You are on page 1of 70

Philosophy in the Present

Philosophy
in the Present

ALAIN BADIOU and SLAVOJ IEK

Edited by Peter Engelmann

Translated by
PETER THOMAS and ALBERTO TOSCANO









polity

This is an unauthorized digital transcription that consciously breaks


copyright laws. The possession of this document in any form is
illegal in most countries and may result in severe legal action taken
by the copyright holders. Although Ive tried to replicate the books
structure, the fonts and page numbers differ from the printed book.
Please report any spelling or transcription errors.
SIMON @ MARIBORCHAN.COM

First published in German as Philosophie und Aktualitt. Ein Streitgesprch


Passagen Verlag, 2005
The English edition Polity Press, 2009
Polity Press
65 Bridge Street
Cambridge CB2 1UR, UK
Polity Press
350 Main Street
Malden, MA 02148, USA
All rights reserved. Except for the quotation of short passages for the purpose of
criticism and review, no part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a
retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic,
mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without the prior permission of
the publisher.
ISBN-13: 978-0-7456-4096-9 (hardback)
ISBN-13: 978-0-7456-4097-6 (paperback)
A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library.
Designed and typeset in 12/17pt ITC Garamond Light
by Peter Ducker MISTD
Printed and bound in Great Britain
by MPG Books Limited, Bodmin, Cornwall
The publisher has used its best endeavours to ensure that the URLs for external
websites referred to in this book are correct and active at the time of going to
press. However, the publisher has no responsibility for the websites and can make
no guarantee that a site will remain live or that the content is or will remain
appropriate.
Every effort has been made to trace all copyright holders, but if any have been
inadvertently overlooked the publishers will be pleased to include any necessary
credits in any subsequent reprint or edition.
For further information on Polity, visit our website:
www.politybooks.com


Contents



Editor's Preface vii

ALAIN BADIOU
Thinking the Event 1

SLAVOJ IEK
'Philosophy is not a Dialogue' 49

Discussion 73


Editor's Preface

The former French President Franois Mitterrand was known for
inviting philosophers to the Elyse during his period in office in
order to discuss political and social questions. He thus positioned
himself in a long tradition in which enlightened power sought to
come closer to the philosophers and to draw legitimacy from this
proximity. We do not know whether or not these meetings
influenced Mitterrand's political decisions, but at least he has
remained in our memory as an intellectual president.
Whether their advice is earnestly sought or they are only used as
decoration or intellectual cover, in reality the invited intellectuals
usually don't come out of such performances particularly well.
Nevertheless, being invited to the tables of power seems to exercise
a great attraction for them.
The times when what philosophers like Simone de Beauvoir or Jean-
Paul Sartre, Michel Foucault or Jean-Franois Lyotard had to say
about contemporary events, or the suggestions they would make for
the improvement of things, were regarded as important, belong to
the past. Today, even the impersonators of philosophers who
displaced philosophers in the 1970s have themselves been replaced
by entertainers and models, by footballers and boxers.
We might therefore be tempted to speak of a golden age when the
opinion of philosophers still seemed to count; but were they really
better times?
It was not after all very long ago that we talked about what the role
of the philosopher Karl Marx had been in the totalitarian regime of

the Soviet bloc. Wasn't the mass murder Pol Pot an intellectual
educated in Paris? How many people were humiliated, expelled and
murdered during the Chinese Cultural Revolution?
The question that governs this book, whether the philosopher
should take part in contemporary events and comment on them, is
the question regarding the role of intellectuals in our society, treated
in a philosophically specific fashion. It no longer suffices to answer
that the philosophers should not only interpret the world, but rather
change it.
The answer to this question today must take into account two
extremes. On the one hand, the participation of intellectuals in the
crimes of the twentieth century weighs heavily on the self-
understanding of this social group, at least insofar as it maintains a
practical memory of history. On the other hand, we could ask
ourselves if we really get a good deal if we let models, presenters,
sportspeople and similar groups occupy the position of the
intellectual in our contemporary media society.
The answers of the Parisian philosopher Alain Badiou and the
Slovenian philosopher and psychoanalyst Slavoj iek during their
discussion of this theme in Vienna 2004 turned out to be more
modest and more sceptical than one might perhaps expect from
philosophers. Instead of taking refuge in an old glory that has long
since become historically obsolete, they try instead to recall the
specific quality of philosophical thought and derive their answers
from that.
Alain Badiou and Slavoj iek have known and esteemed one
another for a long time. Slavoj iek was continually proposing
Alain Badiou for the Passagen publishing programme. Badiou, for
his part, has been helping to translate iek's work into French.
Both know what the other will say and how he will argue, at least in

broad outlines. They are not in agreement about important


philosophical concepts and notions, as they affirm once again in this
discussion. That is the case regarding their concepts of event and the
Real, but also for their understanding of the role of the imaginary or
of politics. On the other hand, they agree that philosophical
engagement must result out of the specificity of philosophical
thought and should also establish its limits in this sense.
We owe the idea of this book to the initiative of Franois Laquieze,
the former director of the French Cultural Institute in Vienna, who
invited Alain Badiou and Slavoj iek to Vienna for a public
discussion. His partner in this initiative was Vincenc Rajp, director
of the Slovenian Scientific Institute in Vienna. The only specification
was the theme; everything else was open to discussion, which was
moderated by the Viennese journalist Claus Philipp.
During his time in Vienna, Franois Laquieze provided much
stimulus to the exchange between French and German-language
culture, and imparted a new vitality to the Institut Franais of
Vienna that is still observable in the city today. Above all, he was not
afraid to complement the usual programme of cultural institutes
with substantial contributions of contemporary thought and
philosophy. We are in his debt.
We have avoided polishing the texts for publication. We consciously
wanted to maintain the spontaneous character and not to distort the
spoken word into a systematically grounded and articulated thought-
structure. The book should, rather, stimulate contradiction, thought
and further reading.

Perhaps iek is right that philosophy is not a dialogue.


