You are on page 1of 31

LEGAL RESEARCH PAPER SERIES

Paper No 15/2012 April 2012






Subsidiarity, a Political and Legal Analysis



PAUL P. CRAIG



(2012) 50 Journal of Common Market Studies 72












The full text of this paper can be downloaded without charge from the
Social Science Research Network electronic library at:
<http://ssrn.com/abstract=!"!#$$!>


An index to the working papers in the
University of Oxford Legal Research Paper Series is located at:
<http://www.ssrn.com/link/oxford-legal-studies.html>
Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2028332
1


Subsidiarity, a Political and Legal Analysis

PAUL CRAIG
St Johns College, Oxford

Introduction

Subsidiarity may well have been the word that saved the Maastricht Treaty (Cass,
1992), but the topic has remained emotive ever since. This article considers
subsidiarity from a political and a legal perspective. The discussion begins with the
historical rationales for inclusion of the subsidiarity principle in the Maastricht Treaty.
This is followed by consideration of the five principal challenges to realization of the
subsidiarity principle. The third part of the paper analyses the classic legal
perspective, which is premised on the assumption that the EU courts do not take
subsidiarity sufficiently seriously, a problem that would be obviated through more
intensive judicial review. The limitations of this thesis are explored. The final section
of the paper examines a more radical legal critique, the argument being that
subsidiarity should either be replaced or supplemented by a principle that would
enable the EU courts to monitor via proportionality the extent to which EU action
unduly intrudes on Member State values/autonomy. The legal, political and normative
difficulties with this suggestion are explored in the final section of the paper.

I Historical Rationales

Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2028332
2
It is important at the outset to reflect on the rationales for inclusion of subsidiarity
within the Maastricht Treaty. The broader historical foundations for subsidiarity have
been discussed elsewhere (Barber, 2005). We can discern a number of rationales for
subsidiarity within the EU.
First and foremost was the perceived role of subsidiarity as a mechanism for
alleviating disputes concerning the division of competence between the EC and the
Member States. Prior to the Lisbon Treaty there was no discrete body of Treaty
provisions that explicated clearly the different types of Community competence.
Different types of EC power could be discerned in different areas (Dashwood, 1996;
von Bogdandy and Bast, 2002; Schutze, 2006), but this did little to assuage Member
State concerns. The very absence of an explicit Treaty schema, combined with the
broad interpretation given to Articles 114 and 308 EC, gave rise to Member State
concerns about the expansion of EC power to the detriment of states rights, (Pollack,
1994). The picture was further complicated by inter-institutional battles over the
correct Treaty provision to be used for EU legislation in particular areas, the key
being the degree of participation and voting rights afforded to the institutional players,
(Bradley, 2011). Subsidiarity was perceived as a way of alleviating the competence
problem. The taxonomy of EC competence was still unclear post-Maastricht, but it
was felt that subsidiarity would help prevent excessive use of power by Brussels. The
S word in the Maastricht Treaty was thus important in allaying fears about the F
word, federalism. The same theme is apparent in the Lisbon Treaty, with
reinforcement of subsidiarity seen as a way to bolster the division of competence.
Secondly, subsidiarity had an important normative dimension. The divide
between shared and exclusive power was elusive and contested pre-Lisbon. This
should not conceal the relative novelty of subsidiarity as a device for distinguishing
Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2028332
3
between federal and state power. The assignment of subject matter areas to
respective spheres of government, a classic mode of federal divide, was
complemented by subsidiarity. The message was that in areas where it was difficult to
decide with exactitude the limits of federal power, subsidiarity would be used as part
of the criterion, (Bermann, 2009). This was further emphasized and reinforced by the
wording of subsidiarity: if the desired objective could be sufficiently achieved at
Member State level, it was incumbent on the EC to show that it could be better
achieved at Community level.
A third and distinctive rationale for subsidiarity was the desire to avoid
excessive centralization. Whether the fear was real or imagined, important players
perceived the EU as becoming too centralized. Some national governments in the late
1980s and 1990s were new conservatives, intent on redefining the boundaries of the
state. At the same time new areas of competence were assigned to the EU and existing
areas were expanded through Treaty amendment or judicial interpretation. The EU
was only just discovering the new mode of harmonization, such that most regulatory
initiatives were detailed and intrusive. Small wonder then that there was concern
about centralization in the broadest sense of that term, and little surprise that
subsidiarity was seen as one way of addressing the problem.
Finally, there was a further normative rationale for subsidiarity: it was
perceived as a way of enhancing pluralism and the diversity of national values. The
very idea that if an EC objective could be sufficiently achieved at national level then
this should be the regulatory route, meant not only that the task was undertaken
locally, thereby avoiding excessive centralization, but also that it could be achieved in
the way that best accorded with Member State values, provided that the Community
objective was duly attained. The 1980s and 1990s saw an upsurge in literature
4
questioning the EUs legitimacy. Scholars explored the potential for differentiated
integration, thereby avoiding unwarranted uniformity, (de Brca and Scott, 2000;
Tuytschaever, 1999). Subsidiarity provided one space in which this diversity of
national values could flourish.

II Difficulties with Realization

The balance between centralization and decentralization is endemic to any polity in
which power is divided between levels of government, (Coglianese and Nicolaidis,
2001; Kelemen, 2004). How to ensure that the division of power between the
respective levels of government is respected is an equally endemic problem, (Young,
2002). Subsidiarity was intended to aid resolution of such issues within the EU. The
effluxion of time has however revealed the difficulties with realization of these
objectives. Five such difficulties will be explored here.

