him to sin, just as God does not personallycause the
other outcomes that are effectsof contingencies.
Thus far, Abelard has shiftedan initiallyAugustinin argument
preoccupied with grace and predestinationto an Aristotelian argument forpossibilityand contingencyas compatible witha universe in
whichnaturallaws impose theirown physicalnecessities. He now proceeds to shifthis argumentonce again. Still another way of handling
the problem is to transposeit fromthe realm of necessity,possibility,
and contingencyas theyoperate in the natural order to the realm of
modal propositions.This option is even more attractiveto Abelard,
since, once the subject has been reformulatedin these terms,the propositionsin which theyare framedexpress the ideas of possibilityand
necessityand theirrelationshipsaccording to the formadstructureof
the propositionsused. The conclusions flowingfrom these propositions can be evaluated in termsof whetherthey followlogically from
their antecedentsquite independent of times, places, and conditions
thatmay or may not existin the physicalor metaphysicalorder. From
thisperspective,Abelard now seeks to expose the logical fallacyof the
claim thatGod errs if it can be shown that anythingcan happen in a
way differentfrom the way in which it does happen. The rule he
invokes here is this: if the antecedent is possible, the consequent
attaches the judgment "Yes, it is possible" to the proposition itself,
not to the subject matter or content stated by the antecedent. His
treatmentof this rule is a clear articulation of the strictlylogical
approach to theproblemof possibilityand necessityhe is talkingat this
juncture, an approach which he also advocates as more elegant and
satisfactorythan the ones that he had set forthbefore presentingit.
If one applies this kind of logical analysis to the question of
foreknowledgeand predestination,as defined above, it follows that
propositions admitting of possibility and contingency can be constructedfrompropositionsin which foreknowledgeis asserted. Also,
'
as Abelard points out, it depends on how the word 4' differently'
{aliter)is used in propositionsthathypothesizeon whetherthingscould
have turnedout differently
than the way they do turn out. Alitercan
be used as a relativeterm,and also as a negative term. Its causal force
is strongerin the latterusage. In the formercase, when aliteris used
as a relativeterm,the presenceof logical possibilitycan be entertained
without a contradictionwith foreknowledge,in stating a contingent
claim. The use of hypotheticalsyllogismsto structurethe propositions
145

09:11:47 AM

in question here itselfemphasizes the formal quality of the logical


analysis involved.14
It is perfectlyobvious what Abelard is tryingto accomplish in this
handling of the question of God's foreknowledgeand future con"
tingentsin the Logica ingredientibusIn moving froma theological
account derived fromthe late Augustine to a physicalaccount derived
fromAristotleto a strictlylogical account of the issues, to which he
is guided by Boethius, he places his argumentsin, what is, for him,
an ascending order of importance and persuasiveness. Even though
Abelard gives a far more elaborate treatmentof the De interpretations
formulationof the problem than Boethius does in his commentaryon
that work, taking it throughits paces in great detail, and offeringa
host of variant syllogisticformsin which the ideas involved can be
stated, situatingthem withinthe larger contextof the logical rules for
affirmation,negation, and contradiction, and yoking them to an
express discussion of hypothetical syllogisms, equipollent propositions, and theirprobative force,he ends by reducing the Aristotelian
position to the position of formallogic far more systematicallythan
Boethius does. Abelard grants more authorityto logic understood
purely as a science of discourse than to anythingelse in his handling
of this problem, reading across Aristotleand across Boethius himself
to obtain a more consistentlypost-Aristotelianlogic than his sources
provide. He shows his instinct for moving away from theological
reasoning, in redefiningthe divine nature, or propositionswhich refer
to it, as part of the subject matterof logic. While Abelard does admit
that the debate at issue can be approached in other ways, the other
alternativesare clearlyless compellingand persuasive, forhim. Above
all, the logical sense of propositions is his point of conclusion,
whateversense theymay have in the worldof physicalor metaphysical
reality.
Abelard also takes up these same questions in his Theologia
<(
"scholarium".His argumenthere is similarto thatin the Logica ingre"
dientibus
except for the fact that he frames the issue of futureconhere
along the lines of Aristotle'saccount of the sea battle in
tingents
De interpretatione
9, giving attention to the claims made in terms of
natural law as well as in terms of logic itself.The main differences
between his initial treatmentof the subject and this one are that, in
the Theologia((scholarium'
' Abelard wants to accent man's freedom
14Ibid.,426-47.
146

09:11:47 AM

and responsibilityin the moral lifeunder the heading of contingency;


and he wants to emphasize more stronglythe point that God can suspend the natural law when He performsmiracles. From a logical
standpoint,it is also at this precise juncture that Abelard framesthe
question of the compatibilityof God's eternalforeknowledgeand contingent events in the light of the nominalist theory of the unitary
significationof the noun, although its consignificationin statements
using the past or futuretenses of the verb may reflectshiftsin our
knowledge or in our descriptionof what the noun signifies.15Let us
keep in mind the company in which this nominalisttheorytravels,in
Abelard' s presentationof it.
Abelard returnsto the argument offeredin the Logica "ingredientibus" fora thirdtime in his most mature logical work, the Dialctica,
there offeringa refinementon it.16He reprises the point that past,
present,and futureare categories irrelevantto God, since He lives in
the eternal present. He also repeats the observation that God so
ordains thingsthatsome events are capable of occurringcontingently,
and that, when this happens, these contingenciesdo not conflictwith
divine providence. Nor do events which, as God ordains them, occur
of necessityas consequences of the laws of nature which He put in
place. In thiswork, Abelard moves as well fromthe Augustinin and
Aristotelianargumentsto attach the idea of possibilityto the logical
relations between antecedent and consequent propositions that formulate the alternativesin hypotheticalform.At the same time, in the
DialcticaAbelard admits that the idea of necessityalso attaches properly to actual natural outcomes, and that, even propositionally,a
futurecontingentcan only be defended as a possibility.This conclusion impartsa rathermore Aristoteliancoloration to his handling of
"
necessityand possibilitythan he had given to it in theLogica ingredien
tibus". Another shiftis that, in the Dialctica,he omits the distinction
between God's foreknowledgeand God's causation in treatingdivine
providence. He collapses these two ideas into a view of providencethat
takes it to mean God's legislationfor,and action in, the natural order,
and not merely God's oversight of that order. The theme of
predestinationand grace likewise departs fromAbelard' s agenda in
this work. These shiftsin emphasis notwithstanding,the bottom line
15TSch
, 3.5, 3.87-116,526,536-47.
16Dial., 2.2.10-11,217-22.
147

09:11:47 AM

for his handling of the entire question, both early and late, remains
logic as a science of discourse done, and not the divine nature.
By express contrast with Abelard, when the Lombard addresses
himself to the same constellation of ideas, he does so in an unambiguously theological way. The firsttopics he takes up in Book 1 of
the Sentencesdeal with the Trinity and the theological language
appropriate to denote the divine nature as such and, alternatively,to
denote the persons of the Trinity vis--vis each other. As he shiftsto
the next part of the book, he remarksthatall the remainingquestions
that he plans to address there deal with the divine nature possessed
equally and in common by all members of the Trinity.This condition
applies, in force, to all God's actions relative to the creation and
man.17 Peter's observation is a rejoinder to Abelard in two ways. In
the firstplace, it attacks Abelard' s attributionof the names power,
wisdom, and goodness as proper names to the Father, Son, and Holy
Spirit. Secondly, the firstissue he takes up under the heading of God's
action ad extra
, divine providence, foreknowledge,predestination,and
futurecontingents,is raised expressly fromthe standpoint of God's
knowledge, not thatof human logic. In introducingthe subject in this
way, the Lombard makes it clear thathis chieffocus is going to be the
divine nature as a theological and metaphysicalreality. While God's
role as a cause in the physical order is going to receive some attention
and while care is going to be paid to the logical consistencyof his
arguments, and to those of thinkerswhom he criticizes,Peter never
lets the reader forgetthat he is writingabout God here, and that the
subject at issue is not a mere pendant to, or illustrationof, the sciences
of natural philosophy or logic.
God's knowledge is one and simple, he begins. Yet, it can be
thought of, in relation to man and the creation, in terms of foreknowledge, disposition, predestination,and wisdom. Foreknowledge
is God's knowledge, fromall eternity,of all thingsthat will happen,
whether for good or for ill. Disposition can be regarded not only as
God's general governance of the universe but also as His
foreknowledgeof the laws of nature that He will put in place before
He creates them. Similarly, predestinationcovers the preparation of
17PeterLombard,Sententiae
inIV libris
distinctae
, 1, d. 35, c. 1, 3rdrev.ed., ed.
1971-81,I, 254.
IgnatiusC. Brady,2 vols.,Grottaferrata
18Ibid.,c. 1-6,I, 254-8.On predestination
as thegraceofpreparation
in theLomdesPetrus
imBreisgau
Lombardus
bard,seeJohannSchupp,Die Gnadenlehre
, Freiburg
1932,105-15,141-58,204-6.
148

09:11:47 AM

grace whichGod grantsdirectlyto His elect and His salvation and coronationof them with bliss in the next life, as well as His knowledge
from all eternityof who they will be. Wisdom, finally, is God's
knowledge of all things, whether past, present, or future.18Having
mentioned the dimension of time in settingforththese definitions,
Peter next addresses a set of problemsnot raised by Abelard, but ones
with which Hugh of St. Victor and Honorius Augustodunensis had
wrestled ineffectivelyearlier in the period.19 In so doing, he
acknowledgesthe factthat he has a responsibilityto respond to questions, posed by othermastersof the day, that are properlytheological
and not just logical. Supposing that there were no temporal order at
all, and hence no futurein which events not yet in being might take
place, and given thatGod's knowledgeis one withHis essence, would
this not mean, he asks, that God's very being would be in jeopardy?
Peter answers this question in the negative. As he observes, when we
speak of God's foreknowledge,disposition, and predestinationwith
respect to the created world and man, we speak in a relative sense
{relative,ad aliquid),just as we do when we referto the deity as the
creator. Such activitiesvis--visother,created, beings as these relative
termsdenote in no sense exhaust or diminish the infinitereservoirof
being as such which the divine nature possesses, prior to and apart
from the creation. Further, there are two ways of regarding
foreknowledge.First, ifwe consider the subject matter,the future,on
which God's foreknowledgeis exercised, as capable of being there,or
not, then His foreknowledgecan be understood as relative to the
future.But, secondly,ifwe thinkof the knowledgethatGod possesses,
withwhich He is able to know the futurewhen it eventuates, then we
speak of His knowledge with respect to His essence, whetheror not
the temporalworldexists at all, or any particulareventualitythatmay
take place withinit. In any event, since He is eternal, God knows all
thingsfrom eternity.His knowledge is not limited by the temporal
order applying to creatures.20
This solution responds effectivelyto the dilemmas propounded by
Hugh and Honorius and at the same time addresses a question, raised
but not answered by the author of the Summasententiarum
,2 of whether
19Honorius
Elucidarium
Paris1954,
, 1.13,1.15,ed. YvesLefvre,
Augustodunensis,
Desacramentis
PL 176,211D-213B.
363;HughofSt.Victor,
christianae,
1.2.14-18,
fidei
20PeterLombard,
Sent.
, 1, d. 35, c. 7-9,I, 255-8.
21Summa
sententiarum
, 1.12,PL, CLXXVI, 61C-62C.
149

09:11:47 AM

God foreknowsthose futurecontingentsthat are not going to eventuate. For, as Peter continues, he next makes the point that, in the
second sense of foreknowledgewhich he has just indicated, God's
knowledge is of His essence; it would be incorrectto say that,because
He knows all things,all the thingsthat He knows are God or thatthey
share in His essence. Here, he stresses,we have to distinguishbetween
what God is, and what God has in His presence or has within Him.
As an illustrationof that point, Peter notes, God knows who the elect
are; but the elect are human, not divine. They are in God's presence,
not His nature. Similarly,God knows the evils thatwill occur, without
being identifiedwith them,just as He knows the good thingsthatwill
occur and that He will approve, good outcomes which, in this case,
He helps along, to a greateror lesser extent,being partiallyor wholly
an auctoras well as a knower. For, the creation and the temporalorder
are fromGod. They are not of God; that is, theyare not of the same
nature as God. It is at thisjuncture thatPeter acknowledgesthe utility
of Abelard' s distinctionbetween the unitary significationof a noun
and the differingconsignificationsit may have in statementsusing the
past, present, and future tenses of the verb. He also indicates the
limitationsof thisargument,fromhis own perspective.22What is strikingly Lombardian about thiswhole analysis is Peter's success in finding a cogent substituteforthe reductionof this problem to an exercise
in formallogic. At the same time, he retains a philosophical no less
than a theological perspectiveon it, by grounding the subject in the
metaphysical distinction between God viewed in His transcendent
essence and God viewed in those aspects of His being thatHe displays
in His relations with other beings.
Peter moves on, then, to a series of other questions pertinentto
God's foreknowledgethat had been raised and, in his view, answered
unsatisfactorilyby other masters. He deals in a swiftand streamlined
manner with God's foreknowledgeand its relationshipto causation,
relying here on Augustine and other patristic sources and not on
Boethius and Aristotle. Foreknowledge, he agrees, is not causative.
There are some things that God knows, contemplatingthem in His
own mind before He brings them into phenomenal existence as their
one and only cause, as is the case with the created universe. In this
example, He causes the thingsHe knows, not vice versa. In the case
22PeterLombard,
Sent.
, 1,d. 36,c. 1-5;d. 41,c. 3, I, 258-63,293.Thisis thepoint
notedbyCourtenay
1990,53-5;see also Courtenay
1991a,11-48.
150

09:11:47 AM

of contingencies, such as the willed actions of created beings who


possess freewill, God foreseesthe consequences of contingentactions
but does not cause them. His lack of direct causation here is in no
sense a failingor imperfectionin the divine nature, or in the divine
foreknowledge.For, He freelychose to create beings withfreewill and
He knows how they will freelyexercise it.23This section of Peter's
discussionremindsthe reader thatthe divine nature is the perspective
fromwhich he thinksthis topic ought to be examined. The exercise
is designed to enlightenthe reader about God, the subject of thisbook
of the Sentences
, not about the behavior and constitutionof creatures.
Another featureof God's foreknowledgethat requires discussion,
not only in and of itselfbut because of its bearing on predestination,
is its immutabilityand its exhaustive coverage. As Peter observes,
God's knowledge, like His essence, cannot change, enlarge, or
diminish.God may directHis attentionto thisor that subject, or not,
withoutchanging His knowledge. Since He is omniscientand always
has been, He knows thingsthathave not yet occurred in the temporal
order, and beings that have not yet come into existence. In the case
of contingentoutcomes, He knows whetheror not they will occur.
With respect to such futureevents, beings, and outcomes, this does
not mean thatGod knows thembetterwhen theydo occur. For, while
theyare conditioned by time, He is not; He has always been omniscient. In thisrespect,God cannot know more than He knows because
thatwould be a self-contradiction,
a point on which Peter agrees with
24
the author of the Summasententiarum.
As forpredestination,Peter notes, remindingthe reader of his definition of terms at the beginning of this section of Book 1 of the
Sentences
, predestinationis included in what God foreknowsbut it is
differentfromforeknowledge.Foreknowledge is not causative, while
predestinationis causative, referringspecificallyto God's directdecision to extend the grace of preparation and perseverance to those
people He chooses to save.25Here Peter summarizes the standard late
Augustinin teaching that was the consensus position on predestina23PeterLombard,
Sent.
Future
, 1, d. 38, I, 257-79.See CalvinNormore,
,
Contingents
in: Cambridge
Medieval
etal., Cam, ed. NormanKretzman
History
ofLater
Philosophy
Peter'saccenton God's freedom
here.
bridge1982,363-4,whonotes,correctly,
24PeterLombard,
Sent.,1, d. 39, c. 1.1-4.3;d. 41,c. 3, I, 280-3,292-3.Cf.Summa
Die Lehre
sent.,1.12,PL CLXXVI, 63A-64D.On thispoint,see Schneider,
, 54.
25PeterLombard,
Sent.,1, d. 39, c. 4.3, I, 283-84.Petermakesthesamepointin
Sermo
Die Lehre,
112,PL CLXXI, 860C. See Schneider,
55, 57-60.
151

09:11:47 AM

tion in this period. At the same time, he uses the argument just
developed on the immutabilityof God's foreknowledgeto criticizeversions of thatteachingthathe findsaberrantor problematic. In the first
place, there is the question raised by Abelard and debated by the
author of the Summasententiarum
and by Roland of Bologna26 as to
whetherGod can alterthe number of theelect. Given theway in which
Peter has framed his argument here, he can dispose of the idea that
God could make such a change as a non-question, not only fromthe
standpoint of God's will but also in the light of God's immutable
omniscience. Just as God does not alter His eternal decree, so, since
He knows eternallywhat that decree will be with regard to His elect
and since His knowledge never changes, the alteration of God's
There is also the question of
arrangementshere is a non-possibility.27
the relationbetweenelectionand the behavior of the elect. Here, Peter
wants to criticizethe position of William of Champeaux and Anselm
of Laon, who argued that God chooses the elect in the light of their
praevisa merita.2*For the elect, predestination enables them to be
justified, to live uprightly,to resist temptation,to persevere in the
good, and to attain beatitude in the next life. God foreknowsthat the
elect will respond appropriatelyto the grace He extends to them,just
as He knows that the reprobate will fall into sin, although in the first
case He actively prepares the elect for their salvation while He
prepares nothingforthe reprobate. But, Peter insists,withAugustine
and against Anselm and William, God does not choose the elect
because He foreseesthat theywill respond positivelyto His grace and
earn merit. Rather, what He foresees is the fact that His grace will
provide the elect with the enabling condition for their acquisition of
merit afterthe fact.29
In the case of God's foreknowledgeand related matters,as can be
seen fromthe above, Peter demonstratesclearlythat thisconstellation
of ideas can be treated in as sweeping a manner as needs be, embracing issues of genuine theological interest and pertinence which
Abelard omits as well as those he includes, from the perspective of
26RolandofBologna,DieSentenzen
Rolands
1969
, ed. Ambrogius
Gietl,Amsterdam
im Breisgau1891ed.), 62-67;Summa
sent.,1.12,PL CLXXVI,
(repr.ofFreiburg
63A-64D.
27PeterLombard,Sent.
, 1, d. 40, c. 1, I, 285-86.
28Sentences
ofAnselm
, 240,ed. OdonLotofLaon, 11; Sentences
ofWilliam
ofChampeaux
etmorale
auxXIIeetXIIIesicles
tin,in: Psychologie
, Louvain1959,V, 22, 199-200.
29PeterLombard,Sent.,1, d. 40, c. 2-d.41, c. 1,1, 286-92.
152

09:11:47 AM

God's knowledge. Throughout, he grounds his support for the compatibilityof contingencyand freewill with divine foreknowledge,and
withthe existenceof directdivine causation in some areas, not on the
relationsbetween necessityand possibilityin natural philosophyor in
logic but in thedistinctionbetween the transcendentGod and the God
Who acts, in a varietyof ways, in the world He created, but without
being exhausted or consumed by His economic role.30 Peter's
resolutelymetaphysicaladdress to this question enables him to put it
on as philosophicala foundationas is true forAristotleor forAbelard,
although it is a metaphysicalfoundation,and one that also affordsa
good vantage point fromwhich to consider the specificallytheological
dimensions of these problems as well.
While space does not permit as extended an analysis of the topic,
the Lombard's handling of the related issue of whetherGod can do
better, or different,than He does, and his rejection of Abelard's
negative answer to that question, yields additional evidence as to why
he findsAbelard's reasoning, and the uses to which Abelard puts it,
, Abelard's
fundamentallywrong-headed. In the TheologiaChristiana
him
to
tackle
this
as
a
leads
to
conflate
God's
problem
urge
logician
power with God's will, forcinghim to conclude that God always acts
in thebest possible way, since a consequent statinga divine action that
is not good or just cannot followlogically froman antecedent stating
thatHe is good and just. As Abelard puts it: "What He wills, He must
will necessarily,and what He does, He must do necessarily" ( Quae
, necessario
vult,necessario
velit,et quaeJacit
facial.) Logical necessityconstrains God's behavior, behavior which, he states, takes place
inevitabiliter.3i
Reformulatingthis claim in the Theologia"scholarium}'
Abelard stillframesit in the language of antecedent and consequent
propositions,but shiftshis accent to the nature of God as a perfect
being. Since God is perfect,Abelard reasons, He must always act
perfectly,as a necessityof His own being. The perfectionof God's
being thus entails, for Abelard, the perfectionof the exercise of His
will. Hence, God could not have made a betterworld.32This version
30Thisorientation
is alsofoundintheLombard'sPaulineexegesis.See PeterLomPauli ad Romanos
bard, In Epistolam
, 1:7, 8:29, PL CXCI, 1310B-1311D,
1449B-1450B.
31Tchr
, 5.42,366.
32TSch
ofthispointis provided
, 3.27-64,511-27.A gooddiscussion
by Lawrence
UseoftheTimeaus
Moonan,Abelard's
, in: AHDL, 56 (1989),30-3,72-4.
153

09:11:47 AM

of the argument imposes a metaphysical as well as a logical


necessitarianismupon the deity.
It is, among other things, preciselyin order to freeGod fromthe
axiological necessitarianism with which Abelard encumbers Him,
whetherlogically or metaphysically,that the Lombard takes his own
stand. His aim is to liberate God simultaneouslyfroman economic
theology and fromthe limits of logic understood purely as a science
of discourse. His emphasis on God's freedomis reflectedby his placement of this topic under the heading of God's omnipotence, and by
his reimportinginto the discussion an Augustinin distinctionwhich
Abelard had dismissed, the distinction between God's power and
God's will, employed as well by recent thinkerssuch as Anselm of
Canterbury. From this perspective,God's power is His ability to do
whatever He wills.33In actuadpractice, according to Peter, what God
does is good and just. But, he argues, this factimposes no constraints
upon the choices God might have made and it does not limit His
capacity to have done what He has chosen not to do. In making His
just and good choices, God remains free. Bringing to bear on this
question an argumenthe had made concerningGod's foreknowledge,
where he had argued that divine omniscience includes the range of
options out of which God selects the actions that He decides to perform,Peter observes that the force of the Augustinin distinctionto
which he adheres is decidedly not to reduce God's power to the scope
of whateverHe actually wills to do, but rather,just the reverse. What
the distinctionmeans is thatGod not only is capable ofdoing whatever
He wills, but also that whatever He can do always remains more, in
principle, than what He actually does do. What the Lombard is
articulating here, although without using this terminology,is the
distinctionbetween God's absolute and ordained power.34So acute is
Peter's desire to emphasize the principlethatGod always remains free
to act differendythan the way in which He chooses to act that he does
not hesitate to maintain that, although Christ was incarnated,
crucified,and resurrectedonce for all, if God willed it, He could be
33The besttreatment
in theEarly
of thissubjectis Ivan Boh,DivineOmnipotence
andOmnipotence
inMedieval
: Islamic
and
Sentences
Omniscience
, in:Divine
,Jewish
Philosophy
Christian
, ed. Tamar Rudavsky,Dordrecht1985, 193-200.See also
Perspectives
Die Lehre
Schneider,
, 39-41.
34PeterLombard,Sent.,1, d. 43, I, 298-303.This pointhas been notedby
Courtenay,1990, 55; MariateresaBeonio-Brocchieri
Fumagalliand Massimo
Bari1989,254-5.
della
medievale
da Boezioa Wyclif,
Parodi,Storia
filosofia
154

09:11:47 AM

incarnated, crucified,and resurrectedagain. It is in defense of this


extreme example of his general point that Peter brings forwardthe
nominalistanalysis of the unitarysignificationof the verb firstnoted
by Landgraf, Chenu, and Schneider. On the analogy of the action
signifiedby the verb, God's power is always the same. What He was
able to do in the past, He is able to do in the present or the future:
" Deum
semper
posseetquidquidsemelpotuitid esthabereomnemillampotentiamquam semelhabuit
. "35
If anything,this nominalist argument concerning the verb is even
more appealing to Peter than the nominalistargumentconcerningthe
noun which he applies to God's knowledge. For, the dimension of
time is built into the verb, by its verynature as a part of speech. This
fact enables him to underscore the transcendence of the timeless,
omnipotent God over the things He decides to do in the temporal
order, relative to creatures. Peter's use of this argument thus allows
him to stay in the essentially metaphysical arena within which he
plants his standard in treatingthe divine nature. While the Lombard
is not so forthright
as the early Porretansin hoistingAbelard explicitly
on his own logical petard, he agrees with them, implicitly,that logic
seen only as a science of discourse is indeed a feebleinstrumentforthe
work of theological research.
With respect to the Lombard's contribution to the history of
nominalism in the twelfthcentury,then, we may offerthree conclusions. First, fromour considerationof Abelard' s case, it is clear that
the opinioNominaliumcould be, and was, yoked to a post-Aristotelian
kind of logic. From our consideration of the Lombard's case, it is
equally clear that the opinioNominaliumcould just as easily be yoked
to a mode of reasoning deemed capable of yieldingcogent ontological
thinker
conclusions. In this respect, the fact that a twelfth-century
he
mean
is
that
Nominalium
does
not
the
automatically
espouses
opinio
or necessarilyrequired to embrace one ratherthan the other of these
different
conceptionsof logic. Second, it was not just the factthat the
Lombard was a theologian but his particular agenda as a theologian
who sought to affirmGod's omnipotence and God's essence as the
35PeterLombard,
is at c. 2.4, 306.
Sent.
, 1, d. 44,c. 2.1-4,I, 305-6.The quotation
withtheverbis atc. 2.3, 306: "Verbaenimdiversorum
Thecomparison
temporum,
adiunctaadverbiis,
eundemfaciunt
et diversis
diversis
sensum,
prolatatemporibus
dicimus:Istepotestlegerehodie;erasautemdicemus:Istepotest
utmodoloquentes
potentia."
legisse,velpotuitlegereheri;ubi uniusreimonstratur
155

09:11:47 AM

transcendentmetaphysical realitythat accounts for both his borrowings fromAbelard and his more fundamentalhostilityto Abelard in
thisarea. And, finally,thanksto the rapid and enduringsuccess of the
Lombard's Sentences
as a textbook,he was able to place both his position on divine transcendence,the distinctionbetween God's absolute
and ordained power, and the opinio Nominaliumwith which he
bolsteredthese teachingssquarely beforethe eyes of his scholasticcontemporariesand successors.
Oberlin, Ohio
OberlinCollege

156

09:11:47 AM

Vivarium
XXX, 1 (1992)
Peterof Capua as a Nominalist
WILLIAMJ. COURTENAY

Peter of Capua holds a special place in the textual historyof the


Nominales.Throughout the period from the mid-twelfthto the midthirteenth century- the period from which come most of our
- only one
references to the Nominalesor the opinionesnominalium
author whose name we know identifieshimselfas a nominalist: Peter
of Capua ( #44c).* Many figureshave been so described in the earlier
'
4
literature,but that 'naming' or labeling, no matterhow accurate it
may or may not be, is based on positions maintained or the witness
We have, it is true, several
of others, not on self-identification.2
1 Christopher
thispaperthatthestateinthediscussion
Martinsuggested
following
in whichPeter
ment"Nos Nominales"(#44c)shouldbe readas directdiscourse
...") and
Nominalist
butallowsa fictional
notforhimself
("Haec oppositio
responds
Realist("Haec species...") to addressthereader.The case wouldbe
a fictional
inOxford,
similar
tothatin theanonymous
Bodl.,Laudlat.
commentary
Porphyry
Canter,
and
the
vocalis
has
the
author
where
speak
67,f.7 (cf.Iwakuma's
paperabove)
ofthepassagewouldbringtheCapua evidence
forthemselves.
Thisinterpretation
werea
moreintolinewithwhatotherwise
appearstobe thecase:thattheNominales
thatbytheendof
in thethirdquarterofthetwelfth
sectamonglogicians
century,
rather
thanstillactive,andthatCapualike
remembered
thecentury
theyweresimply
tocreatecontrasting
andReales
oftheNominales
other
appliedthepositions
theologians
is thefactthatinthe
In favor
ofthisinterpretation
totheological
solutions
questions.
andeven
contrasts
ofa question
orresponsio
solutio
positions
Capuasometimes
portion
andRealis( #44a,44b,44d).AsattracoftheNominalis
doessobyusingthecharacters
makesitunlikely.
ofCapua'sSumma
thestyle
andstructure
tiveas I findthissolution,
ofthe
a position
whenmentioning
discourse
direct
Nowhere
elsedoesCapuaemploy
whenCapua says"nos dicimus"in his
or Realist.Moreimportantly,
Nominalist
hisownposition,
it is invariably
to a question,
solution
e.g. Vat. lat. 4296,f. 2rb:
quia ..."; Vat. lat.
quod...; Nosdicimus
"Quidamdicuntquod...; Aliiconcedunt
f.4va: "Nos vero
adiectiva
omnia
ibid.,
4304,f.4rb:"Nos verodicimus
quod
fi.26ra:"Nos dicimus
'talis'vel 'qualis' dicimus
ibid.,
quodperhocnomen
" The last
examplecomesearlierin thesamequestion
quodnonestaliussensus
as thetextunderdiscussion.
2 In theuniquemanuscript
ofStephenLangton'sglosson Lombard'sLibrisentennos".
on divinepoweris introduced
tiarum
, thenominalist
by "secundum
position
for
between
'nos' andtheabbreviation
ofscribalconfusion
Butgiventhepossibility
with'reales'inthesamepassage,theeditor
andgiventhejuxtaposition
'nominales',
is the
thisreading
Arthur
emended'nos' to read'nominales'.
Supporting
Landgraf
in Peter
The statement
tradition
thatplacesLangtonamongthePorretani.
scholarly
Allmanuscripts
ofCapua'sSumma
is notsubjecttodoubtor textual
interpretation.
so farexamined
read"nos Nominales".
157

09:11:54 AM

'
"
anonymous textsthat stem fromthis group or school,' two of which
do have self-identification:specificallya late twelfth-century
treatise
on predication( #22), the so-called Positiones
nostrae
#
and
proba( 60),
bly the Vienna Quaestionesuncovered by Iwakuma (#24). But with
anonymous texts we have no way of going behind these works to
explore the academic contextand teaching traditionfromwhich they
derive. The case of Peter of Capua is all the more precious to us
because it may affordus preciselythat opportunity.3
Peter of Capua is not yeta household name in the historyof twelfthand thirteenth-century
thought,although his importance in his own
day as a Paris master was considerable. Peter's theological Summa,
presumably an outgrowthof his lectures as regentmaster at Paris, is
dated to 1201-1202 by its dedication to Walter, Archbishop of
Palermo.4 At some point beforeOctober 1206 he resigned a prebend
as canon at Tours, presumably in favour of one at Sens.5 Whether
continuouslyteaching or not, he was still active as regent master at
Paris in the autumn of 1218 when Pope Honorius III wrote him on
November 16, requesting that another scholar, Matthew of Scotland,
3 In theremainder
ofthispaperthename'Peter',without
further
has
identification,
forPeterofCapua. Othertwelfth-century
'Peters'(e.g., Peter
personal
supposition
PetertheCantor,and PeterofPoitiers)
Abelard,PeterLombard,PeterComester,
willbe mentioned
fullname.
by
4 Thisdedication,
mentioned
in Chartularium
Universitatis
byDeniflein hisfootnote
Parisiensis
andE. Chatelain,
vol.I (Paris1889),85(subsequently
cited
, ed. H. Denifle
as CUP), presumably
occursin one or moreofthemanuscripts
ofCapua's Summa
citedbyDenifle:MonteCassino354 and 475,andMontpellier
(Bibi.de l'colede
340. M. Grabmann,
Die Geschichte
derscholastischen
Methode
mdicine)
, II (Freiburg
Denifle
knewthese.
1911),532-4,addedVat. lat.4296and4304,although
probably
desmatres
enthologie
deParisauXIIle sicle
BythetimeofP. Glorieux,
Rpertoire
(Paris
hadbeenexpanded
toninewiththeaddition
ofMunichClm
1933),265,thenumber
14508(identified
Vat. lat. 4303,ParisBN lat. 483,andextracts
in
byGrabmann),
F. Stegmller,
Paris,BN lat. 15972,ff.156r-165v
(identified
byLandgraf).
Reper
torium
commentariorum
insententias
Petri
Lombardi
(Wrzburg
1947),321addedAdmont
a workknown
387,Melk337(198)and843(19),andTodi51. Capua alsoauthored
as Lexicon
contionatorium
or Rosaalphabetical
, Arsconcionandi
variously
Bruges253,
Charleville
230,Douai 433, MonteCassino255,Paris,Mazarine1007and 1008,
ParisBN lat. 16894and 16896,Troyes114.
5 Papalletter
tothedeanandchapter
ofSt. Martinat Tours,Register
ofInnocent
III (PL 215, 994): "ut resignationem
praebendae,
quam in ecclesiavestratenuit
dilectus
P. Capuanus,canonicus
Senonensis Glorieux,
filius,
magister
,
Rpertoire
Innocent's
letter
tomeanthatPeterexchanged
a canonry
atSoissons
265,interpreted
forone at Sens,butthatis notstipulated.
After
Peter'sresignation,
Innocent
had
ofthatprebend
at TourstothebishopanddeanofNotreDameat
giventhecontrol
Parisin favorofpapallyrecommended
suchas thenextrecipient,
candidates,
John
ofCangeiaco.
158

09:11:54 AM

be permitted to incept as master of theology.6 We do not know


whetherPeter and his fellowmasters, William de Pont d'Arche and
Richard the Englishman to whom Honorius also addressed his letter,
were successfulin persuading the chancellorof Notre Dame, Philip de
Grve, to grant the license. The chancellor may only have been
abiding by the bull of Innocent III in 1207 restrictingto eight the
number of regents in theology at Paris.7 Either by expansion or
substitutionan opening in the Paris magisteriumwas soon created.8
William de Pont d'Arche was elected bishop of Louvain soon after
Honorius's request, and in the followingspring Peter of Capua was
made Patriarch of Antioch and, a few months later, cardinal deacon
of St. George.9 The restof Peter's career lay in papal service. He died
in 1242, probably in his seventies.
Those are the known details of Peter's life, most of them recorded
Universitatis
in a footnotein the Chartularium
Parisiensisand expanded
only slightlyby subsequent scholars.10But what can we conjecture
6 Reg. Vat. Honor.Ill, an. 3, ep. 113,f. 25, editedin CUP, I, 85.
7 CUP I, 65; Courtenay,
and
attheUniversity
Careers
ofParisintheThirteenth
Teaching
Fourteenth
Centuries
, NotreDame 1988,26-30.
8 It is notknown,however,
Matthewin factreceivedthelicenseand
whether
oftheology
at Paris
Thisnamedoesnotappearamongtheknownmasters
incepted.
after1218.
9 Forhispromotion
ofAntioch
toPatriarch
(Apr.25, 1219)see Reg. Vat. Honorn
CUP I, 85. In Augustof1227Peter,then
takenfrom
III an. 3, ep. 417;information
ofrelicsandprecious
a grant
cardinal
deaconofSt.George,oversaw
objectstoClairvaux;PL 185,1771.
10Apartfromoccasional
ofscholastic
textbooks
in nineteenth-century
mention
phiMartin
into
our
well
unstudied
until
was
of
Peter
century.
essentially
Capua
losophy,
derscholastischen
Methode
threepagestohimin hisGeschichte
devoted
Grabmann
, and
inGlorieux
andStegmller
mention
he received
(see above,note4). Butitwasnot
until1940thatCapua becamethesubjectofa separatestudy.In thatyearArthur
underthetitle:"A Studyofthe
an articlein NewScholasticism
published
Landgraf
ofPeterofCapua." The word"latitude"is onlyoneofa series
Latitude
Academic
one
thearticle
wordsthatthetranslator
ofill-chosen
used,andinordertounderstand
as faras
as bestonecan whattheGermantext,neverpublished
hasto reconstruct
forhis
PeterofCapua wasexamined
tosay.After
I know,wasattempting
Landgraf
undder
oftheological
on a variety
issues;see F. Holbck,Die eucharistische
position
LeibChristi
, Rome1941,150,160,165-66,189,213,222;A. M. Landgraf,
mystische
derFrhscholastik
Literatur
dertheologischen
indieGeschichte
1948,
, Regensburg
Einfhrung
etmorale
1954,347,844; L. Hdl,Die
, vol.4.2,Gembloux
109;O. Lottin,
Psychologie
i.W.
derSchlsselgewalt
Literatur
undderTheologie
derscholastischen
Geschichte
I, Mnster
1960,218,258,259,277,289-96,304,371,378,379,381,383-5,389;J. Grndel,
imMittelalter
derMenschlichen
vondenUmstnden
DieLehre
1963,87,
, Mnster
Handlung
der
Die Unsterblichkeit
151,260-72,316., 391,396,402,571,649; R. Heinzmann,
desLeibes
SeeleunddieAuf
169,172,
, Mnster1965,122-9,130,137,165ff.,
erstehung
197,247;J. Baldwin1970,I, 45.
159

09:11:54 AM

about the early career and intellectualformationof Peter? He must


have taughttheology,presumablyat Paris, at least one year beforethe
completion of his Summa, probably much longer. In lightof the close
similarity(indeed, extensive borrowing) between his Summaand the
of Peter of Poitiers (regent at Paris from 1167 to 1205), it is
Sententiae
likely that he studied theology under Peter of Poitiers and thus
academically stands within the tradition of Peter Lombard. If he
studied philosophyat Paris beforeturningto theology- and his Summa
shows familiaritywith the techniques and terminology of litterae
- this would probably have been in the 1180s.
saeculares
Before assessing Capua's relation to former and contemporary
mastersand the possible implicationsof such links forthe presence of
a nominalistschool among theologians at Paris in the decades before
and after1200, we firstneed to look closely at the positions thatPeter
fourtimes in his
identifiesas nominalistic.Peter refersto the nominales
Summa.The firstinstance occurs in his chapterson divine knowledge
and foreknowledge,specificallyin the contextof the question whether
God knows somethingthathe previouslydid not know.11The problem
here, as discussed earlier in the twelfthcentury,is thatas thingscome
into existence,propositionsabout themeitherchange theirtruthvalue
(e.g. "Peter of Capua exists" was true in 1200 and false in 1100) or
are expressed in differenttenses (e.g. " Peter of Capua will exist" and
" Peter of
Capua does exist"). Similarly, God's knowledge
since he knows the existingPeter at one point in
changes,
presumably
time and does not know Peter as existinga centuryearlier or later.12
Peter attributesto the Realist the position that the contentof God's
knowledge changes across time as thingsbegin or cease to exist. But
for the Realist that does not mean that God becomes more knowing
or less knowing, since the faculty or power of knowing does not
increase or diminishby reason of the objects of knowledge,just as the
power or facultyof sight does not increase or diminish by reason of
the number of objects seen. The Realist, in Peter's view, grounds the
11PeterofCapua, Summa
, c. 17 (in listoftexts,#44a).
12If thequestionoftheimmutability
ofdivineknowledge
is posedin termsofan
increase
ordecreasein whatGod knows,theimplication
ofquantitative
changecan
thatthetotalnumber
be avoidedbynoting
ofknown
remains
thesame.
propositions
is either
whena proposiaffirmative
ornegative,
andconsequently
Everyproposition
trueorceasestobe true,itscontrary
tionbecomes
becomes
thenumber
true,keeping
ofpropositions
thesame.Ifthequestion,
in terms
of
is posedqualitatively
however,
no suchsolution
seemspossible.
changesin content,
160

09:11:54 AM

immutabilityof divine knowledge in the immutabilityof the divine


capacity for knowing, not in the contentof God's knowledge which
changes withchangingobjects, whetherunderstood as things,events,
states of affairs,or propositions about things, events, and states of
affairs.
The Nominalist on the other hand, according to Peter, maintains
thatPeter's existence,in the sense of the proposition'me esse', always
signifiedand was always true, and thus was always known by God.
Put another way, if God from all eternityknows that Peter would
exist, God in eternityknows the proposition 'me esse' as true. Peter
does not expand on this teaching because it was familiar to his
audience and potentialreaders. It was what was known in this period
13
as the classic opinioNominalium.
Just as a nomensignifiesat any point
in time and has the same significationacross time, although it may be
cases in propositions,and just as a verb signifies
expressedin different
tenses in prothe same across time althoughit is expressedin different
in
different
tenses at difidentical
so
propositionsexpressed
positions,
ferentpoints in time signifythe same thing. The contentof the belief
of all the faithfulis identical across time despite the fact that
Abraham's faithconcerningChrist was expressed in the futuretense
and that portionof the Christian creed is expressed in the past tense.
Similarly, God's knowledge is the same across time despite the fact
thateventschange and the tense structureof propositionsabout those
events changes. Thus the immutabilityof God's knowledge for the
Nominalist is grounded in the belief that that which is signifiedby
(i.e., the significatimi
of) a true proposition does not change, despite
structures.Semelestverum
events
and
tense
, semperestverum'
changing
if the significatum
of a propositionis ever true, it was and will always
be true.14
The theoryof nominaon which the Nominalist theoryof propositions was based did not originate with Abelard nor, as Chenu suggested,withBernard of Chartres, but was already a fundamentalpart
of ancient grammar. It was commonly accepted that the nominative
case of nouns and the present tense of verbs were primary, and the
oblique cases and non-presenttenses were secondary and subsumed
under nominative nomina and present-tense verbs. Moreover,
13Seelistoftexts,#29,46,48c,50a,50b,51a,52d,52f,62d,64a,64c,65a,70,71.
14See especially
Chenu 1934;Chenu 1935-36;Chenu 1957; Nuchelmans
1973;
1991a.
Courtenay
161

09:11:54 AM

significationwas a function only of these nominative nominaand


present-tenseverbs. Other cases and tenses co-signified.15
Although Peter does not at this point apply the distinctionbetween
signification and consignification, which was usually used by
between a nomenand its oblique
nominalisttheologiansto differentiate
cases or between a verb and its tenses- thus the slogan: one nomen
,
in
his
form
of
elsewhere
this
Peter
does
voces
analysis
employ
many
Summa.Here he restrictshis analysis to the companion theses that the
of a proposition, once true, is always true, and that the
significatum
immutabilityof God's knowledge,just like the identityof beliefwithin
the Church across time, is based on that principle.16
Peter followsthis passage with a discussion of whetherGod is able
to begin to know something.17Again, he describesthe Realist position
as believing thatjust as somethingthat is not true is able to begin to
be true, so God is able to begin to know something as true which
previously was not true. The Nominalist, by contrast, argues that
'
statementsthat are not true are able to be true, but theydo not begin
to be true'. Truth is not a process thatadmits of gradual change. Propositions are eithertrue or false. Thus God is able to know something
that he did not know, but he is not able to begin to know something,
just as someone who is not predestined is able to have been
predestined, but he is not able to begin to be predestined.
The identityor oneness of the Church's faithacross time, fromthe
Patriarchs to Peter's own day- i.e., the assertion of the unity of the
object of belief, which was the opinioNominaliumto which Chenu and
Nuchelmans devoted most of their attention when discussing
15Forexample,
'ofPhilo','to Philo',
OnInterpretation
2: "The expressions
Aristotle,
ofthesecases
notnouns,butcasesofa noun.The definition
and so on, constitute
3:
thesameas thatofthenounproper..." OnInterp.
ofa nounis in otherrespects
carrieswithit thenotion
to itspropermeaning,
"A verbis thatwhich,in addition
arenotverbs,buttenses
'hewillbe healthy'
'he washealthy',
oftime.""Similarly,
liesinthefactthattheverbindicates
ofa verb;thedifference
time,whilethe
present
thosetimeswhichlieoutsidethepresent."See alsoPristensesoftheverbindicate
Latini,
, ed. M. Hertz,in: Grammatici
cian,Institutiones
Leipzig1855,I, 54.
grammaticae
ofthesetheories,
seeCourtenay
On theearlier
1988;Courtenay
[1992b].
background
16It is interesting
as described
to notethattherealistposition,
byPeterofCapua,
andevents
butseemstograntthat
inthings
theobjectofknowledge
doesnotground
and
events.
Peter'sRealistsseemstatements
about
is
concerning
things
knowledge
is aboutenunciables
rather
thanthings.
Theyalsogrant
inglygrantthatknowledge
orobjectsofknowledge
thatthecontent
changein spaceandtime,
changeas things
doesnotchange.
ofdivineknowledge
thepoweroffaculty
although
17PeterofCapua,Summa
, c. 17 (in listoftexts,#44a).
162

09:11:54 AM

nominalism- is directlyaddressed by Peter the last time he mentions


a positionof the Nominalists.18As described by Peter, the Nominalist
positionis thatAbraham never believed thatChrist nowwill come but
thatChristthenwould come. Althoughthe beliefof Abraham and contemporaryChristians is expressed in differenttenses, it is one and the
same faith. The significationof true propositions remains the same
across time.
, it is not surAlthough not identifiedas opinions of the Nominales
that
Peter
solves
the
of
the
prising
problems
immutabilityof divine
volition and power in preciselythe same way he solved the problem
of the immutabilityof divine knowledge. Not only are the facultiesof
divine volition and action unaltered and unrestrictedby the implementationof God's will or by eventsin time; what God wills and does
remain the same throughouteternity,unchanging and immutable.
Once willed, always willed. What God was once able to do, he is
always able to do.19
In an earlier chapter Peter asks whetheractions, undeterminedto
a particulareffect,are fromGod, i.e., come under the will of God.20
- the
It is here that Peter identifieshimself among the Nominales
second time that he uses the label. Peter constructsa hypothetical
situationin which all actions are evil. Yet the genus 'action' itself,like
all genera and species, is part of the nature of thingsand is therefore
fromGod. One mightconsequentlyargue that individual instancesor
applicationsof action were also fromGod, and thus God would be the
cause of evil. Peter hastens to point out that this opposing argument
or hypotheticalcase does not argue against the Nominalist position- " since we
nonestcontranosNominales
say that genera and species are
nomina
, and all nominaand any applications or impositionsof them are
fromGod."
One mightinferfromthis passage thatthe Nominalesin Peter's day
were credited with the position that genera and species were only
categories made up of individual instances, and thus if the genus
'action' was fromGod, then all individual actions or cases that go to
make up that genus are also from God. But this is, for Peter, a
misunderstandingof the Nominalist position. Nomina have a reality
18See listoftexts,#44e.
19Peterof
, c. 12(Vat.lat.4304,fol.6rb);c. 13 (Vat. lat.4304,fol.
Capua,Summa
6vb).
20PeterofCapua,Summa
, c. 26 (in listoftexts,#44c).
163

09:11:54 AM

apart from individual instances or cases, since it is the propertyof


nominathat they can be predicated of many individuals. Universais,
as nomina
, are built into the very nature of thingsby God and are not
creations of the human mind thathave no basis in externalreality.As
nomina
, in contrastto voces
, genera and species are part of the inherent
structureof reality, not a product of language and human conceptualization.
A differentunderstandingof nominaand voces
, however, seems to be
in
the
third
of
the
four
where
the Nominalesare
operative
passages
mentioned.21 Chapter forty-sevenof Peter's Summa addresses the
theological virtues, beginning with faith. Peter poses a case in which
a Jew might believe God to be a rational substance of an individual
nature, and thereforebelieves God to be a person, since thatis the definitionof a person. But 'person' has a different
meaning when applied
to creatures than when applied to the creator, and one has to understand how a word is being used in a propositionor argument. Thus,
when a Catholic is asked whethera Jew believes God to be a person,
the answer would be 'no', since the Jew's understandingof 'person'
is not what a Catholic would understandby the Father, Son, and Holy
Spirit. Similarly, a Nominalist would concede that a Realist reckons
'genus' to be a noun, because according to the Nominalist the noun
'genus' in a sentence or propositiondoes not supposit except as a vox,
although the Realist thinks it to be a nomen.But if questioned, the
Realist would say that he does not believe 'genus' to be a nomen
because somethingother than a verbal sound {vox) is signifiedby the
noun 'genus'. So too theJew might say that he believes God to be a
person, since he would believe that somethingelse is signifiedby the
noun 'person' than a Catholic believes.
The steps in Peter's discussion here are difficultto follow,and there
may be some corruptionsin the text. It appears on the surfaceto suggest that the Nominalist equates nomenand vox, while the Realist is
brieflycreditedwith the position that 'genus' is a nomen.We are best
served by reading the passage in light of Peter's main point. Just as
the Jew and Catholic understand very differentthings by the word
'person' {persona
), so too the Nominalist and Realist understand very
differentthingsby the word nomen
, and perhaps also by the word vox.
We should be careful, therefore,not to read the Nominalist position
according to the Realist's understandingof these terms. The debate
21PeterofCapua, Summa,
c. 47 (in listoftexts,#44d).
164

09:11:54 AM

between the two groups on this issue was just as much at crossmeanings of the same word, as a debate
purposes, plagued by different
over the nature of God.
a
Christian
between a Jew and
These thenare thepassages in which Peter mentionspositionsof the
Nominales
, a group with which, in one of the passages, he apparently
allies himself.Two of the positions concern the objects of divine and
human knowledge and/or belief, and they follow the classic
Nominalist theory of enunciables: once a proposition is true, it is
always true. The other two passages concern genera and species.
However one interpretsPeter's treatmentof this second issue, it is
clear thatby 1200 Nominalistswere associated with a particularposition on the question of universais. But it is unclear to what extentthat
position resembles what has traditionally been thought to be
'Nominalism'.
Perhaps some light on this question of the relation of Peter's
Nominalesto the discussion of genera and species can be shed by looking at the othertextsreferringto the Nominaleson thisissue. In the list
compiled by Iwakuma and Ebbesen there is a sizable group. Taking
elenchorum
these in the order assembled, the Summasophisticorum
, dated
by De Rijk c.1150 but more likelylater, indicates that the Nominales
distinguishedpropernouns fromappellative nouns, placing universais
in the latterclass because it is theirnature to be predicated of many.22
Nothing in this passage necessarilyrelates it to the modern notion of
, nor does it speak of voces.We
nominalism, nor does it define nomina
have more to go on with Ralph of Beau vais' s GlosaesuperDonatum,
writtenbetween 1150 and 1175.23Building on Augustine's definition
of person as the individual essence of a rational creature, essence is
furtherdefinedas thatwhich is signifiedsubstantiallyby a noun. And
because essence is signifiedsubstantiallyby a universal noun, just as
the noun 'man', the Realists call thisa universalwhile the Nominalists
call it a special or general statuswhich, since person is not of thiskind,
the term 'individual' is added.
The nominalisttreatiseon predication,presumablydating fromthe
last half of the twelfthcentury, limits the application of the terms
'genus' and 'species' to one-word nouns.24 It gives as a rule of this
22See listoftexts,#5.
23See listoftexts,#13.The reference
ofstatus
hereto a theory
maybe linkedto
Abelards views;see Tweedale1976.
24See listoftexts,#22b.
165

09:11:54 AM

group that no compound or multi-wordexpression {sermocomplexus)


can be a genus or species, presumably because the latter are
designated only by appellative nouns. This is contrasted with the
Realist position, which apparentlyheld that a definitionof a genus is
itselfa genus,just as a definitionof a species is itselfa species. Another
anonymous treatiseon universais, presumably dating fromthe same
period, maintained that the Nominalists believed that genera and
species are words and supported this position by appealing to Aristo,25For Aristotle,one describes a primarysubstance bettle's Categories
ter by statingits species ratherthan its genus.26But since Stating' is
proper to words, genera and species are words {voces).Again, Aristotle
maintained that substances signify.27And since 'to signify'is proper
to words, so genera and species are words. One immediate reaction
to this text is to argue that for the Nominalists nominaand vocesare
interchangeable,which iftruewould lend supportforIwakuma's view
that the Nominalesderived from the Vocales.We must, however,
remember that this treatise is anti-Nominalistand not an unbiased
witness. We also should recall Peter of Capua's observation that
Nominalists and Realists understand differentthingswhen theyhear
the words nominaand voces.It is perhaps less a matterof two different
views on universais than two differentunderstandingsof what nomen
and vox, as words, signify.
At the end of the centuryAlexander Nequam in his Speculumspecula
tionumnoted that the nominalist affirmationthat 'genus is a noun'
does not mean they hold that diverse species withina genus are one
noun, nor does that affirmationfullyor adequately reflecttheirposition.28This passage in particular should be read alongside Peter of
nostraey
Capua's remarks.In the Nominalist Positiones
dating probably
fromthe early thirteenthcentury,their stated position on universais
is that universais such as genera and species are nouns.29 But that
statement,without furtherelaboration on what is meant by 'nouns'
and whethertheyare only nouns, does not take us very far. It is not
in the second quarter of
until Albert the Great's Liberdepraedicabilibus
the thirteenthcenturythat the Nominalist position on universais is
construed to mean that universais are only in the intellect.30
25See listoftexts,#4.
26Categories
, c. 5 b 10).
27Ibid.,3 b 10. (2
28See listoftexts,#40a.
29See listoftexts,#60.
30See listoftexts,#61.
166