Philosophical discussion is nevertheless always stimulating, as the
presentation and now this book demonstrate.
PETER ENGELMANN

Thinking the Event


ALAIN BADIOU

Tonight, we are asking ourselves: to what extent does philosophy
intervene in the present, in historical and political questions? And in
the end, what is the nature of this intervention? Why should the
philosopher be called to intervene in questions regarding the
present? We - Slavoj iek and I - are going to introduce this
problem, and then discuss it. We are in agreement on many things,
so we can't promise you a bloody battle. But we'll see what we can
do.
There is a first, false idea that needs to be set aside, which is that the
philosopher can talk about everything. This idea is exemplified by
the TV philosopher: he talks about society's problems, the problems
of the present, and do on. Why is this idea false? Because the
philosopher constructs his own problems, he is an inventor of
problems, which is to say he is not someone who can be asked on
television, night after night, what he thinks about what's going on. A
genuine philosopher is someone who decides on his own account
what the important problems are, someone who proposes new
problems for everyone. Philosophy is first and foremost this: the
invention of new problems.
It follows that the philosopher intervenes when in the situation -
whether historical, political, artistic, amorous, scientific ... - there are
things that appear to him as signs, signs that it is necessary to invent
a new problem. That's the point, the philosopher intervenes when
he finds, in the present, the signs that point to the need for a new
problem, a new invention. The question then becomes: on what
conditions does the philosopher find, in the situation, the signs for a
new problem, for a new thought? It is with regard to this point, and

in order to lay out the grounds for our discussion, that I want to
introduce the expression 'philosophical situation'. All sorts of things
happen in the world, but not all of them are situations for
philosophy, philosophical situations. So I would like us to ask the
following question: what is a situation that is really a situation for
philosophy, a situation for philosophical thought? I am going to
offer you three examples, three examples of philosophical situations,
in order to give you some grasp of what I am referring to.
The first example is already, if I can put it like this, philosophically
formatted. It can be found in Plato's dialogue, Gorgias. This dialogue
presents the extremely brutal encounter between Socrates and
Callicles. This encounter creates a philosophical situation, which,
moreover, is set out in an entirely theatrical fashion. Why? Because
the thought of Socrates and that of Callicles share no common
measure, they are totally foreign to one another. The discussion
between Callicles and Socrates is written by Plato so as to make us
understand what it means for there to be two different kinds of
thought which, like the diagonal and the side of a square, remain
incommensurable. This discussion amounts to a relation between
two terms devoid of any relation. Callicles argues that might is right,
that the happy man is a tyrant - the one who prevails over others
through cunning and violence. Socrates on the contrary maintains
that the true man, who is the same as the happy man, is the Just, in
the philosophical sense of the term. Between justice as violence and
justice as thought there is no simple opposition, of the kind that
could be dealt with by means of arguments covered by a common
norm. There is a lack of any real relation. Therefore the discussion is
not a discussion; it is a confrontation. And what becomes clear to
any reader of the text is not that one interlocutor will convince the
other, but that there will be a victor and a vanquished. This is after
all what explains why Socrates methods in third dialogue are hardly

fairer than those of Callicles. Wanting the ends means wanting the
means, and it is a matter of winning, especially of winning in the eyes
of the young men who witness the scene.
In the end, Callicles is defeated. He doesn't acknowledge defeat, but
shuts up and remains in his corner. Note that he is the vanquished in
a dialogue staged by Plato. This is probably one of the rare
occurrences when someone like Callicles is the vanquished. Such are
the joys of the theatre.
Faced with this situation, what is philosophy? The sole task of
philosophy is to show that we must choose. We must choose
between these two types of thought. We must decide whether we
want to be on the side of Socrates or on the side of Callicles. In this
example, philosophy confronts thinking as choice, thinking as
decision. Its proper task is to elucidate choice. So that we can say the
following: a philosophical situation consists in the moment when a
choice is elucidated. A choice of existence or a choice of thought.
Second example: the death of the mathematician Archimedes.
Archimedes is one of the greatest minds ever known to humanity.
To this day, we are taken aback by his mathematical texts. He has
already reflected on the infinite, and had practically invented
infinitesimal calculus twenty centuries before Newton. He was an
exceptional genius.
Archimedes was a Greek from Sicily. When Sicily was invaded and
occupied by the Romans, he took part in the resistance, inventing
new war machines - but the Romans eventually prevailed.
At the beginning of the Roman occupation, Archimedes resumed his
activities. He was in the habit of drawing geometric figures on the
sand. One day, as he sits thinking at the sea's edge, reflecting on the
complicated figures he'd drawn on the shore, a Roman soldier

arrives, a sort of courier, telling him that the Roman General


Marcellus wishes to see him. The Romans were very curious about
Greek scientists, a little like the CEO of a multinational cosmetics
corporation might be curious about a philosopher of renown. So,
General Marcellus wants to see Archimedes. Between us, I don't
think we can imagine that General Marcellus was well up on
mathematics. Simply, and this curiosity is a credit to him, he wanted
to see what an insurgent of Archimedes' calibre was like. Whence
the currier sent to the shore. But Archimedes doesn't budge. The
soldier repeats: 'General Marcellus wishes to see you.' Archimedes
still doesn't reply. The Roman soldier, who probably didn't have any
great interest in mathematics either, doesn't understand how
someone can ignore an order from General Marcellus. 'Archimedes!
The General wishes to see you!' Archimedes barely looks up, and
says to the soldier: 'Let me finish my demonstration.' And the soldier
retorts: 'But Marcellus wants to see you! What do I care about your
demonstration!' Without answering, Archimedes resumes his
calculations. After a certain time, the soldier, by now absolutely
furious, draws his sword and strikes him. Archimedes falls dead. His
body effaces the geometrical figure in the sand.
Why is this a philosophical situation? Because it shows that between
the right of the state and creative thought, especially the pure
ontological thought embodied in mathematics, there is no common
measure, no real discussion. In the end, power is violence, while the
only constraints creative thought recognizes are its own immanent
rules. When it comes to the law of his thought, Archimedes remains
outside of the action of power. The temporality proper to the
demonstration cannot integrate the urgent summons of military
victors. That is why violence is eventually wrought, testifying that
there is no common measure and no common chronology between
the power of one side and the truths of the other. Truths as creation.