Applicability of Subsidiarity pre-Lisbon

There was a paradox in the post-Maastricht world that was readily foreseeable, albeit
problematic nonetheless. The subsidiarity calculus was applicable in areas that did not
fall within the Communitys exclusive competence. The subsidiarity concept that was
intended to alleviate competence disputes between the EC and the Member States was
therefore predicated on the meaning of exclusive competence, for which the
Maastricht Treaty provided no ready definition.
This naturally led to diverse interpretation of this term. The Commission took
the view that an area fell within exclusive competence if the Treaties imposed a duty
to act (European Commission, 1994). This elastic criterion was interpreted broadly to
5
include the four freedoms, the Common Commercial Policy, competition, agriculture,
fisheries and transport policy. It might seem over expansive to include the four
freedoms within the sphere of exclusive competence, and so it is. The four freedoms
were however assigned to exclusive competence until late in the drafting of the
Constitutional Treaty, when they were shifted to shared competence. The fact remains
that until the Lisbon Treaty provided a list of exclusive competences, there was
inevitably room for disagreement as to the meaning of that term. (Toth, 1994; Steiner,
1994).
It would be wrong to suggest that the Commission stuck rigidly to the very
wide reading of exclusive competence, such as to exclude all consideration of
subsidiarity across a broad terrain of Community policy. The impact of Article 5 EC
was evident in relation to the existence and form of Community action. The
Commission considered whether action was required at Community level, and its
reasoning was included in the recitals or explanatory memorandum, (European
Commission, 2000). The uncertainty as to the meaning of exclusive competence
nonetheless cast a shadow over subsidiarity in the pre-Lisbon era.

Applicability of Subsidiarity post-Lisbon

We have already seen that a principal rationale for subsidiarity was that it would
alleviate the competence problem. The S word in the Maastricht Treaty was thus
used to allay fears about the F word, federalism. The same theme is apparent in the
Lisbon Treaty, with reinforcement of subsidiarity seen as a way to bolster the division
of competence, more especially given that the taxonomy of competence had become
clearer because of the Lisbon schema. There are however difficulties with this in the
post-Lisbon world.
6
The scope of EU competence is determined in significant part by Member
State decisions during Treaty amendment as to the subject matter over which the EU
should have competence and the type of competence that it is accorded. This is not
however the whole story. The scope of EU competence is also affected by the
interpretation accorded to Treaty provisions by the EU courts, and there is little
evidence to suggest that the EU courts take systematic cognizance of subsidiarity
when making this determination.
There is moreover a less obvious difficulty, even in relation to competence
issues that are the result of Member State choice as expressed through successive
Treaty amendment. This is in part because of the difficulties with the application of
the subsidiarity calculus, discussed below. It is however also in part because the
implicit assumption is that subsidiarity can be bolted on to the grant of any
competence with equal ease, so as to condition the exercise of EU power. This may be
true in formal terms, it is indeed the schema of the Lisbon Treaty in areas other than
exclusive competence. The reality in substantive terms is more complex.
Thus, for example, there were a plethora of reasons for according the EU
competence over social policy broadly defined, a prominent rationale being the need
to remedy the imbalance between the economic and the social within the Treaty. It
is however more difficult to apply precepts of comparative efficiency that underpin
subsidiarity to heads of competence that are social rather than economic. The very
meaning of the key phrases in Article 5(3) TEU, that the objectives of the proposed
action cannot be sufficiently achieved by the Member States and that the scale and
effects of the action require EU intervention, is more contestable when applied to the
social sphere.