09:11:54 AM

These statementson genera and species, with the exception of the


late witness of Albert the Great, are not, as I have suggested, as
Nominalist positionon universais
helpfulin defininga twelfth-century
as theyfirstappear. Every grammarian would accept that the words
'genus' and 'species' are nouns. Many of the statementswe have just
examined say littlemore than that. And in the "game" of obligations,
it was common practiceto temptan opponent into a fallacyby accepting as simple supposition what was meant only as material or personal supposition, or by equivocations or confusions in meaning.
Moreover, much of the language is simply terministlogic that does
not clarifywhetherthe categories themselves,not just the words, are
only in the mind.31 A furtherdifficultyis that while some antinominalist texts seem to make nominaand vocesinterchangeable,far
more texts,especiallythe pro-nominalisttexts,distinguishthem from
each other. Nominamight be thoughtof as fallingwithin the larger
category of verbal sounds (voces). Voceswas also the label used for
inflectionsof nouns and verbs that only consignify,while nomina
Most importantly,forthe Nominales,nominawere the bearers
signify.32
ofmeaning apart fromthe particularsof timeand place. It may be that
the so-called nominalistposition on universais did not grow out of vox
theory(verbal sound, not a 'thing') as has been suggested, nor the
view that common natures or universais are mere names as opposed
to real entities,but has anotherorigin.33Just as the Nominalist theory
of propositional truthwas based on the timeless meaning of nomina
(i.e., behind tensed propositionsthat are true lies an untensed form
that is always true as believed, known, willed at any point in time),
31In thiscontextit is well to recallDe
between''logical
Rijk's distinction
nominalism"
and "philosophical
nominalism"
in his introduction
to Abelard's
Dialctica
believethatlogicis an arssermocinalis
' xci-xciv.
, thatit
Logicalnominalists
is aboutlogicalentities
andthewaylanguages
andonlyindirectly
hasexteroperate,
nalreality
as itsprincipal
thatphilosophical
nominalism
object.De Rijkmaintained
orsubjectivist
thatwecannotreallyknowextra-mental
conceptualism,
namely
things
becausetheyaredependent
on andshapedbythehumanmind,wasneverseriously
or defended
entertained
in themedieval
nominalism
period.Logical(or medieval)
an indirect
linkbetween
whichmight
be thought
accepted
logicandexternal
reality,
ofas logic'ssecondary
object.
32See, forexample,Williamof Auxerrein listof texts,#52c.Cf. Rolandof
Summa
Cremona,
, in listoftexts,#54a.
33In discussing
realist
Abelard,De Rijknoted(Dialctica
, xciii)thattherespective
andnominalist
ofuniversais,
whilehavingreceived
themostattention
interpretations
in discussions
of realismand nominalism,
are onlyparticular
oftwo
applications
different
viewson thenatureoflogic.
radically
167

09:11:54 AM

so it is the abilityof nominato embrace many entitiesin time and many


individual cases withoutchange of meaning or truththat reveals why
certain typesof words can be predicated of many individuals and yet
retain meaning and truth. Put another way, universal words can be
predicated of many individuals because nominaretain an identityof
tensed propositions about the same truth.
meaning in differently
Turning now from the positions Peter identifiesas Nominalist to
other aspects of his thoughtthat coincide or relate to what we know
to be nominalistic from other sources, two observations can to be
made. First, as was stated above, whereverPeter treatsproblems of
divine knowledge, will, and power, his solution coincides with the
position of Lombard that was generally viewed as Nominalist.
Whatever God knows, he always knew; whatever God wills, he has
always willed; whateverGod can do or could have done, he always can
do. The objects of divine knowledge, will, and power, understood
of true profromthe standpointof divine capacity and the significatum
the same,
at
time
remain
some
true),
positions (i.e., propositions
of
Peter's
method
and
undiminished.
Second,
theological
unchanging
analysis, i.e. his way of approaching theologicalproblems, is through
the studyof termsand theirmeanings. Chapter afterchapter,moving
from God and the Trinity to Christ and the Church, are arranged
around the analysis of terms( nomina
) in theologicalstatements,particularly the creed and scripture.Peter's opening chapter is a discussion
of the nomen'Deus', followedby the treatmentof the names forGod
and divine attributesas nomina.3*
Adjectives and adverbs used in the
traditionalstatementsabout God, the Trinity,and the relationof persons are also treated as nomina.35The approach is an analysis of
34PeterofCapua,Summa
'Deus'." Ibid.,
, c. 1(Vat.lat.4296,fol.Ivb): "De nomine
SanctussuntDeus
concedi:FiliusetSpiritus
fol.2rb:"Nos dicimus
quia sanepotest
de Deo.,,
etsituna essentia
ibiessentialiter,
de Deo, et hocnomen'Deus' ponitur
Sicutenimhicnomen'Deus', ita
Ibid.,fol.2vb:"De sapientia
genitavelingenita.
Similiter
ethicnomen'sapientia'...." Ibid.,fol.3ra:"De hocnomine'principium'.
ethocnomen'principium':
Ibid.,
quandoquepersonaliter."
quandoqueessentialiter,
an sitconfol.4va: "Cum autemhocnomen'iustus'significet
essentiam,
quaeritur
ibiessen'Pateret Filiussuntiusti'.Si enimhocnomen'iusti'supponit
cedendum:
"
"De
numeralibus
c.
27:
essentiae
sunt
tiampluraliter,
Ibid.,
plures
ergo
scilicet'duo' vel 'tres'." Ibid.,c. 28: "De hoc nomine'Trinitas'vel
nominibus,
'trinus'."
35Ibid.,c. 5: "De adiectivis,
de Deo essentialiter."
scilicet
nominibus
quaedicuntur
Ibid.,Vat. lat. 4304,fol.4vb: "Nos verodicimusquod perhocnomen'talis'vel
inpraedictis
locutionibus."
essentiam
Ibid.,c. 8: "De hocnomine
'qualis'signifcat
'aequalis'." Ibid.,c. 9: De hocnomine'similis'."
168

09:11:54 AM

theological statements through the techniques of terminist logic,


especially supposition.
This method of theological analysis was not the approach of Peter
Lombard, but it was also not inventedby Peter of Capua.36 As Martin
Grabmann noted at the beginning of this century, and as Arthur
Landgraf furtherdocumented, Peter of Capua borrowed extensively
fromPeter of Poitiers both in contentand approach.37 Although the
subjects treated as well as theirorder differbetween Capua's Summa
and Poitiers's Sententiae
, the same analytical techniques are employed
in bothworks. In his second chapterPeter of Poitiers setshis program:
that theologicaldiscourse and analysis has to do with words, and the
words used in theologicalstatementsfallinto various grammaticaland
logical groupings.38 Theological expressions are further divided
between words that are only vocal (sola voce), such as 4simile' and
'aequale*, and those that also have signification(et voceetsignificatone),
such as 'Pater', 'Filius' .39 From there on the chapters revolve around
the analysis of nominasuch as 'persona', 'aliquis', ' unus' 'voluntas', etc.,
applyingthe rules of theologicalvocabulary established in his opening
two chapters and identifyingthe fallacies that occur in theological
syllogismswhen seeminglyvalid equivalents or circumlocutionsare
substitutedin these syllogisms.40The same approach and techniques
are evident in several of Peter of Capua's contemporaries, most

36It shouldbe notedthatalreadyin Lombardand in


conprevioustheologians
siderable
attention
was givento theprecisewording
and meaningof theological
andhowthemeaning
can changewithchangesin wordorder,evenin
statements,
an inflected
suchas Latin.
language
37Grabmann,
Geschichte
derscholastischen
Methode
to
, was thefirstto call attention
on PeterofPoitiers.
MostofGrabmann's
discussion
wasabout
Capua'sdependence
thescholastic
structure
beforehim.
employed
by Capua and by Peterof Poitiers
Grabmann
alsonotedtheterminological
approachthatCapua appliedto thesame
issuesas Lombard
hadtreated.
numerous
Landgraf
produced
parallel
passagesinhis
ofPeterofCapua".
"StudyoftheAcademicLatitude
38PeterofPoitiers,
Sententiae
, ed. P. S. MooreandM. Dulong,NotreDame 1961,
sciendum
I, 10: "His itaquepraemissis,
vocabulorum
quodquae de Deo dicuntur
aliaDeo conveniunt
ab aeterno,
aliaex tempore.
Nectamenintelligendum
estaliqua
ab aeterno
vocabula
convenire
Deo eo quodsintab aeterno,
sedquiacuiuslibet
eorum
ab aeterno
Deo convenit."
Ibid.:"Eorumquae relative
dicuntur
aliasunt
significano
relativa
solavoce,ut'similis','aequalis',secundum
quosdam;aliavoceetsignificatone,ut 'Pater','Filius',et huiusmodi."
39Ibid., 11.
40See, forexample,
3, 4 and following.
chapters
169

09:11:54 AM

notably in Prepositinus of Cremona, but also to some extent in


Stephen Langton.41
When we move beyond the circle of Peter of Poitiers, Peter of
Capua, and Prepositinus we find that the Nominalist solution to the
problems of divine knowledge, volition, and power, as well as the
analysis of theologicalproblemsthroughnominawere thecommon propertyof a much broader group of Parisian theologians at the end of
the twelfthcentury.Most theologians, to some extent,employed terministlogic, suppositiontheory,and the language of significationand
consignification.And most of those who commented on Lombard's
text or who were influencedby it found his solution to the problems
of divine knowledge, volition, and power persuasive. It should be
added that these groups are far fromidentical. Stephen Langton, for
instance, in his gloss on Lombard, employed terministlogic while
eitherignoringor being noncommittalon the principleof semelverum
,
semperverum.42
Does this mean that Parisian theologywas dominated or at least
heavily influence by a group of theologians who saw themselves as
belonging to a Nominalist school? Or is it the case that many
theologians, no matter what their general orientation or affiliation
might be, adopted or applied the opinioNominaliumnot because they
were Nominalists but because this was the opinion of the Lombard or
because it was in itselfa persuasive solution or an attractiveformof
41On Prepositinus
dePrvostin
seeG. Lacombe,La Vieetlesoeuvres
, Kain 1927,esp.
ededuzione
storica
della
distruttura
Analisi
L 'Otodossia
e lagrammatica.
168-70;G. Angelini,
thisaspect
diPrepositino
trinitaria
, Rome1972,whichinpartexplores
precisely
teologia
was a
One problemwiththeviewthatPrepositinus
of Prepositinus's
theology.
on theobjectsof
is thathe seemstohavehelda restheory
nominalist"
"theological
knowledgeand belief;see Nuchelmans1973, 177-85.On Langtonsee Der
Mnster
desKardinals
Sentenzenkommentar
1952,
, ed. A. M. Landgraf,
Stephan
Langton
44
ut hoc nomen'essentia';alius
aliusessentialis,
e.g. 7: Nota,quod terminorum
ut'Pater','Filius',et
ut'paternitas',
'filiado','spiratio';aliuspersonalis,
notionalis,
Non
tamensupposita
est
vera:
Pater
Haec
Sanctus'.
perpaternitas.
ergo
'Spiritus
de
notio."The approachis notusedin PetertheCantor'sSumma
sonasupponitur
ofthatworkdoesnotlenditself
consiliis
etanimae
sacramentis
, butthesubjectmatter
oftheTrinity.
as wellas thedoctrine
to terminist
analysis
42Langtonchosenotto comment
on God'sknowledge
on thecrucialthirdchapter
secin bookI, dist.41 ofLombard'sLibriSententiarum
, andat theequallyimportant
Sentenzenkommentar
tionon divinepowerin dist.44, Langtononlyremarked,
, 62:
"SecundumNominales,
quicquidpotuit,potest.SecundumRealesaliter,quibus
thatthe
haecdubiaest:quicquidpotuitpotest."ThisviewofLangtonpresupposes
of"Nominales"is inerror,
ofthiswork,whichreads"nos" instead
solemanuscript
as Landgraf
concluded.
170

09:11:54 AM

analysis? I am inclined toward the latterview.43 For Peter of Capua,


'
taking his "nos Nominales' statement at face value, being a
Nominalist and being a Lombardian may have been the same thing.
In conclusion I want to make a few observationsand, I hope, raise
some questionsforfurtherinquiryand discussion. First,thoseof Peter
of Capua's generationthoughtof the Nominalesprimarilyin termsof
language and logic, part of secular letters, not as a school or an
as a
approach among theologians. Peter of Capua's self-identification
Nominalist, iftrue, recalls his early years as a studentof logic, not his
membershipin a contemporarytheological 'school of thought'. Jacques de Vitry's anecdote about Maugrinus (#53) suggests that
Nominalist logicians could later in life become theologians and even
bishops, retainingelementsof theirearlier training.Some theologians
around 1200 applied Nominalistpositionsto theologicalquestions and
believed thatthe Nominalist theoryof enunciables was especiallywellequipped to solve problems relatingto the object of belief,knowledge,
or volition, even if those solutions failed in the eyes of many subsequent theologians.
Secondly, nothing in Peter of Capua suggests that he saw an
Abelardian backgroundto eitherthelogical or theologicaltenetsof the
Nominales.In theologyhe would have traced his Nominalist solutions
to Lombard, not Abelard, and on the side of secular lettersthere is
also no indication that Capua saw any Abelardian ancestry. In fact,
his sole referenceto Abelard suggestsa stance of opposition, not of distant discipleship.44 Moreover, the majority of references to the
Nominalescome in the last quarter of the twelfthcentury,two generations afterAbelard. To talk about them as disciples of Abelard when
not even the anonymous textsso acknowledge Master Peter calls for
some rethinking.Whateverparallels may existbetween these textsand
those of Abelard- and the parallels are many- , the Nominalesdo not
seem to be self-conscious
disciples of Abelard in the same way as the
theologians and texts identifiedby David Luscombe.45
43Prepositinus,
forexample,
referred
totheNominales
as iftheywerea grouptowhich
he didnotbelong.Moreover,
he seemstohaveheldtoa restheory
on theobjectof
belief.
44Peterof
, Vat. lat. 4296,f. 27ra:"Ad hocdicuntquidamet hoc
Capua,Summa
dicebat,ut fertur,
Abaialardus,
quodactuset voluntas,
quamvissintdiversa,sunt
tamenidempeccatum,
nechabentproinconvenienti
si aliquodpeccatum
estduo,
immoetiamtria."
45Luscombe1970.
171

09:11:54 AM

Thirdly, as Calvin Normore and I independentlyargued some time


back, nominalism seems initiallyand primarilyto have concerned a
theory of propositions as bearers of truth,and the significationof
nouns in propositions.To the degree thatit came to embody a theory
of universais, it grew out of significationand a view of the proper
sphere of logic. The question is not whetherevery genus and every
species is a noun. Grammar teaches that much. And it is the nature
of nouns that are not proper to be predicable of more than one
individual thing. Such an approach does not address the question of
whethersuch nominaare creations of the human mind or have some
basis in externalreality.Perhaps we should be more inclinedto accept
Peter of Capua's descriptionof the Nominalist position, namely that
nominaare part of the nature of thingsand that theirimpositionsare
fromGod, not man.
Madison, Wisconsin
University
of Wisconsin

172

09:11:54 AM

Vivarium
XXX, 1 (1992)
:
Logico-TheologicalSchoolsfrom the Second Half of the 12th Century
A List of Sources1
IWAKUMAYUKIO and STEN EBBESEN

Severallogico-theological
areknowntohavebeenactiveinthesecondhalf
schools
ofthe12thcentury.
Thisis an exhaustive
ofthesources
collection
weknowinwhich
arereferred
tobyname.We haveonlyomitted
theHelistae
, who
anyofthoseschools
Promisimus
appearsolelyinGlossa
(seetextsin Hunt1940/43,
pp. 52-54).Forthetwo
schoolsknown,WaldicellHWaldilli
and vocales
, see sourcesin De
early12th-century
Our collection
does not
Rijk 1966,p. 4 and Iwakuma1992b, 1, respectively.
includepassagesinwhichtheadjective
fora school-name
is attached
to thenameof
theschool-founder
toAdam).
attached
(e.g. Parvipontanus
The following
school-names
occur.
Adamitae
21, 52e,53, 55-57,(cf.42).
Albricani
18, 24, 25b.
11.
Coppausi
Gilebertini 33c,34.
Meludinenses16b,21, 23, 25c,38, (cf. 15, 16a).
Montani
10, 11, 25a, 36n,41a, (cf. 1).
nominales 4, 5, 8, 9, 11, 12, 13, 18, 19,20, 22b,23 25h,26, 29, 30, 31, 32,
33a-b,35,37,39a,40a-b,44a,44c-e,45,46,47,48a-d,50a-d,51ab, 52c-d,f,53, 54, 58, 59, 61, 62d,64a-c,65a, (cf.60).
Parvipontani 14, 18, 24, 39b,49, (cf.2, 7b, 26, 28, 41b,42).
Porretani
17,18,25d-g,27,36a-m,44b,47,52a-b,62a-b,62e,63,65b,66a-e,
67a-b,68, 69, (cf.etiam11,62c).
reales
5,9, 13,18,22a-b,25h-i,29,31,32,35,43,44a,44c-d,45,46,48cd, 52d,53, 59, 60.
Robertini
18.
The Coppausi
areotherwise
unknown
andno convincing
hasbeenfound
explanation
forthename,whichis undersuspicion
of beinga scribalerror.Thereis also a
reference
wellbe a locative
'in Chartres';
no
, whichmight
(No. 3) toCarnoti
genitive
Carnotenses
havebeenotherwise
foundso far.
ofSt. Victor,whowasnota member
ofanyoftheaboveschools,in his
Godfrey
Fonsphilosophiae
thatin his day therewerefiverivalsects,the
(No. 18) reports
and foursortsofreales
nominales
Robertini
and Parvipontani.
, viz. Porretani,
Albricani,
in hisEntheticus
schools.
JohnofSalisbury
(No. 7a) seemstoalludetofourdifferent
We thenarriveat thefollowing
oftheschooldivisions
in thesecondhalfof
picture
the12thcentury.

1 We wouldliketoexpress
hereoursincere
to Dr. C.H. Kneepkens,
and
gratitude
Mrs.K.M. Fredborg,
Dr. I. Rosierand Prof.K. Tachau,whoprovided
thetexts
numbered
whogavemuchgood
25h,17,43 and 70, and to Prof.W.J.Courtenay
adviceandinformation.
173

09:12:08 AM

followers
of othernames
John
he whocorrects
errors
of
Abelard
PeterAbelard
nominales
Gilbert
ofPorretaGilebertini
reales Porretani he whobelieveshimself
Albricani to be wiserthanhisown AlbericofParis Montani(?)
Alberic
master
Godfrey

Robertini he whosmellslikeMelun RobertofMelun Meludinenses


ofthe
Inhabitant
"ModicusPons"
Parvipontani

AdamofBalsham
'Parvipontanus' Adamitae

betweenschool-names
and particular
thinkers
The correlations
proposedin the
In particular,
newnoruncontroversial.
W. Courtenay
abovetableareneither
([1986]
thetraditional
ofnominales
identification
as followers
1991a,[1992a])haschallenged
ofPeterAbelard.
areidentical
wasfirst
ThatMontani
andAlbricani
byDe Rijk(1966).Hunt
proposed
Promisimus
bothnamesinGlossa
theyreferred
(No. 25a-b),thought
(1950),whofound
tothink
so (thusSouthern
andsomescholars
havecontinued
totwodifferent
schools,
ofideninfavour
1982,p. 114.Kneepkens
1987,I p. 373).In fact,theonlyargument
onMtSainteGenevive
(henceMontani
); butsodidAbelard
tityisthatAlberic
taught
andRobertofMelun(seeJohnofSalisbury,
Metalogicon
11-10).Threeconsiderations
viz.(a) Glossa
Promisimus
usemore
theidentification,
doesnototherwise
speakagainst
Alberic
is notknown
tohavetaught
thanonelabelforthesameschool;(b) Whereas
are of a
almostall the thesesthatthesourcesascribeto theMontani
theology,
school-names
are derivedfromthefounder's
character;
(c) Generally
theological
thatwerealsoappliedtothe
name(Adamitae
, Robertini
, Gilbertini
) ortheyareadjectives
Porretanus
Montanus
founder
,
(Meludinensis,
Parvipontanus,
), butno sourcecallsAlberic
toWilliamdeMonte.
to himand not,as commonly
unlessNo. 41a refers
supposed,
is lessdoubtful,
butone worry
ofMeludinenses
withRobertini
The identification
Is itnotstrange,
rather
thanas a logician.
Robertwonfameas a theologian
remains.
is theological?
toMeludinenses
then,thatnoneofthethesesascribed
Theyall belong
to thesphereoflogic.
intothenature
research
ofsourceswillstimulate
further
We hopethiscollection
ofsources
andwouldbe grateful
tobe informed
of12th-century
andidentity
schools,
we haveoverlooked.
Editorial
principles
in a roughchronological
order.
The textshavebeenarranged
fromwhichsourcewe quoteeachtext.
The sign(#) indicates
theirinformation
editions
wedo notin generalreproduce
Whenquotingprinted
emendations.
and conjectural
aboutvariantreadings
wenormalize
theorthography
andusethefollowfrom
Whenquoting
manuscripts
ingconventions:
addition
or interlinear
'X/ X is a marginal
bythescribe.
buthas beenaddedbyus.
<X> X is in no manuscript,
174

09:12:08 AM

butshouldbe deleted.
[X] X is in themanuscript(s),
buthas beendeletedbythescribe.
[[X]] X is in themanuscript,
ofX and Z as XYZ.
consisting
X(Y)Z We solvetheabbreviation
toexhaustivity.
do notpretend
underLit. ( = relevant
Theentries
literature)
see
Fora keyto theabbreviations
(author'sname + datewhennecessary),
thebibliography.
List
1

to De Rijk 1966p. 38)


ANON., IN CATEGORIAS
(late1130'saccording
a 'Monte',
denominative
nonsumitur
Dicimusquodhocnomen'montanus2'
triaessentnecessaria,
sumptum,
quia ad hoc <ut> essetdenominativum
nomenetutnomenadiacentis
ethaberet
essetin subiecto
utproprietas
scilicet
insubiecto,
itaquod
existentis
a nomine
< sum> ptiessetsumptum
proprietatis
et differret
in fine.Quia omniahuicdeficiunt,
cumeo in principio
conveniret
ab abitatione
ab eo. Sed sumitur
sumptum
quare non est denominativum
hocnomine'montanus',quod sumitur
Montis.... Set hicrusticus
participai
monte:ergomonsestin eo.
a 'monte',ergoet re;sicparticipt
denominatiue
2 Itisdoubtful
De Rijk(1966p.
thisword
ismeant
as a school-name,
whether
although
isa MonofAlberic
ofParis,
theanonymous
a follower
itasevidence
that
author,
37)takes
1987p. 274f.
tanus.
Cf.thediscussion
byLewry
MS Padua,Bibl.Universitaria
2087,f. 4vb.
Lit. De Rijk1966p. 37 (#), Lewry1987p. 274f(#).

GOLIAE
METAMORPHOSIS
Interhoset aliosin parteremota,
ParviPontis
nonloquorignota,
incola3,
in iota,
195
directis
disputabat
digitis
et quecumquedixerat
erantperse nota.
3 Thisisa reference
toAdamParviponianus
, nottohisschool.
Terzaserie
aus
Ed. Huygens,
R., Mitteilungen
, in:StudiMedievali,
Handschriften
III, 1962,p. 771(#).
1954p. 163.
Lit. Minio-Paluello
49

S
ANON., IN PERIHERMENIA
TRANSPOSITANOMINAET VERBAIDEM SIGNIFICANT(DeInt.10,
20bl).
Ne alicuivideretur
siclegithunetransitm:
noster
quodtransposita
Magister
removet
Aristoteles
nominaet verbavariarent
sensusorationis,
illuddicens:
inquibustransponunTRANSPOSITANOMINAET VERBA,i.e. orationes
turnominaetverba,IDEM, i.e. eosdemintellectus,
SIGNIFICANT,uthaec
oratio'estalbushomo'et haec'homoestalbus'. .../262a/...
intellectus
sed
habentur,
MagisterGuidodicitquod numquamcompositi
sicutipereuunt(!)
vocesproferendo,
sicet simplices
intellectus.
Sed secundum
estuerusuel falsus.
hocnullusintellectus
Carnotidicuntorationem
intellectum
eteumposse
in
simplicem
significare
Jundari
anima- habentenimmirumquomodocompositus
in re
intellectus
fundetur
175

09:12:08 AM

sicutnonestmirum,
caren'tepar/tibus.Undedicimusnoressemirandum,
est
in
re
< composita
>.
unitas
'est/
'res
simplex
rex)/
quae
(]
quod
Ms Orlans,Bibi.mun.266,pp. 261b-262a
(#).
1987I p. 374.
Lit. Kntfepkens
4

DE UNIVERSALIBUS
etspecies
sibiconfingere
uocabula.
nominales,videntur
Alii,scilicet
Quod
genera
In primoper Aristotelem
dicentemin
videturhaberiposse multipliciter.
Si quis assignet
Praedicamentis:
quid sit,convenientius
primamsubstantiam
estvocumproferri,
proferens
speciemquam genus;proprium
assignabit[ur]
in Praedicamentis,
quare generaet speciessuntvoces. ... ItemAristoteles
ait:Omnissubstantia
videtur
etindividuis,
etspeciebus
loquendode generibus
estvocum,
autemproprium
hocaliquidsig< nifi> care;significare
quaregenera
et speciessuntvoces....
Clm 29520(2(fragment)
Ms Mnchen,
(#).

to De Rijk
ELENCHORUM(1155/60according
SUMMASOPHIST1CORUM
1962,p. 89)
alia 'temptando',
Etdicitur
quiatamdiutemptat
'temptativa'
(seil,disputatio)
Ut
quem,quasi velitad<d>iscere, quousqueducateum ad inconveniens.
sunt
sic:
"nominum
reales
dicunt
nominales
propria,
erga
quedam
quidam
quedam appellativa;que autemsunt appellativa,sunt nata predicaride
igitur
quedamnominasuntuniversalia".
pluribus;
Ms Paris,Bibi.Nat.,lat. 15141,f. 3vb.
Ed. De Rijk1962p. 276.3-7(#).

OTTO OF FREISING, GESTAFRIDERICI (1156/58)


Rozelinum
Habuittarnen
quenprimopreceptorem
(seil.PetrusAbaelardus)
et post
in logicasententiam
vocum
instituit,
dam,qui primusnostris
temporibus
Guillelmum
ad gravssimos
Laudunensem,
viros,Anshelmum
Campellensem
dictorum
Catalaunensem
pondustamquam
migransipsorumque
episcopum,
induens
nondiusustinuit.
Indemagistrm
vacuumiudicans
acumine
subtilitatis
ininventionum
subtilitate
nonsolumad phylosophiam
Parisius
venit,plurimum
animisutilium
ad iocoshominum
sed et pro commovendis
necessariarum,
monachusin
valens.Ubi occasionequadamsatisnota non bene tractatus
ac meditationi
lectioni
est.Ibi dienoctuque
effectus
sanctiDyonisii
monasterio
intantum,
utpostalide litterato
efficitur
incubans
de acutoacutior,
litteratior,
sui
solutus
ad
abbatis
obedientia
ab
docendique
publicum
prodiret
quodtempus
in naturali
tenens
seunominum
assumeret.
Sententiam
officium
rursus
ergovocum
docenset
admiscuit.
noncautetheologiae
facltate
Quarede sanctatrinitate
sedres
trespersonas,quas sanctaaecclesianonvacuanomina
scribens
tantum,
et fideliter
hactenus
et pie credidit
discretas
distinctas
suisqueproprietatibus
eadem
caeteradixit:Sicut
inter
nonbonisususexemplis,
nimisadtenuans,
docuit,
etfiliusetspiritus
essentia
estpater
etconclusio,
itaeadem
oratio
estpropositio,
assumptio
sanctus.
Ed. G. Waitz,MGH in usumscholarum
46, p. 69 (#).
1991app. 14-15,32-33,Iwakuma[1992b].
Lit. Normore
p. 203,Courtenay

176

09:12:08 AM

7
a

JOHN OF SALISBURY,ENTHETICUS(1154/62)
49
novusauctorin arte,
IncolasumModiciPontis,
essemeum:
dumpriusinventum
glorior
quoddocueresenes,necnovitamicaiuventus,
inventum
iurofuissemei!
pectoris
53
circumdat
Sedulameiuvenum
turba,putatque
nonnisiveraloqui."
grandiaiactantem
dicaxredolet
Isteloquaxminimumque4
Melidtunum
,
Albrico
creditur
doctioristesuo,
hicAbaelardi.
57
errores
verbosus
corrigit
4 minimumque
siced.,annimiumque
legendum?
Ed. JanvanLaarhoven
I, p. 109(#).
II
1954p. 163,Van Laarhoven
Lit. De Rijk1967Pt 1 p. 288,Minio-Paluello
p. 263.
meusa Chonchis
Willelmus
205
Hunc( = Furvum)
saepelegebat,
amat.
huncetiamnosterPontilianus5
5 a reference
toAdamParvipontanus
II, p. 277,n. 206,&p. 263,
(?); cf.VanLaarhoven
n. 49b.
Ed. Van Laarhoven
I, p. 119(#).
II p. 277.
Lit. Minio-Paluello
1954p. 164,Van Laarhoven

JOHN OF SALISBURY,METALOGICON
(1159)
Deindepostdiscessum
eius( = Abaelardi),
uisusest,
qui michipreproperus
enitebat
et
adhesimagistro
dialecticus
Alberico,
qui interceteros
opinatissimus
eratreueraNominalissecteacerrimus
impugnator.
Ed. Webbp. 78.6-10(#).
1991ap. 16.
Lit. Reinersp. 59 n. 1, Courtenay

JOHN OF SALISBURY, EPIST. 238 MAGISTRO BALDEWINO


ARCHIDIACONO
EXONIENSI(1167/8)
Nostipridem
nominalium
tuorum
eo michiminuspiaceresententiam,
quodin
totaconsistens
rerumnon assumpserit,
cum rectum
sermonibus
utilitatem
indubium
sitquodresquaeritphilosophia,
nonuerba.Vtergocomsapientibus
Benedicto
pendiosius
agamtecummeorummorerealium,exlitteris
quaenostro
directae
suntcolligesin quo calculocausasacerdotii
et regni.
uersetur
Ed. W.J.MillorS.J.& C.N.L. Brooke,TheLetters
Vol. II,
ofJohnofSalisbury,
Oxford1979,p. 450 (#).
Lit. Du CangeV p. 604,Reinersp. 59 n. 2, Courtenay
1991app. 15-16.

10 ANON., QUAESTIONESTHEOLOGICAE
Itemquaeritur
utrum
Christus
habuerit
animametcorpusetcaputet
partes,
MontaniMs) dicuntquodethabuit
pedes.Ad hocquidam(etinmargine
scripsil
haspartesethas(] hocMs), etquodaliquaparsestvelp(erson)aex illiscomsedaliposita;nontarnen
aliquidestexilliscompositum,
quia nullasubstantia,
qua p(erson)a.Contrahoc ....
177

09:12:08 AM

Ms Oxford,
Bodl.Libr.Laud., lat. 105,f. 249va(#).
Lit. Hunt1950p. 89.
11 COMPENDIUMLOGICAE PORRETANUM ( 1155/70)
Atcumfereab omnibus
totum
dicatur
disgregativum
plura,ettotum
contiguum
dicaturesse plura; quod tarnena Montanis negaturac <a> raris6
<conceditur>nisia Nominalibus
et Coppausis,quideomni
toto
concedunt
Jere
Sed hecpositiononab omnibus
nostredoctrine
quodsitsuepartes.
professoribus
a quibusratioveritatis
noninvestigatur.
recipitur,
6 quodtamcn
- raris
ante
totum
habet
Codex
editores.
, transposuerunt
contiguum
Ms Oxford,
f.
Christi
21rb.
Corpus
College250,
Ed. Ebbesen/Fredborg/Nielsen
1983,p. 39 (#).
Lit. Normore
p. 204,Ebbesen& Iwakuma1983p. 81.
12 ROBERT OF PARIS,SUMMA'BREVESIT' (1160,according
toKneepkens)
Similiter
etaliudpredicatorii,
locutioni
ut'Socrates
est
apudNominalesaliudsubicitur
homo1:
scilicet
homo
subicitur
sed
iste
terminus
sitie
hocnomen
Socrates,
tile,
locutioni,
*subicitur
'Socrates
predicationi.
Ed. Kneepkens
1987II, pp. 162.32-163.2
(#).
13 RALPH OF BEAUVAIS,GLOSESUPERDONATUM (1150/1
175)
Personamsic definiuit
Augustinus:
personaest indiuiduaessenciarationalis
creature.
Essenciadicitur,
nomine
substantialiter.
quodsignificatur
Quia essencia significatur
nomine
uniuersali
substantialiter
uthocnomine
'homo',quaeest
Nominalesuerodicuntstatumspecialem
communis,
quodRealesuniversale,
- ethuiusmodi
uelgenerlem
nonestpersona- , ideoadditur
'individua'....
Ed. C.H. Kneepkens,
Glosesvper
Donatvm
, (= Artistarium
RalphofBeauvais,
2),
Nijmegen1982,p. 21.2-8(#).
14 ARSMELIDUNA(1170/1180
to Hunt1975p. 112n. 8)
according
Contraid veroquodpraediximus
ad categoricam
nonsequicontinuativam,
sic
obiciet
sustinens
necessarium
exquolibet
enuntiabili
Parvipontanus
sequi:'si Socrates
esthomo,Socrates
estanimal,ergosiesthomoestanimal,si esthomo'.Instantia ....
Ms Oxford,Bodl.Libr.,Digby174,f. 236ra(#).
Lit. De Rijk1967Pt 1 p. 277 & 356,Iwakuma[1992a].
15 SECTAMELUDINE
<S>ecta Meludina
veluterroris
medicina.
Hac fitdoctrina
nota,notagemina
<M>eludinaeprofessionis
quam ea parsphilosophiae
quae ratiodisserendi
dictaest,sibiducemelegit,perfecta
etintegra
inhuiusoperisvolumine
consummaturcognitio.
178

09:12:08 AM

Ms London,Brit.Libr.,Royal2 D XXX, f.95ra(#).


1983p. viii.
Lit. De Rijk1967Pt 1 pp. 282-283,Ebbesen/Fredborg/Nielsen
MELIDUNAE
16 FALLACIAE
a

Non
nonesseduoettria
estquinqu
Meludinensis
, necduoettriaessequinqu.
positio
necdisiunctam
nisi
nisiverasit/21rb/disiuncta,
enimconcedimus
coniunctam
istam'duo ettriasuntquinqu',nec
verasitconiuncta.
undenonconcedimus
istam'quinqusuntduo et tria',necistam'Socrateset PlatosuntSocrateset
...
sicopponitur.
Plato'.Nobistarnen
f.
lat.
Ms Paris,Bibl.Nat.,
4720A, 21ra-b(#).
exquibus
nullam
esseveram
nisicategoricae
Meludinensium
sententia:
hypotheticam
'si Socrates
estasinus,
sintverae.
constat
Undefalsaesthaechypothetica
hypothetica
'Socratesestasinus(] animal
estanimal',quiafalsaesthaeccategorica
Socrates
huiushypotheticae.
Ms)', quae estin constitutione
Ms Paris,Bibl.Nat.,lat. 4720A,f. 22ra(#).

17 ANON.,IN PRISCIANUMMAIOREM
siccontra(?).... Item
Dato enimhocnomen'homo'significare
qualitatem,
hoc quodlibetsubstantivum^
nomenesse denominative
accidetsecundum
ab aliquaproprietate.
Socrates
denominatur
etsic
enima Socratitate
sumptum
de aliis,quae mentiuntur
Porretani.
s transcription
K.M. Fredborg'
(#).
Ms Leiden,BPL 154,f. 59va.
18 GODFREY OF ST. VICTOR, FONSPHILOSOPHIAE(1178)
De modernis
philosophis
de nominalibus
et realibus
et primm
245
Addunt
hicse sociosquidamnominales,
Nomine,nonnumine,taliumsodales;
Aliiuicinius
assuntquosreales
248
res,quodsuntueretales.
Ipsa nuncupauit
Namsi proreatibus
uariiserrorum
Poterat
realiumnomendicihorum,
Tamenexcusabilis
erroresteorum;
mosestinsanorum.
Menticontradicere
252
nomenessegenus,
Namquemensuel cogitet
mentisalienus,
Solushoccrediderit
Cumsittotgeneribus
rerummundusplenus
Cuiusgenusnomenestsempersitegenus.
256
Ceterum
realiumsuntquamplures
secte,
a reaturecte,
Quas reaiesdixeris
noneuntdirecte
Quia ueritramitem
Nec fluenta
260
gratiehauriunt
perfectc.
Ex hisquidamtemperant
Porri
De Porretanis
condimenta,
contenta;
Quorumgenuscreditur
generis
hiipredicamenta,
Decernrerum
triplicant
179

09:12:08 AM

264
ueterum
Euertuntur
perhocfundamenta.
De Albricanis
erratAlbricanus,
Alitersedpariter
CuiusSortesegersit,sednonmanetsanus;
homouanus,
transit
Sed quia uelociter
268
maneatinsanus.
Etiamdummoritur
De Robertinis
Herentsaxiuerticeturberobertine,
Saxeeduritieuel adamantine,
Quos nec rigatpluuiaequerosdoctrine;
272
mine.
Vtantamnisaditumscopulorum
nihil
uere,
Istifalsum
litigant sequi
posthocabiere,
ipsimet
Quamuistarnen
millefere:
nomine
solo
de
fingunt
Qui
276
Igiturpronihilolicethoscensere.
De
extruxerunt
suis
manibus
Paruipontanis
pontem
Quidam
fecerunt
transitm
Et peraquas facilem
In quo sibisingulidomosstatuerunt,
280
nomenacceperunt.
incole
Undepontis
Louvain/Lille
Namurcensia
Mediaevalia
Analecta
8,
P.
Ed.
Michaud-Quantin,
1956,pp. 43-44(#).
1991app. 15-16,35-36.
Lit. De Rijk 1967Pt 1 p. 282; Courtenay
19 WALTER MAP, DE NUGISCURIALIUM(1181/2)
indialetica
quamin
... magisti
Nominalium,
qui pluspeccauit
Petri,principis
inillacontracorlaborauit,
diuinapagina;naminhaccumcordesuodisseruit,
et muitosin eosdemlaboresinduxit.
Map,De
Ed. M.R. James,rev.byC.N.L. Brooke& R.A.B. Mynors,Walter
78
Oxford
Courtier's
1983,
Curialium:
,
(#).
p.
Trifles
Nugis
1991c
1977p. 128 n. 10, Normore
Lit. Green-Pedersen
p. 204, Courtenay
n. 23.
20 ANON., COM. HAEC EST ON DIF. TOP. (thesecondhalfof the 12th
century)
sintassignandi
(Cf.PL 64,
Etestconsilium
quilociinquibussyllogismis
aperire
esse
locos
errornominalium
destruitur
quinegant
col. 1173C).Et indemanifeste
hanc Boethii,quoniamdicunt
litteram
, molesteexponentes
aptossyllogismis
locosesseaptossyllogismis.
mediantibus
enthymematibus
lat.
Bibl.
Ms Paris,
Arsenal, 910, f. 58va(#).
1984p. 425,Nor1977p. 128& 142n. 88,Green-Pedersen
Lit. Green-Pedersen
morep. 204.
IN SOPH. EL.
21 ANON.CANTABRIGIENSISCOMMENTARIUM
et
estquae potestfieriad unuminterrogantem
secundum
Instantia
opinionem
'Si id
utaturtaliargumentatione
utsi aliquisMelidunensis
nonad quemlibet;
necid quodcurrit
movetur,
ergosi nihilmovetur
aliquidmovetur;
quodcurrit
in universali,
, et
dariinstantia
quoniamexfalsonihilsequitur
movetur',
poterit
hocmodo:'Si
inparticulari,
etiamdariinstantia
Poterit
estnihilmoveri.
falsum
180

09:12:08 AM

estmargarita,
Socrates
nonestlapis,Socrates
nonestmargarita;
ergosi Socrates
in similisecundum
ut si
Socrates
estlapis'.Sed dabiturinstantia
opinionem,
'hoc genusanimalest genushuic
quis Adamitautaturtaliargumentatione
specieihomo,ergoomnishomoestanimal':'hocgenusanimaliaestgenushuic
instantia
inconspeciei<homo>, ergoomnishomoestanimalia'.Itemdabitur
si quis Melidunensisfaciattalemargumentatrariosecundum
opinionem,
tionem:'istasuntopposita,
unum,ab eodem
ergode quocumquepraedicatur
risibile
suntparia,
removetur
reliquum':'haecspecieshomoet hocproprium
haecspecieset hocproprium'.
ergode quocumque
Ms Cambridge,
St.John'sCollegeD.12, f. 11Ova.
Lit. Ebbesen& Iwakuma1983p. 84 (#).
TIONE
22 DE PRAEDICA
a

viverbisubstantivi
termino
dicitur
Stricte
copulari
(praedicari
seil.)terminm
'Terminm
etde praesenti
veraaffirmativa
<in> propositionefm]
simpliciter.
in
estad differentiam
termino
dictum
propositionum,
hypotheticarum
copulari'
scilicet
termino
sedpropositio
(]
propositioni,
copulatur,
quibusnonterminus
esthomo,Socrates
ut'si Socrates
sedMs)consequens
antecedenti,
(] sedMs) est
nosteranimal'.Vel ad differentiam
realium,qui dieuntremde repraedicari,
minm
de termino.
Ms Mnchen,
Clm 14458,f. 56rb(#).
Lit. De Rijk1967Pt 1 p. 48.
non
descriptio
generis)
quod haecdescriptio
( = Porphyrii
Amplius[quaeritur]
animatasensoligeneriprobatur
in hunemodum,quia 'substantia
conveniat
de pluribus
differentibus
sibilis'estpraedicabile
specieinquid
quodpraedicatur
etunivoce,
deasino,de capra;ergohaecdescriptio
(] inquitMr)
quiadehomine,
nosnominales
convenit
ei; ergoestgenus.Sedregulaestsecundum
quodnullus
animata
sermocomplexus
estgenusvel species;sed constatquod 'substantia
haec
sensibilis'
est sermocomplexus;
ergonon est genus.Et sibi convenit
soligeneri.
nonconvenit
descriptio,
ergohaecdescriptio
Ad hocduplexestoppositio.
Quidamenimdicunt,et maximereales,quod
convenit
omniet soligeneri;dicuntenimquoddefinitio
(]
praedicta
descriptio
differentia
estgenusetdefinitio
Ms)specieiestspecies.
Mr)generis
(] differentia
est genusvel
Nos autemnominalesdicimusquod nullussermocomplexus
'tantum',et sic est
species.Dicimustarnen
quod addendaesthaecdifferentia
differentibus
de pluribus
ordinanda:
quod praedicatur
genusestpraedicabile
et univoce....
speciein quidtantum
Ms Mnchen,
Clm 14458,f. 57r(#).
Lit. De Rijk1967Pt 1 p. 48.

23 FRAGMENTUMMONACENSE
Contranominales
autemcauteexaffirmativa
coninferendo
Ms) negativam'
(] -rens
traMelidunenses
autemexvero
vele converso
falsum
inferendo
quocumquemodo.
Ms Mnchen,
Clm29520(2[unfoliated
fragment]
(#).
Ed. Iwakuma1992.
Lit. Ebbesen& Iwakuma1983p. 82, Normore
p. 204,Iwakuma[1992a].
181

09:12:08 AM

24 QUAESTIONESVINDOBONENSES
<ex quo generesit> illecumquo < sermo
Et estconsiderandum
> conseritur
Ms). Parvipontanis
(] ParvisPontanis
Ms) concedentibus
(] conserunt
necessarium
: ... (counter
quod (] qui Ms) ex quolibet
(] -rioMs) qui<d>libet
: ...
.... ItemAlbricanis
sunt
omnia
(] alb'icisMs) dicentibus
tempora
arguments)
....
(counter
arguments)
Ms Wien,VPL 2459,f. 108va(#).
Lit. Iwakuma[1992a]n. 7.
25 GLOSS "PROMISIMUS" (thelastquarterofthe12thcentury)
a

demonstratiua
Nota quod dialeticisub nominepronomina
comprehendunt,
sub
necsuntpartesorationis;
relatiuauerodicuntconsignificare,
participium
dicunaduerbia
uelpassionem
uerbo,quiaactionem
quesinerespectu
significat;
habent
non
utbene,maleetsimilia;
subnomine,
turponunt
queuerorespectum
suntuinculapartium
etconiunctiones
dicuntessepartesorationis.
Prepositiones
Interiectiones
orationis.
ponuntsubnomine
quasdam,aliasnon.TarnenMonorationis
nonesse
demonstratiua
tanidicunt
, quiaexdemonstratione
partes
pronomina
non
deberent
dicereuerbaprimeetsecunde
sedhacratione
persone
significant,
habent.
essepartesorationis,
quia demonstrationem
Ms Oxford,Bodl.Libr.,Laud. lat. 67, f. 46va.
Lit. Hunt1950p. 51 (#), De Rijk1967pp. 255-7,Courtenay
[1986]pp. 8-9.

et communis,
internominadubiigeneris
Hec autemestdifferentia
quod illis
istisuero per copulationem.
duo sub disiunctione,
articulara
preponuntur
'Esthomo,ergoesthomo
ad hecargumenta.
instantias
Albricaniindesumunt
'Hie uel hec
'Hic magister',
uel asinus'.Fallacia.Declinatur
ergodeclinatur
Nichilest:bis deberet
ponere'declinatur'.
magister'.
Bodl.Libr.,Laud. lat. 67, f. 66rb.
Ms Oxford,
1987I 298.
Lit. Hunt1950p. 50 (#), Kneepkens
nomen
dicunt
Hoc contraMeludinenses
equiuocum.
qui nullum
Ms Oxford,
Bodl.Libr.,Laud. lat. 67, f. 7Ivb.
Lit. Hunt1950p. 50 (#), De Rijk1967Pt I p. 281.

POSSUNT COMPLECTI OMNES PERSONAS(Inst.Gr.V 74,p. 186.22)


et indesupcuiuslibet
ad dictionem
id estapplicari
persone,
pereuocationem
ponitexemplain omnicasu.
nomen
contra
estPriscianus
Notaquodhicmanifeste
quidicunt
Por(retanos),
substanDicuntenimquodcumnomensignificat
essepersone.
inapposito
nullius
sed
estalicuiuspersone,
substantiam
indequod significat
tiamcumqualitate,
remde qua agitur
ubi supponit
Undein supposito
nonindequodqualitatem.
estalicuiuspersone;in appositoueroubi tantum
apponitnonest
qualitatem
alicuiuspersone.Cum enimdicitur'Ego sum albus', ibi 'albus' tantum
id estpertinet
substantiam,
quodibisignificat
apponit.Nosdicimus
qualitatem
ad substantiam
substantiam,
Porre(ta)nidicuntquodnonsignificat
suppositi.
facitintelligi.
necsubstantiam
eiusintellectus,
nonclauditur
i.e. in substantia
sunthec: cum dico 'Ego sum Socrates'ibi
M(agistri)propria7
Argumenta
ueladiectiuum,
Estsubstantiuum
'Socrates'tantum
ergo
qualitatem.
significat
cumqualitate,
substantiam
estnominis
Itemproprium
adiectiuum.
significare
uel
cumqualitate,
substantiam
sed 'Socrates'ibi nonsignificat
ergouariatur,

182

09:12:08 AM

de tertia
dicitquodibieuocatur
ItemPriscianus
inui nominis.
ergononponitur
et proprie
esttertie
ad primam,
persone,
ergoibiestprime.Itemcumdicitur
etnonexinstitutione,
'Istudestalbum',per'album'qualequidsignifcatur
ergo
et cum dicitur'Ego sum homo', 'homo' significat
quale quid, cum illud
ex institutione.
ItemPor(retani)et clericiMagistiPe(tri)He(lie)
significet
ibi
dicuntomnesquodcumdicitur'Ego Socratessumhomo','ego' significat
sed cumsitproprie
circaquam Socratesdeterminat
substantiam
qualitatem,
cumin propria
cumqualitate,
substantiam
nomen,uidetur
quodibi significet
ibi retineatur
significatione.
7 M(agistri)
corhaud
dubie
m(etadd.etexp.
sicHunt
, Mslegit
propria
dicit)
propria;
propria
est.
nominis
ruptio
proprii
Ms Oxford,
Bodl.Libr.,Laud. lat. 67, f. 74vb.
Lit. Hunt1950pp. 51-52(#).
e

etsic
in-iusessepronomina,
habentia
NotaquodPorre(ta)ni
dicunt
genetiuum
et
declinatione
Ista'unus' 'solus'et similiadeclinantur
pronominum
probant:
Isteloquitur
Instantia.
nisisua, ergoipsa suntpronomina.
nondeclinatione
nisisua lingua,ergoestAnglicus.
et nonloquitur
Anglice,
Bodl.
Ms Oxford,
Libr.,Laud. lat. 67, f. 75rb.
Lit. Hunt1950p. 52 (#).

UNDE QUIDAM8 (Inst. Gr. VI 3, p. 196.21) Donatusquem secuntur


Porre(ta)ni.
8 Inst.Gr.VI3,p. 196.21
: undequidam
ea (seil,
reads
inter
decepti
pronomina
posuerunt
nullus
unus,ullus,
etc).
Ms Oxford,
Bodl.Libr.,Laud. lat.67, f. 75vb.
Lit. Hunt1950p. 52 (#).

HUMNIIOUES (Inst.Gr.VI39,p. 229.17)idestdii.Notaquodquandocumuel recipitadiectiuum,


ut 'AliquisSocrates',uel in plurali
que proprium
Debet enim
retinetur9
ponitur,ut 'Aiaces', non in propriasignificatione
unumaliquid,quare pluralitatem
refugit.Ubi autemnon est
significare
ibinonestpartitio.
UtenimdicitPorretanus:
aliquisetquidamparpluralitas,
Ubi autemnon
de pluralitate.
titiuum
est,undesemperuultaliquidexcerpere
estpluralitas,
neclocumhabet.Quarenonconcedunt
'Aliquisfenix',necetiam
est.Ideoque
ad proprium
fierirelatio
quiaetipsumpartitiuum
per'qui' potest
dicimusquod 'NullamputoPhillidanosti'(Ovid. Ep. II 105)quod 'Phillida'
nonretinetur
in propriasignificatione.
9 ourreading
read
retinentur.
, MsandHunt
Ms Oxford,
Bodl.Libr.,Laud. lat. 67, f. 77ra-b.
Lit. Hunt1950p. 52 (#).

Item.Notaquod sententiam
animivoluntatem
dicimusdefinitam
scriptovel
vocemanifestatam.
Undesententia
realiumdicitur.
sententia
nominalium,
Ms Oxford,
Bodl.Libr.,Laud. lat. 67, f. 46rb(#).

CENSUALIS (Inst.Gr.VI23,p. 131.10)quodad censumpertinet.


Secundum
hancregulam
dicidebeta 'res''ralis*.Undemagister
R(adulphus)
Bel(vacensis)
deridendo
eos semperdicebat'hocdicuntli rales(] raletMs)'. Dicimusquod
'e' estinterpositum
causaeuphoniae.
183

09:12:08 AM

Ms Oxford,Bodl.Libr.,Laud. lat. 67, f. 63va(#).