Let's recall in passing that during the US army's occupation of the


suburbs of Vienna, at the end of the Second World War, a GI killed,
obviously without recognizing who he was, the greatest musical
genius of the time, the composer Anton Webern.
An accident. An accidental philosophical situation.
We can say that between power and truths there is a distance: the
distance between Marcellus and Archimedes. A distance which the
courier - no doubt an obtuse but disciplined soldier - does not
manage to cross. Philosophy's mission is here to shed light on this
distance. It must reflect upon and think a distance without measure,
or a distance whose measure philosophy itself must invent.
First definition of the philosophical situation: clarify the choice, the
decision. Second definition of the philosophical situation: clarify the
distance between power and truths.
My third example is a film. It is an astonishing film by the Japanese
director Mizoguchi, entitled The Crucified Lovers. Without a doubt, it
is one of the most beautiful films ever made about love. The plot
can be easily summarized. The film is set in Japan's classical era, the
visual qualities of which, especially when it comes to black and
white, appear inexhaustible. A young woman is married to the owner
of a small workshop, an honest man of comfortable means, but
whom she neither loves nor desires. Enter a young man, one of her
husband's employees, with whom she falls in love. But in this
classical period, whose woman Mizoguchi celebrated both in their
endurance and their misfortune, adultery is punished by death: the
culprits must be crucified. The two lovers end up fleeing to the
countryside. The sequence which depicts their flight into the forest,
into the world of paths, cabins, lakes and boats, is truly
extraordinary. Love, prey to its own power over this hunted and
harassed couple, is enveloped in a nature as opaque as it is poetic.

All the while, the honest husband tries to protect the runaways.
Husbands have the duty to denounce adulterers, they abhor the idea
of turning into their accomplices. Nevertheless, the husband - and
this is proof indeed that he genuinely loves his wife - tries to gain
time. He pretends that his wife has left for the provinces, to see
some relatives ... A good, honest husband - really. A truly admirable
character. But all the same, the lovers are denounced, captured, and
taken to their torture.
There follow the film's final images, which constitute a new instance
of the philosophical situation. The two lovers are tied back-to-back
on a mule. The shot frames this image of the two bound lovers
going to their atrocious death; both seem enraptured, but devoid of
pathos: on their faces there is simply the hint of a smile, a kind of
withdrawal into the smile. The word 'smile' here is only an
approximation. Their faces reveal that the man and the woman exist
entirely in their love. But the film's thought, embodied in the
infinitely nuanced black and white of the faces, has nothing to do
with the romantic idea of the fusion of love and death. These
'crucified loves' never desired to die. The shot says the very
opposite: love is what resists death.
At a conference held at the Fmis, Deleuze, quoting Malraux, once
said that art is what resists death. Well, in these magnificent shots,
Mizoguchi's art not only resists death but leads us to think that love
too resists death. This creates a complicity between love and art -
one which in a sense we've always known about.
What I here name the 'smile' of the lovers, for a lack of a better
word, is a philosophical situation. Why? Because in it we once again
encounter something incommensurable, a relation without relation.
Between the event of love (the turning upside down of existence)
and the ordinary rules of live (the laws of the city, the laws of

marriage) there is no common measure. What will philosophy tell us


then? It will tell s that 'we must think the event'. We must think the
exception. We must know what we have to say about what is not
ordinary. We must think the transformation of life.
We can now sum up the tasks of philosophy with regard to
situations.
First, to throw light on the fundamental choices of thought. 'In the
last instance' (as Althusser would say) such choices are always
between what is interested and what is disinterested.
Second, to throw light on the distance between thinking and power,
between truths and the state. To measure this distance. To know
whether or not it can be crossed.
Third, to throw light on the value of exception. The value of the
event. The value of the break. And to do this against the continuity
of life, against social conservatism.
These are the three great tasks of philosophy: to deal with choice,
with distance and with the exception - at least if philosophy is to
count for something in life, to be something other than an academic
discipline.
At a deeper level, we can say that philosophy, faced with
circumstances, looks for the link between three types of situation:
the link between choice, distance and the exception. I argue that a
philosophical concept, in the sense that Deleuze speaks of it, which
is to say as a creation - is always what knots together a problem of
choice (or decision), a problem of distance (or gap), and a problem
of the exception (or event).
The most profound philosophical concepts tell us something like
this: 'If you want your life to have some meaning, you must accept

the event, you must remain at a distance from power, and you must
be firm in your decision.' This is the story that philosophy is always
telling us, under many different guises: to be in the exception, in the
sense of the event, to keep one's distance from power, and to accept
the consequences of a decision, however remote and difficult they
may prove.
Understood in this way, and only in this way, philosophy really is
that which helps existence to be changed.
Ever since Rimbaud, everyone repeats that 'the true life is absent'.
Philosophy is not worth and hour's effort if it is not based on the
idea that the true life is present. With regard to circumstances, the
true life is present in the choice, in distance and in the event.
Nevertheless, on the side of circumstances, we should not lose sight
of the fact that we are forced to make a selection in order to attain
the thought of the true life. This selection is founded, as we have
said, on the criterion of incommensurability.
What unites our three examples is the fact that they are rounded on
a relation between heterogeneous terms: Callicles and Socrates, the
Roman soldier and Archimedes, the lovers and society.
The philosophical relationship to the situation stages the impossible
relation, which takes the form of a story. We are told about the
discussion between Callicles and Socrates, we are told about the
murder of Archimedes, about the story of the crucified lovers. So,
we hear the tale of a relation. But the story shows that this relation is
not a relation, that it is the negation of relation. So that ultimately
what we are told about is a break: a break of the established natural
and social bond. But of course, in order to narrate a break, you first
need to narrate a relation. But in the end, the story is the story of a
break. Between Callicles and Socrates, one must choose. It will be

necessary to break absolutely with one of the two. Similarly, if you


side with Archimedes, you can no longer side with Marcellus. And if
you follow the lovers in their journey to its very end, never again will
you side with the conjugal rule.
So we can say that philosophy, which is the thought, not of what
there is, but of what is not what there is (not of contracts, but of
contracts broken), is exclusively interested in relations that are not
relations.
Plato once said that philosophy is an awakening. And he knew
perfectly well that awakening implies a difficult break with sleep. For
Plato already, and for all time, philosophy is the seizure by thought
of what breaks with the sleep of thought.
So it is legitimate to think that each time there is a paradoxical
relation, that is, a relation which is not a relation, a situation of
rupture, then philosophy can take place.
I insist on this point: it is not because there is 'something' that there
is philosophy. Philosophy is not at all a reflection on anything
whatsoever. There is philosophy, and there can be philosophy,
because there are paradoxical relations, because there are breaks,
decisions, distances, events.
We can throw some further light on this with examples which are
neither legends, like the death of Archimedes, nor literary
constructions, like the figure of Callicles, nor filmic poems, like the
tale of the Japanese lovers. Let's take some good, simple
contemporary examples. A negative one and a positive one.
My negative example is very simple. It concerns the reason why
philosophers in general do not have anything interesting to say about
electoral choices. Consider the usual situation of standard
parliamentarianism. When you are confronted with electoral choices