7
Application of Subsidiarity

This naturally leads to the third problem, which is application of the subsidiarity
criterion judged in terms of comparative efficiency and proportionality, (Estella,
2002). Subsidiarity might mean either that the entirety of an EU objective could be
sufficiently achieved at Member State level, or that aspects such as enforcement,
oversight etc, met this criterion. The latter was more common than the former.
If the EU decided to pursue a subsidiarity strategy it had choices as to how to
do so: it might simply leave certain aspects of the regulatory regime to be dealt with at
national level; it might specify EU rules to govern all aspects of the regulatory
schema, but do so at a relatively high level of generality, thereby leaving more scope
for national input and variation; or it might pursue an admixture of both strategies.
Lighter touch intervention through directives rather regulations has been designed to
foster subsidiarity, and the EU Courts regard directives as indicative of subsidiarity in
terms of means of implementation, (T-263/07, T-374/04).
This approach is however predicated on the feasibility of the divide between
different aspects of a regulatory scheme, some regulated at EU level, others being left
to subsidiarity-based national rules. This might be the optimal way to regulate the
area. We cannot however assume that this is so. We, commentators, bear some
responsibility in this regard. We wish to be able to criticize EU policies where they
are inefficacious or badly designed. We wish also to be able criticize the EU for not
taking subsidiarity seriously. There may well be circumstances in which it is coherent
to maintain both positions.
There are, however, significant instances where the impulses cannot be
reconciled. The reality is in many areas, such as telecommunications, energy,
agriculture, the structural funds and financial services regulation that the desire to
8
foster subsidiarity, either by leaving certain aspects of the regulatory regime to
national rules, or through EU rules that govern the issues but are set at a high level of
generality so as to allow for national choice, have led to regulatory failure, with the
consequence that the rules have had to be revised and the level of EU control
ratcheted-up.
The de Larosiere Report on failures in the regulatory regime concerning
financial supervision provides merely one high profile example of this (de Larosiere,
2009, paras. 102-105). The report noted the lack of cohesiveness in EU policy, and
concluded that the principal cause stemmed from the options provided to Member
States in the enforcement of directives, which was itself the result of the discretion left
to Member States by the primary directives that governed the area. The excessive
diversity was manifest in, for example, different meanings given to core capital,
differing degrees of sectoral supervision, diverse reporting obligations, distinct
accounting provisions in areas such as pensions, and highly divergent national
transposition.
While the precise form of this regulatory failure differs in different areas, a
pattern or pathology can nonetheless be detected, (Craig, 2006). It begins with the
primary regulation, which embodies the political choices that shape the regulatory
schema. This may leave significant discretion to the Member States through
subsidiarity in the ways adumbrated above. Thus the legislation may be cast in
discretionary terms with room for national manoeuvre, and/or the enforcement regime
may be left to Member States. Problems with the application of the primary regulation
become apparent, often because of the very substantive or enforcement discretion left
to the Member States. This in turn leads to Comitology regulations, which seek to
remedy the malaise revealed in the primary regulation. The Commission is aided by
9
the ECJ, which takes a teleological interpretation of the primary regulation in order to
plug gaps. After a period of time the primary regulation is replaced. The new primary
regulation embodies lessons learned from the previous regime. Control and oversight
are ratcheted up. The new primary regulation is nonetheless shaped by the prevailing
political realities. These may dictate a shift in direction, such as from price to income
support for farmers. This legislation may be predicated on subsidiarity in substantive
and/or enforcement terms, and secondary Comitology norms combined with judicial
intervention may once again be required to close gaps revealed in the new schema.
The stages in this cycle can now be exemplified more fully in relation to the
structural funds. The primary regulation contains the political choices that shape the
policy area, (Sutcliffe, 2000). Law creates incentives or disincentives to certain types
of action. The legislation contains, for example, procedural and substantive conditions
for eligibility to funds. It specifies rules as to liability if things go wrong. The design
of the legislation is crucially important to the overall efficacy of the regime.
There is a tension in the framing of this legislation between the collective
interests of the Member States in the Council, and the interests of individual Member
States as recipients of regional funds. The Member States in their collective capacity
have an interest in the correct allocation of the EU budget. There is however a strain
between this objective, and accountability of individual Member States for the correct
disbursement of funds. Individual states sought to minimize their liability for incorrect
regional fund allocations, and this was reflected in the content of the legislation and in
the way it was applied (Committee of Independent Experts, 1999).
Thus, for example, the successive primary regulations on the structural funds
embodied commitments to concentration, additionality, partnership and programming
as ideals that shaped the collective interest in EU regional policy. The legislation
10
accorded the individual Member States significant discretion concerning the
application of these ideals in the context of project selection. The collective interest
required the proper deployment of Union resources to attain EU regional policy. This
required machinery to ensure that projects were properly monitored, and that there
was effective machinery to detect financial irregularity through audit and the like.
Individual Member States had however an incentive to avoid these constraints, more
especially where the consequences could be financial penalties imposed on the state.
This was all the more significant given that the strategy in the 1999 regulations was to
devolve more responsibility for project monitoring on the Member States, since the
Commission did not possess the resources to do the job. It was then all the more
important that the legislative rules casting the Member State as gamekeeper did not
allow it to become poacher or to turn a blind eye to poaching by others.
The tension between the collective Community interest and that of individual
Member States was particularly prevalent in relation to the output stage, in relation to
matters such as payment, monitoring, audit and the like. (Craig, 2006). There had to
be effective control systems over the disbursement of funds at national level. The
Commission sought to close the gaps through Comitology regulations, and to
incorporate these provisions in the next round of primary regulations. It was aided by
the EU courts, which made significant contributions to ensuring the efficacy of the
regulatory regime (C-271/01, C-383/06).
The importance of the cycle described above is reflected in changes to the
Financial Regulation, which contains the overarching rules applicable to the discharge
of EU policy. It was revised in 2002 in the wake of the resignation of the Santer
Commission and embodies principles concerning direct and shared administration
(Council Regulation, 2002). The 2002 Regulation was amended in 2006 and these
11
changes together with others will be enshrined in the 2012 Financial Regulation
(European Commission, 2010). Space precludes detailed consideration of these
amendments. Suffice it to say for the present that the draft Financial Regulation 2012
is designed to strengthen the controls on national bodies that implement EU policy by
establishing more detailed rules concerning matters such as sound financial
management, transparency, non-discrimination, internal control systems, accounting
systems, and external audit. Experience with the 2002 Regulation revealed
weaknesses in these respects, and the inclusion of such rules in the draft 2012
Regulation means that they will bind Member States irrespective of whether such
rules are replicated in sector specific regulations.