LiberTytan
Lit. Hunt 1950p. 47; RalphofBeauvais,
, ed. C.H. Kneepkens,
Nijmegen1991,p. X.
26 ANON.PARIS.COM.SOPH. EL. (ca. 1150/ca.1180)
sit
exquo genere
estconsiderare
veromodusducendiad inopinabile
Proprius
etsicinaliis,velcuiusopinionem
an dialecticus
an sitgrammaticus
quidisputt,
In qualibetenimopinionealiquidestquod aliarumprofessoribus
profiteatur.
velutiNominalium
videtur,
Ms) opinioquodnullares
(] opinalium
inopinabile
est
estid in quonullascientia
homo
crescit
, nullus
(] crescisMs), et quod quilibei
ad opinione<m> terreri
dicuntur
nullaratio. Qui veromagisti
J10
intellectus,
autem/ex
eumesseregem.Comperto'
esseasinumsequitur
quodad Socratem
verocomest.Respondenti
eiuspositiointerroganda
quo generesitrespondens,
sed
orationem
modum
estutdicatnonaccidere
interrogantis
inopinabile
propter
pro<pter> positionem.
10 Qui - dicuntur]
teneri
dicuntur
ad opinionem
Fortasse
Qui< dam> veromagisti
eximpossibili
utseil,auctorem
deParvipontanis
quidlibet
sequitenentibus
cogitasse
scribendum,
theseos
eumdeauditoribus
dicuntur
scribenti
dicamus.
Parvipontanae
Qui< dam> ... terrcri
thesim
dicuntur
Nominalibus
Sinvero
dicendum
erit.
scribas,
Parvipontanam
Qui... teneri
cogitasse
tribues.
Ms Paris,Bibl.Nat.,lat.4720A,f. 17rb(#).
Ed. Ebbesen& Iwakuma1990.
27 ANON., QUAESTIONES'1
et eo est
Sanctusaliquoestprocedens
contraPorretanos:
Spiritus
Augustinus
Sanctuset eodemestDeus.
Spiritus
11Thetheological
ff.232-253,
are
lat.1708,
inMsParis,
Bibl.Mazarine,
found
questions
Butthisattribution
isfalse,
aswasshown
toPrevostin.
inthemanuscript
attributed
byA.
14
in:TheNewScholasticism
Latitude
A Study
Academic
ofCapuay
ofPeter
ofthe
Landgraf,
atp. 65andp. 69f.
(1940),pp.57-74,
Ms Paris,Bibl.Mazarine,lat. 1708,f. 252a.
I - La
Omnia
Parisiensis
Cancelarii
Lit. G. Lacombe,Prepositini
(1206-1210)
Opera
dePrvostin
vieetlesoeuvres
, Kain 1927,p. 55 (#); Courtenay
[1986]n. 40.
28 GUIDO OF BAZOCHES, EPISTULAIV (1175/90)
autdisputantibus
autspatiantibus,
PonsautemParvus
, autpretereuntibus,
logicis
est.
didicatus
Parisiensis
Universitatis
Ed. H. Denifle,O.P., Chartularium
I, Paris1899,p. 56
s deBasochis,Stockholm
Guidoni
Liber
1969,p. 14.
epistularum
(#); H. Adolfsson,
29 STEPHAN LANGTON, IN SENT. (1180's)
I, dist.44, cap. 2
Secundum
nominales(] nosMs) quiequid
Preterea".Secundum
potest.
potuit,
Realesaliter,quibushecdubiaest:quiequidpotuit,potest.
Ms Napoli,Bibl.Nazionale,VII C 14, f.90va.
184

09:12:08 AM

Ed. A. Landgraf,
DerSentenzenkommentar
desKardinals
, ( = Beitrge
Stephan
Langton
zurGeschichte
desMittelalters
i.
derPhilosophie
undTheologie
XXXVII-1), Mnster
W. 1952,p. 62 (#).
1943p. 186n. 12.
Lit. Landgraf
to BaldwinI p. 13)
30 PETER THE CHANTER,IN COR.(1170's/97
according
vel'infletur'
alterius,
tanquamipse
(1 Cor.4,6) proaltero,id estprodoctrina
licetillesitNominaiis,illein alterius,
cum
meliorsitilio.Nonenimirascor,
bonuspossitessesicutet ego.
Ms Paris,Bibl.Mazarine,lat. 176,f. 178v.
1943p. 184n. 8 (#).
Lit. Landgraf
to BaldwinI p. 13)
31 PETER THE CHANTER, INJOB.(1170's/97
according
nomenChristi,
remad litteram
etiametnontantum
... decernes
contemplando
ut potiussitrealisquamnominalistheologus.
et humanitatem,
seddeitatem
Ms Paris,Bibl.Mazarine,lat. 178,f. 22v.
Lit. Landgraf
1943p. 184n. 8 (#).
to
ATUM(1191/92
32 PETER THE CHANTER, VERBUMABBREVI
according
BaldwinII p. 245)
deberemus
debentessedomusuniusmorisundeambulare
Itemscoletheologie
scissuras
utinsecularibus
Cumquidamineisfaciunt
indomodeicumconsensu.
litteris,
philosophia
cogitur
quidamreales,quidamnominales.Et sic celestis
uthabetur
inboeicio.
de scissura
vestium
suarum
Baldwin)
conqueri
(] conquere
nilhabetistadomus.
Sed privati
Ms VaticanoRegin.lat.106,f.4ra-b;Paris,Bibl.Sainte-Genevive
250,f.4vb.
Lit. BaldwinII p. 69 n. 74 (#).
33 PETER THE CHANTER,SUMMADE SACRAMENTEET ANIMAE CONto BaldwinII p. 245)
SILIIS (1191/97
according
sitpera
Item.Notaquodquidameoiumdicunt
quodcumhomoilleassumptus
suntVerbumet
scilicet
nullomodoconnumerabilia
incarnatum,
sona,Verbum
Potesttarnen
fierisermode homineilioitaquodnonde
illehomoassumptus.
nominales
litteris
secundum
Verbo,sicutinsecularibus
quodsubstanquidicunt
eniminter
tiaqueestSocrates
desinit
esse.Distingunt
desinit
Socrates
esse,nontarnen
et substantiam
etpersonam.
Nullaconnumeratio
estinterSocratem
essentiam
licetnonloquarde Socrate.
possumloquide illaessentia,
que ipseest,tarnen
Licetenimnon recipiant
conSed istinon ob hoc uitauerunt
obiectionem.
Verbiad hominem
numerationem
connumerationem
illum,tamenrecipiunt
estduo,sicut
diuinenaturead hominem
illum.Vndeconcedunt
quodChristus
scilicet
homoilleassumptus
etdiuinanatura.Etitasecundum
eos,ista
priores,
duopredicabilia,
homoassumptus,
diuinanatura,ponuntur
de eodem,scilicet
de Christo;neutrum
tamende alio,quia necdiuinanaturaestillehomo,nec
e conuerso.
eos utraqueistarum
Item.Secundum
a
estuera: 'Istehomoestassumptus
a Verbo',quia si demonstretur
Verbo','Istehomononestassumptus
persona,
185

09:12:08 AM

istehomo,istehomoest
a Verbo.Si demonstretur
istehomononestassumptus
debent
concedere
a Verbo.Eademratione,
istas;'Iesusestassumptus
assumptus
a Verbo',uthincsupponatur
a Verbo','Iesusnonestassumptus
homo,illinc
Immodebent
hancconcedere:
'Iesusassumpsit
Iesum'.Quodinconuepersona.
in hocnomine
niensest,cumnonsitequiuocatio
Iesus,eo quodnonhabetnisi
Si autemdicatur
inhocnomine
Iesusesseuniuocationem,
unaminstitutionem.
estquod proprium
nomenfaciat
hocinauditum
id estuariamsuppositionem,
uniuocationem.
Preterea.
Si concedunt
istam:'Diuinanaturaetistehomosunt',debentconcederequod illehomocongrueet uerepotestdicere:'Ego et diuinanatura
sumus'.Quod si est,ergoillehomoestalia personaa diuinanatura.
Ed. Dugauquier1967,pp. 480-481(#).
1991ap. 20 + 41.
Lit. Landgraf
1943pp. 189-90,Courtenay
b

cumhocnomenaliquidrectesitsuperius
ad hocnomen
Mirumesttarnen
esthomoquinonestPater',ethecfalsa:
homo,quomodohecsituera:'Christus
'Christusest aliquidquod non est Pater',ut hoc nomen'aliquid' habeat
eamdemsuppositionem
quam habuithoc nomen'homo'. Quare nonpotest
habere?Fortenonestrectesuperius
hocnomen'aliquid'ad hocnomenhomo,
sicutdicuntnominales.Vndesecundum
eos,Socratesesthomoqui ipseerit,
nontarnen
estaliquidquod ipseerit.
Ed. Dugauquier1967p. 493 (#), butwithslightly
changedpunctuation.
Lit. Landgraf
1943p. 190.

Si dicaturquod modo,cumsit tantumpena,est a diabolo;ergoaliquod


bonumesta diabolo,quiaomnispena,saltemineo quodpena,bonaestetiusta
Gilebertini
dicerequodoriginale
inreiueritate
non
est,quiasolebant
peccatum
est peccatum,sed quedamobnoxietas
siue conditiopriuandiuisioneDei.
Iudicaturtamenpeccatumquia idemfacitquod peccatum,
priuatsciliceta
militis
uisioneDei. Sicutetiamidemfacitdelictum
serui,quia
quod seruitas
a mensaDominisui,sedmilespropter
seruusnon
peccatum,
uterquepriuatur
conditionem.
peccatum
aliquod,sed propter
propter
Ed. Dugauquier1967pp. 552-553(#).
Lit. Courtenay
[1986]n. 39 + 75.

34 ANON., QUAESTIONES
ex partepredicamenti
Dicuntad hocGilebertini
tantum,
quodunitasnotatur
sunt
et estsensus:'Pateret FiliussuntunusDeus', id estuniusdivinitatis,
simul
etnominaque attribuuntur
unum,id estuniusessentie
pluribus
personis
nonpredicant
aliquidquodsitDeus,necsupponunt
aliquidvelproaliquoquod
sunttalianomina,utsupraostensum
sitDeus,sedresoluenda
est,etdicuntse
inuenissein Hilarioquod nichilunicumest Deus. De nulloenimunicoet
secundum
eos,potestdici,hocestDeus.
singulari,
Bibl.
Ms Paris,
Nat.,lat. 3477,f. 2rb& f. 113va.
Lit. Dugauquier1961p. 317 n. 101(#), Courtenay
[1986]n. 75.
35 HUMBERTOS DE BALESMA,SERMO(1192/93)
Deo generare
Ex hocsacroconiugio
utranis
bonorum
valeamus,
operumfilios
lutoEgypti
corvisdialectice
relictis,
supercadaverade pedesocratico
logicalibus
186

09:12:08 AM

Dei Patrisassumatur(!),
crocitan
tibusdimissis,
nosex hac molaad dexteram
nominalesvelnominaliter
utsimustheologi
reaies,nonneutraliter
satagentes
ut de caritateprius ordinatain nobis perplexisscripturarum
neutrales,
argentosponse Christi,scilicet
dogmatibus<murenulas> vermiculatas
nostreDeum per fanEcclesiefaciamus,
caventesne in lectulovoluptatis
tasticarum
scientiarum
noctescumphilosophis
prophanis
queratis,sed bonis
civitatem
Dei, ipsum
operibusvigilescum vigilibussanctisqui custodiunt
utlectulisacreScripture
utinveniatis,
nosvitaetdoctrina
laborantes,
queratis,
existentes,
ligna cedrinaauditorumvobis compaginanpossitislaqueara
non ad questumvel gloriam
ut verbumDei sincerepredicando,
cipressina,
veriSalomonis
de LXtareginis
secularem,
sitis,nonde LXXXtaconcubinis,
ne patrimonium
in seculipompiset nugis
caventes
crucifixi
vobiscommissum
inutiliter
sed visceraChristireficiendo,
eius tegendo,
nuditatem
consumatis,
illudpauperibus
utillos,nondivites
vobiscum
commensales
habeatis,
erogetis,
nec quisquilias
vestrasporeisrelinquendas,
vel secundivel terciipaismicas
utsecundum
lectionem
lectamin
pauperibus
quasicanibusimmundis
proiciatis,
si vultisesseChristiani,
nontantum
Christo,
nominales,
quodparumvalet,sed
etiamsemperreales,in vobissemper
legatis.
Ed. M.T. D'Alverny,
Humbertus
deBalesma,
in:AHDL 1984,pp. 127-191,
atpp.
178-179(#).
Lit. D'Alverny
op.cit.,p. 128& 157.
"
36 HUMBERTUS, SUMMA" COLLIGITEFRAGMENTA
accord(1194/1200
ingto Heinzmann)
a
Circa artculos
eiusdemet diversihaec primoproponitur
/5va/quaestio:
utrum
idemsitdeoesseessentiam
.... Conquodessepersonam.
Quodprobatur
tra....
Solutio.Superha<n>c quaestionem
fuitopinio.Quidamenim,ut
triplex
PetrusLongobardus
etsequaceseius,dixerunt
hocnomen'personam'
magister
esseessentiale;
Robertus,
quidam,utmagister
personale;
quidamvero,utPorretanimixtim,
i.e. partim
et /5vb/
essentiale.
personale
partim
Primidixerunt
.... Secundidicunt.... Tertiidicunthocnomen'personam'
essentiam
etnihilominus
distinctionem.
Ethoc
significare
significare
personalem
secundum
nominis
Diciturenimpersonaquasi perse una vel
etymologiam.
unumutunumfaciat
inessentiam
etindistinctionem
utsitsensus:
personarum,
istisuntpersonae,
i.e. suntdistincti
etunum;paterperse estpersona,
i.e. per
se distinctus
etunum.Cumergodicitin plurali'istisuntpersonae',potiushoc
nomen'persona'redundat
inconsignificationem
quaminprinciplem
significationem.
Concedunt
secundum
ergoquodhocnomen'persona'essentiale
prinet personale
secundum
ciplemsignificationem
consignificationem.
Ms Mnchen,
Clm 28799,f. 5rb-vb
(#).
Lit. Heinzmann
p. 14.
b

Et sumitur
haec solutioex auetoritate
Priscianidicentisquod omnenomen
substantiam
et qualitatem,sed aliud pro substantia,
aliud pro
significai
subiectum
qualitate,utputahoc nomen'albus' pro substantiasignificat
utei concretam;
ethocnomen'homo'pro
albedinis,
proqualitate
albedinem(P)
substantia
hocetiamnomen'albedo',ut
hominem,
humanitatem;
proqualitate
placetPorretanis,pro substantia
ipsamalbedinem,
significat
pro qualitate
albendieffectum
qui forte'albities'fictonominepotestvocari.Et ipsihuic
inhaerentes
in tantum
extenderunt
regulaenimispertinaciter
eam,utdicerent
187

09:12:08 AM

hoc nomen'deus' aliudprosubstantia


et aliudproqualitatesignificare,
stainter deum et deitatemsicut inter hominemet
tuentesdifferentiam
humanitatem.
est....
Quod falsum
Ms Mnchen,Clm 28799,f. 13va(#).
Lit. Heinzmann
p. 14.
i.e. circapraedestinationis
effecactionis,
Sequiturviderecircapraedicatum
tum:utrumseil,solapraedestinatio
sitcausavitaeaeternaean etiammerita.
ex auctoritate
.... /33rb/
Contra.Dicitauctoritas
....
Quod sola haberetur
Solutio.Propterhaec et alia dixerunt
Porretanimeritanostranon esse
causamsedviamvitaeaeternae,
etquodnonpropter
merita
necex meritis
sed
meritadaturnobisvitaaeterna.Potesttamen....
propter
Ms Mnchen,Clm 28799,f. 33ra-b(#).
Lit. Heinzmann
p. 14.
de numeralibus,
Secundoqueritur
seil,an pluralitas
sitdicenda
personarum
et an numerus
et an sitibi ternarius.
pluralitas
auctoritate /42vb/Vel siccontraPorretanos,
Quod probatur
multiplici
adessedeo et noninesse
Contra
/43ra/
qui dicuntternarium
hicopiniones.
Solutio.Tresfuerunt
'duo'
Quidamenimneganthisvocabulis
'tres''plures'ethuiusmodi
.... Secundiettertii
dixerunt
significan
pluralitatem
his nominibuspluralitatem
et huiusmodi,
sed differenter,
significan
quia
ternarium
sui generissignifican,
secundi,i.e. Porretani,dixerunt
illumque
adesseetnoninessepersonis,
necesseillastrespersonas,
similiter
etinaliis.Tertiivero.... Ultimamveroopinionem
....
videtur,
quia potioret probabilior
/43rb/Videturtamenet supradictae
opinionesposse salvari.Quod enim
- qui dixerunt
dixit( = primaopinio),.... Similiter
Petrus
Porretani
magister
huiusmodi
vocabulis
numerum
nonsignificari,
etnon
quiquidemadestpersonis
inestnecestdeus- nonmultum
a veroexorbitasse
videntur
Ms Mnchen,Clm 28799,ff.42va-43rb
(#).
Lit. Heinzmann
p. 14.

Porretani
enimquasiinfinitas
intrinitate
introducunt
proprietates,
quasdicunt
adesseetnoninesse,et [et]ideoalia proprietate
dicuntillaspersonas
( = pater
et filius)esseprincipium
sancti.
spiritus
Ms Mnchen,Clm28799,f. 51rb(#).
Lit. Heinzmann
p. 14.

nonesseperQuidamvero,ut Porretani,dixerunt
personarum
proprietates
etquasisinenumero
intrinitate
nam(] non
sonas,multas
fingentes
proprietates,
triaformarum
seu proprietatum
Ms) distinguunt
genera,dicentes
quod formarum
aliaesuntsubsistentiae,
aliaeinsistentiae,
aliaeassistentiae;
subsistentiae
sunt proprietates
substantiales
ut
praedicamenti
quibus res subsistunt,
animalitaset lapiditaset huiusmodi;insistentiae
sunt formaeduorum
seil,quantitates
etqualitates,
insunt
quae itasubiecto
praedicamentorum,
quod
secundum
se afficiunt,
et immutant;
assistentiae
dicuntur
aliorum
disponunt
omnium
etnoninsunt
formae,
praedicamentorum
quaequidemassuntsubiectis
sed quodammodo
sed quodammodo
secundum
Boethium
affixae
extrinsecus,
esse videntur,
nec suntverinominisproprietas.
Et iuxtahuncmodumin
et
subsistentiam
seil.i.e. essentiam,
theologicis
quasiduplexgenusassignant,
- , negantes
assistentiam
ut (] velMs) paternitatem
et aliasproprietates
proesse personas,et forteconcederent
aeternam
et temprietates
paternitatem
poralemunivocedici.

188

09:12:08 AM

Ms Mnchen,
Clm 28799,f. 54ra(#).
Lit. Heinzmann
p. 14.
g

Dicuntenimquidamhaec(] hcMs) nomina,seil,'pater'et 'filius',significare


etappellare
cumproprietate;
alii,
personas
quidamveroproprietates
personas;
ut Porretani,quasi idemdicuntsed distinctius,
dicentesquod haecnomina
'pater'et'filius'prosubstantia
personas,
significant
proqualitate
proprietates.
Ms Mnchen,
Clm 28799,f. 56vb(#).
Lit. Heinzmann
p. 14.
Itemcircaeundemarticulum
essepatremsit
potestquaerian paternitatem
articulusfidei.Quod videturposse probari,quia universalis
ecclesiahoc
< n> turut Porretani,nihilominus
qui' a /etsialiqui[d]dissentia
dogmatizai,
estuniversalis
/59vb/
hocconcedere,
et itaer<r>ant Porretani.
Solutio.Forteprimafalsa,quia praeter
Porretanos
multidixerunt
nonesse
et itanegaverunt
essepatrem
' proprietates
/inpersonis,
paternitatem
Si veroquaeritur
maiuspeccatum
sit,seil,an negarepaterquod illorum
nitatem
si ipsaestpater,an asserere
essepatrem
si ipsanon
ipsamessepatrem
estpater,potestresponden
.... Itemuna solaestpaternitas
patris,quia dicere
et
esset;sedde ea Porretanus
quodpluresabsurdum
negatipsamessepatrem,
aliiconcedunt
Solutio Oppositio Nonenim
ipsamessepatrem;
de eadempaternitate
velproprietate
de paterloquu<n>tur, sed Porretanus
nitte
etaliidepaternitate
nectamenminus
respectus,
quaeesttantum
persona,
estuna solapaternitas
patris.
Ms Mnchen,
Clm 28799,f. 59va-b(#).
Lit. Heinzmann
p. 14.
Itempositoquodvirexlongotempore
sanctissimus
libidinis
furore
labatur
in
amoreminiquitatis
vel
fornicationem,
numquiddiceturquod istepraeponat
meretricis
dilectioni
dei
Solutio.Ad hocdistinguebant
Porretaniintercaritatem
finalem
et ferialem,
earndicentes
finalem
subitaneas
quae nonextinguitur
perhuiusmodi
passiones,
velirae,et negantes
libidinis
illaessemortalia,
i.e. mortedigna.
putafurorem
Latetenim,utaiunt,inradicecaritatis
ad fructum
quamv<i>s nonextenditur
exteriorem.
Ferialemearndicuntquae temporalis
estradiemnonhabenset
Etitasecundum
deficit.
eoscaritasestsimulcumhisquae
tempore
temptationis
mortalia
iudicantur.
Si autemeis opponatur
dicuntquod iliadicta
auctoritas,
suntmortalia
invirotamen
'in suinaturaeo quodsaepead mortem
perducunt,
non/.
perfecto
Ms Mnchen,
Clm 28799,f. 106va(#).
Lit. Heinzmann
p. 14.
Porretanorum
infundatur
(] porretanori
Ms) estopinioquodnullagratiavirtus
veroomnium
puero;aliorum
quodeademprimagratiaquae daturadultodatur
etpuero.
Ms Mnchen,
Clm 28799,f. 152va(#).
Lit. Heinzmann
p. 14.
Circaformarum
causamquaeritur
de virtute
an se ipsavel
quo ipsasitvirtus
..
alio,et si alioquo. .../154vb/.
Solutio.Hoc videntur
concedere
adeostricte
utetiamin trinitate
Porretani,
voluerint
illudservare,seil,cumdicitur'deus est deitatedeus' aliud notet
et aliudnominativus,
ablativus
undeetiamdixerunt
deitatem
nonessedeum,
quodesterroneum.
189

09:12:08 AM

Clm 28799,f. 154va-b(#).


Ms Mnchen,
Lit. Heinzmann
p. 14.
1

et alia
Solutio.Duae sunthic opiniones;una specialisPorretanorum,
generalisomniumaliorum.Porret(an)ibene conceduntvirtutes/156vb/
naturales
esseetiamin pueronondum(] nundum
dicentes
eas
Ms) baptizato,
virtute
fitpoliticaet
dona.Et dicuntquodde naturali
essequaedamnaturalia
notandum
de politicafitcatholica.Quod ut pleniusintelligatur,
quod virtus
dicitur:naturalis,politica,et catholica.Virtusnaturalisest vis
tripliciter
rebusa naturaet cumnaturasimulinsita,etdicitur
virtus
quaedamnaturalis
virtus
etestverenaturalis;
esthabitus
mentis
bene
nitens,
politica
quasiviribus
virtus
estgratiaquamoperatur
deusin hominesine
etc;catholica
const(itutae)
et fineset opera
homine,
qua nemopotestmaleuti.Et hae quidemperofficia
estsimilia
desimilibus
virtutis
naturalis
suntdiscretae.
Officium
facere;
specialia
moreset
virtutis
civilisestcongruus< actus> ' personae
officium
/secundum
velsua,quae duplexest,
sedviseiusestutilitas
reip(ublicae),
institta
gentis,
estcongruus
actusChristiani
autemcatholicae
et honor;officium
seil,utilitas
Christi
etecclesiae.Finiseiusestsummum
moresetinstitta
secundum
bonum,
estillaluctaquamdescribit
virtutis
dicens
i.e. deus.Opus naturalis
apostolus
etc.(Rom.7.14)" etibi"Spiritus
venundatus
concupisci
"Ego autemcarnalis
enimvirtus
carnemetc.(Gal.5.17)". Naturalis
adversus
quae in quolibetest,
rationis
quaenecinCainpotu<i>t extingui,
quae,utputo,
ipsaestillascintilla
contravitium
a quibusdamsuperior
vocatur,quae suppeditata
parsrationis
"Veliemihiadiacet,
naturaliter
cuiusestilludveliede quo apostolus
reluctatur,
autemnoninvenio(Rom.7.18)". Opera veropoliticaesuntopera
perficere
et huiusmodi.
civilia,ut Romanorum
Opera
prudentiae,
opera,seil,iustitiae,
Et notaquodcumdicitur
suntmerita
catholicae
vitae,seil,operaecclesiastica.
ut referatur
ad disposiet finemfaciunt
sane intelligatur
'officium
virtutes',
civilefacitde naturalivirtute
ut sit sensus:officium
tionemipsiusvirtutis,
estad taleofficium,
virtutis
i.e. dispositio
qua (] quo Ms) disposita
politicam,
de catholica.
Etprimaquidem
similiter
naturalem
essepoliticam;
facitvirtutem
secundanaturale,
i.e. ex
i.e. a naturaetcumnaturainsitum;
dicitur
naturale,
seil,naturae
tertia
dicitur
exmotibus,
naturam
naturaetsecundum
proveniens;
velnaturale
estei
i.e. naturaeconsentaneum
homini,
naturale,
quia naturale
De primafitsecunda,de secundafittertia.Itemprima
talemhabereformam.
tertiaest tantum
/157ra/
secundaesttantumofficialis,
est tantumnaturalis,
hominis
desursum
veniens.Nec
et praeoperatione
seil,sineartificio
gratuita,
melius' istapossunt
/intelligi
quam persimilitudinem
quattuor
supradictam
eorundem.Exempli
et naturalium
membrorum
proprietatum
principalium
et
unumhabensnaturales
membris
causa: Cor estde quattuorprincipalibus
ad
exquibusdisponitur
formas
substantiales
quaeadesseetabessenonpossunt,
etcerebrum
ethuiusmodi.
Similiter
animositatis
etad officium
sanitatis
statum
in corpore,
hoc(] haecMs) est
et reliqua.Quod ergoestmembrum
principale
forma
hoc
in anima;et quodestnaturalis
visseupotentia
membri,
principalis
invi. Etsicutaliquandoinnaturales
naturalis
estvirtus
supervenientes
qualitates
et naturalesproprietates
membroipsumaegrumefficiunt
quoddammodo
et forvimanimaecorruptam
itavitiasupervenientia
et opprimunt,
superant
ut vixeiusscintilla
i.e. virtutem,
mamnaturalem,
extinguunt
quoddammodo
aliforma
Haecautemprimanaturalis
luctetur.
morbum
remaneat,
quaecontra
et
in politicam
formatur
actualiter
vitiispraevalens,
quando quodammodo
utdictumest.Sic qualitercumque
opinio
potestintelligi
politicain catholicam,
Porretanorum
quodnemopotest
Ms),etexquo sensudixerint
(] porretinorum
velramorum.
rationeseil,radieiset nontrunci
amittere
caritatem,

190

09:12:08 AM

estquodnullavirtus
estnaturalis
nisiforte
Aliorum
sententia
dicatur
generalis
Istaeopinionessubtiliter
in
i.e. naturaeconsentanea.
naturalis,
perscrutanti
nullovelin modicosibicontradicunt
Ms Mnchen,
Clm 28799,ff.156va-157ra
(#).
Lit. Heinzmann
p. 14.
etquodDavidhabuerit
m Porretani
dicuntquodcaritaspotestessecummortali,
et homicidio;
sedhocdicuntratione
cumadulterio
caritatem
stipitis,
quoniam
habuiteamin radice,nonin foliis.
Ms Mnchen,
Clm 28799,f. 181ra(#).
Lit. Heinzmann
p. 14.
n

a verbo,an
Circaarticulum
causaematerialis
quaeritur
quidsitassumptum
....
/204vb/
aliquishomovelnon
lili de monteconcesserunt
Solutio.Duae sunthicopiniones.
quodquidam
a verbo,nontamenpriusfuitquamassumptus,
homoad litteram
fuitassumptus
etubireperitur
inauctoritate
ete converso.
Aliinegaverunt;
quodquidamhomo
ibi nominehominis
sitassumptus,
humananatura,seil,animaet
intelligitur
In verbisergoconconsistere
caro,etexillisduobusnegant
aliquemhominem.
sonabant
Namutrique
auctores
sedinsensudissonant.
conutriusque
opinionis,
fuisseassumptum
a verbo,sed Montaninominehominis
cedunthominem
hominem
excarneetanimasubsistentem,
sedaliinomine
quemdam
intelligunt
hominis
etnonaliquemveri
humanam
tantum
natura,seil,animametcarnem,
hominem.
Prioriopinioniconsentimus.
nominis
Ms Mnchen,
Clm28799,f. 204va-b.
Lit. Heinzmann
p. 14.

V
37 DIALECTICAMONACENSIS
estquodestcontra
omnium
utmatrem
nondiligere,
vel
Inopinabile
opinionem
utsolemesseoctiesmaiorem
utsi
terra,veleiuscumquo disputatur,
plurium,
sitnominaliset probetur
ei quodaliquid
crescit.
Ms Mnchen,
Clm 14763,f. 108va.
Ed. De Rijk1967Pt 1 p. 558 (#).
Lit. Normore
p. 205 n. 14.
38 JOCELIN OF BRAKELOND,CRONICA(ca. 1200)
nactaoportunitate,
astansei a secretis
dixi:'Duo sunt
Egouerohocattendens,
miror
de uobis;'etcumquesisset
que multum
que duo: 'Unumest,quodadhuc
intalistatufouetis
sententiam
Meludinensium
dicentium
exfalsonichil
, et
sequi
ceterafriuola.'Quibuscumipserespondisset
quoduoluit,adieciego: ...
Ed. H.E. Butler,
TheChronicle
Londonetc.1949,pp.35-36
ofJocelin
ofBrakelond,
COLit. Salisbury,
Metalog.
p. 78 n. 12,De Rijk1967Pt 1 p. 282.
39 ALEXANDERNEQUAM,DE NATURISRERUM(1187/1204,
to
according
Hunt1984p. 26)
a Secundum
doctrinam
autemnominalium
consimilis
oritur
objectioin hister191

09:12:08 AM

aliusestcomplexus,
aliusincomplexus.
Sic enimdividitur
minis.Sermonm
in sermones
sermoincomplexus
incomplexos.
Ed. Th. Wright,
RollsSeries
34, London1863,p. 298(#).
o mores,o studia,o inquisitiones!
DocuereParisius.... Docuere
O tempora,
vel praemissorum,
esse habitudinem
ad illatum,
licet
argumentum
praemissi,
essedictum
condi
quorumfuitunusEthion,dicantargumentum
Parvipontani,
ab argumentatione.
tionalis
transfrmatele
Ed. Th. Wright
pp. 302/307
(#).
Lit. Lewry1983p. 11.

40 ALEXANDER NEQUAM, SPECULUM SPECULATIONUM{ante1213


to Hunt1984,p. 125;post1201Thompson
1988p. 57)
according
a Sed utinsipientem
et uirprudens
sibi,queroa tequi catholicus
es,
relinquam
utrum
hocnomine'Deus'
qui dicitincordesuo'NonestDeus' utatur
insipiens
in iliointellectu
quo tu uteris,aut non.Si in iliointellectu,
numquidpotest
summum
essenonesse?Si inaliointellectu
utitur
hocnomine'Deus'
intelligere
Deumnonesse,sedquoddamfigmentum
quodintelligat
quamnos,nonuidetur
de Deo. In logicisquidem
animinonesse.Vndeetiamuidetur
quodnoncogitet
dicerem
nominalem
nonopinari
genusessenomen.Nonenimmagispossetquis
rerum
similitudinem
diuersarum
essenomen,
opinarisubstantialem
specierum
esseasinum Licetquideminsipienti
uideatur
alicuiquod
quamhominem
hecsituera,'Deus nonest',nonob hocdaboquodintelligat
Deumnonesse,
sicutnominalis
putathancesseueram,'Genusestnomen',sednonputatgenus
essenomen.
MediiAeviXI, Oxford1988,p. 57(#).
Ed. Thompson,
Britannici
R.M., Auctores
b Soletautemin logicisqueriutrumessePetrumsitessequem,et utrumesse
Petrum
sitessequid.Quibusdatis,infer
ergo'Essequemestessequid'uelecontrario.Multisuntetpresertim
iudicant
de
nominales,
quieodemmodoprorsus
diuine.Dicuntergo
create,quo etde suppositione
suppositione
persone
persone
estessequemetnonessequid.Vndeetad hanc,'Quis curquodessePetrum
'Petrus'.Ad hancautem,'Quid currit?',
dicunt
rit?',dicuntrespondendum
'Substantia'.Vt enim aiunt, 'Petruscresci,non tamen
respondendum
'Substantia
cresci.Sed nonnecrementum
quodestin Petroestinsubstantia?
Nonnehomospeciesest huiusgeneris'substantia'?
Nonneesse Petrumest
inferius
ad esse substantiam?
Nos uerodicimusquod hoc nomen'Petrus'
undeessePetrum
nonestessequemsedestessequid.
quasiconcretiue,
significat
Ed. Thompson
pp. 123-124(#).
41 ALEXANDERNEQUAM, DE LAUDIBUSDIVINAE SAPIENTIAE(ca. 1213
to Hunt1984p. 125)
according
Lincolniasinecolumna,
a
Lindisiae
colutnen
felixgente,repletabonis,
Munifica,
si te tuusillemagister
Par tibinullaforet,
adhucmoribus
Informaret
atquefide.
sedmonsstabilisfideique
columna,
Montanus,12
840
Cui se coelestis
paginatotadedit.
192

09:12:08 AM

Montanus,meritis,
honesti,
pius,et servator
fuit.
dignafavore
Veraquesimplicitas
cathedram
huicprimam
secundam
Contulit
Genovefa,
honos.
Matervirgo,sacraevirginitatis
Transiit
ad montem
Montanus,monterelicto;
En montana
Syonet loca celsatenet.
sitsignumseu testisamoris;
Haecdigressio
lauseritistaminor.
Condignafateor
12Usually
as a reference
toWilliam
deMonte.
interpreted
RollsSeries
Ed. Th. Wright,
34, p. 460 (#).
Lit. De Rijk1967Pt 1 p. 442.
Vix aliquislocusestdictamihinotiorurbe,
parvacolumnafui.
Qua ModiciPontis
Hic artesdidicidocuiquefdeliter,
inde
Accessit
studiolectiosacrameo.
Ed. Th. Wright
p. 503 (#).
Lit. Hunt1984p. 5.

333

42 GILES OF CORBEIL, VIATICUS(ca. 1200)


manarefluenta
.... cessent
2346
13, Parvipontana
adamantis
columna
fontis
submissim
deponatonus....
13sicinoneofthetwoms,adaratici
intheother,
Adamatici
conj.Rose.
Viaticus
designis
etsymptomatibus
Ed. V. Rose,EgidiiCorboliensis
, Lipaegritudinum
sae 1907,p. 97 (#).
Lit. Lewry1983p. 11,Minio-Paluello
1954p. 165.
43 ANON.,SOPHISMATA
GRAMMA
TICALIA (late12thor early13thcentury)
estressecundum
. 14
Genus
quodrealesdicunt
14'Genus
- dicunt'
isthesophismatic
Thediscussion
concerns
itssyntax
and
proposition.
notthedogmatic
content.
Ms Paris,Bibl.Nat.,lat. 3454,f. 45vb(#).
44 PETER OF CAPUA,SUMMA(1201/2)
a

auteman Deus sciataliquidquodpriusnonscivit.


Quaeritur
quia seitmeesse,quodnonsemperscivit.
Quod videtur,
Solutio:Realisconcedit
fuit
quodsicut'meesse'estverumetnonsemper
itaipsumseitmodoDeusetnonsemper
necideoestscientior
illudscivit,
verum,
sicutistevidetaliquidquod priusnonvidit,non tarnen
habet
quam fuerit;
maiorem
visum.Nominaiisdicitquodsicut'meesse'semper
fuitverum,
itaet
Deus semper
scivitillud;hocenima principio
mundisigniflcabatur15
hacpro'Petruserittune',ettuncDeus scivitsignificatum
huiuspropositionis
positione
'Petruserit',16
et ideoscivitmeesse.Secundum
hosnihilseitquodab aeterno
nonseiverit.
CumDeus possitaliquidscirequod modononseit,quaeritur
utrumpossit
ineipere
aliquidscire.
193

09:12:08 AM

Solutio:Realisdicitquodsicutaliquidpotestincipere
esseverum,itaDeus
scireillud.Nominalisdicitquodsicutaliquidpotest
esseverum
potestincipere
esseverum,ita Deus potest
quodnonestverum,nonpotesttarnen17
incipere
scirealiquidquodnonseit,nontarnen
scireillud;sicutistequi
potestincipere
nonestpraedestinatus
essepraedestinatus,
nontamenpotest
esse
potest
incipere
praedestinatus.
15significabatur]
si potest
Similiter
quaeritur
praescire
aliquid
quodnonpraesciverit.
dealiquodiscrete,
verum
ali/Si divisim
'Responsio.
est,i.e.potest
intelligitur
praescire
sedhocnonconvenit
Deo,se.praescire
quid,etilludnonpraescivit,
aliquid
quodnon
Add
. VI.
praesciverit
16Petrus
eritV2y
DeuseritM a.c.,om.VIetM p.c.
17nonpotest
tamen
'tamen/
tamen
V2.
, necpotest
Vl>necpotest
M,necpotest
scripsimus
=
=
M
f.
#
VI
Vat.
Clm
14508
7vB-8rA
Ms
Mnchen,
Vaticano, lat.4296f.
( );
7vB(#); V2-V at. lat. 4304:f. 7vA-B(#). The apparatus
omitssomeminor
variants.
Lit. Landgraf
1943p. 185.
in personis
Quidamdicunt,ut Porretani,quod huiusmodi
proprietates
quidemsunt,sed nonsuntipsaepersonae;sedsuntproprietates
personarum
in essentiaveronec ipsaesuntnec suntipsa
quasi adiacentes
ipsispersonis,
essentia.
Ms Mnchen,Clm 14508f. 14vA(#).
Itemgeneraetspeciessuntrerum
naturae;ergosunta Deo. Ponoergoquod
nullaactiositbona,nihilominus
verumestquodhocgenus'actio'est,etipsum
esta Deo, ergoaliquodeiusindividuum
esta Deo.
Haec oppositio
nonestcontra
nosNominales,
Responsio.
quiadicimus
genera
essenomina
etspecies
a Deo sunt.
, nominaautemomniaet eorumimpositiones
Reales18auteminstantargumento:
Haec species'homo' 'est/ secunda
estsecundasubstantia;
immoprima,19
substantia,
ergoaliquodeiusindividuum
secundo
circailluddaturintelligi
haec
quiaprimooccurrit
quodestindividuum,
species'homo'vel <hoc genus> 'animal'.
Instantia:Hoc genus 'dare elimosynam'
est a Deo, ergo aliquodeius
individuum.
Quod estfalsum
positoquodomnisfaciatcausainanisgloriae.
18Realesetquaesequuntur
adinanis
insoloVIinvenimus,
om.M etV2.
usque
gloriae
19prima
VI.
scripsimus,
primo
Ms M= Mnchen,Clm 14508f. 26vB(#); K/= Vaticano,Vat. lat. 4296f.
26rB(#); V2= Vat. lat. 4304:f. 26rB(#).
Lit. Landgraf
1943p. 189.
rationalem
individuae
Item,iste Iudaeus creditDeum esse substantiam
nonpotest
naturae,
ergopersonam.
Quia haecestdescriptio
personae,
aliquem
formare
intellectum
circaremrationalem
quinintelligat
ipsamessepersonam.
In Iohanneetiamdicitur
"Est Paterquemvosdicitis,
est
quia Deus vester20
etc." (Ioh.8.54); ergode Patrecredunt
ipsumesseDeum,et sciuntquodnon
potestpateressequin filiussit,ergohabentfidemde Filio;sic et de Spiritu
et Unitatem.
Trinitatem
Sancto,et itacredunt
si Iudaeuscredit
Deumessepersonam,
inhoccredit
nec21
Praeterea,
falsum;
estillapersona,
sicetFiliusetSpiritus
ergoDeusestillapersona.Patersimiliter
Sanctussuntunapersona,
etitatresperSanctus;ergoPateretFiliusetSpiritus
sonaesuntuna persona.
de
Responsio.Catholicusdicitquod hoc nomen'persona'aliterdicitur22
etpraedicta
dataestde hocnomine'peraliterde creatura,
creatore,
descriptio

194

09:12:08 AM

de creaturis.
Cum ergoproponitur
Catholicoan Iudaeus
sona*proutdicitur
Deumessepersonam,
debetaccipere
hocnomen'persona'proutaccipitur
credat
Catholicum
nonsupponat
apudeum.Cumergohocnomen'persona'secundum
IudaeusnoncredatDeum
nisipropersona
PatrisvelFiliivelSpiritus
Sancti,et23
debetdicerequodnoncreditDeumessepersonam,
sicut
essealiquamillarum,
'Realis putatgenusesse nomen',quia secundum
Nominalisconcederei24
nisivox,quam revera
Nominalemper hoc nomen'genus'non supponitur
Realisputatessenomen.Sed interrogatus
Realisdiceret
'Ego nonputogenus
hocnomine'genus'quamvocem.
essenomen',quia ipsedicitaliudsignifican
Sic et Iudaeusdiceret'Ego credoDeumessepersonam',
aliud
quia crederet
hocnomine'persona'quamCatholicus.
significari
Quod verodiciturin Iohanne"Est Pateretc." 'Pater' ibi poniturpro
dicitur
Vel dicaturquod
'Creator'secundum
quodtotaTrinitas
paternobis.25
et in creaturis,
et tuncconcedeneodemmodoaccipitur
'persona'in Trinitate
ad
dumquodIudaeuscreditDeumessepersonam,
sednonestdescendendum
Patrisvel Filiivel SpiritusSancti,nec est
ut personam
aliquamspecialiter,
admittenda
relatio,ut dicatur'Deus estvelnonest illa' sed tantumconfuse
'persona'.26
20vester
VI etV2.
noster
M,utvidetur'
21necVIetV2y
nonM.
22dicitur
V2,om.M etVI.
23et VI, itaM,om.V2.
24concederei
M etV2y
concedit
VI.
25nobis
M etVI,noster
V2.
26persona
VI, personam
M etV2.
Ms M= Mnchen,
Clm 14508f. 38vB(#); VI = Vaticano,Vat. lat. 4296 f.
40rA-b
omitssomeminor
(#); V2= Vat. lat.4304:f.40vA(#). The apparatus
variants.
1943pp. 188-189.
Lit. Landgraf
etantiquorum.
modernorum
Item,aneademsitfides
Quodvidetur,
quiaauctoritas
dicit:"Et quipraecedebant
etqui sequebantur
clamabant
'Osanna' " id
estpraecedentes
adventm
Christiet sequentes
conveniunt
in eiusfide.
Contra.Abraham
habuitfidem
de Christo
venturo
etcredidit
Christum
venesse venturum'
et
turum,modernicreduntipsumvenisse.Sed 'Christum
'Christum
venisse'suntdiversa
enuntiabilia
siveeredita.
Ergoaliudcrediderunt
Christi
moderni.
antiquicircaadventm
quamcredant
Nominaliumquod Abraham
Responsio.Possetdicisecundum
opinionem
credidit
Christum
esseventurum,
namChristum
esseventurum
est
numquam
ipsummodoesse venturum,
quod non crediditAbraham,immocredidit
Christum
venisse,quia istud,licetmododicaturhac 'Christusveni,olim
dicebaturhac 'Christusest venturus';sed Abrahamtunc credebatquod
dicebatur
ista'Christus
estventurus',
etideocredebat
Christum
habuit
venisse;
tarnen
fidemde Christoventuro,
nonimportt
Christum
quia haeciunctura
nuncventurum
sedestsensus'de Christotuncventuro'.
Sed cumnoncrediderit
Christum
determinate
in aliquotempore
venturum,
neccredidit27
Christum
nuncvenisse,
etideonec28
Christum
cumidem
venisse,
sit29
secundum
Nominalem'Christum
nuncvenisse'et 'Christum
venisse'.
Christum
etitaaliRevera,si inhocfiatvis,noncredidit
Responsio.
venisse,
moderni
sed nonestde hoccuran
Abraham,
quidcredunt
quodnoncredidit
dum,quia credidit
aequipollens.
27Sed{velSi)cumnoncrediderit
... noncredidit
... neccredidit
Ml.
Af,Sednoncredidit
195

09:12:08 AM

28nccM, nuncVI.
29sitVI,ponit
(?) M.
Ms AfMnchen,Clm 14508f. 39rA(#); VI= Vaticano,Vat. lat. 4296f.
M and theapparatus
omitsinsignificant
in
variants
40vA(#).The textfollows
VI.
Lit. Landgraf
1943p. 186,Chenu1935/36
p. 13,Chenu1976p. 94 n. 2.
45 PETER OF CAPUA,IN ACT.
Scolavelcollectione
Libertinorum
(Act.6,9). In unascolaeratsectaquorumin alia Cirenses,
sicutnuncaliiNominales,
alii
dam,qui dicebantur
Libertini,
Reales.
Ms Paris,Bibl.Mazarine,lat. 176,f. 246.
Lit. Landgraf
1943p. 183(#).
46 PREVOSTIN, SUMMA(1206/1210)
... Si dicas,sicutdicuntNominales,quia quodsemel
estverum
eritverum
,
semper
secundum
eosdicendum
eritquodHabrahamcredidit
Christum
essenatum,et
Christum
essenasciturum,
esse
quod Habrahamnoncredidit
quia Christum
eos semperfuitfalsum...
nasciturum
secundum
Ms Brugge,Stedel.bibl.237,f. 52v;Paris,Bibl.Nat.,lat. 14526,f.34v(#).
Lit. Chenu1935/36
p. 13.
47 EVRARD OF BETHUNE, ANTIHAERESISCONTRAVALDENSES(1210)
... Lex enimab Euangelio,30
alia quidemest,sed nonaliud.Zachariasenim
fuitnonaliuda se
mutus,fuitnonaliuda se loquente.Velumtempliscissum,
nonaliuda se apertis.Eodempenitus
clausa,fuerunt
integro.Monumenta
differ.
enimnihilaliudest,quamapertio
modo,lexab Euangelio
Euangelium
legis,quae eratobscura.Ne simusNominalesin hoc,sed potiusPorretani.
& Prophetae
laborantes
in legeseminarunt;
illudidem
Quod enimPatriarchae
messuerunt,
Apostoli& Doctoresin Euangeliodesudantes
quibusdictumest:
ne pereant(Jo.6, 12).
Colligite
fragmenta,
30ab Euangelio
Ed.
ourconj.
, inEuangelium
Ed. La Bign,Maximabibliotheca
..., Lugduni1677,XXIV, 1529b( = J.
Triasscriptorvm
adver
svsWaldensivm
sectam Ingolstadii
Gretservs,
1614,p. 49)
(#).
Lit. Du CangeV p. 604,Courtenay
[1986]nn. 36, 44, 88.
48 GODFREY OF POITIERS, SUMMA(1212/19according
to Landgraf
1973
p. 171)
a (In question"Utrumactuset voluntas
sintidempeccatum
veldiversa")
Si sequamur
viamNominalium
dicerepossumus
etactussunt
quodvoluntas
- de volntate
idem31
concomitante32
dico,nonde praecedente
quae
peccatum
nonconcomitatur
actum.Etomnesillaeauctoritates
veliequod33
quaevidentur
sint34
diversapeccataintelligendae
suntde volntate
etactusubsepraecedente
quente,nonde concomitante.
196

09:12:08 AM

31suntidemKP, secundum
B.
32concomitante
B.
incerta
KP,lectio
33quodBP, quiaK.
34sintBP, suntK.
Stiftsbibl.
Ms Brugge,Stedel.bibl.220,f. 3Ira (#); Klosterneuburg,
299,f.
36ra(#); Paris,Bibl.Nat.,lat. 15747,f. 36vtesteLandgraf.
1943p. 189.
Lit. Landgraf
b

idemquodnos")
(In question"Utrumantiquipatrescrediderint
id estde eisdem,secundum
Dicimusquodeademestfides,
omne,velsecunetsimiliter
secundum
eademfides,
dumillos35
quodressuntarticuli,
qui dicunt
Nominales.
35velsecundum
aliosK.
illosB, secundum
Stiftsbibl.
Ms Brugge,
Stedel.bibl.,lat.220,f.75ra(#); Klosterneuburg,
299,
f. 8lva (#).
1943p. 187,Chenu1935/36
Lit. Landgraf
p. 12.

of"Christus
estmaiorse")
(In discussion
K
concdt'senexestmeliorse puero'nontarnen
UndecumPorphyrius
117va/concederei
'estaliuda se puero'vel 'alius'.
'Socratesestaliudquamfuerisecundum
Licettarnen36
concederem37
opinionemNominalium(qui, cum dicuntnihilcrescere
, dicuntquod quodlibet
eos38nonideoconcederem39
instanti
desinit
esse),secundum
corpusinquolibet
substantiae
diversae
fuitfuturus
'Christus
estaliudquamipsesit'.Quia Socrates
sednonpossumdicerede Christo
necestiliasubstantia
quod
quaepriusfuerat,
'Christus
concederem42
substantia
quae ipsenonsit,sedbene41
ipsesitaliqua40
est aliud quam fueri.Sed43dicendout Realis negaremillam. Et sic
addiperpartium
quia licetdicamquodnihilcrescat
responderem
simpliciter,
estsicrespondere.
Catholicum
dicoquodaliquidcrescit
tionem,
permateriam.
nonestaliudquamfuerit44.
Similiter
licetsimNominaiis
dicerem
quodSocrates
36tarnen
incerta
K.
lectio
B,
37concederem
B, concederet
K.
38Socrates
nominalium
estaliud- secundum
eosK, hocsecundum
quidicunt
opinionem
B.
nihil
estaliudquamfuerit
crescere
Socrates
39concederem
K.
B, concederetur
40aliquaK, a(li)aB.
41beneB, om.K.
42concederem
B, concedere
meK.
43sedB, om.K.
44etsicresponderem
- quamfuerit
K, om.B.
Stiftsbibl.
Ms Brugge,
Stedel.bibl.220,f. 103vb(#); Klosterneuburg,
299,f.
117rb-va
(#).

est
solafiliatione
Adhocdico,sicutdicebaminrespondendo,45
quodChristus
a quolibet
alioratione
distinctus46
estsufficienter
individuum,
quiasolafiliatione
cuiuslibet
omniumsuarumproprietatum
sedquilibetaliusfascculo
temporis;
est individuum,
sufficienter
ratione
quia47nullasua proprietate
distinguitur
sit
cuiuslibet
UndedicendoutRealisnondicerem
temporis.
quodindividuum
praedicabile,quia non significaialiquam rem naturalem,est tamen
undenonestdirecte48
sub specie;/K 122rb/
praedicamentale
quia continetur
nonest49
enimin praedicamento
sed subpraedicamento
praedicamentale,
Ad illud quod obicitquod intelligamus
divinamnaturamab humana
197

09:12:08 AM

dicoquod hocbene50
estlicetsitimpossibile,
itaquod
separatam,
intelligibile
ex animoetcorpore.
Si tarnen
remaneat
hocfieret,
dicerem
aliquidconiunctum
etdicerem
'istehomoincipit
fuit,
esse',immo
quodilludconiunctum
numquam
%haec
substantia
esse' quodplusest.Si dicatquodeaedempartesquae
incipit
- nonvalet,
sunteteaedemproprietates,
priusfuerunt
ergoidemcompositum
nonenimposuitremoveri
filiatio
ab illisconiunctis51
quiailludnovumindueret52
essecumsubstantialem
formam
amitteret.
Sed obicitur:
manereidemcompositum
sublatafiliatione;
modo
intelligatur
haecestvera'hoccompositum
esthomo';sedpriusnoneratpersonanisisola
nonestpersona;
sedsi nonestpersona,
nonest
filiatione,
ergosublatafiliatione
nonestpersona]53
nonest
homo;[sedsublatafiliatione
ergosublatafiliatione
homo.
Ad hocdicimusquod nonesthoc54intelligibile.
Idemestenimac si diceret
sublata55
filiatione".
Tamenhaeccondipersonaistacomposita
"Intelligatur
tional estfalsa'si nonestpersonanonesthomo'secundum
quod'si' sumitur
Sic enimdebetsumiin omniimpossibili
continuative.
positione.
etaliudessentiam,
Nominalis,
quidicitquodaliudestdemonstrare
personam
posset
ad hancimpossibilem
de facilirespondere.
Potestenimconcedere
positionem
istas'hoc compositum
fuit'demonstrato
coniuncto
ex corporeet anima;et
concederei
terminis
et negaretsumptis
essentialibus
generaliter
sumptis
personalibus,sicuticoncedit'iste homoherifuit',non tamenconcedit'haec
substantia
herifuit';similiter
'istehomocrevit',nontamen'haec substantia
crevi.Et sicuthancdistinguerem
'haecsubstantia
animatasenmultiplicem
sibiliscreviitaet hanc56'haec substantia
individua
rationalis
naturaefuit',
'substantia'
et sic
tantum,
quia haecdictio'haec' potestadiungihuictermino
demonstratur
essentiaet alii termini
et est sensus'haec
veniuntappositive
substantia
rationalis
naturae
fuit',etsicvera,etnonsequitur
quaeestindividua
ad personalem;
velhocsignum'haec' potestde'ergoistehomo'ab essentiali
monstrare
totalem
definitionem
'substantia
sitpersonalis
etc',et cumdefinido
sicutet definitum,
nondemonstratur
ibi nisipersona,et ideofalsa.Similiter
haec57
vera'hoccompositum
fuit',nontamen'istehomofuit'.
45sicut- respondendo
K, om.B.
46distinctus
B, distinctum
K.
47quiaB, quodK.
48directe
K, rccte
B.
49estK, om.B.
50beneK, unum
B.
51ab illisconiunctis
illisB.
K' a coniunctis
52novum
indueret
innovum
B.
K' induceret
53sedsi nonestpersona
- filiatione
nonestpersona
K' om.B.
54hocK; om.B.
55sublata
K' subB.
56hancB, haecK.
57haec+ estB.
Ms Brugge,Stedel.bibl.220,f. 106vb(#); Klosterneuburg,
Stiftsbibl.
299,f.
122ra-b(#).
49 GERVASEOF MELKLEY, ARS VERSIFICATORIA
1216according
to
(before
Faraip. 37)
Adiectiuum
solamueritatem
notansestab omnicarminerepellendum
per
immediatam
constructionem
cumadhucindubiositan congruitas
apposit(um),
198

09:12:08 AM

talemdeterminationem.
admittat
olim,quicquidnuncdicamus,
Paruipontani
hanccensuerunt
'Socratesqui estalbuscurri.Similiter
ethanc:
incongruam:
enimquodofficium
huiusrelatiui
'Socratesalbuscurri.Dixerunt
'qui'siisemper
sicposite
discretiue
teneri
ettalisdictionis
adiectiue
immediate
. Undecumnon
, similiter
facerein termino
discreto
censuerunt.
possettalemdiscretionem
incongruam
Moderniueronostridicuntquod hecdictio'qui' quandoqueamittit
officium
discretionis
etretinet
referendi.
Similiter
adiectiuum
estquantantum
officium
sedsiuesitcongruasiueincongrua,
hieestneuus
tantum,
doquenotaueritatis
librifaciem
estimmediata
coniuncqui totam
appositus
deturpat.
Que appositio
tiouniussubstantiui
cumaliosubstantiuo
ut'MnsOssa'. Immediata
diconon
semperuoce tenus,sed quoad sensum,ita scilicetut terminus
appositus
exeademparteex qua estprincipale
ut'Mariauirgo
substantiuum,
intelligatur
Christum.'
uirginum
portauit
Ms Oxford,BalliolCollege276,f. 132ra;Glasgow,Univ. Libr.,Hunt.511
unfol.
Lit. Hunt1950,pp. 54-55(#).
50 ANON., IN SENT.
a I, dist.41, cap. 3, n. 4
OLIM SCIVIT. Magister
inhoccapitulo
nominalisestsequensillud58:
quicestverum59,
estverum.
quidsemel
semper
NOS AUTEM CREDIMUS. Haec solumnominalibusvideturesse concedenda.60
Sanequidempotestconcediquodaliudcredimus,
aliudantiqui.
58illudP, om.N.
59verum
P, om.N.
60concedenda
P.
N,concedentia
Ms Napoli,Bibi.Nazionale,
VII.C. 14,f.109vb(#); Paris,Bibl.Mazarine,lat.
to Landgraf
758,f.46v (according
1943).
Lit. Landgraf
1937p. 190,Landgraf
1943p. 191f.
b

I, dist.44, cap. 2, n. 1
POTUIT ERGO QUOD MODO NON. Hoc simpliciter
falsum.61
Potuit
tarnen
creareinhocinstanti,
nonpotest,
aliquid,uthancanimam
quodmodo62
cumsitiamab hericreata.Etitaaliquidfuitsubiectum
divinaepotentiae,
quod
modononestsubiectum
ei.63Magister
nonprocedit
hac
PetrusLombardus64
165
Nominalisdicensquicquidsemel
estverum
via, immoprocedit
tamquam
semper
estverum.
61hoc- falsum
P, om.N.
62modoP' om.N.
63subiectum
eiN' ei subiectum
P.
64Petrus
Lombardus
P.
N, autem
65quicquid
- verum
P
verum
esseverum
Ntsemel
semper
Ms Napoli,Bibl.Nazionale,VII.C. 14,f. llOra-b(#); Paris,Bibl.Mazarine,
lat. 758,f. 48v(according
to Landgraf
1943).
Lit. Landgraf
1937p. 190,Landgraf
1943p. 193.
I, dist.46, cap. 7, n. 4
NEMO POTEST DICERE ore,cordeetoperequodestverum.
Opinioquorundam Nominaliumfuit:tu audis significatum
huius 'angeli
propositionis
In propositione
enimagitur
canun,ergoaudisangeloscanere.Nonsequitur.
199

09:12:08 AM

de re,etestsensus:tuaudisangeloscanere,idestaudis
de dicto,inconclusione
canentes.Item,tu dicishoc 'angeloscanere',ergotu dicisangelos
angelos66
Nonsequitur
canere.67
secundum
eos. Hunemodmsolvendi
videtur
magister
haberein hoccapitulo.
66canere
idestaudisangelos
Ntom.P.
67canere+ ergoP
Ms Napoli,Bibi.Nazionale,VII.C. 14,f.llOvb(#); Paris,Bibl.Mazarine,
lat.
to Landgraf
758,f. 51 (according
1943).
Lit. Landgraf
1937p. 190f,Landgraf
1943p. 194.
d

II, dist.3, cap. 3


hocenuntiabile
velattributum
esteiscomQUOD SPIRITUS ERANT. Num68
mune?Ita dicebant
Nominales.
quidam69
68NumP, nuncN.
69quidam
P
N,quidem
Ms Napoli,Bibl.Nazionale,VII.C. 14,f.11Ivb(#); Paris,Bibl.Mazarine,
lat.
to Landgraf
758,f. 55 (according
1943).
Lit. Landgraf
1943p. 196.