under standard parliamentarianism, you don't really possess any of


the criteria that justify and legitimate the intervention of philosophy.
I am not saying that one shouldn't be interested in these situations. I
am simply saying that one cannot be interested in them in a
philosophical manner. When the philosopher offers his views about
these matters, he is an ordinary citizen, nothing more: he does not
speak from a position of genuine philosophical consistency. So, why
are things like this? Basically, because in standard
parliamentarianism, in its usual functioning, the majority and the
opposition are commensurable. There is obviously a common
measure between the majority and the opposition, which means you
do not have the paradoxical relation. You have differences, naturally,
but these differences do not amount to a paradoxical relationship;
on the contrary, they constitute a regular, law-governed relationship.
This is easily grasped: since sooner or later (this is what is referred to
as 'democratic alternation') the opposition will replace the majority,
or take its place, it is indeed necessary for there to be a common
measure between the two. If you don't have a common measure,
you will not be able to substitute the one with the other. So the
terms are commensurable, and to the extent that they are
commensurable you do not have the situation of radical exception.
What's more, you do not have a truly radical choice: the decision is a
decision between nuances, between small differences - as you know.
Elections are generally decided by the small group of the hesitant,
those who do not possess a stable, pre-formed opinion. People who
have a genuine commitment constitute fixed blocs; then there is a
small group of people in what is called the centre, who sometimes
go one way, sometimes the other. And you can see why a decision
taken by people whose principal characteristic is hesitation is a very
particular decision; it is not a decision taken by decisive people, it is
a decision of the undecided, or of those who have not decided and

who will then decide for reasons of opportunity, or last-minute


reasons. So the function of choice in its true breadth is absent. There
is proximity, rather than distance. The election does not create a gap,
it is the rule, it creates the realization of the rule. Finally, you do not
have the hypothesis of a veritable event, you do not have the feeling
of exception, because you are instead in the presence of the feeling
of the institution, of the regular functioning of institutions. But there
is obviously a fundamental tension between institution and
exception. So the question of elections for the philosopher is a
typical matter of opinion, which is to say that it doesn't have to do
with the incommensurable, with radical choice, distance or
exception. As a phenomenon of opinion, it does not constitute a
sign for the creation of new problems.
My positive example concerns the necessity of an intervention faced
with the American was against Iraq. In the case of the American war
against Iraq, unlike in parliamentary elections, all the criteria are
brought together. First, there is something incommensurable in a
very simple sense: between American power, on the one hand, and
the Iraqi state, on the other, there is no common measure. It's not
like France and Germany during the war of 1914-18. In the war of
1914-18 there was a common measure between France and
Germany, which is precisely why you could have a world war.
Between the United States and Iraq there is no common measure of
any kind. This absence of common measure is what lent all its
significance to the whole business of 'weapons of mass destruction',
because American and British propaganda about weapons of mas
destruction sought to make people believe that there was a common
measure. If Saddam Hussein effectively had atomic, chemical and
biological weapons at his disposal, then you would have something
that legitimated the intervention, in the sense of a common measure
between American power and Iraq. You wouldn't be dealing with a

war of aggression of the very strong against the very weak, but with
legitimate defence against a measurable threat. The fact that there
were no weapons of mass destruction makes patently clear what
everyone already knew: that in this matter, there was no common
measure. Second, you have the absolute necessity of a choice. This is
the kind of situation in which it is not clear how one could be
something other than either for or against this war. This obligation
to choose is what gave the demonstrations and mobilizations against
the war their breadth. Third, you have a distance from power: the
popular demonstrations against the war create an important
subjective gap with regard to the hegemonic power of the United
States. Finally, you have, perhaps, the opening of a new situation
marked, among other things, by the importance of these
demonstrations, but also by new possibilities of common
understanding and action between France and Germany.
Finally, with regard to what is happening, you must first of all ask: 'Is
there a relation that is not a relation? Are there incommensurable
elements?' If the answer is positive, you must draw the
consequences: there is a choice, there is a distance, there is an
exception. And on these bases, you can pass from the mere
consideration of opinion to the philosophical situation. In these
conditions, we can give meaning to philosophical commitment. This
commitment creates its own conviction on the terrain of philosophy,
making use of philosophical criteria.
I insist on the singularity of philosophical commitment. We must
absolutely distinguish philosophy from politics. There are political
commitments that are illuminated by philosophy, or even made
necessary by philosophy, but philosophy and politics are distinct.
Politics aims at the transformation of collective situations, while
philosophy seeks to propose new problems for everyone. And this
proposition concerning new philosophical problems constitutes an

entirely different form of judgement than the one which pertains to


direct political militancy.
Of course, philosophy can work on the basis of political signs, it can
constitute problems using political signs. But that does not mean
that it can be confused with politics itself. This means that we can
very easily imagine that, at a given moment, certain circumstances
may be very important for politics, but not for philosophy, or vice
versa. That is why philosophical commitment can sometimes seem
very mysterious, even incomprehensible. Genuine philosophical
commitment the kind which is immersed in the incommensurable
and summons the choice of thought, staging exceptions, creating
distances and, especially, distancing from forms of power is often
a strange commitment.
There is a very interesting text by Plato on this point, a text that you
can find at the end of Book IX of the Republic. As you know, in the
Republic, Plato outlines a kind of political utopia. So that one could
precisely think that in this book philosophy and politics are very
close. At the end of Book IX, Socrates is discoursing with some
youths, as always, and some among them say to him: 'This whole
story's very nice, but it will never be realized anywhere.' The critique
of utopia was already in place. So they say to him 'Your Republic will
never exist anywhere.' And Socrates replies: 'In any case, perhaps it
will exist somewhere else than our country.' In other words, he says
that it will take place abroad, that there will be something foreign
and strange about it. I think it is very important to understand this:
genuine philosophical commitment, in situations, creates a
foreignness. In a general sense, it is foreign. And when it is simply
commonplace, when it does not possess this foreignness, when it is
not immersed in this paradox, then it is a political commitment, an
ideological commitment, the commitment of a citizen, but it is not