Taking Subsidiarity Seriously

In addition to the difficulties with the application of subsidiarity charted above there
has been concern that subsidiarity is not taken sufficiently seriously. There is little
doubt that in the early years the Commissions reasoning concerning subsidiarity was
often exiguous. The Lisbon Treaty revisions whereby greater power has been given to
national parliaments is relevant in this respect, since the Commissions reasoning will
be subject to greater and more routine scrutiny than hitherto. There have also been
other improvements.
Impact Assessment is important in this context. It began in earnest in the new
millennium (European Commission, 2002, 2007) and developed significantly since
then (European Commission, 2009). Impact assessment is a set of steps to be followed
when policy proposals are prepared, alerting political decision-makers to the
advantages and disadvantages of policy options by assessing their potential impacts.
The results of this process are presented in an Impact Assessment Report.
12
A typical Impact Assessment will address a range of issues including: the
nature and scale of the problem, how it is evolving, and who is most affected by it; the
views of the stakeholders concerned; should the Union be involved; if so, what
objectives should it set to address the problem; the main policy options for reaching
these objectives; the likely economic, social and environmental impacts of those
options; a comparison of the main options in terms of effectiveness, efficiency and
coherence in solving the problems; and the organization of future monitoring.
The Impact Assessment Report considers the very issues that are pertinent to
our inquiry. This includes the justification for EU action in terms of the need for
harmonization, and the subsidiarity calculus, which is an explicit step in the overall
Impact Assessment process. If the data in an Impact Assessment Report is felt to be
wanting in these respects, then we should press for improvement and not be satisfied
with exiguous or laconic argument. The very fact that there is a framework within
which these issues are considered is however a positive step, which facilitates scrutiny
as to the nature of the justificatory arguments and their adequacy.
This should in turn facilitate judicial review. The ECJ should be willing to
consider the adequacy of the reasoning for EU legislative action, and to look behind
the formal legislative preamble to the arguments that underpin it derived from the
Impact Assessment. It has recently made reference, albeit cautiously, to the Impact
Assessment (C-58/04). The ECJ should be mindful of the Commissions expertise as
evinced in the Impact Assessment. It should also be cognizant of the precepts in the
Treaty, which in the case of Article 114 TFEU condition EU intervention on proof
that approximation of laws is necessary for the functioning of the internal market. If
the justificatory reasoning to this effect in the Impact Assessment is wanting then the
ECJ should invalidate the relevant instrument, and thereby signal to the political
13
institutions that the Treaty precepts are taken seriously. This is equally the case in
relation to subsidiarity. If the verification or justification for EU action contained in
the Impact Assessment appear merely formal, scant or exiguous then the ECJ should
not hesitate to so conclude, thereby indicating that the enhanced role accorded to
subsidiarity in the Lisbon Treaty will be taken seriously.
There is little doubt that the Commission often believes that action at EU level
in an EU of twenty seven Member States is the only realistic way to get the job done.
The reality is, in many instances, that it is correct, more especially given the earlier
point concerning the danger of regulatory failure resulting from subsidiarity-driven
national room for manoeuvre. It should however be recognized that although the
Commission may believe that action at EU level is required, it has been willing to
craft legislation so as to meet subsidiarity concerns. The allegation is sometimes made
that the Commission will always seek harmonization, the implication being that this is
most intrusive on Member State autonomy. The assumption that EU intervention
through harmonization is necessarily more intrusive than, for example, mutual
recognition, is however mistaken, since whether it depends on the degree of
harmonization.
The recent evidence of the post-Lisbon rules indicates, moreover, that the
Commission will listen to concerns from national parliaments, even where the number
expressing such concerns has not reached the formal trigger required by the Protocol,
(European Commission, 2011). Thus during 2010 the Commission sent 82 draft
legislative acts to national parliaments for subsidiarity scrutiny, and received 211
opinions, of which 15% raised subsidiarity concerns. The number of opinions from
national parliaments on a particular draft legislative act never came close to triggering
the yellow and red card mechanisms under the Protocol on Subsidiarity. The
14
Commission nonetheless replied to each of the opinions within the broader context of
the political dialogue that it engages in with national parliaments on policy proposals.
The Commission has in addition made clear that while subsidiarity controls only
apply to draft legislative acts, it will also consider opinions of national parliaments on
other acts within the framework of the political dialogue.

Subsidiarity and Private Actors

The final tension in the application of subsidiarity is different from those considered
thus far, but equally important. The preceding discussion has focused on national
actors and institutional players. We have said little about the perceptions of private
actors. The uncomfortable fact is that many private actors regard such national
diversity negatively, because of the increased costs and uncertainty that flows from
subsidiarity.
It can be accepted that there might be situations in which private actors benefit
from diversity in the regulatory package that flows from subsidiarity. There will
however be many instances where this is not so, especially for those businesses faced
with regulatory health and safety regimes, or seeking to break down market barriers to
entry.
Each business will have its own first order preference as to the content of the
regulatory provisions for its area. Its second order preference will often be for some
real measure of certainty as to what the regulatory demands actually are, even if the
content of the measure does not meet its first order preference. It may indeed be the
case that a business faced with the choice between its first order preference applied
with a relatively high element of national variation through subsidiarity, would in fact
15
prefer its second order preference applied with a regime of greater regulatory certainty
and less subsidiarity.
Consider the preceding in the light of, for example, EU rules concerning the
regulation of the pharmaceutical sector, including the safety regime for the running of
clinical trials (Directive 2001/20). The companies undertaking such work may have
their own first order preference as to the content of the regulatory regime. They will
however also place a very high premium on certainty, on the fact that the clinical
trials run in one country really cohere with those in another, since otherwise costs
inexorably rise and there is attendant uncertainty as to what really constitutes good
clinical practice. This certainty can be undermined by subsidiarity if that takes the
form of leaving certain parts of the regulatory schema to the Member States. It can
also be undermined if subsidiarity is manifest in the form of EU rules that cover the
entire area, but are drafted so as to leave considerable discretion to the Member States
in relation to certain aspects of the regulatory regime.
Consider once again a firm seeking to break into energy markets, gas or
electricity. It will have its first order preferences as to what a regime of open energy
markets should look like and how it should be structured. It will however also place a
high premium on certainty as to what the rules are, whatsoever their content, and a
high premium on the fair application of those rules by national players in the Member
States. The latter is especially important. If the relevant regulatory package allows too
much latitude to the national players, either because the relevant rules are
insufficiently rigorous and/or because there is national latitude through subsidiarity,
then there is a danger, in some countries at least, that the regulatory schema will not
be properly applied, and that costs, direct and indirect, to business will increase
(European Commission, 2007A).
16
This private dimension to the subsidiarity debate is important in economic
terms. It also sheds light on the normative aspect of subsidiarity. We saw that part of
the subsidiarity rationale was the fostering of national diversity, and preservation of
pluralism. This is predicated on attachment to those national values, not only by those
wielding governmental power, but also by the people.
The preceding discussion reveals that attachment to the national values that
provides the foundation for subsidiarity might not be as firm or embedded as many
would like to think. It also reveals something subtly different. The benefits of
subsidiarity are equally applicable to all Member States. The private dimension of the
discussion shows, however, that whatsoever a particular private player might feel
about its own national rules, if the consequence of attachment to those rules through
subsidiarity brings uncertainty and increased costs because all other Member States
can evince a similar attachment to their national rules, then the private player will
often be sceptical as to the resultant outcome.