51 ANON., SUMMA
a
Dicuntenimquidam,quod articulisuntenuntiabilia,
scilicetChristum
alia. Sed hocvidetur
starenonposse,quoniam
natum,passumet huiusmodi
secundum
hocaliifuerunt
articuli
aliimodernorum
etitaaliafides.
antiquorum,
Set auctoritas
sintvariata,tarnen
fidesnonest
dicit,quoniamlicettempora
mutata.Adhocdicentforte
ipsi,quoniamNominalessuntetfereomnesde hac
esse natumest
sententia,
articuli,
quod non alii fuerunt
quoniamChristum
etquodsemel
estverum
estverum.
Sedhocsimiliter
starenonpotest,
verum,
semper
quia si Christumesse natumsemperfuitverum:ergo antiquihoc non
crediderunt
Christum
nasciturum.
Seddicitauctoritas:
venquemillicredebant
turumnoscredimus
noscredimus
venisse;quemillipassurum
passumfuisse,
credimus
et huiusmodi.
Itemhoc sic probatur
indirecte:
Antiquicredebant
Christum
nasceretur.
subfuit
natum,antequam
Ergoipsierrabant.
Ergofalsum
articulis
illorum.Quod nullaopiniovel sententia
admittit.
Propter
predictas
obiectiones
vitandasdicuntquidam,quod Christum
essenatumet huiusmodi
nonsuntarticuli
essenatumvelnascivelnasciturum
fidei,setChristum
esse,
ut comprehendantur
quelibettempora.Sed contraistossic: Judeicredunt
Messiamvenirevelvenissevelventurum
esse.Ergoidemcredunt,
quodnos.
Nonergoerrant.
Aliidicunt,
enuntiabilia
nonsuntarticuli,
sed
quodhuiusmodi
scilicet
et huiusmodi....
eventus,
nativitas,
passioet resurrectio
Ms Vaticano,Vat. lat. 10754,f. 5.
Lit. Landgraf
1943p. 187(#).
Non est hoc dicere,quod ingenitum,
b
ItemAugustinus:
etsi Filiumnon
nilprohiberet
diciingenitum.
Setsi Filiumnongenuisset,
nonesset
genuisset,
Pater.Si nonesset,non essetingenitus.
Ergonondiceretur
ingenitus:
ergo
falsum
Ut Nominales,ad hocquidamdicunthanc
est,quoddicitAugustinus.
essefalsam:Si nonessetPater,nonesset.Et solvunt
perinteremptionem.
Ms Vaticano,Vat. lat. 10754,f. 19v.
Lit. Landgraf
1943p. 190(#).
200

09:12:08 AM

52 WILLIAM OF AUXERRE, SUMMAAUREA(1215/20)


a Lib. 1, Tr. 5, cap. 2
Ad hocdicuntPorretaniquod hocnomen'Dominus'significai
quandam
relationem
que estdominium
quo DominusestDominus,etillarelationonest
divineessentie,
sedassistit
ei etincipit
intempore
assistere
etextempore,
scilicet
quandoincipithabereservum.Eodemmodohoc nomencreator
significai
etillarelatio
assistere
divine
quandamrelationem
qua Deus estcreator,
incepit
oririab ea.
essentie,
quandocreature
inceperunt
Ed. J. Ribaillier
Bonaventurianum
1980I-IV,Spicilegium
XVI-XIX,Paris/Roma
87, I p. 70 (#).
Lit. Courtenay
[1986]n. 36.
b Lib. 1, Tr. 7, cap. 1
Circaprimum
notandum
estquodde notionibus
multesuntopicapitulum
niones.DicuntenimPorretani
quodmultopluressuntnotiones
quamquinqu
et quodnotiones
nonsuntpersone.Aliidicunt...
Ed. J. Ribaillier
I p. 110(#).
Lit. Courtenay
[1986]n. 36.
c Lib. I, Tr. 7, cap. 1
Ista etiamformafallitsecundum
Nominalesqui dicuntquod unum
nomen
est
voces.
Positoquodnonsintnisiistetresvoces:canis,canem,cane;secunplures
dumeosnonvalethecargumentado:
omnenomenesthecvoxcanis;sedomnis
voxestnomen;ergoomnisvoxesthecvoxcanis.
Ed. J. Ribaillier
I p. 115(#).
Lit. Landgraf
1943p. 188,Courtenay
[1986]n. 36.
d

Lib. 1, Tr. 9, cap. 2


hecestvera:Deus potestscire
Quodautemdicimusquodin hacsignificatione
estde scientia
rerumincomplexpluraquamsciat,in unosensuintelligendum
arum;multaenimpossuntesse que nunquamerunt;sed de scientiaenuntiabilium
nonestverum,
scirealiquod
reales,cumDeusincipit
quia secundum
desinit
scireeiuscontradictorie
Necvalet:Deus sciebat
enuntiabile,
oppositum.
hocpriusetmodononseit;ergooblitus
reiaccidit
est,quiapertranscendentiam
nominales
estverum
quodnonseit.Sed secundum
quidicunt:quodsemel
semper
erit
verum
veldesinit
, Deusnichilincipit
scire,ethocmagisconcordat
Augustino
et Magistro
in Sententiis.
Ed. J. Ribaillier
I p. 181(#).
Lit. Landgraf
1943p. 185p. 201,Chenu1935/36
p. 13,Chenu1976p. 94 n.
2, Courtenay
[1986]n. 36.
Lib. 1, Tr. 14,cap. 1
Dicitureniminlibro
QuodDeussitubique,ostenditur
primoauctoritatibus.
Dominireplevit
orbemterrarum Etperhocpatetnullam
Sapientie:
Spiritus
esseopinionem
Adamitarum
universale
unumnumero;
si enimhoc
qui ponunt
una numero
essetubique.
esset,substantia
Ed. J. Ribaillier
I p. 261(#).
Lit. Courtenay
[1986]n. 29.
Lib. 3, Tr. 12,cap. 7
Notandum
esttamenquodquiaarticuli
idemsuntformaliter
eteffective
apud
modernos
ideosoient
Nominales
dicerequodidem
quietfuerunt
apudantiquos,
201

09:12:08 AM

articuli
et apudantiquos,
suntsimpliciter
etquodarticuli
non
apudmodernos
etabsolute;
etsoient
necfidessimpliciter
suntmutati,
dicerequodhecargumentado nonvalet:enuntiabilia
mutatasunt;sed enuntiabilia
suntarticuli;
ergo
suntmutati.Et estibifallaciaaccidentis.
articuli
Instantia.
Hoc nomen'albus'
esthecvox'albus';sedhecvox'albus'estaliavoxquamhecvox'alba'; ergo
et estaliudnomen.
III p. 221 (#).
Ms J. Ribaillier
Lit. Landgraf
1943p. 186.
53 JACQUES OF VITRY, EXEMPLA(ante1227)
105De Maugrinoqui excommunicauit
Nominales.
Hic est Maugrinus,cui quidamtrufator
quem ego Parisiusvidi dixit:
'DomineMaugrine,vos scitisquod Deus omniabonacreatet multiplicat
ac
crescere
facit.Quidamautemscolaressuntin parochia
vestraqui dicuntquod
nichil
crescit.
Rogo vos quod die Dominica,quandoscolareseruntin missa,
excommunicetis
eos.' Vndefactum
estquod prximaDominicadie, cumad
conuenirent
multiNominales,
ecclesiam
crescit
, et
quorum
opinioestquodnichil
eorumaduersariiAdamitequi contrariam
tenentsentenciam,
Maugrinus
ait: 'Quidamsuntinhacparochiaheretici
accensacandelacunctis
audientibus
asserunt
qui Dei operibus
derogantes
quodnichilcrescit.
Ego veroomnesqui
eta liminibus
hocdicunt,excommunico
snetematris
ecclesiesequestro.'
Quo
auditovaldeconfusi
suntNominalesetgauisisuntReales.Episcopus
autemin
artibusParisiusdocueratet fueratNominalis;et vocatopresbytero
ait:
'Maugrine,
quomodoaususes meexcommunicare?
Ego enimsumNominalis
etdicoquodnichil
crescit.'
Atilleobmutuit
etiterum,
neparochiam
que magnis
habundabat
centum
librisParisiensis
monete
se redemit.
amitteret,
prouentibus
DieExempla
Ed. J. Greven,
ausdenSermones
etcommunes
desJakob
vonVitry
,
feriales
1914,p. 62 (#).
Heidelberg
Lit. Normore
p. 205.
54 ROLAND OF CREMONA, SUMMA(1228/30)
a
... Et possunt
inducere
Nominalium,
prose opinionem
qui dicuntquodistud
nonvalet.Sit70quod nonsintnisiistetresvoces:albus,alba,
argumentum
album.Omnenomenesthecvoxalbus,sedomnisvoxestnomen,ergoomnis
voxesthecvoxalbus,quod falsum
est.
70valet.Sitourconj
., valet,
sicChenu.
Ms Paris,Bibi.Mazarine,lat. 795,f. 17.
Lit. Chenu1935/36
p. 13 (#).
b

In librode sexprincipiis
dicitur
estsimplici
et invariabili
essentia
quodforma
consistens
... Ad illudquoddicitquodforma
estsimplici
etinvariabili
essentia
dicimus
deomnibus
consistens,
formis,
quodistudnonestverum
equedicimus
Aristotelem
dixisseilludverbum,
sed Porretanum71.
71Seil.Gilbertm.
Thisistheearliest
false
attribution
oftheLiber
sex
toGilbert
principiorum
Porreta.
Ms Paris,Bibl.Mazarine,lat. 795,f. 19v.
Lit. L. Minio-Paluello,
Amsterdam
'MagisterSex Principiorum',
Opuscula,
1972,p. 539 (#); Lewry1987p. 257 n. 21.

202

09:12:08 AM

55 ROBERT GROSSETESTE, QUIBUSMODISHABEANTRES SUBSISTERE


(1220*s/35)
HinceciamillaAdamitarum
posicioque rebussecundum
quodin se ipsissunt
tribuit
secundum
nostro.Secundum
quodeis conuenit
quodsuntin intellectu
enimquod in se ipsissunt,nichilidempartici
patura multisita quod sitde
substancia
secundum
ueroquodsunt<in> intellectu
nostro,
participancium;
idema multis
et estde substancia
participatur
participancium.
Ms Assisi,Bibi.conv.138,f. 262va.
Ed. Lewry1983p. 21 (#).
56 ROBERT KILWARDBY,IN ISAG. (ca. 1240)
Adidem,dicitBoeciusintercio
De consolacione
quodomnequod
philosophie
estideoestquia unumnumero
nonestunumnumero,
est;setuniuersale
quia
sicessetsingulare:
nonest....
igituruniversale
Adaliuddicendum
enimhecassumpcio,
quodestfalsa:si recteumat,suberit
uniuersale
estquodest,ethecestfalsa;estenimquoest,estquiditasetessencia
et formaindiuidui;
nec estunumnumeroin quolibetsingulari
ut posuerunt
Adamite,setestunumpermodumsecundum
quemformaperse considerata
dicitur
uel persimplicitatem
sue essencie.
una,scilicet
perconuenienciam
Ms Madrid,Bibl.Univ.72, f. 2va; Cambridge,
Peterhouse
206,f. 34rb-va.
Lit. Lewry1983p. 7 (#).
57 TRACTATUS EMMERANUSDE IMPOSSIBILIPOSITIONE
Et notandum
non sequitur
quod in hac questioneex obligatione
impossibili
Undeconsequentia
Adamitarum72nonestconcedenda
in hacquesquidlibet.
Sed tantummodo
ilia consetione,scilicet
quod eximpossibili
sequitur
quidlibet.
quentiaest concedendain hac questionein qua intellectus
consequentis
in intellectu
claudatur
antecedentis.
Undecumtantumtalisconsequentia
sit
admittenda
inhacquestione,
notandum
nonestadmittenda
quodconsequentia
inhacquestione
inqua negatio
exaffirmatione.
Undetalisconsequensequitur
tia nonestconcedenda:
'si homoest,nonestasinus'.Quod patet,si homo
uniatur
asinoomnmoda
identitte.
72sicMs,DeRijkreads
Adamitorum.
Ms Mnchen,
Clm 14458,f.40va.
Ed. De Rijk,SomeThirteenth
Tracts
on theGameof Obligation
/, in:
Century
12 (1974),94-123,at p. 118(#).
Vivarium,
Lit. De Rijk1974p. 102f,Lewry1983p. 11 n. 29, Braakhuis
p. 39.
58 OBLIGA
TIONESPARISIENSES
Ex predictis
huiusregule:
patetVeritas
Positofalsopossibili,
potestconcediet probari
quodquecontingens.
Preterea.
Sciendum
quodpredicta
regulanontenetsecundum
consequentiam
Nominalium.
Si enimteneret
secundum
falsopossibili
ipsos,contingeret
posito
falsiimpossibilis
in copulativa
probari
quodqueimpossibile,
supposito
opposito
cum posito.Fieretenim ilia copulativafalsumnon sequenssecundum
203

09:12:08 AM

illiusetposito
Nominales.Undeestnegandasecundum
ipsos.Sed ex opposito
faisum impossibile.
sequitur
Ms Oxford,Bodl.Libr.,canon,mise.281,f.85r.
on theGameofObligation
Tracts
Ed. De Rijk, SomeThirteenth
//,in:
Century
13 (1975),22-54,at p. 31 (#).
Vivarium,
Lit. Normore
p. 204.
59 ANON., DE COMMUNIBUSD1STINCTIONIBUS
Solutio.Dicendumquod in veritatesecundumopinionemquorundam,
ex
veritatem
tamensecundum
eximpossibili
nominalium
scilicet,
sequitur
quidlibet;
realium.
et hocestsecundum
nichilsequitur,
opinionem
impossibili
Ms Vatican,Vat. lat. 7678,f. 81rb.
onDistinctiones
Tracts
Parisian
Ed. De Rijk,SomeEarlier
, Nijmegen
Sophismatum
1988,p. 206 156(#).
I p. 63, Courtenay
1991p. 36.
Lit. Pelsterp. 157,Braakhuis
60 POSITIONESNOMINALIUMsivePOSITIONESNOSTRAE(early13thc.?).
haecsunt.Primoconsentimus
nostraecircauniversalia
Positiones
quoduniverrealium
contra
Secundoponimus
sunt
nomina.
etspecies
saliasicut
opinionem
genera
...
Tertio
nihil
est
particulare.
praeter
quod
Ms Vaticano,Vat. lat. 7678f. 88ra.
Ed. Ebbesen1991p. 431 (#); Pelsterp. 158.
I p. 34.
Lit. Braakhuis
61 ALBERTUS MAGNUS,LIBER DE PRAEDICABILIBUS
Sunttamenqui aliterea quaedictasunt,interpretantur
dicentes,
quodinsolis
solus
sintetquomodoessehabeant,
suntiliaquoadnos,quaeutrum
intellectibus
illiqui
haberedixerunt
universalia
Et tale esse in intellectu
seitintellectus.
univervocabantur
Nominales,qui communitatem
(ad quam particularia
inintellectu
esse
tantum
salium,dequibusdicuntur
referuntur)
ipsauniversalia,
non
dicebant.Nudosautemvocantintellectus,
qui ad scibilequod accipiunt
eorum
ad speculationem
intellectum
habentpraescriptos
habitus,
qui disponant
habitm
conclusionum
quaerit
praescriptum
quaein ipsosunt.Sicutintellectus
et
intellectus
fit
conclusio,
praescriptum
principiorum
perquem
principiorum
et sic de aliis.Purosautemdicunt
habitmnotitiae
sibiquaerit
terminorum,
nonaccipiuntur.
intellectus,
phantasmate
qui mediante
omnia
Ed. Borgnet,
I, Parisiis1890,p. 19b(#).
Opera
62 ALBERTUS MAGNUS,IN SENT (1246)
a I, dist.5, art.4
Sed contra:.... 3. Item,In LitteravultquodPateressentia
sit,et sapientia
ad Patrem:
sehabeant
formaliter
etsapientia
quaePorsapienssit,quasiessentia
in Deo compositio
retanusdixit,quodreprehensum
fuit,quia sicnotatur
in nomine,
intalibusnisicausaformalis
Ad aliuddicendum,
quodnonnotatur
autemposuitin reipsa.
et nonin re. Porretanus
omnia
Ed. Borgnet,
XXV, Parisiis1893,p. 480b(#).
Opera
204

09:12:08 AM

I, dist.26, art.10
Itemobjicitur
fortius:
AutPorretanus
suamaliquidesseens
ponitrelationem
in divinis,autnihil.Si aliquid:tuncoportet
....
Solutio.Dicendum,
etfalsaethaeretica
est,etab
quodopinioPorretanorum
Alexandro
Undedicimus...
Papa in concilioRemensicondemnata.
Ed. Borgnet,
omnia
XXVI, Parisiis1893,p. 20ab(#).
Opera
I, dist.33, art.5
divinae
Utrumrelationes
suntassistentes,
sicutdixitGilbertus
Porretanus?
dicitur
fuisse
Gilberti
sicutdicit
Porretani,
Quia veroisteerror
quemtarnen,
in concilioRemensiretractavit
sanctusBernardus,
et damnavit,consiliis
humiliter
ideo diligentius
considerando
suntistae
Episcoporum
acquiescens:
rationes.
...
Hoc considerantes
dicunt
tarn
virum
nonerrasse:
et
modernorum,
quidam
peritum
inducunt
rationes
quibusprobant
quodlicetdiversaopinariindivinis.Sedquia
haeresis
haecab ore auctorissui in concilioRemensidamnata:ideo contra
sie: ...
objicitur
Ed. Borgnet
XXVI p. 147b,150a(#).

I, dist.41, art.6
Si vellemus
diceremus
parumper
sequiantiquamNominaliumopinionem,
Deumscirequidquidseivit,ettuncdiceremus
velenuntiabile
quodpropositio
quod
semel
estverum,
erit
verum.
Sed unumnumero
enuntiabile
nonestresumensemper
dumnisirespectu
utcumdicitur:
mundum
foreestverum,
ejusdemtemporis,
illud verumest rationeaeternitatis
antecedentis
tempus.Si autemmodo
debetresumi
ratione
eiusdem
hocautemnonsignificatur
resumatur,
temporis;
nuncutfuturum
velpraesens,
sedsignificatur
utpraeteritum;
ergosignificatur
fuisseestverum;et mundum
foretunc,et fuissemodo,
peristam:mundum
etiamenuntiabile
unumet rationeejusdemtemporis
verumest,sed diversis
modissignificando
Et hocpianeextrahitur
de littera,
itasolvit;
quia Magister
et tenendo
illamNominalium
opinionem,
planumestrespondere
objectis.
Ed Borgnet
XXVI p. 350b(#).
Lit. Chenu1935/36
1991a,n. 37.
p li, Courtenay

IV, dist.46, E., art.2


Aliidicunt,
utPorretani,
est,uttollatur
quodhaecdiminutio
geometrica
pars
etnonsemper
ejusdempropositionis
persecundum
suffragium,
ejusdemquantitatis:
utsi primum
tollitpoenae
secundum
centesimam,
suffragium
suffragium
tollit
centesimam
ettertiam
centesimam
illiusresidui:ei
residui,
aequaleprimo,
sicmanetsemperpoena,eo quodestdivisibilis
in infinitum.
Ed. Borgnet,
omnia
XXX, Parisiis1894,p. 630b(#).
Opera
Lit. Courtenay
[1986]n. 41.

63 ALBERTUS MAGNUS,PHYSICA(1251/52)
Et ideo planumest Porretanum73
mentiri
dicentem,
quod ultimasphaera
movetur
subsuperficie
sua convexaetquoadillamin locoest,quia sicessetin
locoextra,quodnonestcorpusdiversum
ab ipso,etlocusessetsuperficies
eius
extraambientis.
quodestin loco,et nonsuperficies
corporis
73Seil.Gilbertm.
Cf.Ps.-Gilbert,
SexPrincipiorum,
Liber
cd.L. Minio-Paluello
Lai.
(Arisi.
1-7),1966Leiden,
p. 47.8ff.
Ed. Opera
Omnia
IV-1,Aschendorff
1987,p. 228 (#).
205

09:12:08 AM

64 BONAVENTURE,IN SENT. (1250/52)


a I, dist.41, art.2, q. 2
est
Aliidixerunt
contrarium,
quia posuerunt,
quod enuntiabile,
quod semel
estverum
, et ita semperscitur.Et, ut meliuspateat,videndaest
verum,
semper
eorumpositioet ratiopositionis.
Fuerunt,
qui dixerunt,
quod albus,alba,
tarnen,
album,cumsinttresvoceset treshabeantmodossignificandi,
quia
suntunumnomen.Perhuncmodumdixeandemsignificationem
important,
erunt,quod unitasenuntiabilis
accipiendaest non ex partevocisvel modi
deinde
sedreisignificatae;
sedunaresest,quae primoestfutura,
significandi,
remhancprimoessefuturam,
deinde
tertio
ergoenuntiare
praeterita:
praesens,
non facietdiversitatem
sed
tertiopraeteritam,
enuntiabilium,
praesentem,
deindepraesens,
sitprimofuturum,
tertio
vocum.- Rursus,cumidemtempus
rei,quod significatur
peroratempusscilicetquod estmensura
praeteritum,
velforeconsignificent
triatempora,
ratione
contionem;
quamvisessevelfuisse
sed variatur
soluma partetemporis
nondiversificam
enuntiabile,
significati
currit
Undesi dicamsemel:Socrates
hodie,et erasdicam:currit74;
significad.
aliudtempus,
etitaaliamactionem;
enuntiabile
detintelligere
cumhocverbum
Et quia, retenta
eadem
mutatasignificatione.
nonestidem,quantumcumque
etnonestidem,nisicumeadem
enuntiabile
semperestverum,
significatione,
ideodixerunt,
retinetur:
quodilludquodsemelestverum,semper
significatio
estverum.Etideo,cumDeusnihilobliviscatur,
dicunt,
quodomneenuntiabile,
illirationi:omneenuntiabile,
quod
quod Deus seivit,seit.- Et respondent
velteesse:ergoetc.;nondebetinferri
sic:
seivit,seit;sedseivittenasciturum
Aliterestibifigura
dictionis,
quia
ergoseit,teesse,sedsic:ergoseit,tefuisse.
ad identitatem
rei.- Et hocmodo
in modosignificandi
ab identitte
procedit
Et istafuitopinioNominalium,
solvitmagister.
Nominales,quia
quidictisunt
unitatem.
suamsuper
nominis
positionem
fundabant
74currit
siced.,anhericucurrit
legendum?
Ed. OperaOmnia
I, Quaracchi1882,p. 740ab(#).
1943p. 185,Normore
Lit. Landgraf
p. 206,Chenu1935/36
p. 11,Courtenay
1991ap. 17.
b

I, dist.44, art.2, q. 1
de sciensicutad sophisma
Adhocestduplexmodusrespondendi,
Responsio:
omninosit
tia. Concessoenim,quod divinapotentiasecundumveritatem
hanc:potest
concedunt
tamenNominalium
secundum
immutabilis,
positionem
suscitare:
illationi:
sedpotuitChristum
ergoet
quidquidpotuit.Et respondent
sedsubalio:
subiliotempore,
modopotest;respondent,
quodnondebetinferri
verbisdiveradiunctum
suscitasse,
quia hocenuntiabile,
ergopotestChristum
estvera,etsialiter
nonestidem.Ideodicunt,
sorumtemporum,
quodpropositio
sive
dictionis
inferatur,
assignantpeccatumin processusecundumfiguram
accidens.
secundum
Ed. OperaOmnia
I, Quaracchi1882,p. 791a(#).
1943p. 186,Normore
Lit. Landgraf
p. 206.

III, dist.24, art.1, q. 3


etad perfecfideiestproprie
Sedquoniamipseassensus
supercomplexionem;
sed etiamoportet
de incarnatione,
tionemfideinon tantumoportet
cogitare
suntenuniamfuisse:ideodixerunt
incarnationem
alii,quodarticuli
credere,
ad
cumfidesquantum
maxime
circacomplexum,
etquodfidesconsistit
tiabilia,
etde nullocreatopossit
etcreatum,
increatum
simulrespiciat
aliquosartculos
quod prius
ipsi increato,secundum
esse, nisi secundumquod componitur

206

09:12:08 AM

illudnoncapitnisipermodmcomplexionis,
habitm
est:si ergointellectus
videtur
illudponereet dicere,quod fidessitcircaverumcomrationabilius
Et quoniamerranscircaverumcomplexum
complexi.
plexumsivesubratione
sicutsi aliiudicatur
ad differentiam
haereticus,
temporis
simpliciter
quantum
ideonon
vel
incarnationem
iam
resurrectionem
crederet
futuram;
factam,
quis
comsedetiamcircaverum
fidem
essecircaverum
solumdixerunt,
complexum,
Et
obiicias
eis
de
mutatione
si
tu
differentia
sub
determinata
temporis.
plexum
secundum
istorumenuntiabilium;
fidei proptermutationem
respondent
tecurnonsuntmutata,
Nominales,
quia teessecursurum,
quodenuntiabilia
idemsignificant,
etunumest
indiversis
rere,tecucurrisse,
temporibus
prolata,
et unumesttempus,
enuntiabile,
proquo
quia una estres,quamsignificant,
remetveritatem,
etideounumsuntsecundum
quamvisvideantur
proferuntur;
Estoquod istaenuntiabilia
essediversa.- Aliteretiamrespondent.
vocaliter
et
sintdiversa,quia tamenuna estVeritas,cui fidesassentiiprincipaliter,
secundum
rationecuiusistaenuntiabilia
credit,quae quidemnon mutatur
nonpropter
hoc
licetipsa enuntiabilia
diversitatem
diversificentur;
temporis,
fidesnonmutata
immoin diversis
et diversificatur,
fidesmutatur
temporibus
consistit.
temdiversorum
Sed quia positioilia Nominalium,
quae dicebat,enuntiabilia
nonapprobatur,
immofalsaest,sicutin primo
esseunum
, communiter
porum
....
librofuitostensum;
Omnia
Ed. Opera
III, Quaracchi1887,pp. 515b-516a
(#).
Lit. Landgraf
1943p. 188.
65 THOMAS AQUINAS,SUMMATHEOLOGIAE
a

I, Q. 14,art.15,ad 3
idemesseenunAd tertium
dicendum,
quod antiquiNominalesdixerunt
et esse natum:quia eademres
nasci,et esse nasciturum,
tiabile,Christum
nativitas
Christi.Et secundum
hocsequitur
perhaectria,scilicet
significatur
natum,quod
quod Deus quidquidscivit,sciat:quia modo seitChristum
essenasciturum.
idemei, quodestChristum
significat
Roma
Ed. Opera
Omnia
IV,
1888,p. 195.
(Leonina)
1943p. 184,Normore
Lit. Landgraf
p. 206,Chenu1935/36
p. 12,Courtenay
1991a,n. 37 + 38.

I, Q. 39, art.6, ad 1
divinaenaturaehaec sitvera,Deus est
Unde,licetpronullosuppositorum
- Quodnonattendens,
esttamenveraproessentia.
Porretanus
earn
Trinitas,
negavit.
Ed. Opera
Omnia
(Leonina)IV, p. 406.

66 THOMAS AQUINAS,IN SENT.


a I, dist.26, q. 2, art.1
ut Porretani,quod relationes
in divinissunttantum
Quidamdixerunt,
assistentes.
...
Quidamverodixerunt
... et hocattendentes
dixerunt,
quidamphilosophi
quod relationonestaliquod unumgenusentium,nec estaliquidin rerumnatura;sed est tantum
inomnibus
etquodrelationes
suntde intenentibus,
quidamrespectus
respersus
tionibus
secundis
quaenonhabentessenisiinanima.Cui etiamPorretanorum
videtur.
Sed hocfalsum
est:quia ...
opinioconsentire
207

09:12:08 AM

Ed. OperaOmnia
(Vivs)VII, Paris1873,p. 328ab.
Lit. Courtenay
[1986]n. 41.
b

I, dist.33, q. 1, art.1
Errorenim iste qui in Litteratangitur,
diciturPorretanifuisse,quem
in rhemensi
concilioretractavit.
postmodum
Ed. OperaOmnia
(Vivs)VII p. 396b.
Lit. Courtenay
[1986]n. 41.

I, dist.33, q. 1, art.2
enimdixerunt,
Porretani
suntinpersonis
utassistentes,
et
quodproprietates
nonsuntipsaepersonae.
Sed hocnonpotestesse,quia ...
Ed. OperaOmnia
(Vivs)VII p. 399a.
Lit. Courtenay
[1986]n. 41.
I, dist.33, q. 1, art.5
... quodestsabelliana?
etideoPorretanus,
impietatis;
qui primohocposuerat,
retractavit.
post,visohocquod sequitur,
Ed. OperaOmnia
(Vivs)VII p. 403b.
Lit. Courtenay
[1986]n. 41.
IV, dist.45, q. 2, art.2
Et ideoPorretanialiummoduminvenerunt,
dicentes,
quodhocmodoprocediturin diminutione
sicutproceditur
in divisione
poenarum
persuffragia,
tamenin infinitum
dividipossunt,
etnunquam
linearum,
quaecumsintfinitae,
dumfitsubtractio
nonsecundum
eamdemquanconsumuntur,
perdivisionem
sed secundum
eamdemproportionem;
velutsi primoauferatur
titatem,
pars
etsecundoquartailliusquartae,
etiterum
et
quartatotius,
quartailliusquartae,
sic deincepsin infinitum.
Et similiter
dicunt,quod per primum
suffragium
etpersecundum
diminuitur
secunaliquotaparspoenae,
parsaliquaremanentis
dumeamdemproportionem.
Sed istemodusmultipliciter
defectivus
invenitur.
Primo,quia ...
Ed. OperaOmnia
(Vivs)XI p. 371a.
Lit. Courtenay
[1986]n. 41.

67 THOMAS AQUINAS,DE POTENTIA


a Q. 7, art.9
... undeetPorretani
relationes
nonesseinhaerentes,
sedassistentes,
dixerunt,
verumest,utposterius
ostenditur.
quod aliqualiter
Ed. Quaestiones
II, Taurini/Romae
disputatae
(Marietti)1953,p. 62va.
Lit. Courtenay
[1986]n. 41.
b

Q. 8, art.2
Undeetiamquidamtheologi,
scilicet
huiusmodi
Porretani,
opinionem
usque
ad divinamrelationem
relationes
nonessein personis,
dicentes,
extenderunt,
sedeisquasiassistere.
Et quia essentia
divinaestinpersonis,
sequebatur
quod
nonsuntessentia
relationes
divina;etquia omneaccidensinhaeret,
sequebatur
hoc solvebant
verbumAugustini
quod non essentaccidentia.Et secundum
nonpraedicantur
relationes
de Deo secundum
substaninductum,
quodscilicet
accidens.
Sedad hancopinionem
non
tiam,necsecundum
quodrelatio
sequitur
sitresaliqua,sedsolumsecundum
radonem:
omnisenimresvelestsubstantia
velaccidens.

208

09:12:08 AM

relationes
essede secundis
Undeetiamquidamantiquiposuerunt
intellects,
hocetiamPorretanos
utCommentator
dicitXI Metaph..Etideooportet
dicere,
Et sicsequetur
rationem.
divinaenonsuntnisisecundum
quod
quodrelationes
distinctio
noneritrealis;quodesthaereticum.
personarum
Ed. Quaestiones
II p. 67ra.
disputatae
Lit. Courtenay
[1986]n. 41.
68 THOMAS AQUINAS,DE VERITATE
Q. 21, art.4
Et hancopinionem
secutisunt:dicebant
enimquod
aliquomodoporretani
de creatura
bonumsimpliciter,
utcumdicitur
homoestbonus,et
praedicamus
bonumaliquoaddito,utcumdicimus
estbonushomo.Dicebantigitur
Socrates
non aliqua bonitateinhaerente
sed
quod creaturadiciturbona simpliciter
bonitate
essetbonitasdivina;
prima,quasiipsabonitasabsolutaet communis
sed cumdicitur
creatura
a bonitate
bonumhocvel illud,denominatur
creata
bonitates
creataesuntsicutet ideae particulares
secundum
quia particulares
Platonem.
Sed haecopinioa Philosopho
...
improbatur
multipliciter:
Ed. OperaOmnia
III1
602a.
(Leonina)
p.
Lit. Courtenay
[1986]n. 41.
69 THOMAS AQUINAS,COMPENDIUMTHEOLOGIAE
I, cap. 67
sed
Non autemdicipotestquod proprietates
nonsintin personis
predicte
exterius
ad eas se habeant,ut Porretanidixerunt.
Ed. Opera
Omnia
(Leonina)XLII, Roma 1979,p. 102b.
Lit. Courtenay
[1986]n. 41.
70 ANONYMUS
, NOTULA(13th/14th
c.)
Internominales,
de quibusin (] 1 trs.)lib. 3 tcapitulo61.0tetrealesestdifdicunt
ferentia,
quiarealesdicunt
generaetspecies
aliquidesseinre,nominales
(] dicerent
rs.)illa nihilesse, videlicetesse quasdamanimiconceptiones.
ut
Secundadifferentia,
quia nominalesdicunttriaesse,scilicetenuntiabile,
scilicetnega'Petrmnegavisse
remsignificat,
Christum'
, quod ipsammet
tionem
dictum
de re,scilicet
Petri;secundo,
ipsalocutioquaede redicit<ur> ;
ut 'Petrus
rem(s.r ] scilicet
restrs.)de praesenti,
tertio,
propositio
significans
dicuntnominalesquod
indicativum.
Circaprimm
perverbum
nega,scilicet
semel
estverum
tunc,igi; sedsemelfuitverumPetrm
fuitverum
semper
negavisse
turmodoestverumPetrm
tuncChristum,
necestdifferentia
nisiin
negavisse
sedeademres.Realesdicuntnonesseverum,immoquodsemelfuit
tempore,
verumnumquam
eritverum;- intelligunt
de dicto,quodestquaedamVeritas,
quia illuddictumquod tunefuitnonestmodo,alia estenimvoxquae nunc
et alia quae tuncdicebatur.
dicitur
Et licetdiversadicerent,
nontamencondereintelligunt,
realesde dicto.Etideosecundum
tradicebant,
quianominales
hocvidetur
debent
dicirealeseteconverso
quodpotiusnominales
tquamsunti;
videlicet
huius<modi> nominaa primaopinionesumpserunt
non ab ista.
Praeterea
dicuntnominalesquod nihilcrescit,
undesi lapisacervolapidum
noneritidem(Jillius
adiciatur,
trs.)acervus<at>que prius,sedalius- quare
209

09:12:08 AM

(]quae trs.)autemhoc sit,bene(s.b.] benesittrs.)cogita- ; realesautem


econtra.
Ms Paris,Bibi.Nat.,lat. 15739,f.2rb.Transcription
(trs.)byK. H. Tachau
andconjectural
Asthems.contains
emendations.
( #), butwithourorthography
in thebeginning
ofthenote
Summa
Aureathereference
WilliamofAuxerre's
is to ourN 52f,supra.
probably
71 WILLIAM OF MARE, SCRIPTUMIN SENTENTIAS(ca. 1270)
' Utrum
scivit':
In question
Deussciatquicquid
Secundum
quodolimscivitquia dicunt
quosdamDeus seitomneenuntiabile
cum dicitur"Sortescurrit"et "Sortescucurrit"et
idemesse enuntiabile
identitatem
reidicuntesseidentitatem
"Sortescurret"quia secundum
proposiutvidetur.. ..
et opinioMagisti
tionset haecfuitopinionominalium
a multis
etmaximis
etnominalium
... primatamenopinioquaedicitur
Magisti
illiqui fuerunt
illiusopieos dicerentur
estetveriussecundum
veriorreputata
nionisrealesquamnominalesquia quandodicuntquodestidemenuntiabile
inA", hoc
inA", "Sortescucurrit
inA tempore",
"Sortescurrit
"Sortescurret
ideodicuntquia nonestvariatioa partetemporis
quia idemesttempusquod
et si nonest
et modoestpraeteritum,
fuitfuturum
et aliquandofuitpraesens
variatioa partetemporis,
quia eademresnon
ergoneca partereienuntiatae
Variaturergoenunhabererespectu
eiusdemtemporis.
potestse difformiter
vocemtantum
tiabilesecundum
praesenti
quandofitenuntiatio
propraeterito,
debetdicialiudet aliud,
sedresnonvariatur
etideonecenuntiabile
et futuro,
sed idem.
inprimum
librum
Sententiarum
dela Mare
Ed. H. Krami(ed.), Guillelmus
,
, Scriptum
Mnchen1989,pp. 503-04(#).
Akademie
derWissenschaften,
Bayerische
AddendumANON., DE FIGURISSYLLOGISMORUM
(ca. 1150)
Nonusmodus< primaefigurae>siefalsificatur Vel sic:quidammodisunt
Petrisunt
sententiam
sednulli(] nulleMs) clericitenentes
nominales,
maistri
Petri.
tenentes
modi,ergoquidamnominalesnonsuntsententiam
maistri
Cod. Guelf.56.20Aug.8, f. 81r (#).
Ms Wolfenbttel,
HerzogAugust-Bibl.,
Addendum(2) ArsMeliduna
(cf.no. 14 above)
/si erit;si nont
similiter
ete converso;
fuitalbus,fuitCandidus,
Itemsi Socrates
ete conven
ete converso;
albus,nonestCandidus,
ergosi estalbus,estCandidus,
h
si hoc momentum
Instantia... Vel sic Adamitis:
| fuitantehocmomentum,
fuitdies;et si erit,eritdies,et e converso;
momentum
ergosi est,estdies.
Ms Oxford,Bold.Libr.,Digby174,f. 240vg(#).

210

09:12:08 AM

Vivarium
XXX, 1 (1992)
TwelfthCenturyNominalism Bibliography

Abbreviations
du moyen-age
et littraire
doctrinale
AHDL = Archives
d'histoire
derPhilosophie
des Mittelalters
zurGeschichte
BGPM = Beitrge
Mediaevalis
Continuado
CCCM = CorpusChristianorum.
= CorpusChristianorum.
SeriesLatina
CCSL
du Moyen-Age
CIMAGL= Cahiersde l'Institut
grecet latin
= Freiburger
frPhilosophie
undTheologie
Zeitschrift
FZPT
= Abelard,
LI
Logicaingredientibus
= Abelard,
sociorum
LNPS
Logicanostrorum
petitioni
Studies
MARS = Mediaevaland Renaissance
= The NewScholasticism
NS
= Patrologia
PL
latina,ed. J.P. Migne
et mdivale
RTAM = Recherches
de Thologieancienne
= Abelard,Theologia
Christiana
Tchr
= Abelard,Theologia
'scholarium'
TSch
'scholarium
= Abelard,Theologia
recension
tsch
', shorter
=
boni'
'summi
Tsum
Abelard,Theologia
texts
Published
Dial.= Petrus
Abaelardus:
ed. L.M. De Rijk.Assen1956;2nded.
Dialctica,
Abelard,
1970.
Ed. = Editio
Aristotelem
deinterpretatione
in:Pietro
Abelardo.
Scritti
dilogica
Abelard,
,
super
ed. M. Dal Pra. Rome-Milan
1969.
voe.= Glossae
secundum
vocales
in: Opusculo
indito
di
Abelard,GL.sec.
super
Porphyrium
Abelardo,
ed. C. Ottaviano.Firenze1933,dd. 95-207.
in: Peter
Abaelards
Abelard,Logicaingredientibus
, ed. B. Geyer
philosophische
Schriften
(BGPM 21, 1-3).Mnster1919-27.
sociorum
in: Peter
Abaelards
Abelard,
, ed.
Logicanostrorum
petitioni
philosophische
Schriften
B. Geyer(BGPM 21, 4). Mnster1933.
= in: Petri
Christiana
and Theologia
recensiones
breviores
Abelard,Theologia
scholarium,
Abaelardi
theolopica
vol. II, ed. E. Buytaert
1969.
Turnhout
opera
,
(CCCM
12).
'
'scholarium
'summi
and Theologia
boni'= in: Petri
Abelard,Theologia
(longrecension)
Abaelardi
vol. Ill, ed. E. Buytaert
& C.J. Mews(CCCM 13).
opera
theologica,
Turnhout
1987.
Arist.
lat.I = Aristoteles
latinus
velPraedicamenta,
ed. L. Minio-Paluello.
I, 1-5:Categoriae
1961.
Bruges/Paris
= Pierre
Summa
le Chantre
deSacramentis
etAnimae
Consiliis
Chanter,
, Summa
, ed. J.-A.
vol. III . 1. Louvain/Lille
1967.
1961;vol. III. 2b. Louvain/Lille,
Dugauquier,
- Alexandi
Nat.rerum
Neckm
De naturis
rerum
libri
thePoem
duo
Neckm,
, with
oftheSame
Author
divinae
, De laudibus
, ed. T. Wright
sapientiae
(RollsSeries34). London
1967.
1857;repr.Nendeln/Liechtenstein,
=Johnof Salisbury's
Entheticus
Maiorand Minor
, ed. J. Van
Salisbury,Enthet.
3 vols.Leiden1987.
Laarhoven,
=Johannis
Saresberiensis
Carnotensis
libriIUI , ed.
Salisbury,
Metalog.
Episcopi
Metalogicon
C. Webb.Oxford1929.
211

09:12:15 AM

Literature
Secondary
= Argumentations
-theorie
-theorie.
Scholastische
zu denlogischen
und
Augmentations
Forschungen
korrekten
semantischen
forMedieval
Regeln
Folgens
(EighthEuropeanSymposium
i.B., May 24-27,1988),ed. K. Jacobi.forthLogicand Semantics,
Freiburg
coming.
theChanter
andMerchants:
TheSocialViews
Baldwin,
, Princes
J.W. 1970,Masters
ofPeter
andhisCircle
, 2 vols.Princeton.
A checklist
C. & Luscombe,
containBarrow,
D., 1984-85,
J.,Burnett,
ofthemanuscripts
andHeloise
Abelard
andother
associated
with
works
Abelard
closely
writings
ofPeter
ingthe
andhisschool
des textes,14/15,183-302.
, in: Revued'histoire
diAbelardo.
Milan.
Beonio-Brocchieri
M., 1969,La logica
Fumagalli,
etthologie
entre
chez
in:Peter
ed.
, physique
, 1974,La relation
Ablard,
Abelard,
logique
E.M. Buytaert.
Louvain,153-62.
andtheProblem
oftheHistory
of
, in:Journal
Boler,J.F., 1963,Abailard
ofUniversals
Philosophy,
1, 37-51.
over
Termen
Braakhuis,
,2
H.A.G., 1980,De 13deEeuwseTractaten
Syncategorematische
vols.Nijmeeen.
l'histoire
dutrait
delafoi, in: Mlanges
Thomistes.
Chenu,M.-D., 1934,Contribution
Paris,123-40.
auxXlleetXIIle sicles,
in:AHDL, 10-11,5-28.
etThologie
Grammaire
, 1935-36,
au douzime
sicle.Paris,90-107.
, 1957,La Thologie
intheTwelfth
andSchools
, notyet
ofThought
Courtenay,
W.J.,[1986],Schools
Century
forpublication.
submitted
andNominalism
andHis Influence
intheMiddle
, 1988,Augustine
, in: St.Augustine
Apes
, ed. E. Kin & T. Schaefer.
Louvain,91-97.
A History
andOrdained
andVolition.
, 1990,Capacity
oftheDistinction
ofAbsolute
Power.
Bereamo.
andNominalism
intheTwelfth
varietates.
, 1991a,'Nominales1
, in:Lectionum
Century
Paul Vipnaux
Hommage
(1904-1987).Paris,11-48.
TwoCenturies
di
Debate
, in: Glistudi
, 1991b,InSearch
ofNominalism:
ofHistorical
traottoe novecento.
Contributo
a unbilancio
medievale
, ed. A.
storiografico
filosofia
Maierand R. Imbach.Roma,214-33.
' andRules
'
, 1992a, Nominales
, in:Argumentations-theorie.
ofInference
inAnselm,
in:Anselmo
d1Aosta.
, 1992b,OntheEveofNominalism:
Consignification
di studio,Milano5-7 Aprii,
(Convegnointernazionale
Logico-Storia-Dottrina
1990),forthcoming.
d1Ablard
del'abstraction
etla thorie
moderne
Crizantema,
, in:
J., 1970,Le conceptualisme
et logique,14,
Revue roumainedes sciencessociales.Seriede philosophie
225-37.
di Abelardo
Dal Pra, M., 1979,Sul nominalismo
, in: Rivistacriticadi storiadella
filosofia,
24, 439-51.
Modernorum:
A Contribution
totheHistory
De Rijk,L.M., 1962,Logica
ofEarlyTerminist
Logic
, vol. I. Assen.
onTwelfth-Century
andtheSchool
, 1966,SomeNewEvidence
ofMont
Logic.Alberic
in: Vivarium,
SteGenevive
4, 1-57.
(Montani),
A Contribution
vol.
Modernorum:
totheHistory
, 1967,Logica
ofEarlyTerminist
Logic,
II. Assen.
s Solution
totheProblem
, in:
, 1980,TheSemantical
Impact
ofUniversals
ofAbailard'
ed. R. Thomas(Trier
undWirkung,
Petrus
Abaelardus
, Werk
(1079-1142).Person
Studien38). Trier,139-51.
Theologische
in:
onAbailard.
M. Tweedale
SomeCriticisms
Venture,
, 1985,Martin
ofa Fascinating
Vivarium,
23, 81-97.
212

09:12:15 AM

andHis Doctrine
Abelardo
Semantics
, in: Vivarium,24,
, 1986,Peter
ofBeing
85-127.
etinfimae
Du Cange,C., Glossarium
2nded.,6 vols.Paris,
adscriptores
mediae
latinitatis,
vol. IV, 1205-06.
1733-36;repr.Graz,1954,
'Alexander
' andthe
Ebbesen,S., 1990,Philoponus,
, in: Aristotle
origins
ofmedieval
logic
Theancient
andtheir
commentators
, ed. R. Sorabji.Ithaca,
influences
transformed.
N.Y., 445-61.
Texts
, 1991,TwoNominalist
, in: CIMAGL, 61. 429-440.
Porretanum
ex
Ebbesen,S., Fredborg,
L.O., 1983,Compendium
K.M., Nielsen,
Logicae
codice
Oxoniensi
christi
250. A ManualofPorretan
Doctrine
collegii
corporis
bya Pupil
in: CIMAGL, 46, iii-xvii
and 1-113.
ofGilbert's,
'Schools'in:
and 12thCentury
Ebbesen,S., and Iwakuma,Y., 1983,Instantiae
,
CIMAGL, 44. 81-85.
'
Parisiensis
Elenchorum'
, 1990,Anonymus
(ms.ParisBN
Compendium
Sophisticorum
4720A), in: CIMAGL, 60, 47-112.
duXlleetduXlIIesicle.
Farai,E., 1924,Lesartspotiques
Paris;repr.Genve/Paris,
1982.
inMS Vat.lat.1486, in:CIMAGL,
Prisciani
K.M., 1977,Tractatus
Fredborg,
glosm
21 (1977),21-44.
- Gilbert
dePoitiers
etsescontemporains:
auxorigines
dela 'Logica
modernorum
Actes
Gilbert
du septime
de la logiqueet de la smantique
d'histoire
symposium
Europen
ed. J. Tolivet
& A. De Libera.Napoli,1987.
mdivales,
' and'Locus
Green-Pedersen,
of'Maxima
N.J.,ed., 1977,TheDoctrine
Propositio
Differen'
tia' in Commentaries
on Boethius'Topics'
, in: Studia
fromthe12thCentury
Mediewistyczne,
18, 125-63.
intheMiddle
onAristotle's
, 1984,TheTradition
oftheTopics
Ages:TheCommentaries
andBoethius'
Mnchen.
'Topics'.
desMagister
Hubertus
Heinzmann,
R., 1974,Die Summe
'Colligite
Fragmenta'
(Clm
des Grabmann-Instituts,
24 Mnchen.
28799),Verffentlichungen
intheEleventh
Studies
onPriscian
andTwelfth
Centuries
Hunt,R.W., 1941-43,
, I: Petrus
HeliasandHisPredecessors
, in:MARS,1, 194-231;
repr.inhisTheHistory
ofGrammarin theMiddle
Studiesin theHistoryof
Papers
Ages.Collected
(Amsterdam
Science,ser.III, vol. 5), ed. G.L. Bursill-Hall.
1980,
Amsterdam,
Linguistic
1-38.
onPriscian
intheTwelfth
II: TheSchool
, 1950,Studies
Century
ofRalphofBeauvais,
in: MARS, 2, 1-56;repr.in hisHistory
, 39-94.
ofGrammar
The 'Summa'of Petrus
on Priscianus
, 1975, 'Absolute':
'Minor',in:
Hispanus
2.1, 1-22;repr.in History
, 95-116.
Historiographia
Linguistica,
ofGrammar
andtheCloister:
TheLifeandWritings
, 1984,Theschools
ofAlexander
Nequam
(11571217).Oxford.
Iwakuma
Y. , 1981, 'Instantiae':
AStudy
with
ofTwelfth
Century
Technique
ofArgumentation
anEdition
ofMs. ParisBN lat.6674, f. 1-5,in: CIMAGL, 38, 1-91.
in: CIMAGL, 44, 61-80.
, 1983,'Instantiae'
Revisited,
anIntroduction
toa Twelfth
, 1987,'Instantiae';
Century
Technique
ofArgumentation,
in: Argumentation,
437-53.
1,
'
'
Texts.
AnEdition,
in: Zinbun:AnnalsoftheInstitute
, 1989,TwoMoreInstantia
forResearchin theHumanities
24, 13-88.
(KyotoUniversity),
's Thesis'eximpossibili
Comments
onthe
, 1992a,'Parvipontani'
quidlibet
sequitur':
Sources
theTwelfth
, in: Argumentations-theorie.
oftheThesis
from
Century
orearly
in: Traditio,forthcoming.
, [1992b],'Vocales',
nominalists,
casde'platonisme
duVileauXIle sicle,
in:Mlanges
1966,Quelques
Jolivet,J.,
grammical'
RenCrozet,
vol. I, ed. P. GallaisandY.-J.Riou. Poitiers,
93-99.
offerts
213