necessarily a philosophical commitment. Philosophical commitment


is marked by its internal foreignness.
This makes me think of a poem that I love very much, a poem by
the French poet Saint-John Perse, a great epic poem called Anabasis.
In this poem, at the end of section 5, you find the following lines,
which I'd like to read you: 'The Stranger, clothed in his new
thoughts, acquires still more partisans in the ways of silence.' This is
a definition of philosophical commitment. The philosopher is always
a stranger, clothed in his new thoughts. This means that he proposes
new thoughts and new problems. And he acquires still more partisans in
the ways of silence. This means that he is capable of rallying a great
number of people to these new problems, because he has convinced
them that these problems are universal. What matters is that those
whom the philosopher addresses are convinced first of all through
the silence of conviction and not through the rhetoric of discourse.
But as you can see, this figure of the stranger, who with his new
thoughts makes companions for himself, often silent companions,
rests entirely on the conviction that there are universal propositions,
propositions addressed to the whole of humanity, without exception.
That is why I would like to add to this reflection about the
commitment of the philosopher a necessary complement: that of a
theory of universality. For, in the end, the philosopher commits
himself with regard to a paradoxical situation in the name of
universal principles. But what precisely does this universality consist
in? I will respond in eight theses, eight theses on the universal. You
will allow me to be a little more technical, a little more conceptual. It
is something like a summary of my philosophy that I am attempting
here before you. One cannot hope for the summary of a philosophy
to be as simple as a sports summary. Even if philosophy, as Kant
said, is a combat, which is to say a sport.

Here then, bit by bit, is my definition of the universal.


Thesis 1 Thought is the proper medium of the universal
By 'thought', I mean the subject insofar as it is constituted through a
process that cuts through the totality of established knowledge. Or,
as Lacan puts it, the subject insofar as it makes a hole in knowledge.
Remarks:
(a) That thought is the proper medium of the universal means that
nothing exists as universal which takes the form of the object or of
objective regularity. The universal is essentially 'anobjective'. It can
be experienced only through the production (or reproduction) of a
trajectory of thought, and this trajectory constitutes (or
reconstitutes) a subjective disposition.
Here are two typical examples: the universality of a mathematical
proposition can only be experienced by inventing or effectively
reproducing its proof; the situated universality of a political
statement can only be experienced through the militant practice that
effectuates it.
(b) That thought, as subject-thought, is constituted through a
process means that the universal is in no way the result of a
transcendental constitution, which would presuppose a constituting
subject. On the contrary, the opening up of the possibility of a
universal is the precondition for there being a subject-thought at the
local level. The subject is invariably summoned as thought at a
specific point of that procedure through which the universal is
constituted. The universal is both what determines its own points as
subject-thoughts and the virtual recollection of these points. Thus
the central dialectic at work in the universal is that of the local as
subject and of the global as infinite procedure. This dialectic is
thought itself.

Consequently, the universality of the proposition 'the series of prime


numbers is infinite' resides in the way it enjoins us to repeat (or
rediscover) in thought a unique proof for it, but also in the global
procedure that, from the Greeks to the present day, mobilizes
number theory, along with its underlying axiomatic. To put it
another way, the universality of the practical statement 'a country's
illegal immigrant workers must have their rights recognized by that
country' resides in all sorts of militant effectuations through which
political subjectivity is actively constituted, but also in the global
process of a politics, in terms of what it prescribes concerning the
state and its decisions, rules and laws.
(c) That the process of the universal or truth they are one and the
same thing is transversal relative to all available instances of
knowledge means that the universal is always an incalculable
emergence, rather than a describable structure. By the same token, I
will say that a truth is intransitive to knowledge, and even that is
essentially unknown. That is another way of explaining what I mean
when I characterize truth as unconscious.
I will call particular whatever can be discerned in knowledge by
means of descriptive predicates. But I will call singular that which,
although identifiable as a procedure at work in a situation, is
nevertheless subtracted from every predicative description.
Accordingly, the cultural traits of this or that population are
particular. But that which, traversing these traits and deactivating
every registered description, universally summons a thought-subject,
is singular. Whence Thesis 2:

Thesis 2 Every universal is singular, or is a singularity


There is no possible universal sublation of particularity as such. It is
commonly claimed nowadays that the only genuinely universal
prescription consists in respecting particularities. In my opinion, this
thesis is inconsistent. This is demonstrated by the fact that any
attempt to put it into practice invariably runs up against
particularities which the advocates of formal universality find
intolerable. The truth is that in order to maintain that respect for
particularity is a universal value, it is necessary to have first
distinguished between good particularities and bad ones. In other
words, it is necessary to have established a hierarchy in the list of
descriptive predicates. It will be claimed, for example, that a cultural
or religious particularity is bad if it does not include within itself
respect for other particularities. But this is obviously to stipulate that
the formal universal already be included in the particularity.
Ultimately, the universality of respect for particularities is only the
universality of universality. This definition is fatally tautological. It is
the necessary counterpart of a protocol usually a violent one that
wants to eradicate genuinely particular particularities (i.e. immanent
particularities) because it freezes the predicates of the latter into self-
sufficient identitarian combinations.
This it is necessary to maintain that every universal presents itself
not as a regularization of the particular or of differences, but as a
singularity that is subtracted from identitarian predicates; although
obviously it proceeds via those predicates. The subtraction of
particularities must be opposed to their supposition. But if a
singularity can lay claim to the universal by subtraction, it is because
the play of identitarian predicates, or the logic of those forms of
knowledge that describe particularity, precludes any possibility of
foreseeing or conceiving it.

Thesis 3 Every universal originates in an event, and the event


is intransitive to the particularity of the situation
The correlation between universal and event is fundamental.
Basically, it is clear that the question of political universalism
depends entirely on the regime of fidelity or infidelity maintained,
not to this or that doctrine, but to the French Revolution, or the
Paris Commune, or October 1917, or the struggles for national
liberation, or May 1968. Contrariwise, the negation of political
universalism, the negation of the very theme of emancipation,
requires more than mere reactionary propaganda. It requires what
could be called an evental revisionism. Take, for example, Furet's
attempt to show that the French Revolution was entirely futile; or
the innumerable attempts to reduce May 1928 to a student stampede
towards sexual liberation. Evental revisionism targets the connection
between universality and singularity. To quote Mallarm, nothing
took place but the place, predicative descriptions are sufficient, and
whatever is universally valuable is strictly objective. Ultimately, this
amounts to the claim that whatever is universally valuable resides in
the mechanisms and power of capital, along with its statist
guarantees.
In that case, the fate of the human animal is sealed by the relation
between predicative particularities and legislative generalities an
animalistic fate.
For an event to initiate a singular procedure of universalization, and
to constitute its subject through that procedure, is contrary to the
positivist coupling of particularity and generality.
In this regard, the case of sexual difference is significant. The
predicative particularities identifying the positions 'man' and 'woman'
within a given society can be conceived in an abstract fashion. A
general principle can be posited whereby the rights, status,