III Increased Intensity of Judicial Review

The standard legal response to the difficulties with subsidiarity is to argue that the EU
courts do not take subsidiarity seriously, and that this malaise would be overcome if
they increased the intensity of judicial review. Legal academics have criticized, with
justification, the low intensity judicial review of subsidiarity by EU courts (Wyatt and
Dashwood, 2006).
This critique is premised on there being a legal problem, but there is little
analysis as to how many subsidiarity cases have been brought since its introduction in
the Maastricht Treaty, and little detailed thought as to whether the results in the cases
17
were correct, or whether they would have been any different if the ECJ had engaged
in more searching judicial review.
The numbers issue reveals an interesting picture. The reality is that there
have been few subsidiarity challenges since its introduction into the Treaty, less than
twenty, which means roughly one per year. The real figure is lower, since some cases
duplicate earlier challenges; in other cases the challenge was clearly misplaced given
the relevant Treaty provisions or EU regulatory scheme; while in yet others the
Member State adduced no evidence to substantiate the subsidiarity argument. This
leaves just over ten cases in nearly twenty years where has been a real subsidiarity
challenge, (Craig and de Brca, 2011). There have been many thousands of
regulations, directives and decisions during this period, with just over ten subject to
legal challenge. The existence of ten real subsidiarity cases in twenty years is relevant
in assessing the extent of the legal subsidiarity problem.
We can now turn to the related issue, which is whether the ECJ reached the
correct result in these cases, and whether the result would have been any different if
the Court had engaged in more searching scrutiny. This is clearly an exercise on
which opinions can differ. It is nonetheless central to evaluation of the judicial record.
There is little point conducting an analysis on the implicit premise that the ECJ got it
wrong without undertaking the inquiry required to sustain such a premise. In
assessing the judicial record it is important to recognize that in a number of the real
cases the subsidiarity challenge was opposed by other Member States, who argued
that the contested EU legislation was consistent with the subsidiarity principle. Any
idea that Member States take a uniform view concerning the application of
subsidiarity in a particular case is therefore untenable. It should also be recognized
that some subsidiarity challenges were brought by private parties and received no
18
support from any Member State. This does not mean that such challenges were
misplaced. It does mean that no Member State supported the claim that the relevant
EU legislation infringed subsidiarity, (Craig and de Brca, 2011).
It is not self-evident that any of the existing cases should have been decided
differently on the facts. Nor is it obvious that any of the real subsidiarity cases would
have been decided differently if judicial review had been more intensive. It is too easy
to reason from the premise that judicial review should be more searching, to the
conclusion that the result would have been different. The premise is correct, the
conclusion is wrong. The result might be different, it might not. Thus even where the
reasoning of the Advocate General was considerably more searching than that of the
Court, as exemplified by Advocate General Maduros Opinion in Vodafone (C-58/04)
the result was the same. The reality is that whether a particular judicial decision was
right or wrong can only be determined by looking closely at the contested regulatory
scheme and deciding whether it passed the subsidiarity criterion. When judged from
this perspective it is not self-evident that any of the challenged regulations should
have fallen because of subsidiarity.
It is no answer to the preceding argument concerning the paucity of
subsidiarity challenges that it is explicable simply because of the limited intensity of
review. This will not withstand scrutiny. More intensive review may, other things
being equal, encourage judicial claims. It is nonetheless the case that the figure of
approximately ten real subsidiarity legal challenges over a twenty year period is very
low, more especially when contrasted with claims based on other heads of judicial
review. The fact that it is, for example, difficult to succeed in a proportionality claim
against EU action has not deterred claimants from bringing such actions. To put the
subsidiarity figure in perspective, there will often be more than ten legal challenges in
19
a month based on grounds of judicial review such as proportionality, notwithstanding
the difficulties of securing a positive result.
A more realistic political explanation for the relative paucity of challenges,
and the weakness of the challenges actually made, almost certainly resides elsewhere.
A Member State that raises a subsidiarity claim in a legal action will, by definition, be
faced with a recently enacted EU regulation, directive or decision. The very fact of its
enactment attests to the fact that sufficient Member States to secure a qualified
majority believed that action at EU level was required in accordance with the
subsidiarity calculus. A Member State minded to make subsidiarity a principal
element of its legal action will therefore know that its claim is almost certain to be
opposed by legal interventions from other Member States, who will contend that
action at EU level was warranted.