09:12:15 AM

dulangage
etthologie
chezAblard
, (Etudesde philosophie
, 1969,Arts
mdivale,
57). Paris;2nded. 1982.
dulangage
chez
Ablard
etchezlesnominalistes
dethories
duXIVe
, 1974,Comparaison
Abelard,
ed. E.M. Buytaert.
sicle
, in: Peter
Louvain,163-78.
in: Pierre
delexographie
532-43.
, 1975a,Notes
ablardienne,
Ablard,
mdivales
surlesparonymes
de philosophie,
, in:Revueinternationale
, 1975b,Vues
29. 222-42.
entre
chien
etloupin:Cahiersdecivilisation
, 1977,Ablard
mdivales,
20,312-18.
chez
Ablard
. Essaid'interpretation,
in:Ablard
etson
etplatonisme
, 1981, Non-ralisme
dela pense
mdivale:
Paris,175-95;repr.inJolivet,
, ed.J.Jolivet.
Aspects
temps
dulaneae,
Paris1987,257-77.
Ablard
. Doctrine
reali'deJeandeMaisonneuve
etles*epicuri
littrales
Kaluza,Z., 1986,Le 'De universali
in: FZPT, 33, 469-516.
etrealistes
Paris.Nominalistes
doctrinales
auxconfins
duXlVeet
, 1988,LesQuerelles
duXVe sicles.
Bergamo.
Abailard
andtheProblem
, unpublished
dissertation,
ofUniversals
King,P.O., 1982,Peter
Princeton
University.
"
Salvavi
: A NoteontheEarly
C.H., 1976, Mulier
QuaeDamnavit,
Kneepkens,
Development
oftheRelatio
, in: Vivarium,14, 1-25.
simplex
On Twelfth
Guidoandhis Viewon Government:
, 1978,Master
Century
Linguistic
Thought
, in: Vivarium,
16, 108-141.
stuk
vandeconstructio
inde2deHelft
van
Constructions
: HetLeer
, 1987,HetJudicium
de12deEeuw
, 4 vols.Nijmegen.
desLomGlosse
zu denSentenzen
desPseudo-Poitiers
A.M., 1937,DrieZweige
Landgraf,
barden
t,in: RTAM, 9, 167-204.
Latitude
, in: NS, 14,57-74.
, 1940,A Study
ofCapua
ofPeter
oftheAcademic
I : Nominalismus
in den
deszwlften
zur Theologie
, 1943,Studien
Jahrhunderts.
derzweiten
deszwlften
Werken
, in: Traditio,1,
Jahrhunderts
Hlfte
theologischen
183-210.
naissante.
dela scolastique
dela littrature
l'histoire
, 1973,Introduction
thologique
Montral& Paris.
on Subsistence
: An Echoofthe
Grosseteste's
Lewry,O., O.P., 1983,Robert
Question
Adamites
, in:*MediaevalStudies,45, 1-21.
work:
A Study
inAscripsexprincipiorum
', a supposedly
, 1987,TheLiber
porretanean
, 251-78.
tion,in: Gilbert
AnIntroduction.
andLinguistics.
Cambridge.
Lyons,J., 1981,Language
inthe
TheInfluence
s Thought
Abelard.
D., 1969,TheSchool
Luscombe,
ofAbelard
ofPeter
ed. D.
StudiesinMedievalLifeandThought,
Period.
Scholastic
Cambridge
Early
Knowles,newseries14. Cambridge;
repr.1970.
ca.
texts
onaristotelian
andglosses
latincommentaries
Marenbon,
before
logical
J., Medieval
the
arabic
and
onaristotelian
andglosses
1150A.D., in:Commentaries
texts;
syriac,
logical
latintraditions
medieval
London,forthcoming.
, ed. C. Burnett.
in:
and De interpretation
onthe'Categories
andcommentaries
Abelard,
, Glosses
before
forthMittelalter
imfrheren
undhohen
undRhetorik
Dialektik
, ed.J. Fried.Mnchen,
coming.
in: Journal
ofPhilosophy,
83, 567-72.
Martin,C.J., 1986,William's
Machine,
in theDevelopment
Conclusions
andSurprising
of
, 1987,Embarrassing
Arguments
intheTwelfth
Theories
, in: Gilbert
, 377-400.
Century
oftheConditional
theninth
andLiars
, toappearinpapersfrom
sym, [1992],Obligations
European
1990.
St. Andrews,
oflogicand medieval
semantics,
posiumon thehistory
' Peter
in:FZPT, 31,35-55.
Gloss
onthe'Isagoge
by Abelard,
Mews,C., 1984,A Neglected
in: AHDL, 60. 73-134.
theWorks
Abelard,
, 1985,OnDating
ofPeter
214

09:12:15 AM

onsignification
andpredication
Abaelard's
evolution
, 1987, Aspects
,
ofPeter
thought
ofthe
in: Gilbert
, 15-41.
Anecdote
about
a Twelfth-Century
, 1988,In Search
ofa NameanditsSignificance:
andPeter
in: Traditio,
44, 171-200.
Thierry
Abelaerd,
andTheir
I: The'De
andRoscelin:
SomeNewTexts
, 1991,StAnselm
Implications.
' and
inter
et Gentilem in: AHDL, 58,
incarnatione
Christianm
verbi
'Disputatio
55-97.
'
'
L. (ed.), 1954,The'ArsDisserendi'
,
Minio-Paluello,
ofAdam
ofBalshamParvipontanus
in: MARS, 3, 116-69.
andStudies
inedita
, II, Roma.
, 1958,Abaelardiana
, in: Twelfth
Century
Logic:Texts
intheTwelfth
Leiden.
andPhilosophy
Nielsen,L.O., 1982,Theology
Century.
Philosin:Studies
inMedieval
Normore,
C., 1987,TheTradition
Nominalism,
ofMediaeval
ed. J. Wippel.Washington,
201-17.
ophy,
Amsterdam.
Nuchelmans,
G., 1973,Theories
oftheProposition.
Nominales
undRealesim13.Jahrhundert
F., 1944-46,
, Sophia,12-14,154-61.
Pelster,
- Pierre
= Pierre
littraires
et
Pierre
Abe'lard
le Vnrable.
Lescourants
Ablard
philosophiques,
enoccident
au milieu
duXlle sicle.
Paris1975.
artistiques
inderFrhscholastik.
EinBeitrag
der
zurGeschichte
Reiners,
J., 1910,DerNominalismus
an
imMittelalter.
Nebst
einer
neuen
Roscelins
desBriefes
Universalienfrage
Textausgabe
Abaelard
(BGPM 8.5). Mnster.
Abailard.
Sikes,J.G., 1932,Peter
Cambridge.
M. 1976,Augustine
: Every
Word
is a Name
, in: NS, 50, 183-92.
Sirridge,
Medieval
andtheSchool
R.W., 1970,Humanism
Southern,
, in: Southern,
ofChartres
Humanism
andOther
Studies.
61-85.
Oxford,
in: Renaissance
andRenewal
in
, 1982,TheSchools
ofChartres,
ofParisandtheSchool
theTwelfth
Mass.,
, ed. R.L. Bensonand G. Constable.Cambridge,
Century
113-37.
on Universals.
Amsterdam.
Tweedale,M.M., 1976,Abailard
toprof.
De Rijky
in: Vivarium,
, 1987,Reply
25, 3-23.
le
et'sacra
dePierre
dudiscours
Valente,L., 1990,Arts
loquendi'
pagina'dansle 'De tropis
Chantre
, in: Histoire,
Epistmologie,
Langage,12,II, 69-102.
in:Dictionnaire
dethologie
11.1.Paris,cols.
P., 1930,Nominalisme,
Vignaux,
catholique,
717-84.
in: Pierre
Ablard
, 1975,Notesurlenominalisme
d'Ablard,
, 523-29.
du nominalisme
mdival
clairer
desproblmes
, 1977,La problmatique
peut-elle
actuel
de Louvain,75, 293-331.
?, in: Revuephilosophique
philosophiques

215

09:12:15 AM

Vivarium
XXX, 2 (1992)
s Conceptionof theModalities
Avicenna3
ALLEN BCK

I
Modality occupies a central place in the philosophy of Ibn Sn
(Avicenna). For him, realityis divided into necessarybeing and possible being. The realityof possible being is shown by our being directly
acquainted with singular things whose existence looks contingent.
Avicenna proves the realityof necessary being, if not throughmystic
insightand prophecy, throughthe principle of sufficientreason and
thefactof theexistenceof contingentbeings: theirexistencemusthave
a sufficient
cause, and that cause cannot be sufficientif it too be contingent. In this way, then, Avicenna bases his metaphysics of
quiddity.
In order to evaluate the intricaciesof Avicenna' s analysis, as well
as his positionin the Aristoteliantradition,it is useful to have a clear
grasp of how Avicenna understands modalities. Indeed, Avicenna is
well known forhis original contributionsto modal theory.1But little
detailed workhas been done, especially on the work survivingonly in
Arabic. Here I devote myselfto that task. I shall begin with a study
of Avicenna' s modal notions, and shall proceed by discussing some
problems and obscuritiesin them. I shall conclude by sketchinghow
these modal notions functionin his metaphysics.
As we shall see, it mighteasily be thoughtthat Avicenna accepts a
temporalview of modality,as he, like Aristotle,links 'necessary' with
'always', 'impossible' with 'never', and 'possible' with'sometimes so,
sometimesnot'. Indeed, ifAvicenna is offeringthese reductivedefinitions of the modalities in termsof time, this would resemble the view
of modalitythat Hintikka attributesto Aristotle.2But that is not so:
Avicenna does not equate the modal and the temporal operators. For,
again like Aristotle,Avicenna allows forboth singular and universal
1 Frederick
A History
, NewYork1972,115;Etienne
Copleston,
ofMedieval
Philosophy
intheMiddle
Gilson,History
ofChristian
Philosophy
Apes,NewYork1955,191-2.
2 JaakkoHintikka,
TimeandNecessity
, Oxford1973,91-7.
217

09:02:05 AM

possibilities that are never actualized in time. He does so, first,


throughpostulatingtwo sorts of existence, real (in re) and mental (in
intellectu
), and, second, by divorcingmodalityfromactual existencein
time altogether.Still, he tries to accomodate the Aristotelianlinking
of modality to time.
In effectthenAvicenna is tryingto workout an Aristotelianposition
on modality. His explanation, ifconsistent,will have the meritof presentinga unifiedaccount of featuresof Aristotelianmodal theorythat
many have found obscure if not inconsistent.Further,his analysis of
the necessary feature of contingent beings looks original and thus
worthy of study- and may contribute to current discussions of
modality. Finally, from this study we may gain insight into
Avicenna' s systemof metaphysicsas well as those systemsof the many
philosophers who have been influencedby his work.
II
As is usual, Avicenna has his most complex discussion of modality
in the Shif3( TheHealing' his encyclopedia), in Al-Qfys(The Analytics)
.
But as it is also the most obscure, and has his own doctrineintertwined
with otherviews and with sophisms, I propose to structuremy discussion around his more elementarytreatises,and then modifyand complicate the results as necessary fromAl-Qiys.
In Al-Najt(The Deliverance)
Avicenna makes the same distinctionof
the modalityof the matterof the propositionand the modalityof the
proposition as the Greek commentators.3The matter of proposition
consistsin 44the state belonging to the predicate in relationto the subject' '4 That is, the predicate terms refersto a certain attribute,and
the subject termto a subject. The relationof thatattributeto thatsubject determinesthe matterofthe proposition.If the matterofthe prop3 Ammonius,
In Aristotelis
De Interpretatione
Commentarius
, ed. A. Busse,Berlin1897,
In Aristotelis
Priora
Commentarius
, ed. M. Wallies,
215,7;JohnPhiloponus,
Analytica
Berlin1905,43,23-7.
4 Al'Najat
Cairo
, ed I. Madkhour,
, ed. M. Kurdi,Cairo 1938,39,8-10;Al-Qfys
1973,39,8-10.
I offer
a literal
translation
ofcertain
As an appendix,
keytextsthatarenotreadily
ofAl-Ishrt
available.Thereis a Frenchtranslation
by Goichon(Paris1951);a
Frenchtranslation
ofAl-Ilhiyyt
byG. Anawati(Paris1985),as wellas a medieval
edition
critical
forwhichS. Van Riethasgivena current
Latintranslation
(Louvain
trans.M.S. Khan,Delhi1969,99,
ofAvicenna,
1977).A.-M. Goichon,ThePhilosophy
ofAl-Najt.
Latintranslation
also notesa medieval
218

09:02:05 AM

osition is necessary, the attributebelongs to the subject always; if


impossible, never; if possible, neithernecessary nor impossible, and
hence neitheralways nor never.5 In contrast,the mode of a proposition concerns the predication relation between attributeand subject
that is stated explicitlyin the proposition.6Still, the modalities are
definedlikewisehere. The matterand the mode of a propositionmay
differ:e.g., 'it is possible thata man is an animal' has a possible mode
and necessary matter, since it is necessary that a man is an animal.
It will already been seen that here Avicenna seems to maintain a
strictequivalence between the modal and the temporaloperators. The
necessaryis what is compelled to exist, what exists always.7 Hence the
impossible ('necessary no) is what is compelled not to exist, what is
never. Now Avicenna, followingAristotle,distinguishesthe possible
into the one-sided, common possible ('not impossible') and the
strictly,two-sidedcontingentpossible ('not necessary and not impossible').8 It mightthen seem to followthatthe contingentis what sometimes does exist, and sometimes does not exist. So here Avicenna
appears to embrace a principle of plenitude, according to which
everythingthat is possible must exist at some time. But we shall come
to see that his position is a bit more complex, and denies this result.
Ill
Avicenna distinguishes six ways in which a predication can be
necessary. Necessitymeans permanence, but there are differentsorts
of permanence.9The distinctionis based on differencesin the stretch
of time forwhich the predication is supposed to hold.10 It may hold
1) always, withoutqualification,as in 'God is alive' 2) as long as the
essence of the subject is existent,as in 'Socrates is an animal': Socrates
does not always exist, and so thispropositionwill not always be true,
since it asserts Socrates' presentexistence; yet, in the stretchof time
5 Al-Najt
Al-Isharat
wa'l Tanbihat
andRemarks),
ed.
14,21-15,4;
(TheBookofDirectives
S. Dunya,Cairo1947,306,1-12(trans.&comm.A.-M.Goichon,
Le livre
desdirectives
etremarques
, Paris1951).
6 Al-Najt
17,4-8.
7 Al-Najt
17,4;20,2-3.
8 Al-Najt17,17-18,13;
On Interpretation
33,11-35,7;Aristotle,
Al-Qiyas
13; Prior
1.13.
Analytics
9 Al-Najt
17,4-5;Al-Qjys
32,7.
10Al-Najt
Al-Ishrt
20,5-21,6;
21,13-23,15;
32,8-33,8;
Al-Qys
310,1-316,7;
Mantiq
Al-Mushriqiyyn
(Logicoj theOrientals
), Cairo 1973,71,11-72,6.
219

09:02:05 AM

in which Socrates does exist, it is always true. Avicenna remarksthat


these two senses of necessityhave a common structure,since 'as long
as the essence of the subject is existent' is the common condition that
must be satisfiedin each.11 This common condition constitutesstrict
necessity, properlyspeaking.
The last four cases all share the featurethat the stretchof time is
determinedby when the termsof the propositionhold of the subject.
3) A necessarypredicationmay hold as long as the essence of the subject is trulydescribed by the subject term, as in 'every white thing
stands out in sight'. Here, the subject, say, a post, can exist without
being white, but, as long as it is white, it necessarily stands out in
sight. So here the subject always has the predicated attributeduring
only a portion of its existence, namely, during the predication of the
subject term.
Now it followsthat whatever is necessary strictlywill be necessary
in thisway too. For, if S is P as long as the thingthat is S exists, then
S is P as long as that thing is described by 'S'. However, not conversely: a necessityof the thirdcase that is not necessary strictlywill
describe an accidental necessityof the subject; once it happens to be
S, it is necessarilyP thereby,but that necessityneed be only accidental, since the subject need not be S.
4) A necessarypredicationmay hold as long as the predicate is existent, i.e., as long as the predication holds, as in 'Socrates necessarily
walks when he walks': given that Socrates is walking, it is necessary
that he is walking; in those stretchesof his career when he walks, he
is always walking. Here the subject term, 'S', names the thingthat is
the subject. To say here that S is P necessarilymeans that S has the
attributeof being P as long as it has it. The fourthcase of necessity
will then hold of accidental as well as of essential predications.
Predications that are necessary in the first two ways will be
necessaryin thisway too. Likewise, what is necessaryin the thirdway
will be necessaryin the fourth.All threeofthesecases share the feature
that once the subject is determinedit always has its attributesas long
as it has them. However, what is necessary in the fourthway is not
necessary in either of the firsttwo ways; just take an accidental
predication,like 'Socrates walks'. Nor again in the thirdway: even if
Socrates is always walking when he is walking, it does not followthat
11Al-Najt
20,10-1;Al-Qys
31,15-32,6.
220

09:02:05 AM

Socrates is always walking as long as the subject is named 'Socrates'.12


The last two distinctionsboth concern predicates that must hold of
the subject itself,not merelyof it under a description,unlike the third
case. Unlike the fourthcase, here in both cases the predication cannot
hold merelyby accident. Further,unlike the firsttwo cases, the stretches of time for which both predications hold are intermittentand
discontinuous.
Avicenna distinguishestwo cases. 5) These predications may hold
in periods of time that are fixed and determinate,past, present, and
future,as in 'the moon has eclipses by necessity': forthe moon is not
always eclipsed, but it is so at definitetimes. Still, the moon is not
eclipsed permanently,but only forshortperiods of time at great intervals. But, duringthose periods of eclipse, it is eclipsed necessarilyand
not merelyby accident. Those periods are definite,and follow from
the nature of the moon and the heavens.13
6) Somtimes those periods of time forwhich the predication holds
are required and fixed, but are less definite,as in 'Socrates breathes
(inhales)' : Socrates must breathe during a stretchof time, because he
is a human being, but when in particularduring that stretchof time
is leftopen.
So, unlike the fourth case, the fifthand sixth cases deal with
predicatesthat have to be not accidental but essential or inseparable
attributes{propria
) of the subject. Avicenna remarks that what is
necessaryin the fifth(and also the sixth?) sense will also be necessary
in the fourthsense: e.g., the moon is necessarilyeclipsed as long as
12Aninteresting
like'theoneseatedwalkswhen
puzzlecanbe raisedaboutexamples
hewalks'or'thewhiteisblackwhenitisblack'.Clearly
thisis necessary
inthefourth
is restricted
toholding
way.Butwhataboutin thethirdway?Thenthepredication
in onlythosetimeswhenthesubjectis described
bythesubjectterm,e.g., whileit
is seatedorwhite.Butduringthoseperiodsthereneverwillarisean occasionwhere
thepredicate
to thesubjectterm('walks'to 'seated';
trulyarises,as it is contrary
'black'to'white').So suchpropositions
seemtoholdvacuously.
But,as I shalldiscuss
further
hasan existential
condition
forthetruth
of
below,Avicenna
generally
import
a proposition.
Can a proposition
be trueforwhichthereneverexistsa truthmaker?
ForAvicenna,
not.
apparently
Unliketheotherfivesensesdistinguished,
thefourth
senseseemsto concern
the
andnotthething,
andnotdere.However
Avicenna
does
proposition
i.e., tobededicto
notidentify
thefourth
senseas beingofa specialtype.I shalldiscussthedere- dedicto
distinction
issuebelowin VIII.
13Perhaps
notfrom
thequiddities
inthemselves,
butfrom
theminsofar
as theyhave
cometoexistin matter
withtheirconcomitant
attributes.
See belowp.
inseparable
240.
221

09:02:05 AM

it is eclipsed.14 But not viceversa: for Socrates need not be walking


when he is walking; it is not determinedthathe walk at any time. The
fourthcase allows accidental predication; the fifthand sixthcases do
not. Further, necessity in the fifthor sixth way does not require
necessityin the thirdway, since, in the former,the predicationholds
discontinuously, as long as the subject exists; in the latter, continuouslyduring the stretchof time when the subject termholds of the
subject. Again, because of this discontinuity,what is necessaryin the
fifthor sixthway is not necessary in the firstor second, although the
converse does hold, trivially.
IV
Avicenna has distinguishedthese six sortsof necessityin accordance
with certain texts in Aristotle and doctrines in his Greek commentators. He seems to work fromthe work ofJohn Philoponus the most
closely. This is not surprising, given that Avicenna also follows
Philoponus when dealing with space and corporeity.15
As forthe antecedentsof Avicenna' s division of modalityin Aristotle, the firsttwo modes concern Aristotle's simple necessity,with the
distinction based on Aristotle's division of perishable and
imperishablesubstance.16The thirdcase is peraccidensnecessity.17The
fourthmode is tied to the discussion in On theHeavens1.12, where
Aristotleclaims that in a hypotheticalsense, it is necessary that the
seated Socrates sit, even though it is possible, in an absolute sense,
that at that time he be walking about.18 The fifthand sixthcases are
distinguished in accordance with the PosteriorAnalytics.19Still,
Avicenna has not obedientlyheeded all ofAristotle'sremarks.Indeed,
in his list he disregards Aristotle's tripartitedivision of necessity in
PartsofAnimals1.1 and the division of teleological necessityin Physics
II. 9. Further,as faras I can tell, neitherAristotlenor the Greek commentators gives this sixfolddivision in its entirety.
14Al-Qjyas
33,3-8.
15The question
s viewsis ofcourseenormous,
sourcesofAvicenna'
ofthehistorical
I do notmoreherethanpointto a fewkeytexts;I
and enormously
complicated.
a couplein theAppendix.
translate
16Aristotle,
XII. 1; OntheHeavens
1.12.
Metaphysics
17Physics
II. 3; Metaphysics
V.2.
18281b8-15; cf.OnInterpretation
19a23-8.
19Posterior
95a32.
11.12,especially
Analytics
222

09:02:05 AM

v
Avicenna consistentlyaffirmsthe point that necessitystrictlyspeaking is given in the firsttwo cases, which have a common structure.To
say that it is necessarythat S is P claims that the thingreferredto by
'S' is P as long as that thingexists. The only differencebetween these
two cases lies in whetheror not the subject always exists.20
The othercases of necessityare derivative.Avicenna holds thatsuch
necessary propositions do not differ significantly from their
categorical,non-modal counterparts.Thus, we may gain more insight
into those cases of necessary propositionsby looking at what he says
about categorical propositions in general.21
Note that this issue, of the differencebetween universal categorical
and necessary propositions,is a serious one for Aristotelianscience:
forAristotelianscience requires necessarypremises,but inductionand
experience yields only universal generalizations. So how are we to
make transitionfrom the universal to the necessary, and from the
syllogisticof the PriorAnalyticsto the demonstrationsof the Posterior
?22
Analytics
Avicenna distinguishestwo views on the truthconditions required
for universal affirmativecategorical propositions held in late Greek
philosophy,one championed by Theophrastus, and the otherby Alexander of Aphrodisias.23He claims thathis own view synthesizesthese,
which he says indeed agree about the specificationof the subject: in
'every S is P', the claim is about the thingthatis S, but the categorical
proposition does not specifywhether the referenceis to the entire
existenceof that thing,or to it only while it has the attributeof being
S.24 He says thatthe two views differonly about how permanentlythe
predicationis supposed to hold: whetherthe predicate has to hold of
the subject, once determined, always, in any of the six modes of
20Al-Najt
25,8-10;Al-Qtys
33,8-10.
21Al-Qiys
In An.Pr.43,15-7.
33,8.On thisissuecf.Philoponus,
22Aristotle
thatwe graspfirst
induc99b20-100a9,
says,Posterior
Analytics
principles
Butfirst
aresupposedto be indubitable
andnecessary,
so howdo
tively.
principles
we eliminate
thedoubt?Thisproblem
is commonly
in theAristotelian
recognized
De Propositionibus
Necessariis
tradition;
see,e.g.,Zabarella,
, in Opera
, Frankfurt
Logica
1623,368.
23Al-Najt
23,4-5;Al-Qys
24,1-26,14;
28,4-29,9;31,11-2.
The Greektextsforthisclaimare scanty,
butsee Alexander
ofAphrodisias,
In
Aristotelis
Priorm
Librum
I Commentarium,
ed. M. Wallies,Berlin1883,
Analyticorum
36,28-9;156,29-157,2;
158,8-10.
24Al-Najt
23,9-14;Al-Qtys
20,15-21,5;
26,10-27,9.
223

09:02:05 AM

necessitydiscussed above, (so Alexander), or not always but only at


some time (so Theophrastus).25 Avicenna himselftends to side with
Theophrastus here, because Aristotleseems to assertthatpropositions
like 'every horse is asleep' and 'no horse is asleep' are true iftheyhold
merely at an instant of time (ut nunc or kata chronon)although not
always.26
Now let us fix on the differencebetween the necessary and the
categorical. There will be some categorical propositionsthat are not
necessary strictly:the ut nuncpropositions. Yet even these will be
necessary in the thirdor fourthmodes. The only differencebetween
a categorical proposition and its necessary counterpartin such cases
seems to lie in the latter's stressingand stating explicitlyand more
preciselyjust how the predication is intended to hold.27
Why, then, bring in such cases of necessary propositions at all?
Presumably to offera method whereby to select categorical propositions forAristoteliandemonstrativescience. Moreover, as I shall suggest, to emphasize the differencebetween essence (the quiddity in
itself) and being (existence in re or in intellectu).
VI
Avicenna may appear to errwhen he says thatthe last fourdivisions
concern propositions where "the mode" forms parts of the
44
predicate.28For the mode" (al-jihat) is the expression that he uses to
signifythe modality.29By 'forms part of the predicate', Avicenna
might appear to mean that the predicate term contains the modality,
so that, e.g., the predicate of 'Socrates breathesnecessarily' would be
'breathes necessarily'. But neitherhe nor Aristotleshows any inclination to recognize such terms in premises in the syllogistic.Perhaps
then he means, rather,only thatthe specificationof the period of time
during which the modalityhas to hold is on the side of the predicate.
But the firstthree cases of necessitydistinguishedby Avicenna have
the featurethat the subject and the period during which the predication has to hold is determinedindependentlyof the predicate. In contrast,in the last threecases, thatdeterminationcan be made only after
25Al-Najt
24,14-5.
26Al-Najt
34b7-ll.
23,7-9;cf.Prior
Analytics
27Al-Najat
21,6-7;Al-Qiyas
33,8.
28Al-Najt
21,6-13.
29Al-Najt
16,6.
224

09:02:05 AM

the predicate is given as well. So then, why group the last fourcases
togetherand make this claim about them?
We have seen that Avicenna wants to group those four cases
togetherbecause they are not strictlynecessary and thus belong to
what is properlycategorical. Perhaps he has been careless in using the
term"mode". The point is thatthelast fourmodes all require, strictly
speaking, a stipulationof the period of time forwhich the predication
is to hold, in addition to the fixingof the subject by the subject term.
I.e., the last fourcases share the featureof stipulatinga period of time
that is a proper part of the time period during which the subject
exists.30That stipulation,made explicit, becomes- more accurately,
replaces- the modality. Avicenna then could be saying merely that
these last fourcases have an additional stipulation,and that is part of
the predicate. Indeed, Avicenna does say that in the sense that 4it is
necessary that every S is P' means 'everythingthat is described as
being S, as long as it is existent,is described as P, as long as it is P',
the predicate is 'P, as long as it is P'.31 So Avicenna here locates the
temporal specificationon the side of the predicate; likewise, Aristotle
says thatthe significationof time is proper to the verb and so thistemporal specificationtoo will belong to the predicate.32
The text is obscure. Yet Avicenna may be saying something
interestinghere: the modal specificationmust be kept away fromthe
subject so as not to complicate the ontology. For a determinationof
the subject termtypicallychanges the referenceof the original subject
term to some type of part of the subject.33By keeping restrictionson
the stretchof time on the side of the predicate, he then has a way of
giving a single account for all types of necessity: in all six cases, the
necessityconcerns what holds during the whole or some part of the
career of the subject. In effect,Avicenna may be insistingthat whole
substances be subjects, not temporal parts or time-slicesof subjects,
as he would be ifthe modal/temporalspecificationwere on the side of
the subject. For, as we shall see in VIII & XI, the subject will turn
out to be a quiddityin itselfthat has come to exist, in reor in intellectu
,
30So incontrast,
Avicenna
seemstoimplythatinthefirst
twocasesthemodality
is
noton thesideofthepredicate
buton thesideofthesubject.Or, moresimply,
he
mayholdonlythatin thefirsttwocases thereis not any additional
temporal
specification.
31Al-Qys
42,3-6;Al-Najt
21,10-3.
32Aristotle,
OnInterpretation
16b6-9.
33Suchis thetraditional
view.See AllanBck,OnReduplication
, [forthcoming].
225

09:02:05 AM

to which the predicate, another such quiddity,is attached. The proposition then asserts that this attachmentexists, during some stretchof
time. The temporal determination then gives the stretch of time
during which the predication is supposed to hold.
VII
Avicenna complicates his view by distinguishingtwo senses of contingency. As we have seen, Avicenna does recognize one-sided
possibilityas well. In this sense, a propositionmay be necessary and
possible.34But his usual sense of the possible is the two-sided,the contingent.He says thatthe contingentis thatwhich is not necessarybut
which, assumed to exist, leads to no absurdity.35He does not say that
the contingenthas to exist sometime. Rather, he stipulatesonly that
it not be necessary, and that, if it be posited to exist, no impossibility
results.
Avicenna at times distinguishestwo senses of the contingent.36In
the firstsense, he says, the contingentconcernsa subject (S) thatexists
now, where its attribute(P) is neithernecessarynor impossible. Here
the predication of T' of 'S' is contingentwith respect to the present
moment; no attentionis paid to whetheror not the subject will exist
at some futuretime.37In this sense, the possible or contingentis more
inclusive than the actual. Only the relation of subject and predicate
matters; the proposition is contingent if that relation is accidental,
regardlessof whetherit in factholds, eithernow or in the future.That
is, 'it is contingentthat S is now P' is true regardlessof whetherS is
P or S is not P, so long as S exists now and P is an accident of S.
In the second sense, Avicenna says that 'it is contingentthat every
S is P' ifand only ifthereis a time at which the claim thateverything
that is described in act as being S is also P is neithernecessary nor
34Al-Qtys
35,6.
35Al-Najt25,21-2;Al-Qjys
In
33,11-4.See PriorAnalytics
32al8-20;Alexander,
AnPr. 156,19-20.
36See Alexander,In An Pr. 161,6-9;165,18,Aristotle,
PriorAnalytics
32b23;
La logique
in: Archives
1048bl0-8.A.-M. Goichon,
d'Avicenne,
d'histoire,
Metaphysics
doesnotrecognize
thatAvicenna
16(1948),pp. 58-9,takestheposition
contingency
in thenatureof things.
as an "ontological
modality",but onlyas a condition
appearsin hismodallogicanyway.
Perhaps,butcontingency
37
41,7;
319,5;319,17-9;322,7;Mantiq73,4-7;Al-Najt
33,13-5;Al-Ishrt
Al-Qys
In AnPr. 59,15-7.
42,6-7.Cf. Philoponus,
226

09:02:05 AM

impossible.38This time in question typicallyif not always is a future


time; it must be indefiniteand not specify,unlike the fifthand sixth
cases of the necessary,particularsubjects at particulartimes. What is
actual is not contingentin this sense.39Rather, the subject in such a
contingentstatementitselfmay exist or may not exist. Contingency
in thissense is independentof the presentstate of the subject (the S 's)
but is tied to the future.40
What Avicenna means here has its obscurities. It appears that this
second sense of contingencyis a radical sense, where no attentionat
all is paid to present(and past) contingentfacts. In contrast,in the
firstsense, attentionis paid to those facts,and so existentialimportat
a definitetime is required- and so one of the categorical statements
(' S is P'; 'S is not P') that are the correlatesof the contingentstatement ('S is contingentlyP') will be true: categorical, accidental
predicationis being made.41 However, in the second sense, the contingentstatementmay be truewithouteitherof its categoricalcounterparts being true: 'S is P' and 'S is not P' are both false forAvicenna
when S does not exist; he takes the existentialimportcondition as an
explicit truthcondition for the truthof a proposition.42
Avicenna contraststhesetwo senses of the contingentin a discussion
of the example, 'Zayd is sitting'.43While Zayd is sitting,I may say
that it is contingentthat Zayd is sitting- i.e., that the present circumstance is neithernecessarynor impossible: presumably I may say
thiseven when Zayd is standingand not sittingnow. That is the first
sense. In the second, I may say now, while Zayd is sitting,that it is
contingentthatZayd sits, in the sense that in the future,at some time
leftindeterminate,that state of affairsmay be realized, or may not:
Zayd may not even exist in the future.Avicenna denies that 'Zayd is
sitting' is contingentin the second sense.44 Perhaps his point is that
the second sense is ruled out when the existentialimportof the subject
is established. So, given that Zayd is sittingnow, contingencyin the
second sense does not obtain. Yet if we ignore Zayd' s present
38Al-Qtys
Al-lsharat
33,15-34,2;
320,3-8;Mantiq73,10-3;Al-Najat
19,15-22.
39Al-Qys
34,7-10.
40Al-Qtyas
In AnPr.59,17;60,3-5.
34,11-2.Cf. Philoponus,
41Mantiq71,12-4.
42Mantiq72,9-10.Foran
ofAvicenna's
ofpredication
sec Allan
exposition
theory
onExistence
oftheHistory
ofPhilosophy,
XXV.5 (1987).
Bck,Avicenna
, in:Journal
43Al-Qys
34,7-35,7.
34,8-10,butcf.34,12-5wherehe seemsto saythatitis: he says,in that
Al-Qyas
caseat least?,thatthetwosensesaredistinct
butinseparably
trueorfalsetogether.
227

09:02:05 AM

existence, or note that he may not exist now, or if we consider his


future status, contingency in the second sense does obtain.45 This
second sense resembles Aristotle's attitudesabout sea battle and the
example, 'the cloak may or not be cut up in the future'; indeed, the
cloak may not even exist tomorrowto be cut up or not.46
Avicenna also says that 'Zayd breathes' is not contingentin the
second sense of contingencybut in the firstsense.47For here there is
a definitesubject, that actually exists. This example differsfromthe
previous example, 'Zayd is sitting'. As we have seen, Avicenna uses
4a man breathes' as an
example of the sixthcase of the necessary. So,
that
he
must breathe at some time. Yet he need not
exists,
given
Zayd
be breathingnow. So his breathingnow is contingentin the firstsense.
Further, although Avicenna does not say so explicitly,he seems to
hold that it is also contingentin the second sense that Zayd breathes
in the future,as it is contingentthat he will continue to exist.
So the firstsense of the contingentrequires existentialimportof the
subject term at some time; the second sense does not. In the first
sense, if it is contingentthat S is P, then either S is P or S is not P.
But not in the second sense: since S may not at all exist in the future,
4S is P' and 'S is not P' will both be
false, if S never exists. Indeed,
in the latter sense, somethingcontingentneed not exist at all.48
Avicenna may here have in mind the distinctionbetween internal
and external possibilitymade by Aristotlein PriorAnalytics1. 13.49 'It
is contingent that S is P' may mean 1) P contingentlybelongs to
everything to which S belongs or 2) P contingentlybelongs to
everything to which S contingentlybelongs. If so, his discussion
followsthe lead of Philoponus who distinguishesthe contingentinto
the definiteand the indefinite,and connectsthe formerwiththe internally possible, with what is for the most part ( epi topolu), with what
is already in reality,and with the categorical, and connects the latter
with the externallypossible, with what is not for the most part, and
with what is not yet in realitybut mightbe in the future.50
45Al-Ishrt
221,1-6.
46OnInterpretation
19al3-3; 22b34,and,perhaps,
Nicomachean
Ethics1114al5-22.
47Al-Qys
35,3-5.
48Al-Qjys
distinction
ofweak
35,11;35,16-36,1;
Mantiq71,14-5;73,5-7.A similar
versusstrong
in modern
contingency
appears
logic.
4y32b25-30;cf.Alexander,
In AnPr. 166,5-25.
50Philoponus,
In AnPr. 59,15-20;61,12-20;154,29-155,2;
155,11-2;In Aristotelis
Commentario,
InAnPr.
, ed. H. Vitelli,Berlin1887-8,267,1.AlsoAlexander,
Physicos
228

09:02:05 AM

Avicenna' s discussion of contingencyis obscure. It has the unfortunate featureof using examples with singular terms,which do not fit
this distinctionwell: forsingular termsparticular issues of existential
importarise. He may be motivated to use singular termsto connect
the distinctionwith the question of futurecontingents- the sea battle
of On Interpretation
9. For such futurecontingentstatementsas 'it is
possible that there will be a sea battle tomorrow' may be considered
contingentin the second sense. In such cases the subject termmay fail
to referever. On the otherhand, contingentstatementsmay deal with
subjects actuallyexistingat some time, and claim that certain of their
attributesdo not belong to them necessarily. In the firstsense, it is
contingentthat Zayd is sittingor walking, as long as a furthercondition is not attached: i.e., a condition stipulatingthat Zayd is sitting
or standingnow. For, ifthatconditionwere attached, then the proposition would become necessary in the fourthsense detailed above in
HI.
VIII
There may arise the temptationto take strictnecessity,as being on
the side of the subject, as de re, and the derivativenecessity,common
to categorical propositions too, as de dicto.After all, the derivative,
common necessityconcerns the predication, or the dictum.Further,
Avicenna in the traditionof the Stoic lekton
, stresses the conceptual
level of the ma'nan or intentio.
Then, predicational necessitywould be
tied to the purely conceptual level, and so be de dicto, while necessity
fixed solely by the reference of the intention would be de re. So
Avicenna may be appearing to make a distinctionof de reand de dicto
modalityhere.
But this correlationhas flaws. Usually, a proposition is considered
to be necessary de dictowhen it is true by definition, as in 'every
bachelor is necessarilyunmarried'. Here analysis of the subject concept generatesthe necessity.In contrast,de renecessity(if thereis such
a thing)depends on more than the analysis of the concept; e.g., 'every
theseconnections,
hadcollected
andrun
39,18-21;162,1-6.(Bymaking
Philoponus
- perhapslegitimately
- severaldistinctions
madeby Aristotle
in different
together
places.)
thisdistinction
oftwotypesofcontingency
obscure,
Although
maywellresemble
themodern
distinction
ofweakand strong
See MartinDavies,Meaning,
modality.
, London1981,pp. 213-4.
Quantification,
Necessity
229

09:02:05 AM

body necessarilyhas weight' (probably false, but still de re according


to Kant).
Now for Avicenna the strictlynecessary propositions, based on
definitionsholding throughoutthe career of the subject, will contain
those predications here described as de dicto. Thus Avicenna' s
necessarypredicationson the side of the predicatelook more de rethan
those on the side of the subject. Likewise, the necessary propositions
of the last four cases, based instead on the predication of inessential
attributes,might be then taken to correspond to the de re.
So we might turn about and make a case for a correspondence
between the de dictoand Avicenna's distinctionof strictmodality(the
firsttwo cases), and between the de reand derivativemodality,dependent on the predication. Still I have some qualms. First, as we shall
see in XI, Avicenna views all modalitiesto deal withpredicationand
to be grounded in the relation of one quiddity to another. Again, as
we shall see in X, Avicenna recognizes two sorts of existence, in re
Existentsof eithersortmay constitutethe referenceof
and in intellectu.
a universal term and may illustrate all six types of necessity. This
approach does not look congenial to a sharp division of the linguistic
level of the dictumand the thing-levelof the res.Third, in all six cases
of necessity,Avicenna has the basic structureof a predicationapplying
to a subject during some period of its existence. The six cases differ
only in what that period is and how it is determined. This approach
looks radically realist. Finally, the correlationdoes not work well in
particularcases of sense distinguished.Like cases 1 and 2, case 3 looks
de dicto: the thing is taken under a certain description, and then a
necessary featureof that descriptionis predicated of it. Case 4 looks
de dicto: surelyit is trivialthatevery many walks when he walks. Likewise cases 5 and 6 can be seen as followingfromthe meaning of the
terms.
So I do not take Avicenna to make a de re- de dictodistinctionof
modality. He does make a distinction of the determinationof the
modality by the subject or by the predicate. Perhaps, then, we might
reformulatethe de re- de dictodistinctionto distinguishwhat holds in
virtue of real definition,on the level of quiddities in themselves,and
what holds in virtue of nominal definition,on the level of quiddities
in the mind.51This distinctionmay anticipate or be isomorphicwith
51Cf. Aristotle,
Posterior
92b5-8;93b29-32;94all-4.
Analytics
230

09:02:05 AM

thatdistinction,but the two do not clearlyappear identical: again consider the fifthand sixth cases.
IX
Anotherissue to be resolved concerns the principleof plenitude. As
we have seen, at firstAvicenna has apparently taken the common
Aristoteliantemporalattitudetowards the modalities: the necessaryis
what holds always. Then the possible or contingentwould be what
holds neitheralways nor never. But then, if not never, ifit is possible
that S is P, then at some time S is P. Hence every possibilitymust
occur. Here Avicenna seems to identifythe modal and the temporal
operators.
However, Avicenna does not seem to accept this consequence. We
have seen Avicenna clearlyadmittingpossibilitiesthatdo not occur at
any time especially those that are contingentin the second sense.
Hence he rejects a strongprinciple of plenitude: at any rate, not all
singular possibilitiesneed occur.
Further, in his discussion of the universal, Avicenna recognizes
purelyuniversalpossibilitiesthatneed not exist in re.Propositionsmay
be satisfiedby thingsthat have existence in the intellectonly, and not
in re (or, as he puts it, 44existence in individuals").52 This remark
seems to agree withhis view of the universal,where he says thata term
like 'the sun' is a universal even though therehas been and will be in
factonly one sun, and, likewise, 'heptagonal house' is universal even
thoughtheremay never be at any time such a house.33 But he claims
thatsuch termsare universal because the mind is not preventedfrom
supposing them to be predicated of many.
Avicenna holds thatexpressionslike 'heptagonal house' are universal, as they can be predicated of many individuals. But there may
never, at any time, exist in reany individual heptagonal houses. Still,
even then, the intellectmay suppose such individuals to exist. Such
suppositionsufficesto satisfythe requirementthat a universal be said
of many. Hence such expressionsare universal. Thus, Avicenna con52Al-Qtys
21,6;30,2-4.
53Ilhiyyt
(Metaphysics
), ed. Anawatiet al., Cairo 1960,195,11-196,3
( = Met. 86v
col. 1); [I indicate
ofOpera
themedievalLatintranslation
Avicennae
parenthetically
edition
ofthis,
(Venice1508;repr.Frankfurt
1961)whenavailable;thereis a critical
ed. S. Van Riet,Louvain1977,withthesamepagination.].
Also cf. Aristotle,
OntheHeavens
1.9.
1040a28-b2;
Metaphysics
231

09:02:05 AM

eludes that, in the logical sense, the universal is that which it is possible to predicate of many.54 An external cause may prevent this
possibility,but it is a consistent,legitimatepossibility.
Once again, Avicenna has denied a strongprinciple of plenitude:
but this time not forsingulars but foruniversais. It is contingentthat
some houses, or all houses, be heptagonal, since the combination of
'house' and 'heptagonal' is neithernecessary nor impossible. Further
this possibilityobtains, even when no heptagonal house exists in reat
any time. Here Avicenna has divorced modality fromtime.
So, on the one hand, Avicenna seems to identifythe modalitieswith
time, and connects'necessary' and 'always', 'impossible' and 'never',
'possible' and 'sometimes so, sometimesnot'. Yet, on the otherhand,
he recognizes possibilities that are never actualized. How might we
resolve this apparent contradiction?It is easy to say that Avicenna' s
position is incoherent, because he had adopted Aristotle's position
which itselfis incoherent, or because he has conjoined a temporal
Aristotelian view with a timeless neo-Platonist view of modality.
Beforetakingthisroute, let us make the more difficultmove oflooking
at his views more closely.
Indeed, note that Avicenna has not stated an equivalence of
modalities and temporalities explicitly. As we have seen, he does
endorse the followinginferences:
If necessary, always.55
If sometimes so, sometimes not, contingent.56
If impossible, never, [indirect:substitute'-p' for'p' in 'if necessary
p. ']
But Avicenna denies the following inferences explicitly in some
passages, althoughhis wording in yet othersmay seem to implythese
consequences:
If always, necessary.57
If contingent,sometimes so, sometimes not.58
If never, impossible, [substitute'-p' for 'p'].
54llahiyyt
, 196,4-5( = Met. 86vcol. 1); Al-Madkhal
26,9;29,1( = Log.3v col. 1; 3v
col. 2).
55Al-Qtys,
32,7.
56Al-Qtys,
73,11-3;Al-Ishrt
, 280, 14.
57Al-shrt,
thatthequestion
whether
ornotthere
323.1-3;at 329,9-12heremarks
can be something
is nota questionforthelogician
alwayswithout
beingnecessary
to decide.
58 Al-Qiyas
35,1;Al-Isharat
320,3-8;Al-Mantiq
73,5-7.
232

09:02:05 AM

This position does not sufficeto give temporal definitionsof the


modalities. Indeed, there are possibilitiesthat never exist, as can be
seen particularlyin the second sense of the contingent.
It is easy to misread his position. A good example occurs when he
44
says that it is said" thatthe contingentis what does not exist no but
will in the future.59He himselfdoes not necessarilyendorse thisview;
notice how his own view, of the second sense of the contingentdiffers
subtly fromit. To be sure, in this very passage, he asserts: if contingent, then neither necessary nor impossible; if necessary, then
always; if impossible, never. But it does not thereforefollow: if contingentthen not always nor not never- that would be the fallacy of
denying the antecedent.60
So, despite appearances, Avicenna does not hold the strongprinciple of plenitude, sc., thatwhateveris possible must exist in reat some
time, and that whatever is always is necessary.
X
However, mightnot Avicenna hold a weak principle of plenitude,
that whateveris possible must exist in intellectu?
I find his discussion
obscure
and
difficult.
Before
to
share
quite
proceeding
my perplexities
with you, let me merelylist the salient points. To be sure, Avicenna
.61He also
clearlyrecognizestwo sortsof existence: in reand in intellectu
holds that some individuals at a given time may exist in intellectu
without existing in re. Further, he says, there are individuals that have
never existedin re- but whetherall these exist in intellectu
is problematic. If Avicenna does hold thattheyall exist in intellectu
, then he holds
thisweak principleof plenitude; ifhe does not, then he does not hold
it.
Avicenna does claim that universal propositions may state
predicates of individuals that have never existed in re. Thus he says
that the categorical proposition, 'every B is A' deals with everything
"that is described in view of the intellector existence as being B."62
Apart fromany metaphysicalutility,thisdoctrinehas uses in accounting for the truth of mathematical propositions. So, e.g., 'every
59Al-Najt
15,2.
60Likewiseat Al-Isharat
Avicennagivesa commonconception
of
331,4-332,3,
tiedtothetimeoftheexistence
ofthesubject,
andthenrejects
itat 332,4-5.
modality
61Al-Madkhal
15,2-3( = Lop.2rcol. 2).
62Al-Najt
24,12-3;Al-Ishrt
326, 1-2.
233

09:02:05 AM

chiliagon has more than 100 sides' refersto individual chiliagons but
not to those that exist in re, but to those insofaras the intellectcredits
them with actually existing,whetheror not theyexist or do not exist
[in re].63In this way Avicenna explains how mathematicsdeals with
individuals.
So we may postulate individuals that never exist in re. For
Avicenna, such a supposition of individuals sufficesforthe truthof a
statementof possibility.He says that it is possible that every animal
is man since it would have been possible to imagine a time in which
there is no animal but man.64 We may establish the possibilityby a
mental process. To verifya contingentproposition,thinkof the quiddities of subject and predicate, and note that theyare consistentwith,
but not inseparable from,each other. We may then suppose that at
some time a certainrelationholds betweenthem.65Then we may have
some sortof mental experience of that state of affairs,in imagination
or perhaps in pure thought. Thus, e.g., 'every chiliagon has more
than 100 sides' mightcome to hold of the appropriate individuals. It
is in thisfashionthatwe saw in IX Avicenna establishingthe univer
salityof an expressionlike heptagonal house' even when it never has
any instances existing in re. Likewise, the second sense of the contingentdiscussed in VII bases the truthof a contingentproposition
in supposing a futurestate of affairs.
So a contingentproposition about some state of affairsthat at no
time exists in remay be verifiedthrougha mental process: individuals
of the appropriate attributesare supposed or imagined to exist. It
mightbe thoughtthat Avicenna holds that individuals recognized by
For the intellectdoes imagine or
mental supposition exist in intellectu.
suppose instances of them. To be sure, Avicenna is famous forhaving
a notion of the creative imagination whereby we may have mental
experiences of phantasms, built up out of simplerreal elements given
by sense experience. These phantasms themselvesmay never represent things that exist in re, but still they themselves, as mental
If so, then Avicenna is admitting a
experiences, exist in intellectu.
weaker principle of plenitude: all that is possible must exist in
- but not the strong principle that all that is possible must
intellectu
63Al-Qtys
21,6-12.
64Al-Qtys
form
intheir
usestheseexamples
30,10-1.NotethatAristotle
categorical
ofcertain
oftheinvalidity
at Prior
1.42,as wellas whengivinginstances
Analytics
themas useless.
butthendismisses
modicalsyllogisms,
65Al-Qys
30,2-3;31, 1-2.
234

09:02:05 AM

exist in re. This weaker principle has had many adherents, given the
common identificationof the possible and the conceivable.
Yet the hypothesisthat Avicenna holds that whatever the intellect
has some problems. First, what
supposes to exist exists in intellectu
about suppositionscontraryto fact,especiallythose used in reductions
and
to absurdity?Then logical contradictionswould exist in intellectu
so be possible and not impossible! Second, this approach seems to tie
logical possibilitytoo closelyto psychologicalfactsand aptitudes. The
intellectmay or may not suppose an individual withcertainattributes.
So which possibilitiesobtain seems to depend on what in particular
presentlyexistentintellectsare thinkingabout. Or is the possible what
it is possible for an intellect to suppose? This begs the question.
(Maybe the existenceof an infinitedivine intellectremoves thisobjection, but 'conceivable' in any case is not a good definitionfor 'possible', as it itselfcontainsa modal operator: '-able', and so obscures this
question.)
Third, Avicenna often seems to make existence in intellectu
derivativeupon sense perception: somethingdoes not exist in intellectu
thathas not existedin re. Sense perceptionis a passive process whereby
the formis abstractedfroma substance composed of formand matter
where
that exists in re. The abstractedformcomes to exist in intellectu
a
furtheraccidents, proper to being in intellectu
like
,
being species, are
attachedto it.66Still, once in the intellect,the abstractedconcept has,
as it were, a lifeofits own. Thus, 'Homer is a poet' is true, even when
Homer has died: being a poet is predicated of a phantasm of Homer
That phantasm was historicallyderived
presentlyexistingin intellectu.
fromsense perceptionsof the reallyexistingHomer and of real discussions about Homer. Moreover, the phantasm will be in an intellect
thatpresentlyexists in re. What exists in intellectu
, in this way at least,
on
in
re.
But
then
existence
what
the
intellectsupposes
past
depends
to exist now may not exist in intellectu
, in this realisticway, at least:
e.g., the supposition of a heptagonal house or a chiliagon, Avicenna
says, is not based on past perceptionsof such individuals existing in
re.But ifexistencein intellectu
requires such propositionsand hence the
existence in reof such individuals at some time, then individuals supposed or imagined by the intellectdo not exist in intellectu.
66Al-Madkhal
23,10;34,5;34,20;69,7( = Log.3r col. 2; 4v col. 1; 12v
( TheIsagoge)
- dealswithOnIntercol. 1. On 'Homeris a poet',seeAl-Burhn
(TheDemonstration
ed.
AffifT
et
Cairo
Also
see
Allan
on
al.,
1956,109,11-10,1.
Bck,Avicenna
pretation),
Existence
, pp. 359-60.
235