characteristics and hierarchies associated with these positions should


be subject to egalitarian regulation by the law. That's all well and
good, but it does not provide a ground for any sort of universality as
far as the predicative distribution of gender roles is concerned. For
this to be the case, there has to be the suddenly emerging singularity
of an encounter or declaration: one that crystallizes a subject whose
manifestation is precisely its subtractive experience of sexual
difference. Such a subject comes about through an amorous
encounter in which there occurs a disjunctive synthesis of sexuated
positions. Thus the amorous scene is the only genuine scene in
which a universal singularity pertaining to the Two of the sexes
and ultimately pertaining to difference as such is proclaimed. That
is where an undivided subjective experience of absolute difference
takes place. It is well known that, where the interplay between the
sexes is concerned, people are invariably fascinated by love stories;
and this fascination is directly proportional to the various specific
obstacles through which social transformations try to thwart love. In
this instance, it is perfectly clear that the attraction exerted by the
universal lies precisely in the fact that it subtracts itself (or tries to
subtract itself) as an asocial singularity from the predicates of
knowledge.
Thus, it is necessary to maintain that the universal emerges as a
singularity and that all we have to begin with is a precarious
supplement whose sole strength lies in there being no available
predicate capable ob subjecting it to knowledge.
The question then is: What material instance, what unclassifiable
effect of presence, provides the basis for the subjectivating
procedure whose main characteristic is the universal?

Thesis 4 A universal initially presents itself as a decision about


an undecidable
This point requires careful elucidation.
I call 'encyclopaedia' the general system of predicative knowledge
internal to a situation: i.e. what everyone knows about politics,
sexual difference, culture, art, technology, etc. There are certain
things, statements, configurations or discursive fragments whose
valence is not decidable in terms of the encyclopaedia. Their valence
is uncertain, floating, anonymous: they exist at the margins of the
encyclopaedia. They comprise everything whose status remains
constitutively uncertain; everything that elicits a 'maybe, maybe not';
everything whose status can be endlessly debated according to the
rule of non-decision, which is itself encyclopaedic; everything about
which knowledge enjoins us not to decide. Nowadays, for instance,
knowledge enjoins us not to decide about God: it is quite acceptable
to maintain that perhaps 'something' exists, or perhaps it does not.
We live in a society in which no valence can be ascribed to God's
existence; one that lays claim to a vague spirituality. Similarly,
knowledge enjoins us not to decide about the possible existence of
'another politics': it is talked about, but nothing comes of it. Another
example: Are those workers who do not have proper papers but
who are working here, in France, part of this country? Do they
belong here? 'Probably, since they live and work here.' Or: 'No, since
they don't have the necessary papers to show that they are French,
or living here legally'. The term 'illegal immigrant' [clandestin]
designates the uncertainty of valence, or the nonvalence of valence:
it designates people who are living here, but don't really belong here,
and hence people who can be thrown out of the country, people
who can be exposed to the nonvalence of the valence of their
presence here as workers.

Basically, an event is what decides about a zone of encyclopaedic


indiscernibility. More precisely, there is an implicative function of
the type: E d(), which reads as: every real subjectivation brought
about by an event, which disappears in its appearance, implies that ,
which is undecidable within the situation, has been decided. This
was the case, for example, when illegal immigrant workers occupied
the church of St. Bernard in Paris: they publicly declared the
existence and valence of what had been without valence, thereby
deciding that those who are here belong here and enjoining people
to drop the expression 'illegal immigrant' [clandestin].
I will call the eventual statement. By virtue of the logical rule of
detachment, we see that the abolition of the event, whose entire being
consists in disappearing, leaves behind the evental statement ,
which is implied by the event, as something that is:
- a real of the situation (since it was already there);
- but something whose valence undergoes radical change, since it
was undecidable but has been decided. It is something that had
no valence but now does.
Consequently, I will say that the inaugural materiality for any
universal singularity is the evental statement. It fixes the present for
the subject-thought out of which the universal is woven. Such is the
case in an amorous encounter, whose subjective present is fixed in
one form or another by the statement 'I love you', even as the
circumstance of the encounter is erased. Thus, an undecidable
disjunctive synthesis is decided and the inauguration of its subject is
tied to the consequences of the evental statement.
Note that every evental statement has a declarative structure,
regardless of whether the statement takes the form of a proposition,
a work, a configuration of an axiom. The evental statement is

implied by the event's appearing-disappearing and declares that an


undecidable has been decided or that what was without valence now
has a valence. The constituted subject follows in the wake of this
declaration, which opens up a possible space for the universal.
Accordingly, all that is required in order for the universal to unfold
is to draw all the consequences, within the situation, of the evental
statement.
Thesis 5 The universal has an implicative form
A common objection to the idea of universality is that everything
that exists or is represented relates back to particular conditions and
interpretations governed by disparate forces or interests. Thus, for
instance, some maintain it is impossible to attain a universal grasp of
difference because of the abyss between the ways the latter is
grasped, depending on whether one occupies the position of 'man'
or the position of 'woman'. Still others insist that there is no
common denominator underlying what various cultural groups
choose to call 'artistic activity'; or that not even a mathematical
proposition is intrinsically universal, since its validity is entirely
dependent upon the axioms that support it.
What this hermeneutic perspectivalism overlooks is that every
universal singularity is presented as the network of consequences
entailed by an evental decision. What is universal always takes the
form , where is the evental statement and is a consequence,
or a fidelity. It goes without saying that if someone refuses the
decision about , or insists, in reactive fashion, on reducing to its
undecidable status, or maintains that what has taken on a valence
should remain without valence, then the implicative form in no way
enjoins them to accept the validity of the consequence, .
Nevertheless, even they will have to admit the universality of the
form of implication as such. In other words, even they will have to

admit that if the event is subjectivated on the basis of its statement,


whatever consequences come to be invented as a result will be
necessary.
On this point, Plato's apologia in the Meno remains irrefutable. If a
slave knows nothing about the evental foundation of geometry, he
remains incapable of validating the construction of the square of the
surface that doubles a given square. But if one provides him with the
basic data and he agrees to subjectivate it, he will also subjectivate
the construction under consideration. Thus, the implication that
inscribes this construction in the present inaugurated by geometry's
Greek emergence is universally valid.
Someone might object: 'You're making things too easy for yourself
by invoking the authority of mathematical inference.' But they would
be wrong. Every universalizing procedure is implicative. It verifies
the consequences that follow from the evental statement to which
the vanished event is indexed. If the protocol of subjectivation is
initiated under the aegis of this statement, it becomes capable of
inventing and establishing a set of universally recognizable
consequences.
The reactive denial that the event took place, as expressed in the
maxim 'nothing took place but the place', is probably the only way
of undermining a universal singularity. It refuses to recognize its
consequences and cancels whatever present is proper to the evental
procedure.
Yet even this refusal cannot cancel the universality of implication as
such. Take the French Revolution: if, from 1792 onwards, this
constitutes a radical event, as indicated by the immanent declaration
which states that revolution as such is now a political category, then
it is true that the citizen can only be constituted in accordance with
the dialectic of virtue and terror. This implication is both undeniable