IV Competence-based Proportionality Review

The difficulties with legal control over subsidiarity have led some to argue that the
subsidiarity inquiry is misplaced. Thus Davies (2006) has contended that the focus
should rather be on whether the challenged EU legislation is disproportionate by
intruding too far into Member State values in relation to the objective sought to be
attained by the EU. He argues that insofar as there are problems with delimitation of
competence, subsidiarity is ill-suited to providing meaningful demarcation: it is the
wrong rule, in the wrong place at the wrong time (Davies, 2006, p. 66). Davies
contends that the central flaw is that instead of providing a method to balance
between Member State and Community interests, which is what is needed, it assumes
the Community goals, privileges their achievement absolutely, and simply asks who
should be the one to do the implementing work, (Davies, 2006, pp. 67-8). He is
20
similarly sceptical of the application of subsidiarity by the Commission in the pre-
legislative process. (Davies, 2006, p. 76). The remedy for this malaise is
proportionality. The ECJ should consider whether the importance of an EU measure is
sufficient to justify its effect on the Member States (Davies, 2006, p. 83). It should
spell out the competence function of proportionality, and the role of national
autonomy in the balance, and have a go at addressing competence concerns in this
way (Davies, 2006, p. 83). The focus should therefore be on whether the EU norm
violates proportionality by infringing too greatly on Member State values. There is
much that is of interest in this thoughtful analysis. The approach is nonetheless
problematic for the following reasons.
First, the analysis underplays the extent to which the existing Treaty schema
already balances Member State and EU interests. The division between Member State
and EU power is addressed in the heads of competence in Articles 4-5 TEU, and
Articles 2-6 TFEU. The very division between the categories of exclusive, shared and
supporting/coordinating/supplementing competence encapsulates a view as to the
respective EU and Member State interests. These choices were made after ten years of
discursive Treaty reform. Thus the denomination of certain interests as falling within
exclusive competence reflects a considered determination that in such areas the
Member States should have no legislative capacity, given the centrality of such
matters for the functioning of the EU. The concept of shared competence is predicated
on the assumption that Member States should retain competence, at least until the EU
had exercised its competence in the relevant area. The nature of the power sharing
differs as between these areas, as acknowledged by Article 2(6) TFEU. This very
diversity is a reflection of the Treaty framers views as to where the balance between
national autonomy and EU competence should lie in relation to each such subject
21
matter. In those areas where the EU only has power to support, coordinate and
supplement Member State action national autonomy is accorded a higher premium, as
reflected in the greater limits on EU action and the preclusion of harmonization.
Secondly, Davies argument misses the reality of EU decision-making. It is
predicated on subsidiarity operating such that it assumes the Community goals,
privileges their achievement absolutely, and simply asks who should be the one to do
the implementing work (Davies, 2006, p. 67), thereby precluding any balance
between EU and Member State interests, which is what Davies believes is required
(Davies, 2006, pp. 67-8). This fails to take account of the way in which the EU
objective is fashioned. The EU objective will be determined by the interplay of
political forces that shapes particular legislative initiatives in the light of the Treaty
provisions. There will be discussion as to whether the EU should act and if so how it
should it do so. These discussions will involve issues concerning the form, content
and nature of the proposed measure. Discourse on Commission proposals with the EP
and the Council will therefore take cognizance of what the Member States are willing
to accept in terms of impact on their national values and autonomy, and this will be
embodied in the resulting EU objective.
Thirdly, there are difficulties concerning the legitimacy of the role accorded to
proportionality. Proportionality fulfils an independent competence role within the
Davies schema, whereby the EU courts would determine whether the importance of
an EU measure justified its effect on the Member States (Davies, 2006, p. 83). This is
markedly different from use of proportionality within Article 5(3) TEU as part of the
subsidiarity calculus. The schema of proportionality in Article 5(3) and the Lisbon
Protocol are not framed in terms of the kind of free-standing competence-based
proportionality analysis. Nor is there any suggestion of such use of proportionality in
22
the discussions that led to the Constitutional or Lisbon Treaties. Thus Davies
conception of proportionality is premised on proportionality as a general principle of
law modified to bear the competence meaning he ascribes to it. This is problematic.
The Lisbon Treaty was the culmination of ten years of Treaty reform, with no hint of
the kind of competence-based proportionality advocated by Davies. The suggestion is
that this should nonetheless be used to supplement existing Treaty controls. There are
already concerns voiced about over-extensive use of general principles of law
(Weatherill, 2004). We should therefore be wary of introducing a novel form of
proportionality control, which is not part of the Treaty schema.
Fourthly, there are significant difficulties of adjudication. The EU courts
should on Davies view adjudicate as to whether the incursion on Member State
values is disproportionate in the light of the EU objective. This inquiry is more
difficult than other kinds of proportionality analysis. Davies approach would allow a
Member State to argue that EU legislation should be struck down as disproportionate,
because it entailed too great an intrusion on Member State values. However, the very
fact that the legislation was enacted by what would normally be qualified majority
indicates that the majority of Member States do not feel that the legislation entails too
great an incursion on national values. The representatives in the Council are the
guardians of Member State values. It would be prima facie odd and paternalistic for a
Court to say to Member States that have voted in favour of a measure and therefore do
not believe that it entails too great an incursion on Member State values/autonomy,
that the measure is nonetheless disproportionate in this regard. The fact that there is
one Member State in the political minority means that the ECJ would have to balance
not merely the EU objective versus incursion on Member State values, but also the
very fact that most Member States do not agree with the applicant state. The EU is
23
premised on collective action in which Member States have to make compromises.
Thus the mere fact that a Member State honestly believes that the legislation on which
it was outvoted in the Council involves too great an intrusion on its values, does not
ipso facto mean that this entitles it to win the legal action, nor that it should
privilege its vision of the balance between EU objectives and Member State values
over those of other Member States.
The penultimate difficulty with Davies suggestion is that it is not clear that
there is a real problem to be addressed. There is no doubt that some may feel that the
EU is doing too much or going too far. Such concerns have been endemic in EU
discourse since the Community was created. This does not however make the case for
the proportionality control that Davies advocates. It would have to be shown that there
were occasions on which such a control would have made a difference. Davies
grounds the justification for such control largely on hypothetical examples of what the
EU might do (Davies, 2006, pp. 68-9). It is, however, dangerous to fashion new legal
doctrine on the basis of hypothetical examples, more especially if one reflects on the
real world examples that we have to hand. Thus it is difficult to regard any of the
actual subsidiarity cases as ones that should have been struck down via this novel
form of proportionality competence-control. The issue is not whether a commentator
likes the particular EU regulatory provision, but whether the contested measures could
seriously have been regarded as instances where the EU legislation was
disproportionate because it involved too great an intrusion on Member State
values/autonomy etc. It is difficult to think of any instances from the real world
subsidiarity cases that would seriously be regarded as infirm in this respect.
The final difficulty with this form of proportionality analysis is that it would
be of very limited efficacy. Let us assume, contrary to the above, that there are
24
significant instances in which a competence-based form of proportionality control
would have made a difference. If this is so the proposed legal control will, however,
be of very limited efficacy. The EU enacts thousands of primary and secondary norms
every year. If there is indeed a problem of the kind that Davies argument is designed
to resolve, then judicial control will do little to cure the ills. Such control is dependent
on some one invoking the judicial machinery. The ECJ judgment will have little
precedential impact, since its ruling would be heavily fact specific. The ECJ would
decide that this particular EU regulatory intervention was disproportionate because it
involved too great an intrusion on Member State values. The limits to the efficacy of
legal controls would therefore be significant.