09:02:05 AM

I am uncertainjust how faritems may existin intellectu


forAvicenna
withouthaving had counterpartsor some basis for existing in re. He
does recognize intellectual intuition as well as sensible intuition.
: the
Indeed, he seems to admit two sources for existence in intellectu
representation of things existing in re, either by immediate sense
perception or by memory and imagination, or the cognition of
intelligibles that do not need to have any representationof things
existing in re.61Thus, we might suppose a heptagonal house or a
chiliagon to exist withouthaving an image or phantasm of its existing
in intellectu
,68We mightwant to say thatwhat existsin intellectu
depends
forits simple component parts on perceptionsof what exists in re, but
not for the very nature of its complex whole. However, Avicenna
seems to claim that we have knowledge of some quiddities and
simples, especially the mathematical, withoutsense perception.69So
not all the simple components of a complex existing in intellectu
need
have a correlate existing in re.
We may conclude that,at best, Avicenna admits only a weak princiThe problem
ple of plenitude: what is possible must exist in intellectu.
lies in two areas: mental supposition and intellectual intuition. Do
eitherof these sufficeto generate somethingexistingin intellectu
? I am
inclined to say so, but, as I shall discuss in XI, what inevitably
comes to exist in intellectu
is the mental act of supposing or imagining
or intuiting;what is the object or contentof that mental act need not
exist in intellectu.
However, I am still uncertain about just how much
creative synthesisAvicenna will allow- and about what may exist in
intellectu
without existing in re, or at least having some basis existing
in re. But stillin general Avicenna holds thatwhat is conceived exists
in intellectu.
Since Avicenna clearlyholds thatall possibilitiesare in the
divine intellectof the necessarybeing, thisresultwould not be too surprising anyway. (But then, as we shall see in XIV, therearises that
problem of how necessary being does not change if it contains all
possibilities but actualizes only some of them.)
XI
In any case, regardless of how much might exist in intellectu
,
Avicenna clearly says that from the logical point of view existence,
67Al-Madkhal
23,13-5[ = Loe. 3r col. 21.
68Descartesseemsto havesimilar
viewsinMeditations
6.
69De Anima
V. 1-2,22vcol. 2.
236

09:02:05 AM

nor in re,is considered. Rather, only the relationof


neitherin intellectu
and
subject
predicateis considered.70That is, logic deals withthe relation of concepts whose definitionsare determined by quiddities in
themselves.71Now modalityis such a logical relation. Indeed, we have
seen in III thatAvicenna definesthe modalities in termsof the relation of the predicate to the subject, not in termsof the relationof one
existingthing to another. To be sure, most of our concepts used as
subjectsand predicatesreferto existents.But not all need to referthus.
So, fromthe logical point of view, only the definitionsof the subject
and predicate are considered: if they are compatible, they are not
impossible, and hence either necessary or contingent.For Avicenna,
a considerationof items solely withrespectto theirdefinitionsfallson
the level of quiddities or essence in themselves.72Here whetheror not
thesequiddities exist, or what accidents theymighthave, is a separate
issue.73
So modalityis determinedon the level of quiddities in themselves.
This doctrine dovetails with Avicenna's basic definition of the
modalities, in termsof what followsfromsupposing a certain state of
affairsto be the case.74 Here Avicenna may be seen to be making a
sharp distinction of existence and essence: modality concerns the
essences of things; the modality is determinedby the relation of two
concepts solely in regard to their definition.75
This distinctionbetween essence and existence has some problems.
First,even thoughAvicenna says thatmodalities are determinedwith
respect to the quiddities in themselves, he also says that logic deals
with quiddities existing in intellectu.
Indeed, all propositions, strictly
speaking, should be viewed on that level. So, Avicenna seems to say,
even when we say that S does not exist, we have a concept of S, and
70Al-Madkhal
etde
de l'essence
22,7-12{-Log. 3r col. 1); Goichon,La distinction
IbnSn, Paris1957,p. 157.
l'existence
d'aprs
71Al-Madkhal
23,10;34,5( = Log.3rcol. 2; 4v col. 1).
12Al-Madkhal
discussion
22,4-5;22,15( = Log.3rcol. 1); Al-Qtys
30,3. ora fuller
see AllanBck,Avicenna
in
: TheIslamicBackground
andAverroes
, in: Individuation
Scholasticism
, ed.J. Gracia[forthcoming].
73Al-Madkhal
21,9-10("Log. 3r col. 1).
74Al-Ishrt
327,6-8.
75Especially
inthefirst
inthesecondsenseofthecontingent;
sense,thereis existentialimport,
below(p. 240),thisis duetothepredication
relation
but,I shallsuggest
andnottothemodality.
In contrast,
ifweputasidethenecessary
beingfornow,what
existsis determined
externalcausal relations.See Al-llhiyyt
261,17-8
through
( = Met.91vcol. 1).
On thedistinction
ofessenceand existence,
seeAl-Ishrt
261,17-8;262,9.
237

09:02:05 AM

.76 So, Avicenna seems to say, modalities are


that exists in intellectu
determinedon the level of quiddities in themselves,but modal propositions belong to the level of quiddities existingin intellectu.
But how
can he make both of these claims?
Second, the issue of how much Avicenna holds to exist in intellectu
reappears. As we have seen in X, it is not clear how much Avicenna
will allow to exist in intellectu.
Now, if a concept of S exists in intellectu
even when it is true that S does not exist, he seems to allow that
anything,includingimpossibleobjects and conditionscontraryto fact,
exists in intellectu.
Then how can he establish the possibilityof a state
of affairsthroughan act of mental supposition?For ifeverythingexists
in intellectu
and that suffices to establish possibility, then nothing
should be impossible- but Avicenna claims that there are
impossibilities.
Both of these problems can be solved by making a distinctionconThe sense ( ma'nan) of a proposicerningquiddities existingin intellectu.
but
the
tion existsin intellectu
,
quiddities being conceived need not. So,
the
'some
animal
has fourfeet' exists in intellectu
, but
e.g.,
proposition
'
'animal' and four-footed'referto quiddities existingin re' the animal
is not in the mind; the thoughtabout the animal is in the mind. Like,
wise, the modal proposition,qua modal proposition,exists in intellectu
but not all of its constituentsand aspects need be based upon quidTo put thepoint in anotherway, a conceptor a propdities in intellectu.
osition can be considered in two ways: as being a mental act and in
termsof its contentor its object: what the concept is about. In the first
in the second it generallydoes not exist in
way, it exists in intellectu'
unless
it
is
about
intellectu
,
something that exists in intellectui.e.,
unless it is a second intention,and not a primaryone. (Note that in
a way whateverexists in intellectu
will be based on somethingexisting
in re: it is an actual intellector mind existingin rethatmakes it possible
forconceptsto exist in intellectu;
theremustbe a real conceiverforthere
to be concepts.)
So then,modal propositionsmay exist in intellectu
, even thoughtheir
modal characteristicsmay be determinedon the level of quiddities in
themselves. For us to thinkand talk about quiddities in themselves,
we must be on the level of quiddities existing in intellectu.Still,
although quiddities in themselvesmay be manifestedor represented
76Ilhiyyt
15,4-16
32,12-6;33,12-3;34,1-2;34,7-8 Met.72v col. 1-2);Al-Madkhal
( = Log.2rcol. 2).
238

09:02:05 AM

on thatlevel, it does not followthat theyexist in intellectu'


ratheronly
their concepts or propositionsabout them do.
Likewise, this distinctionoffersa partial guide to what exists in
We may talk about impossible objects, and our talk about
intellectu.
them exists in intellectu.
But it does not follow that impossible objects
have an existence in intellectu.
Hence Avicenna says that the concept
of S, in 'S does not exist', exists in intellectu.
But it does not follow
therebythat this S exists in intellectu.
Nevertheless, this distinctionprovides only a partial guide, as it
does not determinejust when somethingexists in intellectu
: e.g., the
individual chiliagons or heptagonal houses or simple properties(like
being and unity)apprehended by intellectualintuition.The problems
raised in X persist. Still, this distinctiongoes a long way towards
Even though all logical items,
clearing up what exists in intellectu.
and
and
relationsof predication,exist
includingconcepts
propositions
in intellectu
, it does not followthat theirentire contentand all of their
featuresdeal withwhat exists in intellectu.
Indeed, in II, we saw that
Avicenna distinguishesthe matterfromthe mode of the proposition.
The latteris determinedby what the proposition states, on the level
of what existsin intellectu
; the formerby the relationsof the quiddities
in themselvesreferredto in the proposition. E.g., 'it is possible that
a man is an animal' has a possible and necessary matter. The
necessary matteris determined by the relation of two quiddities in
themselves, humanity and animality. If we consider a simple,
categorical predication, e.g., 'animal of man', and ask what its
modalityis, we are asking forthe matterof its mode, and thatis determined on the level of the quiddities in themselves. On this level,
existence in time is not considered. Thus, modality is not based on
existence, but on essence, the definitionsof the concepts.77Thus,
Avicenna's modalities do not deal with what exists in time, be the
existence in re or in intellectu.
XII
This conclusion appears to conflict with Avicenna's claim that
modalities have temporal consequences; e.g., if necessary, then
always. For, if modality is determined on the level of quiddities in
77Al-shrt
ofthenecessary
332,4-5.Again,withthepossible
exception
beingwhich
I shalldiscussbelow.
239

09:02:05 AM

themselves,and existence has nothingto do with quiddities in themselves, modalitiesare determinedwithoutregard to existence. Indeed,
as we have seen in XI, Avicenna says this explicitly.But then, as
time is linked to existence, how can Avicenna also allow modalities to
have temporal consequences?
Avicenna does not seem to address thisquestion explicitly,but does
provide materials for an answer. I here offera reconstruction.
Avicenna holds that a proposition asserts existential import.78In
'
general, a proposition having the form, S is P', is to be read: 'S is
existentasaP'. (As we shall see in this section, propositionsdefiling
with quiddities in themselvesare exceptions.) The existence may be
in re or in intellectu
, although in usual contextsit is both.
in
a
modal
Thus,
propositionwe have a combination of a modality
with a proposition asserting existence. Different positions of the
modality yield differentresults. For Avicenna the external modality,
as in his second typeof contingency,appears to be the usual one; here
the formis 4it is possible thatS is P, i.e. 'S is existentas a Pr is neither
necessary nor impossible. On the other hand, internal contingency
would assert: 'S is possibly P'; i.e., 'S is existentand to suppose that
S is P is neithernecessarynor impossible'. Hence his firsttypeof contingencyrequires existentialimport.
My proposal then is that forAvicenna modalityby itselfmakes no
assertion of existence; the primitive notion of necessity is one of
inseparable concomitance.79Quiddities in themselves may be combined in various ways; e.g., rationalityand animality are combined
in the quiddity, humanity,and that combination is necessary.80Likewise, the combination of whiteness and horseness is contingent,and
the combination of humanity and stoneness is impossible. With the
one exception of the necessary being, where the quiddities and being
or existenceare inseparable concomitants,such combinationsof quiddities have their modal status completelyapart fromwhetheror not
they ever exist.
But when we formulatemodal propositions,assertionsof existence
are connected to the modalities.81So, as above, 'it is possible that a
78See AllanBck,Avicenna
onExistence.
79Al-lshrt
327,6-8.
80Al-llhiyyt
28,13-29,6
236,6-8;241,5-16
( = Met.90rcol.1; 90vcol.2)' Al-Madkhal
( = Log. 3v col. 2).
81Al-Ishrat
andmodality
thatclaimsofpredication
336,7ff.asserts
mayeachbe true
theother.AlsoAl-Najt
without
38,Iff.
240

09:02:05 AM

horse is white' claims that the existence of a horse as white is neither


necessary nor impossible; likewise the proposition that a man is
rational is necessary. The existential import is not carried by the
modality,however. It is carried by the propositionalcontext: in particular,the presence of the copula togetherwith the use of a concrete
term. For quiddities in themselvesare signifiedby abstractterms,like
'humanity' and whiteness', whereas quiddities in the mind (in
intellectu
) and quiddities in individuals (in re) are signifiedby concrete
terms, e.g., 'man' and a man' or 'men, respectively. I say that
existentialimportrequires both the copula and a concretetermas subject in order to avoid having to have an existentialimport condition
for propositions about quiddities in themselves, e.g., 4humanity is
rationality'.For Avicenna holds that quiddities in themselvesdo not
exist although theyhave ' 'being" (kuwn) and "subsist". The modal
characterof a propositionis determinedon the level of quiddities in
themselves,even though,when concretetermsare used in theproposi.
tion, as usual, the termreferto quiddities existingin reor in intellectu
The relationsbetween the definitionsof the quiddities in themselves
decide whetherthe proposition is necessary or contingentor impossible in existence.Still, existenceis not a featureof quiddities in themselves, but of themas theycome into existence,generallyvia an external cause.
Here then is a way for modalities not to be tied to existence,
although still to have temporal consequences.
XIII
So the modalitiesare not concernedwithexistencein time. Still they
have temporal consequences. Once the definitionsof quiddities and
their interrelationsare considered, it is a furtherquestion what
actually exists. Here Avicenna distinguishesnecessary and possibile
being; literally,"what is necessary in existence", and "what is contingentin existence".82The veryphrases are suggestive: 'in existence'
is somethingelse added onto the essential level of what the necessary
and the contingent things are in themselves.83The necessary in
existence is what assuredly exists.84It is the basic modality and is a
82'In existence':
an accusative
ofrespect.
83Ilhiyyat
31,10-1;37.6-7;46.8-9(=Met. 72vcol. 1; 73rcol. 1; 74rcol. 1).
84Al-llhiyyt
36,5{ = Met.73rcol. 1).
241

09:02:05 AM

primitivenotion.85What is primitiveis not the notion of necessary


existence, but the notion of inseparable concomitance.86 What is
impossible in experience is what has its non-existenceassured. What
is contingentin existence is what does not assuredly exist nor notexist. Avicenna criticizesothers fordefiningmodalitycarelessly,and
refersto the discussion in Al-Qiys.81
Thus Avicenna has an asymmetrybetween necessary and possible
being. Necessary being settlesthe question of existing{in re) by itself:
given that there is a quiddity of a certain sort, it must exist. In contrast,possible being does not settlethe question of existence foritself:
given such a quiddity,it is leftindeterminatewhetheror not it exists.88
What is a possible being may exist and may not exist. Still, each
thing that may possibly exist has the question of existence settledfor
it: it either exists or does not exist {in re at a certain time). Now,
Avicenna assumes, for every fact there must be a sufficientcause. A
possible being itselfcannot be a sufficientcause forits own existence,
nor forits non-existence,as it does not settlethe question of existence
or non-existenceby itself.So somethingelse must settlethatquestion.
That somethingis an externalcause forthe existenceor non-existence
of a possible being.89 That external cause is either another possible
(i.e., contingent) being or a necessary being. If it were a possible
being, that stillcould not provide a sufficientcause, because its own
existence is not determinedby itself.So to suppose that the sufficient
cause of the existenceof a possible being is a possible being bringson
an infiniteregress.90Hence the ultimate,sufficient,
primary,external
cause must be a necessarybeing. Avicenna goes on to show thatthere
cannot be more than a single necessary being.91Hence the sufficient
cause of all possible beings is the necessary being, the firstcause of
everything.
However, Avicenna denies that the necessarybeing is the cause of
itself.92It might be thought that it should be, as somethingcannot
come from nothing, and the necessary being is surely something!
85Ilahiyyat
36,4-6( = Met.73rcol. 1).
86llahiyyt
In AnPr.26,20-4.
36,3(=Met. 73rcol. 1); cf.Alexander,
87Ilhiyyt
35,4-5( = Met.72vcol. 2).
88Ilhiyyt
39,8-9(= Met.73rcol. 2).
38,17-39,4;
89Ilhiyyt
1; 262,12-4( = 73rcol.2; 91rcol.2;91vcol.2).
; 260,9-1
38,11-6;257,10-1
90Ilhiyyt
39,11-6;262,1-5(= Met.73rcol. 2); 91vcol. 2).
91Ilhiyyt
37,11-2;43,4(=Met. 73rcol. 1; 73vcol. 1).
92Al-Ilhiyyt
37,5-9{ = Met.73rcol. 1).
242

09:02:05 AM

Indeed, as the essence of the necessarybeing requires thatit exist, and


Avicenna identifiesthe formalcause with the quiddity in itself,why
should not the necessarybeing be at least the formalcause of itself?93
His position is ratherclever. In his discussion of cause it becomes
clear that forAvicenna 'being caused' applies only to what comes to
be, and so only to thatwhichhas some sortof shiftfromnon-existence
. Now the necessarybeing does not
to existence,and perhaps viceversa
fallinto that class and so does not have a cause. To be sure, ilex nihilo
nihilfit", but the necessary being is not described by 'fil
So Avicenna may be taken to prove the existence of a necessary
, from his assumption that
being in several ways.94 First, a posteriori
contingentbeings exist. He justifiesthisassumption in two ways: first,
he claims that we have in fact a primitive intellectual intuition of
existence or being; second, we know via sense perception that contingentbeings do reallyexist. So it is a factthatbeing or beings exist,
and so we must proceed to seek sufficientcauses for them. These
proofsboth have as a common premise an assertionof a factabout our
experience. Second, perhaps, a priori: consider the quiddity in itself:
being, i.e., what is.95 Avicenna says that we have a primitivenonsensibleintuitionof being. Being seems to be a quiddity, as it is a constituentof other quiddities. At any rate, Avicenna says that being is
a concept but is not a genus, and that it has accidents particularizing
it.96If being is a quiddity, then being is what it is by definition,and
so by necessity.Now consider 'being is (being)'. It is trueby necessity,
and so being is necessarily. Hence being exists necessarily.
I am a bit dubious about the second, a prioriapproach, although it
is commonly attributedto Avicenna. It is clear that he holds the
necessary being to have a quiddity in itself.97After all, it is the
93Al-Ilhiyyt
257,7-89 (= Met.91rcol. 1).
94Whatfollows
is a summary
reconstruction
ofhisvariousdiscussions,
cf.Goichon,
La Distinction
, p. 355-6.
95Goichon,
La Distinction
, p. 332.
96Al-Ilhiyyt
34,15-35,2;261,10-3( = Met.72vcol. 2; 91v col. 1). At Al-Maqlat
ofsubstance.
100,10he saysthatGod is notin thecategory
97Goichon,
La Distinction
, pp. 343-53;Gilson,History
, p. 216.
ofChristian
Philosophy
Thatthequiddity
ofthenecessary
beinghasneither
genusnotspeciesis noobjection;
Avicenna
23rcol. 2, thatmanyintelligible
substances
haveneither
says,De Anima
speciesnorgenera.
Thewholeissueofthequiddity
ofthenecessary
muchmoreextenbeingrequires
sivetreatment
thanI givehere.Although
I favortheviewthatAvicenna
holdsthe
sucha viewwouldrequire
muchqualification
and
necessary
beingtohavea quiddity,
To be sure,at II. 347,17( = Met. 99rcol. 2), Avicennasaysthatthefirst
exegesis.
243

09:02:05 AM

unmoved mover, and in theAristoteliantraditionthe unmoved mover


is the pre-eminentcase of substance.98What is dubious consists in
whether it is appropriate to call the quiddity of the necessary being
'
being' in the sense of existence. The a prioriproof seems to demand
that in order to be valid; otherwise, to say that being is would not
require that it exist in re. But Avicenna generallyseparates existence
fromessence. Further, his calling being a concept suggests that it is
not a quiddity in itselfbut a quiddity in the mind. So, on the one
hand, it would appear thatthe necessarybeing has a quiddityin itself,
but that quiddity is not strictly"being" in the sense of existence in
re." But thenhow is thea prioriproofsupposed to work?The textsthat
purportedlypresentit are none too clear anyway. On the otherhand,
the connection of being and existence is well fixed in the Aristotelian
traditionin the discussion of being qua being. So perhaps Avicenna
has this proof, and is caught in the vagaries of that tradition.Yet, I
shall not insist upon it, nor stress the a prioriproof.
It does not sufficefor the existence of the necessary being that it
exist in intellectu
alone, For, fromthe a posteriori
perspective,we have
to explain the existence,both in reand in intellectu
of contingentbeings.
he alsosays,349,12,thatthe
However,
beingdoesnothavea genusor a-quiddity.
His position,
necessary
beingis itsessence,and so has one,presumably.
strictly
to
connected
stated,seemstobe that"thenecessary
beingdoesnothavea quiddity
it otherthannecessary
holdsthatthenecessary
existence",
350,11-2.So Avicenna
in a certain
unusualrespect,
without
and
beinghasa quiddity
genusanddifferentia
without
hedeniesthatithasquiddity
composition;
onlyincertain
respects.
E.g., at
344,11-2he saysthatthenecessary
beinghasno quiddity
properto itas necessary
withthenecessary
a quiddity
undersomeother
being.Thisisconsistent
beinghaving
to a quiddity
viewedwithrespect
to itslogical
description:
'necessary
being'refers
inintellectu
and notinre.Again,344,10;345,6;346,1-2;346,7-12;347,7properties
ofthenecessary
10,Avicenna
saysthatthequiddity
beinghasnoquiddity
apartfrom
its"receptacles".
I offer
saidtohave
onlytwofurther
points:1) in theKalm,Godwascommonly
essentialattributes:
'living'and 'knowing'werestandard
examples.Cf. Richard
andTheir
Attributes
offers
Frank,Beings
, Albany1978,pp. 11; 151. NotethatAvicenna
'God is living'as hisstandard
exampleofthefirst
typeofnecessity.
2) Although
scholars
ofLatinmedieval
haveoften
concluded
thatforAvicenna
God
philosophy
hasno quiddity,
thisconclusion
hasbeenstrongly
on textual
challenged
grounds
by
E.M. Macierowski,
DoesGodHavea Quiddity
toAvicenna
?, in: The Thomist,
According
52 (1988),pp. 79-80;84.
98Al-Ilhiyyt
31,15;34,16-7( = Met.72vcol. 2).
99At Al-Ilhiyyt
twosortsof
, 346,5 ( = Met. 99r col. 1) Avicennadistinguishes
existence:
via thematter.
the
1) simple,via theessence2) composite,
Apparently
in thefirst
senseonly;contingent
necessary
beinghasexistence
beingsinthesecond
sense(?).
244

09:02:05 AM

for Avicenna either depends on what


Since what exists in intellectu
exists in reor at any rate does not sufficeto make somethingexist in
re,the necessarybeing must exist in reas well in order to be a sufficient
cause.100Again, on a priorigrounds, we need only consider the quiddity, the necessary real being, i.e., what exists necessarilyin re.
One may well wonder whether such quiddities in themselves as
being are legitimate or even well-formed. I have been offeringa
reconstructionof his argumentsand discussions on the existenceof the
being that exists necessarily. From a modern perspective, Avicenna
appears insensitiveto certain issues. He plunges into a discussion of
necessaryand possible being withoutanalyzing the phrases, showing
and determiningtheirontological
theirconsistencyand intelligibility,
status and reference.Yet his doctrinesdo offermaterials with which
to constructa more sophisticatedposition. He does not say that there
is a thingor real essence, to wit, necessary being.101Rather, he says
that there is a real essence or quiddity that turns out to exist
necessarily. For he holds that modality is not a featureof quiddities
in themselves,although it is determined on their level, but only of
them insofaras they are conceived in the mind. So strictlyspeaking
quiddities in themselvesare neithernecessary,contingent,nor impossible.102Rather they are judged modally when they come to be conceived in the mind, and such judgements depend only on what the
quiddities are in themselves.Thus the necessarybeing need not have
the essence, or quiddity in itself,of necessary being, although it may
turnout to exist necessarily. Its true essence may be hidden. Still, as
discussed above, Avicenna generallyuses 'being' or 'necessary being'
to describe that quiddity in itself.
So, to recapitulate,Avicenna comes to talk of necessary being and
possible being thus: thereare various quiddities in themselves.Some
of these are such thattheirdefinitionsdo not require nor rule out their
existence(in re). Hence theyare possible beings. Now, there must be
a sufficient
reason determiningwhethertheyexist or do not exist. And
the
thereupon
proof proceeds, and we arrive at a quiddity that has
existencenecessarily.We may choose to bringin a posteriori
factsabout
the existenceof contingentthings.We mightalso startaprioriwiththe
100llhiyyt
bothinreand
31,12-5( = Met. 72vcol. 1): simpleexistence
comprehends
inintellectu
existence.
101Goichon,
La Distinction
, p. 174.
102Al-Madkhal
196,6-15( = Met. 86vcol. 1).
15,5-6( = Log.2r col. 2); Al-Ilahiyyat
245

09:02:05 AM

quiddityin itself,being, ifwe wish to allow it, whichhas being by definition.


The proof leads to the assertion that something that is a unique
necessarybeing exists. This something,thisbeing is such that its very
essence, its quiddity in itself,requires existence in re.103Strictly,its
quiddity is not unique, necessary, or in existence. Rather these are
featuresexternal to a quiddity in itselfbut inseparable fromthis one.
Avicenna does not say much about that quiddity- it could have no
definition:how could a simple be defined: perhaps here we may have
an apprehension or an intellectual intuition of it only via mystic
insight(recall Avicenna' s attractionto Sufism), or perhaps we may
know it only throughits effects.104
We mightjust give this necessary
a
'God'
or
'Allah'.
God
necessarilyexists in re: recall that
being label,
Avicenna' s firstcase of the necessaryconcernsthingswhichare always
what they are and whose quiddity always exists. His set example is:
God is living. So the divine essence is always in existence.
XIV
This picture of Avicenna' s modal views that I have extractedfrom
his logical works may seem not to agree with a common view, that
Avicenna is a determinist. So Copleston writes: "In other words,
Avicenna' s universe is one of necessaryconnection. It is deterministic
throughand through. There is no room forhuman freedom,except,
of course, in the sense that a man's actions proceed fromhimself."105
Again, Gilson writes: "What of contingencythere is in the world of
Avicenna is due not to the First Cause, but to the matter", in particular the perishable matter of the sublunary world.106At any rate,
I shall suggest that such claims must be qualified.
We have seen thatthe modalities are based on the level of quiddities
in themselves, although they are not located there. Because on that
level many consistent combinations of quiddities, considered with
respectto theirdefinitions,are not determinedto existnor not to exist,
Avicenna has here a fundamental,radical contingencybased on the
103Ilhiyyt
46,6-9;261,10-1(-Met. 74rcol. 1; 91vcol. 1).
104Goichon,
s attitude
towards
La Distinction
, p. 338.On Avicenna
mystical
insight,
etlercit
visionnaire
seeHenriCorbin,Avicenne
, Tehran1954,vol.2, 4, 15-6;5,6( = p.
(5))105Copleston,
A History
, p. 114.
Philosophy
ofMedieval
106Gilson,History
intheMiddle
, pp. 214-5.
Ages
Philosophy
ofChristian
246

09:02:05 AM

very essence of the quiddities. Just as God acquires the basis for
necessary being and existence in re on that level, so white swans and
blue swans gain the basis for contingentbeing on that level. This
radical contingencyis not erased by always existing or by being
necessitatedby some external cause.107
Avicenna then is no logical deterministithe modal characterof the
quiddities do not require that whateverexists exists by necessity.Yet
he may stillbe a causal determinisi. Since, he argues, there must be
a cause sufficient
to determinewhetheror not contingentbeings exist,
that cause, the FirstCause or necessarybeing, will dictate which contingenciescome to exist in re. But, as he often says, such a cause is
external to those essences or quiddities that are contingent.So then,
it may be said, Avicenna recognizesno contingenciesin the world, but
not because thereare no contingenciesbut ratherbecause an external
cause has determinedwhich contingenciescome to pass in the world;
i.e., God determineswhat the world is.108
A problen thenarises: just how much can Avicenna separate logical
and causal factors?The problem lies in the nature of the necessary
being. That being is what it is necessarily. However, we have seen
some problems concerningwhetherit is strictly,a quiddity in itself.
For on the level of quiddities in themselves, what something is is
generallygiven by the constituentquiddities, that compose its definition. But the necessary being has no definitionand is utterlysimple.
To be sure, it is what it is- but it is not definedas the necessarybeing,
although it turnsout to be necessarily. Perhaps here looms a mystery
that can be penetratedonly by mystical, intuitiveinsight: Avicenna
did turn to Sufism. Yet, be that as it may, we seem to know, a
, that the necessary being, throughbeing what it is, causes
posteriori
some contingenciesto come to be, and causes others to fail to come
to be. Then there would appear to be a necessary reason why some
contingencies obtain, given that every operation of the necessary
being itselfis necessary. But a necessary reason cannot be otherwise,
and so it does not appear to be a non-necessarycontingentfact that
some contingencies come to pass and others do not. Therefore,
because of the necessarycharacterof the First Cause, therecan be no
logical contingencyeither.That is, if the divine essence is simple and
107llahiyyat
oneintheKalm.
47,11-4( = Met.74vcol. 1). Thisviewwasa common
See RichardFrank,Beings
andTheir
Attributes,
76-7;125.
pp.
108Goichon,La Distinction
, p. 160.
247

09:02:05 AM

has causal powers, and ifit is what is necessarily,God's causal nature


seems to be identical to the divine essence. But then there is always
a logical necessityfora causal act. So how can there then be logical
contingencyat all?
I forego furtherdiscussion of this issue here. To pursue it would
require a full-scaletreatmentofAvicenna's account ofCreation, of the
emanation of the intelligences and the sublunary world from the
necessary being. Still let me remark that Muslims are not adverse to
fatalismanyway. Further,note thatwe have here a common situation
in theology: on the one hand, the divine intellectcontains ideas, sc.,
the quiddities, and these appear to be what they are, in themselves,
apart fromwhat the necessary being is.109Thus radical contingency
arises, and the necessary being must make a choice as to which contingenciesshould and will obtain. On the otherhand, ifthe necessary
being must be completelyself-generated,it must generate in itselfthe
contentof the divine intellect.But thenit is the cause ofwhat the quiddities are in themselves, as well as the cause of which ones exists.
Here, as a single, necessary cause is operating, it looks as if that it
builds into the quiddities in themselves their existence or nonexistence in re. Or, even if it does not do that, the necessary being,
assuming thatall of its attributesare necessary,cannot actualize those
contingencies,if it selects by necessity. Hence what is not actualized
looks impossible. (Leibniz has similar problems110!)But then radical
contingencyis destroyed, and the necessary being has no choice to
make.
This same problem can be raised if we ask how God can thinkof
the quiddities. Are the quiddities in themselvesin the divine mind, or
?m
are they there not in themselvesbut only as concepts, in intellectu
In what sense can possible beings 4'exist" in a fully actual divine
intellect?In effect,thisis the quandary: ifthe former,thenthey"are"
independent of God, although they do not "exist" independentlyof
God; if the latter, then the same cause, God, makes the quiddities
what theyare, and singles some of themout forexistence.112But then
109Ilhivvt
260,2-3( = Met.91v col. 1).
110Leibniz,Discourse
onMetaphysics.
14; 28; 35; Monadology
43; 46-7.
1,1Cf.llhiyyt
stillitsomehow
IX.7. Evenifthenecessary
beingthinks
onlyofitself,
in it. However
as somehow
boundup orcontained
thinks
ofall quiddities,
virtually
to
it,thenecessary
beinghasto havesomekindofrelation
youmayliketo express
overthem.
contingent
beings,in orderto havecausalinfluence
112Cf. Ilhiyyt!
IX.3-5.
Metaphysica
248

09:02:05 AM

why say thatessence is internalto quiddities, while existence is external? For the same causal process effectsboth. But then thereis no real
contingency.
So we have a problem of theodicy: can God have freewill and can
there be contingency and freedom for creatures while God is a
necessary,omnipotentbeing? I beg offfromthis question here. What
I hope to have established is that Avicenna does admit contingency
and deny the principle of plenitude froma logical perspective. If he
holds thatopposite froma causal perspective,as he seems to, then we
have to see how he can reconcilethesetwo results,in lightof the divine
simplicity.
XV
Seen in light of his modal theory,Avicenna' s views on necessary
being resemblelater medieval views markedly.This comes as no surprise forlater medievais like Albert the Great, Aquinas, and Scotus
who were directlyinfluencedby his work. Yet it is remarkable how
much his views resemblethose of later philosopherslike Descartes and
Leibniz, although the historical connections have not been fully
investigated.
APPENDIX
Below I give a literal translationof some key texts of Ibn Sln on
modality that are not available in translation. I do not intend this
translationto solve any of the difficulties
or obscuritiesof the original
text. (Goichon has translatedAl-Ishart,and there are translationsof
in French by Anawati and in Latin in the Venice Opera
Al-Ilhiyyt
Omniaand in the criticaledition in Louvain ed. by Van Riet, and so
I omit those passages.)
AMMONIUS
"... [Aristotle]
is twofold:
in oneway,saidsimply
and
saysthatthenecessary
whatbelongs
strictly,
namely,
alwaystothesubjectwhichis notabletosubsist
it(indeed,either
without
since'always'is takeninindefinite
time,as foreternal
as whenwe saythatthesunmovesor thattheanglesofa triangle
are
things,
or as longas thesubjectis present,
as
equalto tworight
anglesbynecessity,
whenwe saythatthefireis hotor thatSocratesis an animalby necessity);
theotheris notlikethis,butwiththedetermination,
whereas
'as longas what
249

09:02:05 AM

is predicated
bytheonesayingthatitholdsthusis true',butno longer
simply,
be thesubjecteternal
or perishable:
forthatthesunis bynecessity
covered
by
thecloudsor themoon,as longas it is covered,
is true,butno longersimply,
and thatyousitor walkbynecessity
as longas oneofthesebelongsto youis
Forneither
do wewalkorsitalways,noras longas
true,butnolongersimply.
we partakeofbeing."In Aristotelis
De Interpretation
commentarius
, ed. A. Busse
(Berlin1895),153.13-26.
PHILOPONUS
in different
"Theysay:someobjectsholdsimilarly
always;others
waysat different
times.Andsomeofthoseholding
similarly
alwayshavesubsisted
perse,
liketheheavens;others
in others,
liketheblackin thecrow.Thus
peraccidens
indicatedwhatalwaysholds
mode,theysay, [Aristotle]
by the necessary
whatalwaysholdsthusperaccidens,
andbythe
; bythecategorical,
similarly
perse
whatholdsindifferent
times.Andtheytrytoshow
contingent
waysatdifferent
thesamething
morepersuasive
butitis not,as itdoesnot
division,
byanother,
havethenecessary:
forobjects,
theysay,areeither
alwaysorat sometime.And
ifat sometime,eithertheyhavehappened
or are goingto happen.Thenthe
modeindicates
thosethatarealways;thecategorical
thosethathave
necessary
whatis goingto happen,"John
happenedat some time;the contingent
In Aristotelis
PrioraCommentarius
, ed. M. Wallies(Berlin
Philoponus,
Analitica
1905),43,8-18.
For[Aristotle]
thatthenecessary
is saidintwoways,one
saysinOnInterpretation
and onebyhypothesis,
and byhypothesis
in twoways:in theformer,
strictly
itis saidto be necessary
so longas thesubjectis present;
in thelatter,
so long
as thepredicate
is present.E.g., thatthesun movesis said to be necessary
thatSocrates
is an animalis necessary
so longas thesubstrictly;
byhypothesis
is present,
itis necessary
thathe be an
For,so longas Socrates
jectis present.
animal,whichis evencloserto thestrictly
too;thethirdis as when
necessary
wesaythatitis necessary
fortheoneseatedtosit.For,so longas thepredicate,
I mean'sitting',
itbelongs
totheoneseatedinvirtue
ofthe
belongs,
necessarily
In An.Pr. , 126,8-17.
hypothetically
necessary."
AVICENNA
Al-Najt
matter
is thestatebelonging
tothepredicate
inrelation
tothesubject
Necessary
without
a doubtthatitbe permanently
at everytime;
bywhichitis necessary
be withthenecessary
at everytime,likethestateofanimal
i.e., thatthetruth
vis visman,anditdoesnotallowthedenial.Andimpossible
matter
isthestate
in relation
ofthepredicate
tothesubjectinwhichthetruth
is permanently
with
thedenial,likethestateofstonevis visman,anditdoesnotallowtheaffirmation.Andpossible
isthestatebelonging
matter
tothepredicate
inrelation
tothe
doesnotpersist,
in affirmation
or in denial,likethe
subjectbywhichitstruth
stateofwriting
vis visman.Anditis saidthatthepossible
is thatwhosejudgementis non-existent
at sometime;i.e., inthepresent,
andthenithasa judgefrom
itsmaking
a judgement
mentinthefuture
inthepresseparate
necessarily
ent.[14,20-15,4]
250

09:02:05 AM

ofdifference
thereis an intention
and theimpossible
Betweenthenecessary
often
uses
inevitable.
Ibn
Sina
in
the
of
the
coincidence
sense
their
[N.B.:
despite
I shalltryto translate
them
'inevitable'and 'necessary'interchangeably;
becomes unbearablybarbaric;
distinctly,
except when the translation
as wellas
'inevitable''darr',liketheGreek'dei', can statea necessity
statesonly a
'necessary''wjib', like 'anangk',generally
impossibility;
in existence,
in
and thelatteris inevitable
The former
is inevitable
necessity.]
it is permissible
forus to
non-existence.
Andwhenwe discusstheinevitable,
tobothofthem.So wesay:inevitable
applytheverysameexplanation
predicain permanence.
And
tionis according
to sixmodes,eachofwhichparticipates
doesnotnorwillnotceasetobe,[Thisexpresisthatthepredication
[1]thefirst
in thesepassagesas
sion,'doesnotnorwillnotceasetobe', occursfrequently
a setphrase;a freertranslation
is: 'in thepresent
and in thefuture'.]
as in
Allahisliving'.And[2]thesecondis that[thepredication]
is as long
'Almighty
is notdestroyed,
as in ourstatement:
as theessenceofthesubjectas existent
thatis a manis permanently
animal';i.e., everything
'everymanis inevitably
butnotpermanently
without
animalas longas itsessenceis existent,
qualification,so thathe be an animalanddoesnotceasenorwillnotcease[tobe one],
andthissecondone
Andthefirst
before
hisgeneration
norafter
hisdestruction.
ordenialis saidtobe inevitable,
wherean assertion
arebothusesandintentions
anda singlesenseis common
to thembothfromsomemode,and [thatsense]
isexistent,
beitpermanently,
isinevitability,
as longas theessence
ofthesubject
iftheessenceexistspermanently,
iftheessencemayperish.
orinsomeinterval,
The third[3] is that[thepredication]
is as longas theessenceofthesubjectis
characterized
withwhich[theessence]is madea subject,
bythecharacteristic
butnotas longas itisexistent.
whitething
hasa colorstandE.g.,wesay:every
doesnot
i.e., it is notthecasethatitpermanently
ingoutin sightinevitably;
ceaseor shallceaseto be, noralso [doesthepredication
hold]as longas the
essenceofthatwhitething
is an existent,
so that,whenthatessencepersists
and
doesnotperish,
andyetwhiteness
mayleave,then[theessence]maybe characterized
as beingtheessenceofa colorstanding
outin sightinevitable.
Butthis
notas longas it is existent,
butas longas itis characterized
necessity
persists
thefourth
is as longas the
Further,
bywhiteness.
[4] is thatthat[predication]
is existent,
anditdoesnothaveinevitability
without
thiscondition,
predication
as whenwesay:'Zaydinevitably
walksas longas hewalks',sinceitisnotpossible thathe notbe walkingand be walking.Further,
thefifth
[5] is thatthe
is at a definite
time,[and]thereis no doubtofit,as in 'themoon
inevitability
is eclipsedinevitably',
butit is notso permanently,
butit is so at thesame
definite
time.Andthesixthis thatitis [thus]inevitably
at sometime,butnot
at a definite
one,as whenwesay:'everymaninevitably
breathes';
i.e., at some
- and,as fortheselatter
norat thesametime
time,andit is notpermanently
fourdivisions,
whena condition
is notstipulated,
thepredication
in themis
calledcategorical,
is stipulated
in them,thefirst
and,ifa modeofinevitability
is thatthemodeis partof thepredicate
and nota modesubjoinedto the
and thatis sincethepredicate
is notpredicated
butrather
predicate,
byitself,
withan addition,
and thatadditiontogether
withthepredicate
is notthought
ofas a singlething,
noris therein ita modein thewaythatitis likea partof
it.Further,
intheinevitable
ifthepredicate
is independent
initself,
in
premise,
thatitspredication
is considered
andthem ode doesnotmakesomething
in it
butrather
in thecopula,thenthepredicate
is through
itsessencelikea single
to it. [20,1-21,13]
sense,and themodeis subjoined

251

09:02:05 AM

On Simple[Propositions]
theview(ofTheophrastus)
Aboutsimpleonestherearetwoopinions,
andthen
andothers;
andtheviewofAlexander
andmanyat present.
ofThemistius
The
are thosein whichthe modeof the
firstis thatthe [simplepropositions]
ofthejudgement
or thepossibility
is notmenofthejudgement
inevitability
thejudgement
butrather
is unrestricted
So itis possible
thatthe
tioned,
simply.
beexistent
andpossible
thatthejudgement
beexistent
not
inevitably,
judgement
Anditis notunlikely
thatthisis theviewof
i.e., notpermanently.
inevitably,
thephilosopher
aboutthe simple[propositions],
inasmuchas he
[Aristotle]
allowstwouniversal
affirmative
andnegative,
tobe true,
simple[propositions],
as whenyousay:everyhorseis asleep,and no horseis asleep,and thatthe
universal
affirmative
is translated
intotheuniversal
simple
judgement
negative
Thefollowers
thattobe possible
ofthisviewconsider
butnot
simple
judgement.
sincethephilosopher
aboutsimple[promayalsobringin examples
necessary,
rather
aboutwhichitis notpossible;
theyareinevitable
positions]
permanently.
ofthesecondview- Alexander
As forthefollowers
and manyat present
who
- theyconsider
himwhois theirleader
follow
thatthistranslation
is necessary
thesimpleis notinevitable
in itsjudgement
in thesimple,eventhough
except
besidesthetwoadjacentmodes.
tooneofthefourmodesmentioned,
according
So thebeingofthesimpleintheir
isthatinwhichthejudgement
isexisopinion
as longas theessenceofwhatis judged
tent,and is notrequired
permanently
is existent,
at sometime,andthattimeiseither:
as longas thesubject
butrather
as beingcharacterized
is characterized
bythat,as whenyousay,'everywhite
outinsight',or:as longas thepredicate
hasa colorstanding
is predicated
thing
or: at a definite,
inevitable
time,as eclipsebelongsto themoon,andbeingin
thewombbelongstoeveryman,or: at an inevitable
butan indefinite
time,as
toanimal.We do notfavor
either
ofthesetwoviewsoverthe
belongs
breathing
ofthesimplein thetwowaystogether,
consider
other,butrather
judgements
andthatwillappearto youwhenwe dividethesimplequantified
judgements.
Thesenseofoursaying
thateveryB isA simply
isthateverything
thatis characinviewoftheintellect
orexistence
terized
as beingB, whether
itbe characterized
orbe characterized
as B atsometimeafter
whichitis notBas B permanently
as beingA, andwedo notknowwhenitis A, when
thatthingis characterized
as beingB, or at another
it is characterized
or notpertime,orpermanently,
Thisis theopinionofTheophrastus.
thesecondviewdoes
Further,
manently.
thefirst
viewin respect
notdiffer
from
ofthesubject.So thereis nodoubtthat
thesenseofyoursaying'everymoving
thatischaracterized
thing'is:everything
andbyitsbeingimposed
onitthatitbepermanently
oratsome
bybeingmoving
time.So thesenseof'moved'on thetwoviewsis thesame,and thereis a difference
thematter
ofpersistence,
and thematter
is something
thatis
through
ofit.Butthetwodiffer
accidentad
tothesenseandnotconstitutive
abouttheside
ofthepredicate,
sincethefirst
understands
thejudgement
thepredicate
through
thanwhatitiscertainly
as morecommon
toconceive
without
possible
stipulation
or impermanence,
ofpermanence
and theyspecify
it through
thecondition
of
So accordingto themthe senseof 'everyB is A' is that
impermanence.
thatis characterized
as beingB, howeveris be characterized,
.
everything
- thatthingis characterized
or non-inevitably
as beingA, not
inevitably
butat sometime,according
towhathasbeensaid.Andsimilarly
the
inevitably
'no A is B' without
is thatno thing
senseofourstatement,
ischarqualification
itbe characterized,
acterized
as beingB, however
unlessA be deniedofit,be
it thatwe do notknowhowandwhenor be itthatwedeny[it]at sometime.
[23,4-25,5]
252

09:02:05 AM

Al-Qys
So itisnotatallunderstood
that
byoursaying'everywhite'thatitiseverything
is established
tobe white.Rathereverything
inactuality
as
thatis characterized
or definitely
or permanently
afterit
beingwhiteis at sometime,indefinitely
comestobe in actuality.
Andthisactuality
is nottheactuality
ofexistence
in individuals
[i.e., inre]
thesubjectmaynothavebeenconsidered
insofar
as itis exisonly.So perhaps
whathastwotenths
as whenyousay:everysphere
contains
tentinindividuals,
ofthebaseofa triangle
is notin accordance
withits
[?], andthecharacteristic
tothething
as itis existent,
butrather
invirtue
ofitsbeingthought
belonging
in actuality
as characterized
in accordancewiththe
by the characteristic
inactuality
intellect's
itas having
tobe such,whether
itsexistence
characterizing
itexistornotexist.So thesenseofyoursaying'everywhite'is everything
charin viewof theintellect
acterized
as makingitsexistence
in actuality
be white
always,or at sometime,i.e., at anytimetherebe. So thisis thesideofthe
subject.
As forthesideofthepredicate,
he [?wesay?]says:indeedtherearesimple
affirmative
statements
and necessary
onesand possibleones. Moreoverwe
desireto speakaboutthesimpleuniversal
affirmative
and to findoutthedifference
between
thesimple
andthenecessary.
So wesay:hereallourstatements
areaffirmative
andthestatesinthemaredifferent.
So wesay:[1]Allahisliving;
i.e., permanently
[and]He is notceasingnorshallnotceasetobe [so].Andwe
is a colorand everymanis living.Andwe meannot
say:[2] everywhiteness
thateverything
is a color,andis notceasingnorshallnotcease
thatiswhiteness
tobe one,orthateverymanis living,andis notceasingnorshallnotceaseto
be living.Rather,we say: indeedeverything
thatis characterized
as being
whiteness
and to whichthatit is whiteness
is said to belongis, as longas its
essenceis existent,
a color.Andsimilarly
everyone to which'man' is saidto
as
belong:notthatitis notceasingnorshallnotceasetobe animal,butrather
anditssubstance
areexistent.
Andwesay:[3] 'everymoving
longas itsessence
thatmovesis a bodyas
thingis a body',andwedo notmeanthateverything
longas itmovesonly,butalsoevenifitdoesnotmove.Stillwe meanthatit
is a bodyas longas itsessenceis existent.
Andthedifference
between
thisand
the[statement]
beforeit is thatthereitdoesnotdistinguish
thestatebetween
oursaying'as longas itsessenceis existent'
and oursaying'as longas [itis]
whereashere it distinguishes
the state betweenour saying
whiteness',
characterized
as moving
as longas itsessenceis existent'
andour
'everything
saying'as longas [itis] moving.Andwe say: 'everywhitethinghas a color
outinsight',
andwedo notmeanthateverything
towhich
wesaybeing
standing
white
as longas itsessenceis existent,
hasa colorstanding
outinsight,
belongs,
butrather
as longas itis characterized
as beingwhite.Andindeedtheessence
ofwhatischaracterized
as beingwhiteisnotnullified
whenitceasestobe white.
Avicenna
todiscussagaintheremaining
threesenses.]
[21,1-22,11;
proceeds
Ratherletus makea fresh
start.So we saythatwe mayuse theexpression
ofinevitability
anditis permanence
in situations.
tothatwesay[1]
According
thatAllahisliving
intherestofthis
likewise
bynecessity
'inevitability';
[strictly:
andHe doesnotceasenorshallnotceasetobe [livpassage];i.e., permanently,
notas intheabovecase
ing],andwesaythateverymanis animalbynecessity,
inthathedoesnotceasenorshallnotceasetobe [so],butas longas theessence
ofthething
towhichbeingmanis saidtobelongis existent;
i.e., as longas he
is characterized
as making
withita subject.Andwesay[3] thatevery
together
253

09:02:05 AM

notthatit [is so] permanently


bynecessity,
movingthingis corruptible
[and]
as
doesnotceasenorshallceaseto be [so],andnotthatitis [so]permanently
is existent,
butrather
as long
longas theessenceofwhatis saidtobe moving
ofitsessence
as itis moving.Andifitis, itmayhappenthatthepermanence
or [and?]itsbeingas saidofitis sucha one,justas wesaythatthe
as existent
as
oftheessenceofeverymanand itsdescription
oftheexistence
persistence
a body;
thingis bynecessity
beingmanis one.Andwe saythateverymoving
itmaybe, thenit
it is saidofitthatit is moving,
however
i.e., thatwhenever
frommotion
andifitis distinct
thenit
is [so]as longas itsessenceis existent,
as longas he is a
is a body.Andwesay[4] thatthewalkerwalksbynecessity
thathe is a walker
Andwesay
butwedo notsaybyitself
walker,
bynecessity.
tothemoonat suchandsucha timebynecessity.
[5] thatan eclipseis present
toitbynecessity
ofitthataneclipseis present
itis established
And,eventhough
of
as longas thereis an eclipse,itssenseis notthatsense.Forthecondition
whereas
is 'as longas an eclipseis existent',
in thesecondstatement
necessity
is thatthereis an occurrence
in thefirst
at
ofnecessity
statement
thecondition
these
thesun.Andeventhough
a timeinwhichthemoonis injunction
opposite
Andwe say:[6] everymanbreathes
twoareinseparable
by
theyaredifferent.
timebutat sometimethereis no
necessity'
[andthis]is nottrueat a definite
as long
doubtofit.Butthesenseofthisis notalsothathebreathes
bynecessity
it.Andallofthesearesimple
from
thatisinseparable
as heisbreathing
although
in themis thatinwhichthe
thenormalnecessity
divisions.
Moreover
universal
is saidordeniedas longas theessenceofwhatis saidtobe thesubject
predicate
inthis.
Andwhatis neither
is existent.
ceasingnorshallceasetobe is included
is as whenwe say
affirmative
theuniversal
Further,
possible[proposition]
thatis characthateverything
Anditssenseis [1] either
'everyB is A possibly'.
havethe
doesnotnecessarily
orimpermanently,
terized
as beingB, permanently
is notconofA, whena condition
existence
ofan A, northenon-existence
is notpaidtothefactthatit[A?]willnodoubtbe
sidered.And[here]attention
thatitnot
for[or:present
existent
to]it[B?]at sometime,orthatitis possible
Andthispossiitpermanently.
thatitaccompany
existatall,orthatitispossible
that
thanthesimplein thesecondmode.Or [2] everything
ble is moregeneral
ifatany
orimpermanently,
as beinginactuality
is characterized
B, permanently
forit,then,ifanyofthefuture
thattimeas existent
timeit determines
parthatatitthatjudgeas itispossible
insofar
ticularizes
it,thattimeisdetermined
tothebegininrelation
mentexistsandthatitdoesnotexist,butitisnotfuture
areparticular
subjects,
ningofa giventime[a "now"?],sothatthenthesubjects
time.And
as beingB at a definite
arewhatarecharacterized
and thesubjects
Andoursaying
ofthegiventimeinquestion.
is thefuture
inquestion
thefuture
as beingB at
thewholethatis characterized
'everyB' willnothaveincluded
thatwe havedetermined.
everytime.Butthatis a difference
ofthepossible.
todo withthissecondconception
Andthesimplehasnothing
ina given
So itis nota partunderiteventhough
theybothcanbe truetogether
withnecessity
but
notinaccordance
individuell.
So, whenZaydsits,heis sitting
in thesensegivenearlier,
sincethis
in thissense,butpossibly
alsonotpossibly
innon-existence
as
inexistence,
noris itpermanently
is notpermanently
sitting
inthis
Indeeditis notinpossibility
longas theessenceofthesubjectis existent.
to
butpaysnoattention
thefuture
inthissenserequires
sense,sincepossibility
attention
to
the
in
it
this
case
whereas
its
current
thepresent
pays
state],
[or:
and in
is possible,
in virtueoftheregardofthefuture
So thissitting
present.
ofthe
Andneither
virtueof theregardoftimeis simplesinceit is definite.
are
is includedin theotheror is saidofit,butthey[thoserespects]
respects
be possiblethatitsbeingdoesnotmakeit required
Andit might
inseparable.
254