and universally transmissible in the writings of Saint-Just, for


instance. But obviously, if one thinks there was no revolution, then
virtue as a subjective disposition does not exist either and all that
remains is the terror as an outburst of insanity requiring moral
condemnation. Yet even if politics disappears, the universality of the
implication that puts it into effect remains.
There is no need to invoke a conflict of interpretations here. This is
the nub of my sixth thesis:
Thesis 6 The universal is univocal
Insofar as subjectivation occurs through the consequences of the
event, there is a univocal logic proper to the fidelity that constitutes
a universal singularity.
Here we have to go back to the eventual statement. Recall that the
statement circulates within a situation as something undecidable.
There is agreement both about its existence and its undecidability.
From an ontological point of view, it is one of the multiplicities of
which the situation is composed. From a logical point of view, its
valence is intermediary or undecided. What occurs through the event
does not have to do with the being that is at stake in the event, nor
with the meaning of the eventual statement. It pertains exclusively to
the fact that, whereas previously the eventual statement had been
undecidable, henceforth it will have been decided, or decided as true.
Whereas previously the eventual statement had been devoid of
significance, it now possesses an exceptional valence. This is what
happened with the illegal immigrant workers who demonstrated
their existence at the St. Bernard church.
In other words, what affects the statement, insofar as the latter is
bound up in an implicative manner with the eventual disappearance,
is of the order of the act, rather than of being or meaning. It is

precisely the register of the act that is univocal. It just so happened


that the statement was decided, and this decision remains subtracted
from all interpretation. It relates to the yes or the no, not to the
equivocal plurality of meaning.
What we are talking about here is a logical act, or even, as one might
say echoing Rimbaud, a logical revolt. The event decides in favour of
the truth or eminent valence of that which the previous logic had
confined to the realm of the undecidable or of non-valence. But for
this to be possible, the univocal act that modifies the valence of one
of the components of the situation must gradually begin to
transform the logic of the situation in its entirety. Although the
being-multiple of the situation remains unaltered, the logic of its
appearance the system that evaluates and connects all the
multiplicities belonging to the situation can undergo a profound
transformation. It is the trajectory of this mutation that composes
the encyclopaedias universalizing diagonal.
The thesis of the equivocity of the universal refers to the universal
singularity back to those generalities whose law holds sway over
particularities. It fails to grasp the logical act that universally and
univocally inaugurates a transformation in the entire structure of
appearance.
For every universal singularity can be defined as follows: It is the act
to which a subject-thought becomes bound in such a way as to
render that act capable of initiating a procedure which effects a
radical modification of the logic of the situation, and hence of what
appears insofar as it appears.
Obviously, this modification can never be fully accomplished. For
the initial univocal act, which is always localized, inaugurates a
fidelity, i.e. an invention of consequences, which will prove to be as
infinite as the situation itself. Whence Thesis 7:

Thesis 7 Every universal singularity remains incompletable or


open
The only commentary required by this thesis concerns the manner in
which the subject, the localization of a universal singularity, is bound
up with the infinite, the ontological law of being-multiple. On this
particular issue, it is possible to show that there is an essential
complicity between the philosophies of finitude, on the one hand,
and relativism, or the negation of the universal and the discrediting
of the notion of truth, on the other. Let me put it in terms of a
single maxim: The latent violence, the presumptuous arrogance
inherent in the currently prevalent conception of human rights of
finitude and ultimately as the insistent theme of democratic
euthanasia indicates the rights of death. By way of contrast, the
eventual conception of universal singularities, as Jean- Franois
Lyotard remarked in The Differend, requires that human rights be
thought of as the rights of the infinite. One can also say: the rights
of infinite affirmation: I would say even more exactly: the rights of
the generic.
Thesis 8 Universality is nothing other than the faithful
construction of an infinite generic multiple
What do I mean by generic multiplicity? Quite simply, a subset of
the situation that is not determined by any of the predicates of
encyclopaedic knowledge; that is to say, a multiple such that to
belong to it, to be one of its elements, cannot be the result of having
an identity, of possessing any particular property. If the universal is
for everyone, this is in the precise sense that to be inscribed within it
is not a matter of possessing any particular determination. This is the
case with political gatherings, whose universality follows from their
indifference to social, national, sexual or generational origin; with the
amorous couple, which is universal because it produces an undivided

truth about the difference between sexed positions; with scientific


theory, which is universal to the extent that it removes every trace of
its provenance in its elaboration; or with artistic configurations,
whose subjects are works, and in which, as Mallarm remarked, the
particularity of the author has been abolished, so much so that in
exemplary inaugural configurations, such as the Iliad and the Odyssey,
the proper name that underlies them Homer ultimately refers
back to nothing but the void of any and every subject.
Thus the universal arises according to the chance of an aleatory
supplement. It leaves behind it a simple detached statement as a
trace of the disappearance of the event that founds it. It initiates its
procedure in the univocal act through which the valence of what was
devoid of valence comes to be decided. It binds to this act as a
subject-thought who will invent consequences for it. It faithfully
constructs an infinite generic multiplicity, which, by its very opening,
is what Thucydides declared his written history of the Peloponnesian
war unlike the latters historical particularity would be: ktema es
aiei, a possession forever.
There we are. If you combine the eight theses on the universal and
the definition of a paradoxical situations, you have the means with
which to answer the question of the commitment of philosophers in
the present.