Conclusions

The application of subsidiarity has proven controversial in the past and this is unlikely
to alter significantly in the future. The connected aims that decisions should be made
at the most efficient level and that pluralism should thereby be enhanced are laudable.
In certain instances there may be no tension between attainment of the EU
objective and subsidiarity manifested in retention of substantive national discretion
resulting from broadly framed regulatory provisions leaving room for national choice,
or from enforcement discretion consequent on conscious assignment of this task to
national administrations. It may indeed be the optimal way of regulating the particular
area.
In other instances the fit between attainment of the EU objective and
subsidiarity has proven more problematic. A range of complex variables can affect
international institutional choice (Jupille, Mattli and Snidal, forthcoming). The
determination of which level of government is best suited for regulatory tasks can be
25
difficult, and the reality is that this decision will be coloured by what the Member
States are willing to accept in terms of the degree of regulatory control in any
particular area. The devil is almost always in the regulatory detail. The EU legislation
will embody choices and allocate risks between levels of government as to who
should bear responsibility when things go wrong. The results of these choices are
crucial to regulatory success or failure.
The stark lesson from some major areas of EU policy is that substantive or
enforcement subsidiarity has impacted negatively on regulatory efficacy. The EU
controls have had to be ratcheted up through Comitology regulations, which have then
been incorporated in later versions of the primary regulation. The very fact that the
revised primary regulation will embody political choice means that the previously
perceived problems might be only partially resolved, or new ones might be created as
a result of a change in direction in that area of EU policy.
The law in the sense of legislative design is therefore crucial. Its importance is
insufficiently appreciated and under-researched. The law in the more commonly
perceived sense of judicial review of compliance with subsidiarity has been of limited
impact for the reasons considered above. This is unlikely to change in the post-Lisbon
world, notwithstanding the enhanced role accorded to national Parliaments. The early
signs are that it will be rare indeed for the yellow and red card triggers to be met. The
Commissions willingness to consider subsidiarity concerns raised by individual
Member States is to be welcomed, although we should be mindful of the dangers of
diluting such concerns if they merely become part of the general political dialogue
between Commission and Member States.