09:02:05 AM

fortheotherrespect
ofpossibility
So sitting
is
toassigntoita timenecessarily.
notlikebreathing
orlikeelimination
bydeathat sometimeorliketheeclipse.
So forthethingitis possiblethatitnotsitat all,butitis notpossiblethatthe
moonnotoccludeat all. So it is possiblethatthenon-existence
of simple
andthenon-existence
thatitrequires
ata timewithout
ofthenecessity
necessity
is
So our statement
thatZayd is sitting
a doubtis thesenseof possibility.
in thissenseofpossibility
Andour
without
included
theregardofthefuture.
thatZaydbreathes
is notincluded
in thispossibility
butin thefirst
statement
division
whichis a permanent,
everything
parnon-necessary
thing.Further,
in thepossible
But
eventhenecessary.
in thesenseofnon-impossible,
ticipates
whatis usedin whatI sayis one ofthetwodivisions
mentioned.
So hewhowantstomakethenecessary
tobe
andthesimpleandthepossible
naturesthatare absolutely
notmixednorunitedin a singlemattermakes
existence
as longas theessenceofthesubjectis existent,
andmakes
necessary
thesimplethatwhoseexistence
is required
atsometime,impermanently,
perse
ornotperse, andmakesthepossiblethatwhoseexistence
noritsdenialis not
at sometime.Further,
ifhe makesthepossiblewhatis notnecessary
required
inreality,
thedivision
mentioned
aboutthesimple
init.And
wouldbe included
ifhe makesitwhatis considered
in virtue
ofthefuture
at anytimethatdeterminedtobe thesame,thenthere
toitandthesimple
wouldbea matter
common
whichdo nothaveexactly
thesametime,eventhough
oneofthemis inferior
totheother.Butitis notincluded
itin matter.
So
in it;rather
itaccompanies
thesimplematter
is in one respect
andthepossible
in another
Andif
respect.
thepossible
insofar
as thereis no necessity
initis takentohaveno permanent
noranynecessity
is isolated
from
atsometime,[andthen]thepossible
necessity
thesimple
anddoesnotspecify
itinsomerespect.
theway
So youmaydiscover
in theconception
ofmodes.Andyourexampleis theuniversal
So
affirmative.
it'sup to youtochangeit intotheotherforms.
[32,7-36,3]
So theproposition
in itscondition
and becomes
['everyB is A'] is inverted
suchas ifitweresaid:'everything
thatis described
as beingB is necessarily
and
as longas itsesssence
isexistent,
as beingA, as long
characterized
permanently,
as itisAlif['A']. AndtheAlif['A'] isnotthepredicate
butpartofthepredicate.
Andthepredicate
is 'is, as longas itis Alif,A'. Andthispredicate
is certainly
notseparate
from
itssubject,
butnecessarily
ontheother
toit.Similarly,
belongs
is inverted
intheaffirmation
and
hand,whenyouconsider
this,theproposition
Ratheritis necessary
topayattention
insimple[proposinegation
necessarily.
toexistence
is notpermanent,
tions]either
onlyortothefactthattheexistence
thatitbe withanycondition
thatis required,
andthenitis someand,further,
to thesimplebynecessity,
and thepredicate
thingthatis connected
changes
fromitsbeingthepredicate
to itsbeingpartofthepredicate.
[42,2-42,10]

255

09:02:05 AM

Vivarium
XXX, 2 (1992)
Valla's Dialectic in theNorth 2: FurtherCommentaries

P. MACK

A few years ago I wrote an article for this Journal about the
knowledge and understanding of Lorenzo Valla's Dialecticaedisputationeswhich Gerardus Listrius showed in his commentary(1520) on
Peter of Spain. I found that although Listrius reported many of
Valla's philosophical innovations he tended not to support them. On
usage and on mattersof argumentativetechnique, on the otherhand,
he quite oftenendorsed Valla's views.1 This article will consider the
receptionof Valla's doctrinesin fiveothersixteenthcenturycommentaries on dialectical texts,withthe aim of correctingand extendingthe
conclusions of the previous article. It goes withoutsaying thatmost of
the humanist dialectic commentaries I have seen over the last few
years make no referenceat all to Valla or to his opinions.
Since the submission of my earlier article several new studies of
Valla's dialectic have appeared. Pride of place must be given to the
critical edition of the firstand third recensions of the text published
by Gianni Zippel, under the now generallyadopted titleRepastinatio
dialecticae
etphilosophiae
, in 1982. 2 This edition provides a fulldescription of the manuscripts and early printed editions,3 and, supplemented by John Monfasani's review,4 new informationon the
(rather restricted)manuscript circulation of Valla's book. A lively
controversy on the interpretationof the work has continued to
develop, with much debate on the questions of its alleged scepticism
and its possible anticipationof Wittgenstein'sordinarylanguage phi-

1 Valla'sDialectic
intheNorth:
A Commentary
onPeter
Listrius
, in:
ofSpainbyGerardus
21 (1983),58-72.
Vivarium,
2 L. Valla,Repastinatio
dialecticae
etphilosophiae
, ed. G. Zippel,Padua 1982(hereafter
RDP).
3 In note6 ofmyprevious
article(n. 1 above)I mentioned,
in addition
to foursixteenthcentury
editions,two incunables.In facttherewas onlyone
(northern)
incunabular
Milan1496-1500.
RDP, xxxiii.
edition,
byGuillaumeLe Signerre,
4 In: Rivistadi letteratura
Italiana,2 (1984),177-94.
256

09:02:21 AM

losophy.5Less attentionhas been given to the problem of the work's


receptionand its influenceon the developmentof dialectic in the sixteenthcentury.6I hope thatthisarticle(and the list of logical doctrines
on whichValla contradictsAristotleand his followers,provided in the
appendix) will help direct attentionback to this issue.
Of the fivecommentariesin which I have foundreferencesto Valla,
two are commentarieson Rudolph Agricola's De inventione
dialctica.So
I shall begin by discussing the connectionbetween that much printed
workand Valla's Repastinatio
, going on to consider the othercommentaries in turn, before looking at the general pattern of the reception
and transmissionof Valla's teaching.
dialctica(completed 1479) was
Rudolph Agricola's De inventione
A further32 editionsof vari44
times
between
1515
and
1579.
printed
ous epitomes of the work appeared between 1530 and 1600. 7 This
work never mentions Valla but it includes a referenceto the Latin
.8 Since
word quiditaswhich Valla had rejected in his Repastinatio
he
to
in a letattributes
this
Valla,
Agrcola
rejection(which contests)
ter of 1480 to Alexander Hegius,9 we can assume that Agricola had
read Valla's workbeforehe startedto write.Since Agricola was study5 L. Jardine,
Lorenzo
Valla
: Academic
andtheNewHumanist
Dialectic
, in: M.
Scepticism
Tradition
Valla
ed., TheSceptical
, Berkeley
1983,253-86,E. Garin,Lorenzo
Burnyeat
e l'umanesimo
Vallae il volgare
andS. I. Camporeale,
Lorenzo
Valla
, M. Tavoni,Lorenzo
< Repastinatio,
liber
> retorica
e linguaggio
, in:O. BesomiandM. Regoliosi
edd.,
primus
Lorenzo
Vallae l'umanesimo
italiano
, Padua 1986,1-17,199-216,217-39.N. Struever,
Lorenzo
Valla'sGrammar
andObject
, in: I TattiStudies,2 (1987),239-67.R.
ofSubject
andMeaning
intheRenaissance
Was
Waswo,Language
, Princeton
1987,J. Monfasani,
Lorenzo
Vallaanordinary
ofIdeas,50
?, in:JournaloftheHistory
language
philosopher
(1989),309-23,and therepliesbyR. Waswoand S. SteverGravellein thesame
Lorenzo
VallaandRudolph
ofthe
number,
324-36,
J. Monfasani,
, in:Journal
Agricola
ofPhilosophy,
28 (1990),181-99.Theinterpretation
andinfluence
ofValla's
History
workis also discussed
in myPhD Thesis,Rudolph
andRenaissance
Dialectic
,
Agricola
of London1983.I have revisedthismaterial
and
WarburgInstitute,
University
addedtoit in a book,Renaissance
whichI hopewillbe published
Argument,
shortly.
6 Butsee L.
Dialectic
ordialectical
rhetoric?
o's criticism
Jardine,
Agostino
Nif
ofLorenzo
Valla
36 (1981),253-70.
, in: Rivistacriticadi storiadellafilosofia,
7 I havedepended
thelistinG. C. Huisman,Rudolph
on,butalsoslightly
emended,
A Bibliography
Works
andTranslations
1985.Forup to
Agricola:
, Nieuwkoop
ofPrinted
datestudiesandbibliography
on Agricolasee F. Akkerman
and A. J. Vanderjagt
Phrisius
1444-1485,
Leiden1988.
eds.,Rodolphus
Agricola
8 R. Agricola,
De inventione
dialctica
, Cologne1539,reprinted
Nieuwkoop1967,
(hereafter
DID), 228,RDP, 30-36,371-373.
9 R. Agricola,
Lucubrationes
, Cologne1539,reprinted
Nieuwkoop1967,190. This
inmythesis,
n. 5 above,
pointwasmadebyMonfasani,
JHP28, 189,butanticipated
160-7,368-73.
257

09:02:21 AM

ing in Ferrara between 1475 and 1479, and since Valla often sent
copies of his works to Guarino, it is not too difficultto accept that he
could have seen it there. Once this connection between Valla's work
and Agricola's is accepted, a fewotherdetails ofAgricola's workbegin
to look as though they could have been taken over fromValla.
Three of Agricola's new topics (those which he calls 'around the
substance'), adjacents, action and subject, parallel Valla's three
categories: quality, action and substance.10 Some details of the
presentation11encourage the parallel, but Agricola's basic position,
that these are three topics among many others, differsfromValla's,
that they are the three categories which comprehend everything.
When he is discussing differenttypes of question, Agricola follows
Valla in denying that 'animal' is a sufficientanswer to the question
'what is a man?', thoughhe had earlier said that it was.12 Like Valla,
Agricola considersthe problem of whetherto translatetheGreek word
.13
ouata as essentiaor substantia
these
details
Although
suggest that Agricola had read Valla's
not support the view that Agricola was
do
carefully,they
Repastinatio
intellectually dependent on Valla, or that he could be called a
populariser of Valla's views.14On the contraryone can point to many
issues on which Agricola's views are explicitlyopposed to Valla's.
1. In the topic of definition,he followsCicero's definitionwhere
Valla had preferredQuintilian's. DID , p. 26, RDP , pp. 168, 400. 15
10DID , 62-76,RDP, 363-6,46-156.
11For exampleAgricola'stopicof adjacentsincludesall the thingswhichare
Thelistofqualities
oftouch
bythesensesorcomprehended
bytheintellect.
perceived
version:"tactus:calidum,frigidum,
echoesthatin Valla's first
humidum,
siccum,
DID , p. 62,
durum,molle,asperum,lene,et reliquaquae tactupercipiuntur",
"Tactusqualitates
suntmolle,durum,
lene,asperum,
calidum,
humidum,
frigidum,
tenue",RDP, p. 435.In mythesis
densum,
rarum,
siccum,
spissum,
(160-161,164)
I wasunsurewhichversionofValla's workAgricola
had seen.NowI am inclined
to believethatitwas thefirst
version
becauseAgricola
(.DID , 228)wasunawareof
ofPatavinitas
andappietas
Valla'shandling
, lentulitas
{RDP,34) andbecauseitwasthe
n. 4 above,181which
circulated
mostwidely
inmanuscript,
first
version
Monfasani,
4, 189.
12 DID , 26, 229,RDP, 164-5,393-6.
13DID , 76, RDP, 37, 41-6,363-5.
14C. Vasoli,La dialettica
e la retorica
dell'Umanesimo
, Milan 1968,157;L. Jardine,
oftheHistory
Dialectic
VallaandtheIntellectual
Lorenzo
, in:Journal
Origins
ofHumanist
15 (1977),143-64(146).
ofPhilosophy,
15Wheretwopagenumbers
fromRDP, are giventherelevant
passageappearsin
recentothethird
recension.
boththefirst
andthethird
up to356refer
Pagenumbers
version.
sion,thosein excessof357 tothefirst
258

09:02:21 AM

2. In the definitionof property,he accepts Porphyry'sfourthdefinition, where Valla had also, in order to praise Quintilian, in effect
accepted the second. DID , p. 50, RDP , pp. 170-172, 398-400.
3. He accepts Aristotle'sview of the relationshipbetween formand
matter.DID , pp. 53-4, RDP , pp. 110-2, 381-3.
4. He agrees with the Aristoteliantraditionthat a substance must
have quantity before it can have quality. DID , p. 76. 16
5. He supports Aristotle's view of sense-perception as passive.
DID , pp. 75-6, RDP, pp. 154-6, 445-6.
6. In his discussion of action he uses the word 'entelechia', which
Valla had rejected. DID , p. 72, RDP , p. 130.
7. He admits place, time and connexaas topics, although Valla had
reduced these categories to quality and action. His discussion shows
no awareness of Valla's critique. DID , pp. 92-104, RDP , pp. 134-5,
137-43, 438-42. [Together with point 4, this probably indicates that
Agrcola accepts Aristotle's account of the categories.]
8. He uses a definitionof time which Valla had rejected. DID , p.
98, RDP , pp. 150-2, 438-40.
9. He sets out the traditionalfourkinds of opposition, which Valla
had reduced to one kind. DID , pp. 154-6, RDP , pp. 235-6, 497-9.
10. He accepts Aristotle's account of subcontraries, which Valla
had rejected. DID , p. 156, RDP , pp. 227-31, 481-5.
11. He accepts Aristotle's four kinds of modal proposition, which
Valla had reduced to two. DID , p. 234, RDP , pp. 237-43, 491-6.
12. He accepts Aristotle's account of induction. DID , pp. 266-7,
RDP , pp. 345-7, 587-92.
13. He accepts the Aristotelianarrangementof fourformsof proof.
DID , pp. 266-8, RDP , pp. 334-55, 578-96.
14. He does not referto any formsof argumentationbeyond these
four.17
15. He distinguishedquality as status from quality as category.
DID , p. 229, RDP , pp. 9-10.
The most importantdifference,however, between the two works is
16"Magnitudoautem,quam interadiacentianumeravimus
si substantiae
comsubiectihabet
accedit:sin reliquisconferatur
adiacentibus
adiacentibus,
paretur,
sedquodnequeatnisiilliusinterventu
vicem,nonquidemutin ipsasintadiacentia,
in substantia
ea praesertim
adiacent,
reponi."DID , 76,cf.RDP, 134,
quae corpori
141-7,415-40.
17Valla teachesmanyotherkindsincluding
variousdeviantformsof syllogism,
sorites
anddilemma.
259

09:02:21 AM

a differenceof scope. Where De inventione


dialcticais centred on the
topics, showing how they can be used to generate argumentative
discourse, Repastinatiois mainly concerned with the categories, the
propositionand the formsof argumentation,in otherwords withthose
elements of dialectic which Agricola would place in the treatise on
judgment and which he thereforeexcludes fromhis book.18Valla does
not produce a new account of the topics but he does insist on their
importance and he places Quintiliano version of the topics beforethe
formsof argumentationin order to emphasize this.19In his discussion
of the proposition and of argumentationhe continuallysubordinates
logical formalityto a considerationof the implicationsof the way particular words are actually used.20 A similar emphasis on arguing in
real language and on the importance of the topics is characteristicof
Agricola's entire work. So we might say that although Agricola uses
relativelyfew details of Valla's teaching, and although he disagrees
with him on many logical issues, they share one or two key preoccupations.21
Phrissemius's commentaryon De inventione
firstappeared in
dialctica
the fourth edition of that work, published in 1523. Thereafter it
accompanied most editions of the text.22 Johannes Matthias
Phrissemius studied at Leipzig and Cologne, taking the MA there in
1516 and going on to teach in the facultyof arts. He was dean of the
facultyof arts in 1522 and 1526 and became a doctor of canon law in
1525. He was chancellor of the city of Cologne between 1525 and
1528. He died in 1532. 23The prefaceto his commentaryindicatesthat
he was teachingDe inventione
dialcticain thepaedagogiaof the Cologne
arts facultyin the early 1520s.
Phrissemius's commentary contains eleven referencesto Valla.24
Four of these referto threeof the detailed parallels between Valla and
18DID , 197,267.
19RDP, 244. 279-80.527.
20E.g. RDP, 304-7,328-44,553-7,575-8.
21Ofcoursetheideaofmaking
dialectic
lessformal
andmoreresponsive
totheneeds
ofactuallanguageuse waspromoted
otherhumanists
as wellas byValla.
many
by
22In Cologneeditions
after1539,Phrissemius's
is replaced
commentary
bya combinedcommentary
In practice,
the
Alardus,Hadamarius).
however,
(Phrissemius,
combined
was a slightabridgement
ofPhrissemius.
commentary
23Thebestsourceofinformation
onPhrissemius
formuch
(andthemostconvenient
is P. Bietenholz
ed., Contemporaries
century
,3
earlysixteenth
biography)
ofErasmus
vols.,Toronto1985-1987.
24R. Agricola,
De inventione
dialctica
cumscholiis
Ioannis
Matthaei
Phrissemii
, Cologne
Hildesheim
a2r-4v.
1528,reprinted
1976,hereafter
Phrissemius,
260

09:02:21 AM

Agricola noted above. Phrissemiusnotes thatValla would have disapproved of Agricola's firststatementthat 'animal' would be an adequate answer to the question 'what is a man?', commentingthat, in
view of his later contradiction of this view, Agricola would have
alteredthisstatementifhe had been able to revise the work. He refers
back to thiscommentin his commentaryon the kinds of question. He
noticesthe parallel between Valla's discussion of ouata and Agricola' s .
He quotes the passage about Valla's views on words in -itas from
Agricola's letter to Hegius. To this he adds a story about Filelfo
baiting Valla by mentioningQuintilian's hispanitasP
In four other cases Phrissemius records Valla's opinions. In his
discussionof definition,Agricola explains thatbecause of the shortage
of truedifferentiae
it is not always possible to give definitionsin the form
He sets out alternative ways of defining by
genus plus differentia.
graduallyexcluding related classes (e.g. an ass is a long-eared animal
with solid feetwhich is capable of reproducing). Since some people
would regard this as a descriptionratherthan a definition,Agricola
justifieshis usage by explaining the differencebetween the two words.
To this Phrissemius adds Valla's definition of description ('an
explanation of the qualities present to a thing and its actions') and
Cicero's. He regardsboth as supportingAgricola, thoughtheyare not
identical with his formulation.26When Agricola comments that the
goodness of a horse lies in its benefitto humans, Phrissemius notes
thatValla would have preferredhim to use ei ratherthan sibi.21When
Agricola says that some animals may have wills, Phrissemiusrefersto
Valla's long discussion of this subject.28 When Agricola refers to
grammar, rhetoricand dialectic as rational arts, Phrissemius recalls
and rejectsValla's opinion that rational knowledge is about reasons,
that is to say, about findingmiddle terms.29
There are threereferencesto more strictlylogical doctrines. When
Agricola mentions modal propositions, Phrissemius notes that Valla
firstreduced the six modais to three (possible, impossible, true) and
then added various other terms which he considered equally useful
certain,uncertain,customary,unheard of, useful,
(e.g. easy, difficult,
25Phrissemius,
27, 196,60, 195-6.
26Phrissemius,
23-5,28, RDP, 166.
27Phrissemius,
suietsuus
Omnia
66, L. Valla,De reciprocatione
, in: Opera
, Basel1540,
Turin1962,239-41,248.
reprinted
28Phrissemius,
63, RDP, 65-71,408-10.
29Phrissemius,
210RDP, 279.
261

09:02:21 AM

useless).30 When Agricola discusses the conventional four forms of


argumentation (syllogism, induction, enthymeme, example),
Phrissemius draws attentionto Valla's attack on the Aristotelianversion of induction. For Valla it was unacceptable to move froma group
of verifiedstatementsabout individuals to a general conclusion about
a whole class. In his view inductionhad to involve questioning, in the
Socratic manner. PhrissemiusreportsValla's opinion and then rejects
it at some length. He includes examples from Plato and Cicero of
general conclusions being drawn fromparticularobservations. When
Agricola discusses the practiceof induction,Phrissemiusobserves that
Valla would disapprove of Agricola's views and refersback to his own
earlier comments.31
Finally it should be noted that Phrissemiusdoes not mentionmany
other topics which come up in De inventione
dialcticaand on which
Valla held controversialopinions which Agricola opposed, forexample, the categories, the contraries,the syllogism,non-standardforms
of argumentation.32
The commentary by Alardus (1491-1544) of Amsterdam was
printedonce, in 1539, to accompany his revisionof the text. Alardus
was one of the Louvain scholars who was involved in producing the
firstedition of De inventione
dialcticain 1515. In later life he became
somethingof an Agricola specialist, continuingto collect lettersand
minor works for publication, tryingto find new manuscripts from
which to publish a better edition of the Dialectic.This culminated in
his publication in 1539 of new editions of Agricola's Lucubrationes
and
De inventione
dialcticawith commentary,in the prefaces and notes of
which he tells the storyof his quest forAgricola' s manuscripts.33He
was a correspondentof Erasmus and edited works of humanist and
educational interest. He also wrote tracts against the Protestants.34
Alardus' s commentaryis deliberatelylearned, fullof referencesto textual matters and parallels from classical and humanist authors. Its
30Phrissemius,
207,RDP, 237-41,491-3.
31Phrissemius,
260-2,266,RDP, 345-52,587-94.
32References
to thesewillbe foundin theAppendix
below.
33DID , a2r,217,459-60,Lucubrationes
203-4.The storyis also
, n. 9 above.*3V-4V,
toldbyP. S. Allen,Theletters
Historical
, in:The English
Review,
ofRudolph
Agricola
L. Jardine
willhavemoreto sayaboutAlardus'srole
21 (1906),302-17.Professor
in herforthcoming
book,Distinctive
Discipline.
34B. de Graaf,Alardus
Amstelredamus
witha
(1491-1544).His Lifeand Works
1958.
, Amsterdam
Bibliography
262

09:02:21 AM

concludingnote ratherself-consciouslyproclaims thatit is entirelydifferentfrom the commentaryof Phrissemius.35In any event subsequent editions which use Alardus' s improved text all carry a composite commentary,which claims to combine Phrissemius, Alardus
and Hadamarius but which in practice is mainly an abridgement of
Phrissemius.36
Alardus's commentary makes 42 referencesto Valla, 15 to the
, 27 to the dialectic. Alardus quite frequentlygives book and
Elegantiae
chapter numbers, though these are not always accurate (and occasionally I have not been able to trace the referenceintended).
The largestclass of references(20 in all, 7 to the Dialectic)directthe
reader to Valla's discussions of particular words which occur in
Agricola's text.In these examples Alardus only rarelyexplains Valla's
point. Usually he contentshimselfwith a referencewhich will enable
the reader to findthe section of Elegantiaeor Repastinatio
in which the
formor usage of the word in question is considered. This, in other
words, is the philological use of referencesto Valla.37
In a similar way there are a few referenceswhich find parallels in
Valla forsomethingthatAgricola says. So, when Agricola talksabout
species divisionswhich don't work, Alardus refersto Valla's criticism
of the tree of Porphyry.Or he findsan example in which Valla uses
an argumentfrometymologyor a parallel in Valla forAgricola's three
typesof magnitude.38In these cases Alardus is seeking to amplifyor
confirmwhat Agricola is saying by citing parallels in Valla.39
There are eight referencesto Valla's logical teachings. Alardus
notes that Valla's definitionof propertydiffersfromAgricola's. He
35DID, 459-61.
36Huisman,n. 7 above,nos. 10,48, 58, 60, 62, 66, 71, 74, 77, 80.
37In thisclassI include:
1.21(virtuosus)'
DID, 56,RDP, 111 uXrj;
DID, 60,Elegantiae,
DID, 60,RDP,83-4(cautio)'
DID, 69,Eleg.,4.78(<affectiones);
DID, 73,RDP, 127-34
DID , 86, De reciprocatione
DID, 73,RDP, 44, 128-30
, n. 27 above
(actio)',
DID , 100,RDP, 153
(sibi);DID , 96,Eleg.,1.21 (planus
); DID, 96,Eleg., 4.96(celeber)tohospes/
whereAlarduswants
(occasio
); DID, 123,Eleg., 4.83(butthisrefers
peregrinus
hostis/
peregrinus
); DID , 123,noreference
(poenitere
); DID, 168,RDP,326-327(violatio)'
DID , 208,Eleg., 6.52(lignis);
DID , 216,Eleg.,4.48(iuscivile);
DID, 352,Eleg.,4.81
DID, 377,Eleg.,2.25 (.siquidem
(orator)-,
); DID, 415,RDP, 150-2(prius
); DID , 415,
Eleg.,6.32 (I havenotfoundthecorrect
reference)
(prius);DID, 420,Eleg.,2.18
Wherenecessary
I haveadjusted
tosuitOpera
references
n.
(nedum).
omnia,
Elegantiae
27 above,1-235.A goodandwellindexed
modern
ofElegantiae
edition
is muchtobe
desired.
38DID, 47, RDP, 46-50;DID, 60, RDP, 20-1;DID, 66, RDP, 141-3.
39Otherexamples
ofparallels:
DID, 47,RDP,219-22(iniustum)',
DID, 60, RDP, 175
on competitors);
DID , 123,Eleg.,6.36,37 (correcting
(attacks
etymologies).
263

09:02:21 AM

points out that their discussions of Latin translationsof ouaiocand


answers to the question 'what is a man?' are similar.40When Agricola
sets out the truth conditions for a disjunctive proposition, Alardus
refersto the discussion of dilemma in Aristotle's Rhetoric
, in Aulus
Gellius and in Valla. He refersto the same sections when Agricola
discusses argumentswhich depend on dividingone issue between two
opposite alternatives.41He records Valla's reduction of the modal
propositions to three possibilitiesand his findingthat indefinitepropositions (propositions with no indication of quantity) are generally
equivalent to universais.42In response to Agricola's treatmentof the
formsof argumentation,Alardus discusses Valla's account of sorites,
a formwhich Agricola does not mention.43
Alardus also records several of Valla's philosophical innovations
outside logic. There are fourreferencesto Valla's remarkson the soul:
his rejection of the vegetable soul, his insistence that animals have
tripartitesouls like those of humans, his account of habitusand affectus
,
and a remark which I have not been able to trace, to the effectthat
the souls of treesand cows lead them to fulfilltheirnatures.44He also
refersto Valla's remarkson the perceptionof colour and on the active
nature of sense perception.45He noticesthatAgricola uses a definition
of time that Valla rejects and that Elegantiaehas some remarkson the
tendencyof historiansto copy other historianswhich are like those in
De inventione
dialctica
,46This last is the only occasion on which a commentatorlinks a remarkfromthe literarycriticalside of Agricola with
a source in Valla.
Althoughboth theselast two groupingsshow Alardus passing on his
knowledge of Valla's logical and philosophical opinions, many of
Valla's most radical innovations (e.g. res, the categories, the contraries, alternative forms of the syllogism) go unmentioned and
Alardus rarely suggests that either he or Agricola actually shares
40DID, 49, RDP, 170-3;DID , 77, RDP, 37-8,41-6;DID , 230,RDP, 164-5.
41DID , 231,374,Aristotle,
Rhetoric
AulusGellius,Noctes
, II, 23, 1399al7-28,
Atticae,
5.11,RDP, 312-28,352-5.
42DID, 236,RDP,237-239;DID, 283,RDP, 186-7.The indefinite
must
proposition
bedistinguished
nonisappliedtoa noun,e.g.nonhomo)
from
theindefinite
use(where
whichValla
RDP, 215-217.
43DID, 271,rejects,
RDP, 306-12.
44DID, 51, 69, 81, 85, RDP, 59-61,77, 67-71.
45DID, 77 (2 references),
RDP, 72-73,113-5,118-9,154-6.
46DID, 100,300-1,RDP, 149-50,Eleg, 6.54.
264

09:02:21 AM

Valla's views. When Alardus fills in the background to Agricola's


referencesto scepticismhe does not mention Valla.47
George of Trebizond' s Isagogedialctica(1433) was printed more
than fiftytimes in the sixteenthcentury. It is sometimes found in
dialctica(supplyuniversityand facultystatutesalongside De inventione
of
dialectic
which
that
works
the
ing
judgment part
lacks) and the two
works are fairlyoften issued by the same printers.48In 1567 when
Orazio Toscanella chose two humanist dialectics to translate into
dialcticaand Isagogedialctica
Italian, theywere De inventione
, in the edition with commentary by Bartholomaeus Latomus and Jan
Bronkhorst(Johannes Neomagus). Bronkhorsts commentary first
49
appeared in 1533 and Latomus's was added to it in 1540. Latomus
had been instrumentalin bringingthe teachingofDe inventione
dialctica
fromCologne to Paris. In 1531 he became professorof rhetoricat the
college of Ste. Barbe, moving in 1534 to the chair of Latin rhetoricat
the Collge Royal. In 1530 he published an epitome of De inventione
dialcticawhich was printed 26 times up to 1600. 50
The commentaryof Latomus and Bronkhorston Georg of Trebizond's Isagogedialcticamakes seven explicit referencesto Valla, but
also touches on a number of other matters to which Valla refers,
almost always disagreeingwithhim.51Three of the referencesconcern
matters of terminology.Bronkhorstremarks on the way in which
Valla uses propositio
(the firstsentence of the syllogism)and enunciatio
.52
(the general word forproposition) in the thirdbook of Repastinatio
He notesthatValla prefersthe terminfimato specialissima
in the phrase
4
speciesspecialissima.He records Valla's objection to the phrase in eo
quodquid es in the definitionof genus, but replies that if it is enough
to say that genus is what is predicated of several thingswhich differ
47DID , 5-6,195,Phrissemius.
4. 184-5.DID . 221 refers
to Valla'sDe vero
bono.
48J. Monfasani,
VallaandAgricola
to hisGeorge
, n. 5 above,referring
,
ofTrebizond
Leiden1976,333-6and Collectanea
NY 1987,473-7.
Trapezuntiana
, Binhamton,
49Huisman,n. 7 above,no. 76, Monfasani,
, n. 48 above,328-337.MonGeorge
Collectanea
15editions
from1533onwards
ofBronkhorst's
comfasani,
, 473-7records
ofhisandLatomus's
from1540/41
onwards.
alone,and11editions
mentary
together
50Bibliographical
detailsin2 articles
byG. Cambierin: Latomus22 (1963),839-44
and 23 (1964),819-27.
51So manyoftheideaswhich
Vallaattacks
comeupinthecommentary
thatI almost
wishto entertain
the(chronologically
thatIsagoge
dialctica
verydifficult)
hypothesis
in Repastinatio.
(1433)wasoneofValla'stargets
52
De redialctica
ofB. Latomusand
, withthecommentaries
GeorgeofTrebizond,
J. Neomagus,
Lyons1559,b4v.
265

09:02:21 AM

in species, he does not see how Valla will distinguish between


and the definitionof genus.53 Three references
accidents, differentiae
concern mattersof dialectic. Bronkhorstagrees withValla (against the
Boethian view that they are like particulars) that indefinitepropositions generally behave like universais but wants to retain the term
indefinite because indefinites sometimes have the force of particulars.54He refersto Valla's objection to Aristotle's use of letter
substitutionsin PriorAnalytics
,55 At the end of his remarks on the
of
contraries
he
work on the markersof quality
recalls
Valla's
square
and quantity, referringto the chaptersin Repastinatio
book two which
deal with this material but urging the reader to omit the sections in
which Valla attacks other dialecticians.56
One detailed discussion touches on Valla's metaphysics. After
notingthatessentiawould be a bettertranslationof ouata than substantia
is, and explaining thatessentiaand esseare the same (thus twice agreeing with Valla withoutnaming him), Bronkhorstgoes on to say that
ouata can also mean the material fromwhich somethingis made and
that in this sense, in spite of Valla's views, substance is the better
translation. He recalls that Aristotle calls the form of a thing its
substance, where Valla prefersto treatformas part of quality.57This
does not support Valla's opinion, nor does it explain it in any adequate way but it alerts the reader to the strikingdifferencesbetween
Valla and Aristotlein metaphysics.
On the souls of animals, Bronkhorstcites Quintilian's view that
animals lack language ratherthan lacking reason, again agreeing with
Valla withoutmentioning him.58On the other hand he upholds the
opposite opinion to Valla's on subcontrariesand on substance having
the propertyof not undergoing increase or reductionof degree, again
without referringto him.59
Bronkhorst,in short, shows some knowledge of Valla and records
his views about terminologyand his definitions. He is unusual in
referringto Valla's ideas about metaphysicsbut he does not support
s3 Ibid.,c2v(2 references).
54Ibid.,b5v,RDP, 186-187,Boethius,
De syllogismo
Latina64,
I, Patrologia
categorico,
802.
55George,n. 52above,a8r,RDP, 548,299-300.Prior
, I, 2-11,25al4-31b36
Analytics
and passim.
56George,, b7r.
57Ibid.,
c6r,RDP, 36-46,110-2.
58George,c3v,RDP, 70-1.
59George,b6v,c6r.
266

09:02:21 AM

him in any of his innovations. Latomus's commentaryis brieferand


tends to restrictitselfto explaining what George is saying.
In 1535 a commentaryon Porphyry'sIsagogeand Aristotle'sOrganon
was published over the name of the arts facultyat Louvain. It was
reprinted in 1547, 1553 and 1568. This commentary is usually
attributedto Johannes StannifexfromGosslies but the introductory
letterindicates that several authors contributedto it and the titlepage
suggeststhat it may have had a semi-officialstatus at Louvain.60 Its
dialcmany referencesto Rudolph Agricola suggest that De inventione
ticamay have been taught there,but thereare also four referencesto
Valla.61
One is grammatical: when discussing a problem of translation,the
commentaryrefersto Valla's discussion of the differencein the usage
of antiquusand senex.62The commentary quotes Valla's abusive
remarks about the pointlessnessof the third figureof the syllogism,
and replies that this sort of invective does not really answer the
argumentsof the peripateticsor detractfromtheir authority.It concludes withsome examples which show thatthe thirdfigureshould not
be omitted.63On induction, the Louvain commentary firstrejects
Valla's observation that afterlisting a series of individual cases one
should then add 'and so all x is y', arguing that this is implied by the
non-intervention
of the exponent. Later it sums up Valla's objections
to inductionfromRepastinatio
book three,chapter sixteen and replies
to them. Valla's point about the juxtaposition of similars is not an
objection because it is an admitted quality of all inductions. His
examples of particularpropositionsare said to be misleading and his
commentthatall inductionsmust involve questioning of the opponent
is answeredwithexamples fromPhaedoand ProlegeManilia. Finally the
commentaryresponds to Valla's wish that inductions should include
the phrase 'and similarlyforthe others' by showing that Valla's own
chosen example from Grgiasdoes not include it.64
It is strikingthatValla should be referredto at all in what is forthe
mostpart a rathertraditionalAristoteliancommentary.The commen60I amgrateful
toProfessor
Gilbert
oftheCatholicUniversity
ofLouvain
Tournoy
forinformation
aboutthiscommentary.
61I shalldiscussthereferences
toAgricolain Renaissance
Argument.
62LouvainArtsFaculty,
inIsagogen
Commentario
etinomnes
de
libros
Aristotelis
Porphyrii
dialctica
, Louvain1568,16v.Elee. . 4.5.
63Louvain,n. 62 above,Q2r,quotineRDP, 297-8.
64Louvain,V6r,
Gg6v,RDP, 345-52.
267

09:02:21 AM

tators seem to think that his challenges to the third figure of the
attractiveand dangerous to
syllogismand to inductionare sufficiently
warrant rebuttal,but that his other innovations, such as his complete
overhaul of Aristotelian metaphysics, are so extreme that they can
safely remain unanswered.
Johann Caesarius was born in Jlich in 1468. He matriculatedat
Cologne in 1491 and also studied in Paris under Jacques Lefvre
d'Etaples. He held teachingposts in Cologne, Munster, Mainz, Leipzig and Moers. He was the author of textbooks on logic, rhetoric,
grammar and medicine. His Dialcticawas completed in 1520 and was
printedmore than seventytimes in the sixteenthcentury.65In a preface of 1525 he lists various humanists (including Agricola, Valla,
Erasmus and Vives) among his authorities,but his treatmentof the
subject is on the whole traditional,followingthe order of the Organon
and making much use of Boethius's De syllogismo
and De difcategorico
The
edition
with
Welsdalius
and
ferentiistopicis.66
commentary by
Glareanus was firstpublished in 1559. 67
Caesarius himselfmakes three incidentalreferencesto Valla, justifyinghis own use of Boethius by noting thatValla called him 'the last
of the erudite', pointingout Valla's oppositionto Boethius's use ofpersona in his work on the double nature of Christ, and notingthat Valla
approves of the word praedicamentum
(for category).68 There is a
referencein the commentarywhich may also be termed incidental,
when Glareanus points out that Valla discusses equivocation in
, book two, chapter two.69
Repastinatio
On the issue of the form of the proposition Glareanus refersthe
reader to Valla's attackon thosewho treatnouns and verbs as the only
parts of speech.70 He reproduces and praises Valla's teaching on
biparticulars in a lengthy note, adding that Valla has not had the
credithe deserves and statingthat althoughhe is not a classical author
he deserves to be compared with them. In a later note he quotes
65Algemeine
Deutsche
, 3, 689. DetailsofCaesariuseditions
Biographie
(basedon W.
, I (1472-1800),Hildesheim
1965,IndexAureliensis
Risse,Bibliographia
, and
Logica
National
UnionCatalog
) in mythesis,n. 5 above,312-4,493.
66J. Caesarius,Dialctica
, Cologne?1525, (British
Library
copy520d6(2)),Aalv.
67Risse,n. 65 above,records
editions
withcommentary
byGlareanus
(1556)andby
I used.
himandWelsdalius
of1567which
together
(1559).He doesnotlisttheedition
68J. Caesarius,Dialctica
andGlareanus,
ColofWelsdalius
, withthecommentaries
1567, + 8V,B4r,C4r.RDP, 4, 8-9,Eleg.,6.34.
ogne
69Caesarius,C6r,RDP, 182-3.
70Caesarius,G8r,RDP, 178-81.
268

09:02:21 AM

Valla's second rule forbiparticulars,also with approval.71 This is a


rare instance of original opinions of Valla being endorsed warmlyby
a sixteenthcenturycommentator.On induction he adds:
ofthethird
all of
LorenzoVallainthelastchapter
bookofhisDialectic
mocked
thisas itis taught
andBoethius.
Forhiman induction
musthave
byAristotle
threeproperties:
thejuxtaposition
ofsimilars
and proof.He was
questioning,
ofQuintilian
moremovedbytheauthority
thanbythatofAristotle,
Ciceroor
Boethius.
Whoever
wishesmayfollow
him.72
This commentsums up a common attitudeto Valla. The commentatorsummariseshis views accurately,but he also, withoutcriticising
Valla, distances himselffromValla's views.
Among these five commentariesa good range of Valla's doctrines
are commented on or referredto. In metaphysics and philosophy,
attentionis directedby at least one writerto his views on persona
, on
the translationof ouaia, on matterand form,on answers to questions
in quid, on the definitionof genus, on the soul, on perception, on
habitusand affectus
, on the souls of animals, and on time. In the area
of the proposition, to equivocation, to parts of speech other than
nouns and verbs, to modal propositions,to biparticulars,to indefinite
propositions and to disjunctive propositions. Within the forms of
argumentationcomments referto the terminologyof the syllogism,
the thirdfigureof the syllogism,induction, sorites and dilemma.
Taken together then, these commentaries confirm that Valla's
dialectic was available, that it was read attentivelyand that several of
its doctrines were thoughtworthyof comment. On the other hand
there are several importantdoctrines which are not reported in the
commentaries,forexample the reductionof the transcendentaisto res,
the reductionofthe categories,the reorganisationof ethics,the reform
of the square of contraries,the promotionof the topics, the attack on
the fourformsof argumentation,the new kinds of syllogism,and the
importanceof measuring the strengthof particular words. The commentaries give no sense of how Valla's doctrines fit together as a
whole, or of which of his innovations are most important.
71Caesarius,I8V-K1'RDP, 199-201.
72"Laurentius
Vallalibro3. de Dialctica,
ridethoctotum
ab Aristotele
cap.ultimo,
et a Boethiotraditum.
adessedebereasserii:interrogaIpse enimtriainductioni
similium
etprobationem;
motusQuintiliani
authoritate
tionem,
appositionem,
magis
velCiceronis
velBoethii.Qui velitsequatur."Caesarius,08v,
quamvelAristotelis
RDP, 345-52.
269

09:02:21 AM

Valla's views are most oftenreferredto on issues of terminology,on


the souls of animals, or translationsforouaia and on induction. Indeed
most of the referencesto Valla are more in the nature of scholarly
indications of contrast than positive endorsementsor interpretative
suggestions. This must have something to do with Valla's rather
ambiguous position. Thanks to Erasmus and to the circulationof the
, Valla was an extremelyprominentauthorityfor northern
Elegantiae
humanists. The display of knowledge of his works was an indication
of the eruditionof the commentator.But his actual views on dialectic
were much too extreme for the basically Aristoteliancontextsof the
works being commented on. The Louvain commentary gives the
impression that although some of his views needed to be rebutted,
otherswere best passed over in silence. But in the othercommentaries
there is not even that much acknowledgementof the revolutionary
effectof Valla's views on logic and metaphysics.
In his Oratio in laudemAristotelis(1510) the well known Dutch
humanist Martin Dorp, who was then teaching at Louvain, attacked
Valla for criticisingAristotle.73He regards Valla as a learned and
acute man and a supreme grammarian who has an unfortunate
tendency to attack all established authorities. He regretsthe recent
publication of Valla's dialectic.74For the most part he answers Valla
by citing greater authorities(including Valla's hero Quintilian) who
admired Aristotle,but he also refersto threedetails fromthe preface
: Valla's criticismof Aristotle's failure to perto Valla's Repastinatio
formany of the really importanttasks of a public man or a writer,his
attack on his contemporaries' veneration forAristotlealone, and his
objection to the Aristotelians' way of using the phrase 'philosophus
dixit'.75 Dorp makes no referenceto Valla's dialectical teachings.
At thispoint it may be worthrecallingtheviews ofJuan Luis Vives,
a more distinguishedhumanist than any of the commentatorsI have
discussed. Vives had witnessed at firsthand both the apogee of late
scholastic logic at the college of Montaigu, where he studied in Paris
between 1509 and 1512 and the early years of the Agricola revival at
73Biographical
n. 23 above,I, 398in Contemporaries
article
byJ. IJsewijn
ofErasmus,
to Dorp's
ofthisjournalfordrawing
to theeditors
404. I am grateful
myattention
oration.
74M. Dorp,Orationes
IV, ed. J. IJsewijn,
Leipzig1986,18-24(18).
75 Ibid.,22-23,RDP,5-7,361(butitishardtoimagine
howDorpcouldhaveknown
thislast).
270

09:02:21 AM

Louvain from 1512 onwards.76In his Adversus


pseudodialecticos
(1520),
Vives endorses some of Valla's general positions (that dialectic
depends on the ordinaryusage of language, that it ought not to formalise itselfby employing letters of the alphabet as substitutesfor
terms, that dialectic is brief, and that philosophers need freedom)77
withoutmentioninghis name. At the end of book threeofDe causiscorartium(1531) Vives comments on Valla's contribution to
ruptarum
dialectic.
Vallaundertook
ofdialectic,
withAristothereconstruction
Lorenzo
disagreeing
bothancientand modern.He makessomerecommendatleandhisfollowers
tionswhicharenotbad,though
thesearefew.In mostcaseshemakesmistakes,
forhe wasan impetuous
He errednot
man,and hastyin making
judgments.
butalsoinphilosophy
whichhe alsodealtwith,and,whichis
onlyindialectic,
in thelawsof theLatinlanguage.But he erredno lessin
moresurprising,
others
inthissubjectthanhedidinElegantiae
andinhisInvectives.
As
reproving
forhisnumerous
indialectic,
errors
weshallpassoverthemhere,orsavethem
foranother
occasionifit seemsappropriate,
forit wouldtaketoolongto get
inan argument
involved
them.In anycaseitis unnecessary
becausehis
against
areneither
basedonsoundreasons,
noraretheyaccepted
arguments
byanyone
as rulesofthisart.78
Most sixteenth-centuryhumanists in the north appear to have
thoughtbetter of Elegantiaethan Vives did, but his judgement that
Valla's reasoning was unsound and his positions insufficiently
well
a
to
fits
in
well
with
the
of
evidence the comsupported require reply
mentariesconsidered in this paper.
In my previous article I suggested that the philosophical importof
Valla's views hardly came across in Listrius's comments, that Valla
was used much more on matters of argumentative technique and
points of stylethan in his logical teaching and that Listrius tended to
76R. Guerlac
thePseudodialecticians
,JuanLuisVives
Against
(Dordrecht
1979),pp.23-7.
77Ibid.,pp.56,
arenotamongthosewhich
Vivestakesover
60,78,104.Thesepoints
from
ThomasMore's1515letter
to MartinDora.
78Opera
omnia
Valla
(Valencia1782),vi,p. 151,Guerlac,n. 73,p. 152:"Laurentius
estreconcinnationem
faceredialecticae,
in qua dissentit
ab Aristotele
et
aggressus
veteribus
ac novis.Monetin quibusdam
Peripateticis
neutiquam
prave,etsiea sunt
ut fuitvirillevehemens
et ad faciendum
labitur,
perpauca.In plerisque
judicium
Necsolumin redialctica
falsus
namhincquoest,sedinphilosophia,
praecipitatus.
etquodmagismirere
inpraeceptis
Latinaelinguae.Sed nonminusillic
que attingit,
aberravit
et invectivis.
Ceterumdialecticae
illius
improbando
quam in elegantiis
errores,
qui suntsane multi,nos vel omittemus
prorsusvel in aliud tempussi
videbitur
reservabimus.
Namsuscipcre
resessetnimium
cumeo disputationem
prolixaminimeque
inpraesens
necmagnisrationibus
necessaria,
quodilliusargumenta
necproinde
suntab ulloreceptatamquam
nituntur,
dogmataartishuius."I made
useofGuerlac
's translation
in preparing
mine.
271

09:02:21 AM

referto Valla's dissentingviews ratherthan explore or support their


subversive potential. All the commentariesstudied in this articletreat
Valla in a more fragmentaryway, and regardhim withmore distance,
than Listrius did. They tend to confirmmy suggestionthatValla was
read throughAgricola, that rather than being an inspiration to the
northernhumanist reformersof logic, Valla's dialectic was more an
incidental, scholarlyinterest,and a guide to usage.
Coventry
University
of Warwick
Appendix
A listoflogicalissueson whichVallaattacks
andhisLatinfollowers,
Aristotle
oron
whichhisviewscontradict
theirs.79
1. Thereare threecategories
andnotten.363,8-10,46-50,112.Arist.,Categories
,
4, Ib25-2a4.
2. Relatives
shouldnotbepartofthecategories.
425.Arist.,Categories
, 7,6a36-8b25.
3. Quantity
is partofquality.425. Arist.,Categories
, 6, 4b20-6a36.
4. All theothercategories
can be reducedto qualityand action.438, 112-115.
5. The termenshas no force.369, 13-15.Arist.,Metaphysics
, IV, 1, 1003a28-32.
6. Valla attacksthe distinction
betweenconcrete
and abstract.373-377,21-30.
etal., Opera
Ockham,Summa
, ed. P. Boehner
, I, St. Bonaventure
Logicae
philosophica
80
NY 1974,I, 5-10,16-38.
7. Vallasuggests
thattheuseofthelatinwordsubstantia
as a translation
forouatais
butgoesalongwithit becausetheusageis so firmly
established.
37-46.
incorrect,
In Categorias
Aristotelis
, I, PL 64, 181D-184D.
Boethius,
8. Thedistinction
between
form
andmatter
is either
frivolous
ordeceitful.
382,110112.Arist.,Metaphysics
, XII, 3, 1070a19-30.
9. Theproperty
ofnottaking
moreandlessbelongs
tonounsgrammatically
andnot
to substances
384, 157.Arist.,Categories
, 5, 3b33-4al0.
logically.
10. Vallarejects
theAristotelian
ideaofthemedium
between
387.Arist.,
contraries.
, 10, 12al-25,Ethics
, II, 6-9, 1106al4-l109b28.
Categories
11. Goodandbadaremorecontrary
thangoodandnotgood.389,(162-3).De inter, 14,23b33-24b9.
pretation
12. Resis thegenusto whichthecategories
In Categorias
belong.392. Boethius,
Aristotelis
, I, PL 64, 180B.PeterofSpain,Tractatus,
II, 7, 18-19.81
79My intention
incompiling
thislistis toincludeall thosedoctrines
ofVallawhich
ina dialectic
onemight
thatis,all thestrictly
expecttofindmentioned
commentary,
andsomefrom
andpsychology
whichareclosely
related
metaphysics
logicaldoctrines
orwhichmight
occurinexamples.
Renaissance
willcontain
a listofdoctrines
Argument
on whichVallainRDP, contradicts
drawnfroma muchbroaderrangeof
Aristotle,
The first
after
eachstatement
refer
totherelevant
groupofnumbers
subjects.
pages
ofRDP.
80'Abstract'
arediscussed
and'concrete'
della
Maier,Terminologia
byAlfonso
logica
tardascolastica
, Rome1972,66-9.
81I am citingthisworkfromtheeditionofL. M. de Rijk,Assen1972,hereafter
Trac
tatus.
272

09:02:21 AM

viewthatthegenusis a sufficient
13. Vallaattacks
answertoa question
Porphyry's
in 'quid'.393-396,164-166.L. Minio-Paluello
translatio
Boethii
ed., Porphyrii
,
Isagoge
Aristoteles
I, 6-7,Categoriarum
Latinus,
Supplementa,
Bruges1966,hereafter
Isagoge,
7-8.
14. Valla attacks
definition
ofdifferentia.
391, 163-164.Porph.,Isagoge
,
Porphyry's
18.
definition
of property.
15. Valla attacksPorphyry's
398-400,170-171.Porph.,
, 19-20.
Isagoge
ofdefinition
is vagueandempty.400, 168.Arist.,Topica
16. Aristotle's
definition
,
I, 5, 101b37.
useofthephrase4species
17. Vallaattacks
medieval
Aristotelians'
' 423,
specialissima
18.
10. PeterofSpain,Tractatus
, II, 7,
is unintelligible.
160.Arist.,Categories
18. Secondary
substance
, 5, 2bl3-3a20.
is inconsistent
andincompatible
withChristianity.
19. The 'TreeofPorphyry'
389In Porphyrium
Commentariorum
, III, PL 64, 103,G. Schepss,S.
391,46-50.Boethius,
inIsagoge
Brandt
Commentarti,
edd.,Boethius
, II,
Porphyrii
Leipzig1906,209. Tractatus
11,20.
53-58.Arist.,
ideaofGodismistaken.
20. Aristotle's
, XII, 7-8,1072b24Metaphysics
1073al3,1074a35-bl0.
21. Animalspossessreason.409-410,67-73.Arist.,De anima,
III, 3, 429a5-9.
in ethics.77-78.Arist.,Categories
22. The notionofhabitis ofno significance
, 8,
8b26-9al0,Ethics
, II, 1, 1103al3-25.
andhabitus.418,79.
23. Therearevariousintermediate
stagesbetween
disposition
, 8, 8b26-9al0.
Arist.,Categories
ofpotential
are absurd.128-129,Arist.,
and evxeAexetoc
s conceptions
24. Aristotle
, IX 7, 1048b35-1049b2.
Metaphysics
25. Thereare notsix kindsof motionbutonlyone.82436-438,132-133.Arist.,
, 14, 15al3-bl7.
Categories
26. Lines do not have longitudewithoutlatitude.428-429,143-144.Arist.,
In Categorias
Aristotelis
, II, PL
, V, 6, 1016b26,13, 1020al4[Or Boethius
Metaphysics
64, 204C-205B].
27. Pointsarepartsoflines.429-430,144-147.
Arist.,
, XIV, 3, 1090b5-20
Metaphysics
loc.cit.in previous
[Or Boethius
item].
is activenotpassive.445-446,154-156.Arist.,De anima,
28. Senseperception
II, 5,
416b32-418a6.
ofa wordthatitssignificance
is fixedby
29. Valla addsto Boethius's
disposition
Inlibrum
De interpretatione
humanconvention.
433,122-124.
, editiosecunda,I, PL 64,
I, 1-5,1-2.
395-396;ed. C. Meiser,Leipzig1880,6-10.PeterofSpain,Tractatus,
- copula- participle.
shouldnotbe reducedtotheform:subject
45030. Sentences
213. PeterofSpain,Tractatus,
I, De introd.,
1, 3-4.
451, 178-181,
45131. Denominative,
andunivocal
areissuesingrammar,
notdialectic.
equivocal
lai
181-183.
-15.
Categories
1,
452,
Arist.,
,
behavelikeparticulars.
Boethius's
viewthatindefinite
32. Vallacorrects
propositions
II, PL 64, 802C.
454, 186-189.Boeth.,De syllogismo
categorico,
ofpropositions.
189-190.
Arist.
33. Vallaattacks
theconversion
, Prior
, I, 2-3,
Analytics
25al-b25.PeterofSpain,Tractatus,
I, 15,8.
34. Vallarevises
ontheeffects
oftheLatinwordsusedas markers
previous
teaching
ofpropositions.
ofthequalityandquantity
457-472,190-215.PeterofSpain,Tractatus
, I, De introd.,
8, 4.
82Vallaalsoallowsthatthere
canbe changes
ofquality,
buthedoesnotregard
them
as partofmotion
strictly
speaking.
273

09:02:21 AM

useofquidam
35. Vallaattacks
Boethius's
as themainmarker
ofparticularity,
arguforthepurpose.
460-461
De inter
, 195-196.
Boeth.,Inlibrum
ingthatitis toodefinite
ed. C. Meiser,Leipzig1880,147.
pretatione
, editiosecunda,II, PL 64, 540A-548B;
viewson biparticulars.
36. Valla attacks
Boethius's
De interpreta199-201.In librum
ed. C. Meiser,Leipzig1880,294-310.
tion,editiosecunda,IV, PL 64,540A-548B83
37. The negative
shouldnotbe appliedto thenoun.472-475,215-219.Arist.,De
2, 16a30,10, 19b38.
interpretation,
477-491
iswrong.
De interpretation,
38. Thesquareofcontraries
, 224-235.
Arist.,
7-8,
17a37-18a28.
39. Thereare not fourkindsof opposite,but two. 497-499,235-236.Arist.,
10, 11b15-13b35.
Categories,
40. The system
of six kindsofmodalproposition
is mistaken.
491-493,237-238.
Arist.,De interpretatione,
12, 21a34-36.
41. VallasaysthatPeterofSpamiswrong
toderive
dialectic
from
between
reasoning
two{duo)people.526,279. PeterofSpain,Tractatus
, De introd.,
I, 1, 1.
isnotspecific
ofsyllogism
42. Aristotle's
definition
280-281.Arist.,
528-529,
enough.
Prior
I, 1, 24bl8-20.
Analytics,
forthepartsof thesyllogism.
43. Valla altersBoethius'sterminology
529-530.
II, PL 64, 811B-C.PeterofSpain,Tractatus,
Boeth.,De syllogismo
IV, De
categorico,
Sill.,2, 43-44.
o proposition
44. Valla attacksthe definition
used by Boethiusand the Latin
tradition.
Aristotelian
529, 280-281.Boeth.,De differentiis
I, PL 64, 1174B.
topicis,
PeterofSpain,Tractatus,
I, De introd.,
7, 3, IV, 1, 43.
45. Valla wantstoaltertheorderofthepartsofthesyllogism.
531,282. Boethius,
In TopicaCiceronis,
I, PL 64, 1051A-B.
46. Manyofthemoodsofthesyllogism
arepointless.
297-300.Arist.,Prior
546-548,
I, 11, 31al9-32a5.
Analytics,
47. Vallaattacks
Aristotle's
useofletters
torepresent
terms
inhisdiscussion
ofthe
and passim.
548,299-300.Arist.,Prior
I, 2-11,25al4-31b36
syllogism.
Analytics,
48. Valla adds manynew typesof syllogism
in wholeand parts,all
(syllogism
all particular
and all singular
basedon
syllogisms,
negative
syllogisms,
syllogisms
304-306.Cf.PeterofSpain,Tracwords)535-537,543-546,553-555,282,289-291,
tatus,
IV, De sill.,4, 45.
49. Valla attacksBoethius'saccountof hypothetical
549-553,300-304.
syllogism.
Brescia1969,
Boeth.,De syllogismo
I, PL 64, 831-832;ed. L. Obertello,
hypothetico,
204-208.
50. Vallaaddsotherforms
ofargumentation
sorites,
(chainsofsyllogisms,
interrogation,dilemma).556-563,306-312.
51. Valla rejectsconversion
as a replyto thedilemma.562-575,312-328.Aulus
5.10.1.
Gellius,NodesAtticae,
52. It is futile
toattempt
a systematic
treatment
oferrors.
575-576,
328,334.Arist.,
.84
Sophistical
Refutations
53. Aristotle
s accountofinduction
is mistaken.
587-592,345-349.Arist.,Topica,
I,
12, 105al3-18.
83Thisreference
comesfromZippel.It is highly
likelythatValla is hereattacking
medievallogician,whoperhapsalso uses theexampleofthefish
someparticular
whichtheJewsare permitted
to eat.
84AtRDP, 304-6,314-6,328-34,553-5,564,575-8,Valla attempts
to accountfor
severalsophism-like
and late
(some of themtakenfromAristotle
ambiguities
recourse
todoctrines
associated
withthesophisms.
without
scholastic
philosophers)
Further
detailsin mythesisand book,n. 5 above.
274

09:02:21 AM

forms
ofargumentation.
54. VallaupsetsBoethius's
offourrelated
scheme
594,352PeterofSpain,Tractatus
353.Boeth.,De differentiis
PL, 64, 1183A-1184D.
, V,
topicis,
85
De loc.,3, 56-58.
85The schemeprobably
derivesfromArist.,Posterior
, I, 1, 71al0. I am
Analytics
indebted
to Zippel'snotesin RDP, forsomeoftheparallels
citedabove.