26
References
Arnull, A., Dashwood, A., Dougan, M., Ross, M., Spaventa, E. and Wyatt, D., (2006)
Wyatt and Dashwoods European Union Law, 5
th
edn, (London: Sweet & Maxwell),
4-018-4-021.
Barber, N. (2005) The Limited Modesty of Subsidiarity. European Law Journal,
Vol. 11, pp. 308-325.
Bermann, G. (2009) National Parliaments and the Principle of Subsidiarity: An
Outsiders View. In Pernice, I. and Tanchev, E. (eds.) Ceci nest pas une Constitution
Constitutionalisation without a Constitution (Baden-Baden, 2009), pp. 155-162.
Bradley, K. (2011) Powers and Procedures in the EU Constitution: Legal Bases and
the Court. In Craig, P. and de Brca, G. (eds.) The Evolution of EU Law, 2
nd
edn,
(Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 85-110.
Cass, D. (1992) The Word that Saves Maastricht? The Principle of Subsidiarity and
the Division of Powers within the European Community. Common Market Law
Review, Vol. 29, pp. 1107-1136.
Coglianese, G. and Nicolaidis, K. (2001) Securing Subsidiarity: The Institutional
Design of Federalism in the United States and Europe. In Nicolaidis, K. and Howse,
R. (eds.) The Federal Vision, Legitimacy and Levels of Government in the United
States and the European Union (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 277-299.
Committee of Independent Experts (1999) Second Report on Reform of the
Commission, Analysis of Current Practice and Proposals for Tackling
Mismanagement, Irregularities and Fraud, 10 September.
Council (2002) Council Regulation (EC, Euratom) 1605/2002 of 25 June 2002 on the
Financial Regulation applicable to the general budget of the European Communities,
OJ 2002 OJ L248/1.
27
Court of First Instance (2009) Case T-263/07: Estonia v Commission. [2009] ECR II-
3463.
Court of First Instance (2007) Case T-374/04: Germany v Commission. [2007] ECR
II-4431.
Craig, P. (2004) Competence: Clarity, Conferral, Containment and Consideration.
European Law Review, Vol. 29, pp. 323-344.
Craig, P. (2006) EU Administrative Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press), Chap. 3.
Craig, P. and de Brca, G. (2011) EU Law, Text, Cases and Materials, 5
th
edn,
(Oxford: Oxford University Press), Chap. 3.
Dashwood, A. (1996) The Limits of European Community Powers. European Law
Review, Vol. 21, pp. 113-128.
Davies, G. (2006) Subsidiarity: The Wrong Idea, in the Wrong Place at the Wrong
Time. Common Market Law Review, Vol. 43, pp. 63-84.
de Brca, G. and Scott, J. (eds.). (2000) Constitutional Change in the EU, From
Uniformity to Flexibility? (Oxford: Hart).
de Larosiere, J. (2009) The High Level Group on Financial Supervision in the EU
(Brussels). Available at
http://ec.europa.eu/internal_market/finances/committees/index_en.htm#review
di Fabio, U. (2002) Some Remarks on the Allocation of Competences between the
European Union and its Member States Common Market Law Review, Vol. 39, pp.
1289-1301.
Estella, A. (2002) The EU Principle of Subsidiarity and its Critique (Oxford: Oxford
University Press).
European Commission (1994) 1st Report of Commission on Subsidiarity, COM(94)
533.
28
European Commission (2000) Better Lawmaking 2000, COM(2000) 772 final.
European Commission (2002) Impact Assessment, COM(2002) 276 final.
European Commission (2007) Better Regulation and Enhanced Impact Assessment,
SEC(2007) 926.
European Commission (2007A) Proposal for a Regulation of the European Parliament
and of the Council establishing an Agency for the Cooperation of Energy Regulators,
COM(2007) 530 final.
European Commission (2009) Impact Assessment Guidelines, SEC(2009) 92.
European Commission (2010) Proposal for a Regulation of the European Parliament
and of the Council on the financial rules applicable to annual budget of the Union,
COM(2010) 815.
European Commission (2011) Annual Report 2010 on Relations between the
Commission and National Parliaments, COM(2011) 345 final.
European Court of Justice (2004) Case C-271/01: Ministero delle Politiche Agricole e
Forestali v Consorzio Produttori Pompelmo Italiano Soc Coop arl (COPPI) [2004]
ECR I-1029.
European Court of Justice (2008) Cases C-383 and 384/06: Vereniging Nationaal
Overlegorgaan Sociale Werkvoorziening and Gemeente Rotterdam v Minister van
Sociale Zaken en Werkgelegenheid [2008] ECR I-1561.
European Court of Justice (2010) Case C-58/08: The Queen, on the application of
Vodafone Ltd v Secretary of State for Business, Enterprise and Regulatory Reform. 8
June.
European Parliament and Council (2001) Directive 2001/20 on the approximation of
the laws, regulations and administrative provisions of the Member States relating to
29
the implementation of good clinical practice in the conduct of clinical trials on
medicinal products for human use, OJ 2001 L121/34.
Kelemen, R.D. (2004) The Rules of Federalism, Institutions and Regulatory Politics
in the EU and Beyond (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press).
Jupille, J., Mattli, W., and Snidal, D. (forthcoming) International Institutional
Choice: Cooperation, Alternatives and Strategies.
Pollack, M. (1994) Creeping Competence: The Expanding Agenda of the European
Community. Journal of Public Policy, Vol. 14, pp. 95-145.
Schutze, R. (2006) Co-operative Federalism Constitutionalized: The Emergence of
Complementary Competences in the EC Legal Order. European Law Review, Vol.
31, pp. 167-184.
Steiner, J. (1994) Subsidiarity under the Maastricht Treaty. In O'Keeffe, D. and
Twomey, P.M. (eds.) Legal Issues of the Maastricht Treaty (Chichester:
Chancery/Wiley), pp. 49-64.
Sutcliffe, J. (2000) The 1999 Reform of the Structural Fund Regulations: Multi-Level
Governance or Renationalization?. Journal of European Public Policy, Vol. 7, pp.
290-309.
Toth, A.G. (1994) A Legal Analysis of Subsidiarity. In O'Keeffe, D. and Twomey,
P.M. (eds.) Legal Issues of the Maastricht Treaty (Chichester: Chancery/Wiley), pp.
3748.
Tuytschaever, F. (1999) Differentiation in European Union Law (Oxford: Hart).
von Bogdandy, A and Bast, J. (2002) The European Union's Vertical Order of
Competences: The Current Law and Proposals for its Reform. Common Market Law
Review, Vol. 39, pp. 227-268.
30
Weatherill, S. (2004) Competence Creep and Competence Control Yearbook of
European Law, Vol. 23.
Young, E. (2002) Protecting Member State Autonomy in the European Union: Some
Cautionary Tales from American Federalism. New York University Law Review, Vol.
77, pp. 1612-1737.

You might also like