275

09:02:21 AM

Vivarium
XXX, 2 (1992)
Reviews
: a Portrait
SaintAnselm
R.W. Southern,
ina Landscape
Press
, Cambridge
University
1990,xxix+ 493p. ISBN 0 521 362628
It is nowalmostthirty
hisfirst
book
yearssinceSirRichardSouthern
published
on Anselm,Archbishop
ofCanterbury
It seemedthenthatSaintAnselm
1093-1109.
andhisBiographer
Press1963)mustsurelybythedefinitive
(Cambridge
University
written
as thisfirst
workwas,matchless
in itsinsights
and
Beautifully
biography.
wonderfull
skilledin itsinterpretation
ofthewritten
it appearedincapable,
record,
ofnewevidence,
thediscovery
either
ofserious
alteration
orofsignificant
exbarring
tension.
retaina smallmeasureoftruth.
Theseappearances
The first
workstillstandsin
bookdoesnotreplacetheformer;
itsownright.The present
indeed,wenowneed
thetwobefore
us. Butit doeschangeandextendit.And,in so doing,italtersthe
at thedeepestand,to many,themostrewarding
oflevels.
messageoftheoriginal
The first
wehavemovedfrom
the
changeis oneofpace.As thenewtitlesuggests,
and toa farlargercanvas.The Europeanbackground
tothe
pentothepaint-brush,
laterEnglish
sceneis discussed
morethoroughly,
andsomeofthebrush-strokes
used
in itsdescription
are bolderand morefullofpigment
thantheearlierinstrument
allowed.The messages
Themost
then,reacha widerreadership.
theyconvey
might,
is thechangeofperspective.
ofthechanges,
In theearlierbook
however,
important
itwas Eadmer,Anselm'sfirst,
andnearlycontemporary,
wholedus to
biographer
theArchbishop.
NowEadmeris, so tospeak,relegated
tothewings,andAnselmis
tocentre
forhimself.
Anselm
When,furthermore,
stagetospeakoutclearly
brought
doesspeakouttohisexpectant
hisprayers,
audience,he doesso primarily
through
andletters.
Ata timewhenprayers
andmeditations
arenotnormally
meditations
the
first
sourcestowhichthehistorian
The Anselm
turns,thisis peculiarly
refreshing.
so firmly
is notAnselmtheArchbishop,
moreover,
but,overwhelmingly,
projected,
monk.
AnselmtheBenedictine
The physical
centre
ofthebookis devotedtoa discussion
ofthisAnselm.We are
to realise that his meditative
both of
broughtimmediately
understanding,
ingeneral
monasticism
andofhisownvocation,
wascrucialtoallofhispublicactions
It wasalsobyno meansa common
andexpressions.
one.Thismayin partexplain
theexasperation
thesaintarousedin someofhiscontemporaries.
andinRejection
droveAnselmto Bee. Self-abnegation
hisgrateful
to the
security
governed
response
lifehefoundthere
andat Canterbury.
Continued
andtheabasement
self-abnegation
ofthemerely
humanwillwere,tohim,thesoleguarantees
ofhistrueliberty
andthat
of others.It was a view bothbleak and immutable.
Anselm'sconception
of
monasticism
is noteasytocomprehend
totranslate
now;norwasiteasythenreadily
it intopractice.
Thesecentral
pagesuponthepartmonasticism
playedin Anselm's
ofpeaceandfreedom,
bothinprivate
andinpublic,and,aboveall,uponhis
pursuit
areamongthemostvaluableinthebook.Theycontain
ideasofmonastic
friendship
gleaming
passagesofprose.
meantforAnselmtheliberty
todo no wrong,
Liberty,
including
political
liberty,
isnotthepowerofchoicebetween
''freedom
goodandevil,butthepowerofsteadfasttothewillofGod,which
comesfrom
theloving
lywilling
nothing
contrary
acceptance
ofthelimitations
ofcreatedbeing",and "...neitherfriendship,
as Anselmusedthe
can be fully
without
an intense
oflife."Such
word,norfaith
experienced
discipline
observations
a badlyneededbalanceandcorrection
totoosimplean associaprovide
tionofmonastic
emotion
withhomosexual
orientation.
Also,at a timewhenfewpersonshavedirectexperience
oftheBenedictine
ofthebook
wayoflife,thesesections
276

09:02:27 AM

thislife,itsseverities
withan aptness
anditsrewards,
evokeandpresent
andintensity
whichis as rareas it is essential
to all understanding
ofthisperiod.
Anselmthusemerges
as a manforwhom,oncehe enterstherealmofstatecraft,
all essential
choiceshavebeenmade.He has no roomfor,or interest
in, political
manoeuvre.
He mustremainfaithful
in thefullest
senseto hiscommitments,
and
so to hisfirst
vocation
as a monk.HereDr. Southern
tackleshead-ona
especially
offered
viewofAnselmtheArchbishop.
to thisviewArchbishop
recently
According
Anselmwas a figure
one
vitallyengagedin theexerciseofpowerand influence;
mindful
of theimpacthis collected
letters
especially
mightmakeuponthelarger
scene.It is no longerpossibletosustainsucha position.
The careful
discussion
of,
andappendix
tradition
ofAnselm's
collected
letters
mustalone
upon,themanuscript
setat restforeverthenotionthatAnselmwas,orwishedtobe, in fullcommand
of
suchmatters.
It alsobrings
toourattention
howcrucialan expert
sharply
knowledge
ofall themanuscripts
is to sucha discussion.
Somestepshavehad, inevitably,
to be retraced.
On certainsubjects,
however,
takeson theforceoffresh
assertion.
Sucha oneis thenotorious
repetition
problem
ofthe"Canterbury
In herworkon Lanfranc,
Gibsonargued
Forgeries".
Margaret
- butis unrepenforan earlydateforthese.SirRichardreviews
thiswork
cogently
tant.The caseforan 1120/21
datehe madein hisfirst
is re-stated
with,
biography
it mustbe said,compelling
power.I cannotsay quitethesameforthecase for
HonoriusAugustodunensis
thewandering
Irishmagpie;butherewe enterregions
beyondthescopeofa review.
The central
feature
ofthisstudyis theportrait.
The re-painting
ofthelandscape
hasbrought
outthefigure
as neverbefore.It is a marvellous
achievement.
Auckland

Valerie I.J. Flint

PeterofSpain,Language
inDispute.
TheSummulae
translation
of
, (An English
Logicales
PeterofSpain'sTractatus
calledafterwards
Summulae
on thebasisofthe
Logicales
critical
edition
established
byL. M. de Rijk).Translated
byFrancisP. Dinneen.
( = Studiesin the Historyof the LanguageSciences,39). JohnBenjamin,
1990.ISBN 90 272 4524X
Amsterdam/Philadelphia
PeterofSpain(ca. 1205-1277)
is oneofthebestknownfigures
in thehistory
of
so. His Tractatus
inthe1230s,provides
written
a full
logic,anddeservedly
, probably
introduction
toAristotle's
oftheAnalytica
Posteriora
logic(withtheexception
), together
witha lengthy
treatment
of thespecifically
medievaldevelopment
of supposition
Theworkwaswidely
usedandcommented
onwellintothesixteenth
theory.
century,
to shapeuniversity
education
thelatermiddleages.At
thereby
helping
throughout
thesametime,theTractatus
contains
muchofinterest
to thehistorian
oflanguage.
Peterwaswriting
at a timewhenthespeculative
ofthemodistae
wasjust
grammar
to takeshape,beforeits culmination
in the greattreatises
on modi
beginning
ofthelastthreedecadesofthethirteenth
andwe findinhimthe
significandi
century,
simultaneous
useoftworather
different
to language.On theonehand,
approaches
his tractson supposition,
relative
and
terms,ampliation,
restriction,
appellation,
distribution
totheeffect
ofcontext
onword-meaning
anduse.On
paycloseattention
theother
themodistic
notionthata spoken
hand,histractonfallacies
emphasizes
(or
wordis endowed
at oneandthesametimewithitssignification
anditsconwritten)
or secondary
so thatsentential
context
will
signification,
grammatical
signification,
ofsuchproblematic
notions
as equivocation.
normally
playnoroleintheexplanation
277

09:02:27 AM

thislife,itsseverities
withan aptness
anditsrewards,
evokeandpresent
andintensity
whichis as rareas it is essential
to all understanding
ofthisperiod.
Anselmthusemerges
as a manforwhom,oncehe enterstherealmofstatecraft,
all essential
choiceshavebeenmade.He has no roomfor,or interest
in, political
manoeuvre.
He mustremainfaithful
in thefullest
senseto hiscommitments,
and
so to hisfirst
vocation
as a monk.HereDr. Southern
tackleshead-ona
especially
offered
viewofAnselmtheArchbishop.
to thisviewArchbishop
recently
According
Anselmwas a figure
one
vitallyengagedin theexerciseofpowerand influence;
mindful
of theimpacthis collected
letters
especially
mightmakeuponthelarger
scene.It is no longerpossibletosustainsucha position.
The careful
discussion
of,
andappendix
tradition
ofAnselm's
collected
letters
mustalone
upon,themanuscript
setat restforeverthenotionthatAnselmwas,orwishedtobe, in fullcommand
of
suchmatters.
It alsobrings
toourattention
howcrucialan expert
sharply
knowledge
ofall themanuscripts
is to sucha discussion.
Somestepshavehad, inevitably,
to be retraced.
On certainsubjects,
however,
takeson theforceoffresh
assertion.
Sucha oneis thenotorious
repetition
problem
ofthe"Canterbury
In herworkon Lanfranc,
Gibsonargued
Forgeries".
Margaret
- butis unrepenforan earlydateforthese.SirRichardreviews
thiswork
cogently
tant.The caseforan 1120/21
datehe madein hisfirst
is re-stated
with,
biography
it mustbe said,compelling
power.I cannotsay quitethesameforthecase for
HonoriusAugustodunensis
thewandering
Irishmagpie;butherewe enterregions
beyondthescopeofa review.
The central
feature
ofthisstudyis theportrait.
The re-painting
ofthelandscape
hasbrought
outthefigure
as neverbefore.It is a marvellous
achievement.
Auckland

Valerie I.J. Flint

PeterofSpain,Language
inDispute.
TheSummulae
translation
of
, (An English
Logicales
PeterofSpain'sTractatus
calledafterwards
Summulae
on thebasisofthe
Logicales
critical
edition
established
byL. M. de Rijk).Translated
byFrancisP. Dinneen.
( = Studiesin the Historyof the LanguageSciences,39). JohnBenjamin,
1990.ISBN 90 272 4524X
Amsterdam/Philadelphia
PeterofSpain(ca. 1205-1277)
is oneofthebestknownfigures
in thehistory
of
so. His Tractatus
inthe1230s,provides
written
a full
logic,anddeservedly
, probably
introduction
toAristotle's
oftheAnalytica
Posteriora
logic(withtheexception
), together
witha lengthy
treatment
of thespecifically
medievaldevelopment
of supposition
Theworkwaswidely
usedandcommented
onwellintothesixteenth
theory.
century,
to shapeuniversity
education
thelatermiddleages.At
thereby
helping
throughout
thesametime,theTractatus
contains
muchofinterest
to thehistorian
oflanguage.
Peterwaswriting
at a timewhenthespeculative
ofthemodistae
wasjust
grammar
to takeshape,beforeits culmination
in the greattreatises
on modi
beginning
ofthelastthreedecadesofthethirteenth
andwe findinhimthe
significandi
century,
simultaneous
useoftworather
different
to language.On theonehand,
approaches
his tractson supposition,
relative
and
terms,ampliation,
restriction,
appellation,
distribution
totheeffect
ofcontext
onword-meaning
anduse.On
paycloseattention
theother
themodistic
notionthata spoken
hand,histractonfallacies
emphasizes
(or
wordis endowed
at oneandthesametimewithitssignification
anditsconwritten)
or secondary
so thatsentential
context
will
signification,
grammatical
signification,
ofsuchproblematic
notions
as equivocation.
normally
playnoroleintheexplanation
277

09:02:42 AM

is equivocalbecauseas a participle
itconsignifies
Thuslaborans
bothpresent
andpast
verb.
time,and notbecauseit isjoinedto anyparticular
ofPeterofSpain'sTractatus
It is notsurprising,
should
then,thata translation
tothehistory
ofthelanguage
Whatis surprising,
sciences.
appearina seriesdevoted
doneandso poorly
shouldhavebeenso poorly
is thatthetranslation
presented.
Any
readers
toa historical
tointroduce
textshoulddo
bookwhichpurports
contemporary
whichtellsthereaderwhothe
fourthings.First,it shouldhavean introduction
historical
authorwas,andwhichsetshimin hiscontext.
Second,it shouldprovide
a fair
a selected
as a guidetofurther
Third,itshouldprovide
reading.
bibliography
numberof explanatory
notes,since even quite recentworksare rarelyselfwhichis bothaccurateand
Finally,it shouldprovidea translation
explanatory.
ofmeeting
thepresent
workfallsfarshort
readable.Unhappily,
anyofthesecriteria.
indexesand
oftheintroduction,
I shallbeginwithan examination
bibliography,
of
notes.The introduction
'Hispanuswasa contemporary
openswiththeremark:
entitheorists
called'Modistae'after
their12th[sic]to14thcentury
writings
linguistic
tledDe ModisSignificando
(p. xvii).Dinneengoeson tellus thatPeterwasbornca.
fora datebefore
De Rijk'sarguments
1205,andthathis'workappeared
1215,despite
toprovide
historical
around1300[sic]'(p. xxvi),buthe makeslittlefurther
attempt
is devotedto a disorganized
seriesof
details.Most of the22-pageintroduction
Thelanguage
isjargon-ridden
remarks
aboutmedieval
(e.g.theuseofthe
linguistics.
arebaffling.
and'etically'),
invented
words'emically'
andsomeoftheremarks
What,
whatthey
from
forinstance,
is onetomakeoftheclaim:'The Medievais
progressed
between
twoofAristorelations
calledLogicaAntiquatoLogicaModernabyrefining
andQuantity:
Substance
otherCategories
tle'sCategories,
(e.g. QualityandRelaadded'(p. xxxvii)?
wereexplicitly
tionitself)
The Bibliography
just fourworks:the1955Loeb editionof
(p. xxxix)contains
edition
1947edition
ofPeterofSpain,Bursill-Hall's
Bochenski's
Aristotle's
Organon,
ofThomasofErfurt,
and De Rijk's 1972editionofPeterofSpain1on whichthis
sourceon
is madeat anypointtoanysecondary
translation
is based.No reference
medieval
grammar.
logicandspeculative
andtheindex
Theindexofwordsandthings
Therearethree
indexes.
(pp.208-260)
on De Rijk's
of sophisms
and examples(pp. 261-271),bothheavilydependent
aresatisfactory,
buttheindexofreferences
indexes,
(pp. 206-207)is useless.Without
thereader,itrefers
onlytothepagesofDe Rijk'sedition;nordoesitgive
warning
as 'Anonymous.
Comm.in de Celo'.
detailsforsuchentries
anybibliographical
aboutthe
similarproblems.
The notesexhibit
Apartfroma fewminorremarks
himself
withcopying
de Rijk'snotes.A number
Latintext,Dinneenhascontented
Latinus
references
totheAristoteles
ofthesegiveunexplained
(e.g. p. 143,n. 78: 'Post.
Minio-Paluello's
An. I 16, 79b 23-25,Jacobi's[sic] translation,
edition,p. 34')
whicharerelevant
onlytotheLatintext.One note(p. 184,n. 6) tellsthereaderthat
hasa pointonlywhenonerealizes
that
which
'box'means'trunk,
coffer',
strong-box,
' ina context
totheword'archa
wherea previous
De Rijk'snote(R, p. 207)referred
'
Noe' (Noah'sark).In oneplace(p. 12)Dinneendoesadd a note
examplewas archa
buton p. 66 line8 he follows
abouta variantreading
foundinDe Rijk'sapparatus,
corrects
De
thefact,andonp. 66 line10hesilently
a variant
without
noting
reading
'
'
'
noto'
. On p. 164he silently
toto
adoptsthe
Rijk's minus
(R, p. 75 1. 16) to minus
to De Rijk's
variantreading'PriscianMajor',buton theverynextpagehe reverts
thereaderanyhelpinunder'PriscianMinor'.Notoneofthenotesoffers
reading,
difficult
logicalpoints.
standing
andnotes,thisbookwouldhave
a proper
Evenwithout
introduction,
bibliography
oftheLatintext.Unfortunately
a reliabletranslation
beenusefulhad itcontained
He is literalwherehe should
Dinneenfallsintoeverytrapthatawaitsa translator.
wherehe shouldbe literal,ifseveralEnglish
be free,he paraphrases
inaccurately
278

09:02:42 AM

or understand
he failsto recognize
wordsarepossible
he choosestheleastsuitable,
andhisEnglishis frequently
hemakesstraightforward
technical
errors,
vocabulary,
I go ontodocument
theseclaims,I wouldlike
Before
orevenunintelligible.
clumsy
TractI andpartofTract
all ofPeterofSpain'stext,apartfrom
tosaythathappily
VII, is alreadyavailablein English.TractsVI, VIII, IX, X, XI and XII were
of
translated
ofPeter
byJ. P. Mullally{TheSummulae
Logicales
ofSpain,University
NotreDamePress,NotreDame,Indiana1945,tobecitedas M). Whilethistranslationis veryold,andwasnotbasedona critical
text,itdoesat leastmakesense,and
himwithDinneen,Mullallyis clearlysuperior.
in all theplaceswhereI compared
TractsII, III, IV, V andpartofTractVII haverecently
beentranslated
byNorman
Kretzmann
and EleonoreStump( TheCambridge
Translations
ofMedieval
Philosophy
Texts.Vol.I. LogicandthePhilosophy
, Cambridge
Press,CamofLanguage
University
withDe
bridge1988,tobe citedas KS). I compared
everylineoftheirtranslation
and I foundit to be immeasurably
Rijk'seditionand withDinneen'stranslation,
to Dinneen's.It is lucid,elegantand accurate.2
superior
Let me first
speakofDinneen'sEnglish.Evenat itsbest,itdoesnotflow.For
he writes:'To becomefamiliar
withthePredicaments,
a few
instance,
prefacing
letus first
a triplemodeofpredicating'
withAristotle
necessary
things,
distinguish
Kretzmann
andStumpwriteTnordertounderstand
thecategories
cer(p. 25)where
tainintroductory
remarks
arenecessary.
wewilldistinguish
withAristotle
three
First,
suchas
waysofmakinga predication'
(KS, p. 88). He usesheavyformulations,
... inseparably'
'blackco-occurs
acci(p. 23, cf.KS p. 86: 'blackis an inseparable
Some
dent')or 'unusableconnexities'
(p. 48,cf.KS p. 225'uselesscombinations').
a mistranslation
sentences
bothcontain
andmakeno sense:e.g. 'Shiftis ambiguous
'
in proof(p. 191)fortheLatin' Quiaduplex
estprocessus
inprobatione
(R, p. 2171.2),
thatis, 'thereis a two-fold
of
in
, M p.
process reasoning thedisproof
'improbatione'
75. He almostalwaysuses'like'wherehe means'suchas', 'forexample'or 'e.g.'.
Thuswe readthatsomewordsare predicated
'like"dog" bya single
equivocally,
nameis predicated
ofthebarker,
marineanimaland heavenly
body'(p. 24).'
he is overly
Sometimes
literal.Thus'essebipedem
inest
omni
homini
sednonsoli (R,
as 'beingtwofooted
is in everyman,notjustone' (p. 22)
p. 22 11.5-6)is rendered
rather
than'beingtwofooted
isineverymanbutnotinmenalone'(KS, p. 85) which
is thesensedemanded
Atothertimeshe supplements
thetext
bytheentire
'
' passage.
inan unfortunate
of'figure'(evenifPeter
way.The wordquartamakeshimthink
ofSpainadmitted
so we twicefindreferences
to the
onlythreesyllogistic
figures)
'fourth
ofthefirst
mood'(p. 153,p. 154,cf.p. 42: 'This is reducedto the
figure
'secundum et
' as
fourth
He sometimes
translates
figure').
prius posterius
'proportionally
or analogically'
in his Tractatus
PeterofSpain
78, cf.
(p.
pp. 85, 89), eventhough
'
'
neveronceuses analogiaorwordsformed
fromit,andeventhough
whenlogicians
didstartdiscussing
itin anysimplewaywith
analogyas such,theydidnotidentify
secundum
predication
priusetposterius.
HisgraspofLatinvocabulary
is unsure.Sometimes
thisis morea matter
ofchoice
thanofactualerror.
Thuswefind'costume'
for'habitus'
inplaceswhere'possession'
' is translated
is thebetterreading(e.g. p. 18, p. 36); 'pena
as 'suffering'
where
is better
as 'he
'punishment'
(p. 60); lpenitet'
deliqui
ergo
(R, p. 701.20) is translated
hasregrets;
therefore
hehasfailed'(p. 62) rather
thanas 'He is repentant;
therefore,
he hasdonesomething
wrong'
(KS, p. 239). In otherplaces,hischoiceofwordis
' volubile
'
mistaken:
totheheavensis translated
as 'changeable'
rather
simply
applied
' is translated
'
than'revolvable'
as 'genus'whenit hasto be 'gender'
(p.
66);
genus
'
'
as 'field'(p. 59, p. 60); 'sanativus'
is
(p. 125); vitrum
('glass') is twicetranslated
translated
as 'healthy'
rather
than'health-giving'
withtheresult
thatthewhole
32)
(p.
'Castrum' the
sentence
is garbled;
is rendered
as 'camp'rather
than'for(in singular)
tress'(p. 64).
279

09:02:42 AM

is
withwordsbecomereallyseriouswheretechnical
Thesedifficulties
vocabulary
ofthewordsalready
isthatDinneenisunaware
Theleastserious
concerned.
difficulty
'extenfor'hypothetical
usedintheliterature.
Thus,hehas'hypothetic'
proposition',
Somenotions
for'confused
'diffuse
sions'for'ampliation',
supposition'.
supposition'
' and'
areroutinely
as 'nonfinite',
translated
Thusboth' indefinita
heconfuses.
infinita
anda nounwitha
an unquantified
between
thedistinction
whichfudges
proposition
' are bothtranslated
'
as
and ' ostensivus
negativeprefix.More seriously,inferens*
as demonstrative
various
of
whichleadstothelabelling
'demonstrative',
syllogisms
sense(seep. 148,153,155).He
notso in thetechnical
whentheyarcconspicuously
' mediumwhichcanmean
as 'middleterm',even
translates
',
'premiss(es)',
resolutely
as 'a middletermis calledthatbecauseithastwo
in suchsentences
whenitresults
' means
so that
that' instantia
extremes'
'counterexample',
(p. 49). He is unaware
'
'
a further
as 'Noristhere
deoratione
estinstantia
objec(R, p. 321.6) is rendered
Neque
a
does not constitute
tion froma sentence'(p. 29) insteadof 'An expression
'
. Thus, secunwith'consequential
counterexample'
(KS, p. 93). He hasgreatdifficulties
'
essentie
dumsubsistendi
consequential
(R, p.
consequential
(R. p. 40 1. 10)and secundum
and'because
insubsisting'
of
the
basis
as
'on
rendered
11.
40 21-22)get
subsequence
and 'a
thanas 'an existential
ofessential
consequence'
dependency'
(p. 35) rather
havingto do withessence'(KS, p. 99. p. 100).
consequence
withLatin
thatisatstake,forDinneenalsohasdifficulties
It is notonlyvocabulary
for
when
his
as
his
own
these
are
of
Sometimes
preference adjectives
making, '
syntax.
nature'(p. 25),
as 'substantial
leadshimto render1ratiosubstantie
overgenitives
' as 'material
'
' nominis
materie
and
as
'nominal
forma
interpretation'
(p.
54),
interpretation
I
shall
stem
from
form'(p. 188).Others
simplemisunderstandings. givea listofthe
a
utnichil
habet
naturalem
dicitur
mostseriousexamples.'Ut sanativus
potentiam
eoquod
as 'One iscalledhealthy
accidentibus
(R, p. 3611.23-24)istranslated
patiatur
quibuslibet
at allthathappen'
from
ofnotsuffering
becausehehasa natural
anythings
capacity
insofar
is saidtobe health-giving
thanas 'So, forexample,
something
(p. 32) rather
accidents'
certain
from
ofpreventing
as ithasa natural
(KS, p.
suffering
any
power
'
dicimur
(R, p. 38 1. 18) is
agere
quamin id quodsubicitur,
96). Actioestsecundum
as 'Actionis thatbywhichwearesaidtoactonwhatis subjected'
translated
(p. 33)
withwhichwe aresaidto
thanas 'Actionis thatin thesubjectinaccordance
rather
'
e'.
existenti!
rulesbymisreading
someofPeter'ssyllogistic
act'(KS, p. 98). He garbles
existenti
Thus' majori
(R, p. 48 11.5-6)is readas 'Ifthemajoris a particular
particulari
is
means'If themajorpremiss
existential"
(p. 40, cf.p. 42, p. 44), whenitsimply
'
estSortes
, animalest
(KS, p. 221). Peter's'exampleof a fallacyanimal
particular'
as
homo(R, p. 82, pp. 143-144)is twicerendered
Plato
,... ergoanimalestomnis
'Socratesis an animal,Platois an animal,... therefore
everymanis an animal'(p.
ofwhythearguofPeter'sexplanations
nonsense
71, 124),whichmakes
complete
'Accidentalis
communis
termini
estacceptio
autem
mentis fallacious.
proeispro
suppositio
'
is
as 'accidental
supposition
adjunctum
(R, p. 81 11.5-6) is translated
quibusexigit
added'
it
demands
for
which
those
for
term
of
a
common
something
things
acceptance
termforall
ofa general
is theacceptance
than'Accidental
supposition
(p. 70) rather
'
.... Sednonnisi
estuniversalis
altera
itsadjunctdetermines'
thosethings
p.
Ergo
5).
(M,
'
is
thefirst
as 'Therefore
estiustus"
hec:" non-homo
(R, p. 225 11.1-2)is translated
universal....Butonlyif "non-manis just" is universal'
(p. 198) ratherthanas'
butitcanonlybe thisone: "Not manisjust"
'Hence,one ofthemis universal...
(M, p. 89).
or omitted
Thereis a fairnumberoftypographical
words,and
errors,
repeated
'not'onp. 69,
is an extraneous
there
I shallmention
othererrors.
onlythefollowing:
as cause'on
before'non-cause
section2, para. 1, lastline;'not'shouldbe inserted
shouldbe
p. 155,section168,lastlinebutone.One p. 148,section146,'healthy'
of'scienceofthesick'.PartsoftheLatin
for'sick'in bothoccurrences
substituted
280

09:02:42 AM

onp. 21,section12,p. 51,section


texthavenotbeentranslated
3, p. 73,section11,
andp. 76, section1.
I do notrecommend
little
thisbook.It reflects
credit
onitsauthororitspublisher.
Ont.
Waterloo,

E. J. Ashworth

Notes
1 PeterofSpain,Tractatus,
called
Summule
Editedby L.M. de
afterwards
Logicales.
Assen1972,to be citedas R.
Rijk,Van Gorcum,
2 However,
ofcomposition'
on p. 250,lines22-23'fallacy
shouldread'fallacy
of
'
division'.I wasa littleunhappy
thattheytranslated
as 'meaning'on p.
appellatio'
89 para.3.
MarianneHeimbach,
Derungelehrte
MundalsAutoritt.
als Quelle
Mystische
Erfahrung
RedeimWerk
Mechthilds
vonMagdeburg
inGeschichte
kirchlich-prophetischer
(Mystik
- TexteundUntersuchungen:
undGegenwart
I: Christliche
Abteilung
Mystik.
von MargotSchmidtund HelmutRiedlinger,Band 6).
Herausgegeben
Canstatt1989.
Stuttgart-Bad
Fromman-Holzboog,
DiesesBuchenthlt
eineStudie,die 1988vonderKatholisch-theologischen
FakulttderUniversitt
alsDissertation
wurde.DerZweckdieser
Wrzburg
angenommen
Arbeit
Licht
derGottheit
den'Zusammenhang
zwiist,anhanddesWerksDasflieende
schenMechthilds
undihremaufdie Kirchegerichteten
mystischer
Gottesbeziehung
undSchreiben'
Sprechen
(S. 11) darzustellen.
In einemersten
H. mittels
dreiGrundlinien
die Grundzge
von
Kapitelskizziert
Mechthilds
1. dieSelbsterkenntnis
desMenschen
imLichtseireligiser
Erfahrung:
nerGottesbeziehung;
2. die gegenstzliche
vonTrostundTrostlosigkeit;
Erfahrung
3. diemystische
als Nachvollzug
derHeilsgeschichte.
Das zweiteKapitel
Erfahrung
einerTugendethik:
zur /m>z;zzwischen
gibtAnstzezurGrundlegung
Beziehung
GottundMenschgehrt
das WirkenundHandeln.Das dritteKapitelbeschreibt
Mechthilds
DenkenundReden.ErstwirdihrKirchenbild
charakkirchenbezogenes
dannwirduntersucht,
wiesie das Wortinnerhalb
dieserKircheergreift,
terisiert,
sowohlimGebetwiein kritischer
Im letzten
WeisungundStellungnahme.
Kapitel
machtH. deutlich,
wieMechthilds
Auftreten
sichin einerprophetischen
Sendung
Sie zeugtvonderErfahrung
dergttlichen
minne
grndet:
, wiesehrsiesichauchals
kritische
einesKonflikts
mitGesellschaft
undKircheaussetzt.
BeginederGefahr
EinAnhang
einegutgegliederte
Bibliogibtdiebibliographischen
Abkrzungen,
vonG.J.Lewis,F. Willaert
undM.J.Govers
graphie
(berdie 1989erschienene,
verfate
zurdeutschen
desMittelalters
konnte
H. nichtverfgen,
Bibliographie
Frauenmystik
aberaus einemVergleich
derbeidenBibliographien
ergibtsichdie Grndlichkeit
ihrerbibliographischen
undeinPersonenundSachregister.
Arbeit),
Die ganzeArbeit
istsehrkohrent
undsystematisch
BeiderLektre
falaufgebaut.
leneinemMittelniederlandisten
verschiedene
Parallelen
vonMechthild
mitHadeundanderenmittelniederlndischen
Autoren
auf.
wijchundRuusbroec
mystischen
AusdieserSichtmchte
icheinigeBemerkungen
zumvorliegenden
Buchmachen.
Im Laufedesersten
die ganzeSchpfung
H., wieMechthild
Kapitelsbeschreibt
sichindemLob Gotteszu vereinen,
wiewohl
siewei,da auchdannGott
einldt,
nichtnachseinerWrdegelobtwerden
kann.DiesesWissenistaberkeinAnlazur
sondern
zur Freude:'Herre,magmandichvolleloben?Nein,des
Entmutigung,
vroeweichmich'(S. 47). H. siehtdenGrunddieserFreudein derEnthebung
des
281

09:02:42 AM

Es wrdemichwundern,
dadieseaufdas eigneIchgerichtete
Leistungsdruckes.
derUrsprung
dieserFreudewre:Das selbstlose
IchderMystikerin
wei
Erfahrung
nurnochumeineFreude:denGeliebten.
DiesesVermuten
wirdverstrkt
durcheine
Brulocht
, diederzitierten
PassageinRuusbroecs
PassagebeiMechthild
analogist:An
dieStelledes'Lbens'tritt
beiRuusbroec
das 'Minnen'.berdies
Ruusexplizitiert
broecaberauchdenGrundderFreude:'Nochtanblivetgodonghement
na weerde
vanallencreaturen.
Endedates derverlichter
redenen
cen grotewalostendeghedatharegoden de hareliefsoehogheendesoe rijckees, dathi allen
noechlijcheit,
crachten
endevan niemenne
en es na sineweerde
ghescapenen
onthoghet
ghemint
danvanhemselven'.( Opera
Omnia
, 3, bl 165-1
169).GrundderFreudeistalsonicht
dieEnthebung
desLeistungsdruckes,
sondern
'datharegodendehareliefsoehoghe
endesoe rijckees', nichtdas Ich,sondern
derGeliebte.
Im selbenKapitelwirdbehauptet,
Mechthild
nehmemitihrerBeschreibung
der
mittels
dergegenstzlichen
desAuf-undAbsteimystischen
Erfahrung
Bewegungen
innerhalb
derTradition
ein,indemsiedasAufstiegsschema
gens'eineSonderstellung
mit
durchbricht,
[...]' (S. 65,Note249).AufjedenFallteiltsiedieseSonderstellung
Ruusbroec
Werken
, Ruusbroec,
, II, S. 57: *[...]wantnedergaen
(z.B. aus Tabernakel
in oetmoedicheiden,
dates eenopgaenbovenallehoecheit
derhemele'),Claesinne
vanNieuwlant
Z. 241: 'doordenneder, hrsg.v. Mommaers,
(z.B. ausSamenspraak
eenenpuurenopganck
inGo) undMarguerite
denmensch
Porete(z.B.
gancheeft
ames
ausMirouer
dessimples
encel, hrsg.v. Verdeyen,
Kap. 98, 5-7:'Ilz s'esbayssent
etsi s'esbayssent
de ce mesmes
luyqui estdu montde sa montaigne,
qui estou fons
de leurvallee').
imselbenKapitelzitiert
H. Richsttters
Abermals
Meinung,da es sichbei der
von Mechthild
in KapitelIV.24 berichteten
Schauum die ltestebisherbekannte
handelt
keinen
Kommen(S. 75,Note308).Da siedieserMeinung
Herz-Jesu-Vision
tarhinzufgt,
scheint
siedieseAnsicht
zu teilen.Die Herz-Jesu-Vision
vonLutgard
vanTongeren
istaberlter.
(1182-1246)
zwischen
undHadewijch
BeiallerVerwandtschaft
Mechthild
ltauchdieLektre
zwischen
diesesBuchesdieUnterschiede
beidenschreibenden
umso strker
Beginen
zu erwhnen:
ThemadiesesStudiums
in
spren.Um nurdas zentrale
nirgendwo
ihrem
sichselbstals'ungelehrte'
oderals 'snoeganzenOeuvreerniedrigt
Hadewijch
VisionzeigtsiesichimGegenteil
deswib'(p. 175).In dersiebten
demmnnlichen,
manbei ihrnichts
vonderganz
gelehrten
'kimpe'berlegen.
Zugleichaberfindet
inderGeschichte
konkret
wurzelnden
derMechthild.
Kirchenkritik
Wohlbtsieoft
scharfe
aberdiesegiltfastimmerdenMitgliedern
ihresmystischen
Kreises
Kritik,
oderdenjenigen,
diediesenKreisbedrohen
Auchbezglich
desvon
(den'vremden').
H. untersuchten
ThemaswirdderBefund
vonFrances
Gooday(Diss.Harvard1974)
bei allerhnlichkeit
istdas WerkbeiderFrauengrundverschieden.
besttigt:
Antwerpen

Guidode Baere

DieAristotelisch-Scholastische
Theorie
derBewegung
: Studien
zumKomSarnowsky,
Jrgen
mentar
Alberts
desAristoteles
vonSachsen
zurPhysik
zurGeschichte
der
( = Beitrge
undTheologie
desMittelalters,
NeueFolge,Band32).Aschcndorff,
Philosophie
Mnster1989.xii + 501 pp. ISBN 3 402 039273
inmedieval
Albert
ofSaxonyis innowaya stanger
butrarely
doesheprescircles,
enta clearcut
andmorerecently
image.His worksfaredwellamongearlyprinters,
hisfairshareofattention
as a notably
thinker
in the
he hascaptured
"progressive"
and naturalscience.Allthishas meantthat
fieldsoffourteenth-century
philosophy
282

09:03:02 AM

a conveniently
availablesourceforsampleopinions
hiswritings
haveprovided
on
Aristotelian
issuesofhistime.Buthe alwaysseemstobe in theshadowofanother,
moreoriginal,
andputatively
or,moreproBuridan,Bradwardine,
greater,
figure,
Oresme.Sarnowsky
facestheproblem,
and seeksa middleposition
blematically,
between
thoseofPierreDuheminhisearlierwritings,
forwhomAlbertwasoneof
"themostpowerful
andmostoriginal"offourteenth-century
andAlexscholastics,
anderBirkenmajer,
whoregarded
himas little
better
thana plagiarist.
A middle
positionis difficult
to developsharply,
whenone is dealingwithsuchan
especially
andSarnowsky'
s strategy
doesnotgreatly
facilitate
thisend.
greyfigure,
apparently
After
someveryuseful
onAlbert's
sourcesandinfluopening
chapters
biography,
toa chapter-by-chapter
ofhiscommentary
onthe
ence,Sarnowsky
proceeds
analysis
Thisis veryhandyforgeneral
butgiveslittlesenseofthecutand
reference,
Physics.
thrustof debate,nor of Albert'sparticular
nuancesof interpretation
and his
immediate
reasonsforchoosingthem.One longsformorediachronic
appraisal
overtheshortterm),butmostquestions
of thiskindare leftto the
(particularly
44
short
finalchapter,
DerPhysik-Kommentar
Alberts
vonSachsenunddie
relatively
derNaturerkenntnis"
Entwicklung
(pp. 405-434).In thisSarnowsky
develops12 +
10 + 4 theses.
and,onemaysaycommendably,
Unsurprisingly
theyaresoundrather
thanexciting.
In thefirst
sethe characterises
Albert's
relation
tocontemporary
and
earlierscholastic
theories
ofmotion:whether
todescribe
hisdeviations
as majoror
minor
willdependonone'shistoriographical
The secondconcerns
Albert
viewpoint.
vis--vis
theClassicalPhysics
oftheseventeenth
thinks
in terms
century:
Sarnowsky
ofpreparation
rather
thananticipation,
andinhissearchfora characterisation
makes
useofhintsprovided
The thirdsetofthesesrelate
particular
byAmosFunkenstein.
tothelimitations
ofhisownprocedures:
hereoneseemstosensean impatience
atthe
constraints
thathehasfeltattheendofcomposing
thisrelatively
earlywork,andthe
desirefora morestimulating
to follow.
Letus hopethatsuchan able
methodology
scholar
infinding
succeeds
one!On a moreprosaic
level,wemustaccordhimespecial
thanks
for56 pagesofveryvaluablecodicological
and bibliographical
information
locatedtowards
theendofthevolume.
Aberdeen

GeorgeMolland

283

09:03:02 AM

Vivarium
XXX, 2 (1992)
BooksReceived
LuisE. Bacigalupo,
Intencin
enla EticadeAbelardo,
Pontificia
Universidad
y Conciencia
Catlicadel Peru,Fondoeditorial
1992339 p.
WalterBerschin,
undEpochenstil
imlateinischen
III Karolingische
Mittelalter.
Biographie
750-920
n.Chr.
AntonHiersemann
1991xii&484p.
Biographie
Verlag,Stuttgart
ISBN 3 777291021 (QuellenundUntersuchungen
zurlateinischen
Philologie
des Mittelalters,
Bd. 10)
AnneBondelle-Souchier,
dansla France
cisterciennes
mdivale.
des
Bibliothques
Rpertoire
d'hommes.
du Centrenational
de
Abbayes
Avant-propos
parA. Vernet.ditions
la recherche
Paris1991lvii& 381 p. & 28 planchesISBN 2 222
scientifique,
045967
duMoyen-Ages
Cahiers
del'Institut
etlatin(Universit
deCopenhague
grec
), Vol. 61 (1991),
440 p. - Contents
: Chr.Troelsgaard,
Themusical
structure
stichera
offiveByzantine
andtheir
Western
A. Jung,TheKathismata
intheSophia
parallels
among
antiphons;
Kliment
Ochridski
cod.gr.814;G. Klima,Latinas a Formal
; C.
Manuscript
Language
librum
A Partial
Posteriorum.
Marmo,Anonymus
Cordubensis,
Questiones
super
primm
andqq.1-5;C. Marmo,Anonymi
Edition:
"Sicut
dicitur
abAristoPrologue
Philosophia
tle".A Parisian
toPorphyry;
C. Brousseau,
Lesophisme
"Amatus
sum
prologue
anonyme
velfui",ducodex
BN lat.16135;K. Friis-Jensen,
Addenda
etCorrigenda
to
parisinus
CIMAGL 60: 319-88;A. Tabbaroni,Henricus
An
Ruyn,
Disputata
Metaphysicae.
S. Ebbcsen,TwoNominalist
Texts.
Edition;
TheVariae
Aurelius
Cassiodorus
Senator.
Translated
withnotesandintroducofMagnus
tionbyS.J.B.Barnish,
1992xlix&204p.
Press,Liverpool
Liverpool
University
ISBN 0 85323436 1
sullatradizione
Documenti
e studi
medievale.
RivistadellaSocietInternazionale
filosofica
: S. Donati,
Latino,I, 1 (1990)vii& 325p. - Contents
perlo Studiodelmedioevo
delle
I : Le opere
Studi
diEgidio
Romano.
del1285.I comperunacronologia
opere
prima
menti
: C. Luna,La Reportatio
aristotelici
dellalettura
diEgidioRomano
III
sullibro
dellesentenze
dell'rdinatio;
dell'autenticit
R. Martorelli
(Clm.8005)e ilproblema
dellagiustizia
e delpeccato
neltrattato
Depeccato
Vico,La dottrina
originale
originale
diEgitio
C. Trifogli,
La dottrina
inEgidioRomano;
deltempo
R.
Romano;
originali
videtur
tres
rationes.
lettore
edinterprete
Lambertini,
Philosophus
tangere
EgidioRomano
dellaPolitica
nelterzo
libro
delDe regimine
principm.
Documenti
e studi
sullatradizione
medievale.
RivistadellaSocietInternazionale
filosofica
: C.
per lo Studiodel medioevoLatino,I, 2 (1990) vii & 320 p. - Contents
nonestyliathim.
Liber
deCausis,
e la
D'Ancona,Cause
prime
prop.8[9]: lefonti
M. McCord Adams,SaintAnselm's
L. Sturlese,Il
dottrina;
theory
of truth;
razionalismo
e scientifico
diAlberto
il Grande;
K. White,St. Thomas
filosofico
Aquinas
andthePrologue
toPeter
's Qiiaestiones
De sensu
etsensato;
M. G.
ofAuvergne
super
Thomas
Il problema
dellostatuto
; C. Trifogli,
Henniger,
Wylton's
theory
ofrelations
nelle
deltempo
di Thomas
e di Giovanni
ontologico
Quaestiones
super
Physicam
Wylton
diJandun;
M. Pereira,Unlapidario
alchemico:
il Liber
deinvestigatione
secreti
occulti
attributo
a Raimondo
Lullo.Studio
introduttivo
ededizione
divia
; E. Randi,Onnipotenza
efuturi
XIVsecolo;
Z. Kaluza,Eugenio
Randi(1957-1990);
indicedei
contingentinel
indicidei nomini.
manoscritti;
AzucenaAdelinaFraboschi,
Cronica
dela universidad
deParis
y deunahuelga
y susmotivos
Instituto
deestudios
"Prof.F. Nvoa".[BuenosAires
(1220-1231),
grecolatinos
1991],143p. ISBN 950 998200 8
TheGesta
Normannorum
Ducum
Orderic
andRobert
Vitalis,
ofWilliam
ofJumiges,
ofTorigni.
Vol. I: Introduction
and BooksI-IV. Editedand translated
byE. M. C. van
Houts,Clarendon
Press,Oxford1992exxxiii& 156p. ISBN 0 19 8222718
284

09:03:27 AM

LatinPoems.Rome1633 and1639. EditionwithIntroduction,


Lelio Guidiccioni,
Translation
and Commentary
byJohnKevinNewmanand FrancesStickney
1992278 p. ISBN 3 615 000749
Newman.Weidmann,
Hildesheim
de
Pressesuniversitaires
et l'averrosme.
M.-R. Hayoun& A. de Libera,Averros
France,Paris1991128p. ISBN 2 13 044203X (Que sais-je2631)
B. R. Grner,Amsterdam-Philadelphia
DesmondPaul Henry,Medieval
Mereology.
StudienzurPhilosophie,
1991XXV
&609p. ISBN 90 6032318 1 (Bochumer
16)
en van
1, 39. Ingeleid,vertaald
en Vrijheid.
Lectura
DunsScotus
, Contingentie
Johannes
A. H. Looman-Graaskamp,
doorA. Vos,H. Veldhuis,
voorzien
commentaar
1992208 p. ISBN 90 211
E. Dekker,N. W. denBok.Meinema,Zoetermeer
35698
of
Terms
RichardA. Lanham,A Handlist
, secondedition.University
oj Rhetorical
1991ISBN 0 520076699 xv&
California
Press,Berkeley/Los
Angeles/Oxford
205 p.
in
Tradition
TheEuropean
TheBeginnings
Science.
DavidLindberg,
Scientific
ofWestern
andInstitutional
600 B.C. toA.D. 1450. The
Context,
Philosophical,
Religious,
1992xviii& 455 p. ISBN 0 226
ofChicagoPress,Chicago/London
University
482316
d'Etienne
duaein Tholosam
et MarcvanderPoel,Les Orationes
Kenneth
Lloyd
-Jones
- Fac-Simile
de l'EditionOriginale- Traduction
Dolet(1534). Introduction
Notes.Droz,Genve1992251 p.
FranO'Rourke,PseudoandtheMetaphysics
Brill,Leiden- New
ofAquinas.
Dionysius
York- Kln 1992ISBN 90 04 094660 xvi& 300 p. (StudienundTextezur
des Mittelalters,
XXXII)
Geistesgeschichte
Literature
andTransmission.
M. Owen, TheMedieval
CanonLaw. Teaching,
Dorothy
e.a. 1990ISBN 0 521393132 xii& 82
Press,Cambridge
Cambridge
University
in Bibliography)
p. (The SandersLectures
d'Occam
deGuillaume
etleschoses.
La smantique
lesconcepts
ClaudePanaccio,Lesmots,
/ Paris1991288 p.
Bellarmin
/ Vrin,Montral
etle nominalisme
d'aujourd'hui.
ISBN 2 890077314 / 2 711694291 (Collection
Analytiques
3)
Centro
sulleideedi unalchimista
delTrecento.
MichelaPereira,L'orodeifilosofi.
Saggio
Italianadi Studisull'AltoMedievo,Spoleto1992vi & 265 p.
inMedieval
Editedby E. P. Bos and P. A.
OnProclus
andHis Influence
Philosophy.
Meijer.Brill,Leiden- NewYork- Kln1992vii& 206p. ISBN 90 04 094296
van Theodericus
en humanisme.
Een intellectuele
CatrienSanting,Geneeskunde
biografie
Rotterdam
1992312 p. ISBN 90
ErasmusPublishing,
Ulsenius
(c. 1460-1508).
5235034 5 /035 3 (Ph.D. Rijksuniversiteit
Groningen)
etdesmthodes
d'enseignement
au moyen
Vocabulaire
descoles
ge.Actesdu colloqueRome
1992220 p.
21-22octobre1989,ditsparOlga Weijers.Brepols,Turnhout
du moyen
intellectuel
ISBN 2 503370055 (CIVIMA: tudessurle vocabulaire
ge,5)

285

09:03:27 AM

You might also like