Philosophy is not a Dialogue


SLAVOJ IEK

There will hardly be a dialogue between us because we are to a large
extent in agreement. Could that be, however to begin with a
provocation a sign of real philosophy? I am of the same opinion as
Badiou when he emphasizes, with Plato, that philosophy is
axiomatic, and asks how the true philosophy could actually be
known. Youre sitting in a caf and someone challenges you: Come
on, lets discuss that in depth! The philosopher will immediately say,
Im sorry, I must leave, and will make sure he disappears as quickly
as possible.
I have always considered Platos late dialogues to be his
philosophical dialogues in the true sense of the word. In them, one
person speaks almost without interruption; the objections of the
others in the Sophist for example, would hardly fill half a page.
They say, for example, You are completely right, Quite clearly, It
is so. And why not? Philosophy is not a dialogue. Name me a single
example of a successful philosophical dialogue that wasnt a dreadful
misunderstanding. This is true also for the most prominent cases:
Aristotle didnt understand Plato correctly; Hegel who might have
been pleased by the fact of course didnt understand Kant. And
Heidegger fundamentally didnt understand anyone at all. So, no
dialogue. But, lets go on.
I will approach the problem in the usual way. Its true: today, we
philosophers are addressed, questioned and challenged; it is expected
that we intervene, that we become engaged in the European public
sphere and so forth. How should we reach to these demands? Not
in a very different way, I think of course, not exactly the same way
for how a psychoanalyst responds to a patient: for the patient also

demands something. Only rarely does he or she exhaust these


demands. They are false demands; they allude to a real problem that
they simultaneously conceal. Lets go back to the theme of
incommensurability mentioned by Alain Badiou. In his terrific essay
about September 11, he takes up the Deleuzian concept of the
disjunctive synthesis. If one asks us philosophers something, in
general something more is involved than providing public opinion
with some orientation in a problematic situation. For example: today
we are in a war against terror, and that confronts us with daunting
problems: should we trade our freedom for security from terror?
Should we carry liberal openness to extremes even if this means
cutting off our roots and losing our identity or should we assert
our identity more strongly? To point out that the alternatives we
collectively face form a disjunctive synthesis, that is, that they are
false alternatives, has to be the first gesture of the philosopher here:
he must change the very concepts of the debate which in my
opinion represents precisely the negative of that which Badiou calls a
radical choice. In our case, concretely, it means that liberalism,
war against terror and so-called fundamentalist terrorism are all
disjunctive syntheses; they are not the radical choice. We must
change the concepts of the debate. To give a further example: in the
summer of 2003, the great European philosophers, Derrida and
Habermas, as well as some others, among whom even some
Americans, honourably intervened in the public sphere and pleaded
for a new Europe. Doesnt that speak volumes about their
philosophical positions? This is always the case: political agreement
among philosophers betrays something about their philosophy. Take
Richard Rorty, with whom philosophically I dont agree with all, but
who I regard as an intelligent liberal, not afraid of pointing out the
obvious a task that more discriminating but impotent liberals are
always too dignified to carry out. He tells us whats going on when

people like him, Derrida, Habermas and (from the cognitive field)
Daniel Dennett engage in philosophical debate. A glance at their
political positions reveals another picture: irrespective of their
philosophical positions, they are all a little to the left of the
democratic middle. On with democracy, perhaps even a little more,
is Rortys typical pragmatic conclusion. That shows that philosophy
is inconsequential. Is that really the case? Lets consider the political
agreement of Habermas and Derrida as a paradigmatic case: could
that not be an indication of the fact that their philosophical
positions are also not really incommensurable? That even their
opposition is merely a disjunctive synthesis?
If you look at the structure of their thought more closely, this
supposition is confirmed: fundamentally, both are concerned in the
same way with the problem of communication, or more precisely
with a communication that opens to the other, recognizes him and
leaves him his otherness, instead of damaging it. We are dealing
here, I believe, merely with two complementary versions, even if
Habermas claims an undamaged communication with the other and
his unique order, while Derrida emphasizes precisely the opposite:
we should open ourselves to the radical contingency of the other.
Badious great service, against these mutually complementary
positions, as it appears to me, is to have changed the entire field with
his ethics. Otherness is not the problem, but rather, the Same. For
me, this should be the philosophers first gesture, when he is
pressured with demands. To change the concepts of the debate itself
now, for example, virtual reality is a fashionable theme; we live in a
virtual universe: do we lose contact with authentic reality? Have we
completely alienated ourselves? Here we meet again the disjunctive
synthesis: we can think of postmodernists whose wonderful
nomadic subjectivity could shift from one artificial reality to the
next; or nostalgic conservatives and left-conservatives for whom that

would be a shame and who say that we must turn back instead to
authentic experience. We should do something different: namely,
reject the concepts of the debate and claim, not that virtual reality is
the problem, but rather, the reality of the virtual. How is that?
I mean: virtual reality Badiou has written that somewhere is a
relatively banal idea. It doesnt give us anything to think. Virtual
reality, that means: look how we can create with our technological
toys an appearance that in the end we believe to be reality. In my
view, it is the reality of the virtual which is interesting for thought.
The virtual is any particular thing, but nothing whole; it is if you
want the actual effect of the real. Here is the actual problem.
Lets go to the next theme that stimulates journalism: hedonism.
What is to be done when the old values fall away and humans lose
their belief, cultivate egotism and dedicate their life only to the
pursuit of pleasures? Once again, the field is divided into two camps:
every fixed moral attitude includes an act of violence Judith Butler
represents this typical postmodern attitude in her last book, still only
available in German, Zur Kritik der ethischen Gewalt
1
we must thus be
flexible and so on, which runs up against the theme of nomadic
subjectivity one again; fixed values and connections are what the
country needs that is the answer from the other side. Of course,
we should here once again tackle the problem directly and put the
concepts of the debate in question, with a type of Brechtian
Verfremdung; the thing itself will thus become strange to us: But wait
a minute? What are we speaking about here? About hedonism in a
consumer society whose chief characteristic is a radical prohibition:
enjoy immediately. It is always: Of course you should enjoy, but in
order really to be able to enjoy, first you have to go jogging, go on a
diet and you shouldnt be sexually harassing anybody. At the end is
total body discipline. But lets go back to the belief, to the clich that
today we have lost belief. This is nothing more than a pseudo-

debate: today we believe more than ever and this is the problem,
as Robert Pfaller has shown. The concepts of the debate are
therefore no longer the same. Unfortunately, however, the great
majority of philosophers havent stepped up to the challenges at this
high level, and thus they burden us with false answers.
The worst are of course answers in the style of New Age
monstrosities, which do not deserve the honour of being called
philosophy. We can all think of some interesting examples here. Try
comparing if you are old enough, which I am and also some of
you unfortunately are too a typical social sciences and humanities
bookshop of today with one from twenty-five years ago. Today,
unfortunately, there is three times as much talk of wisdom,
enlightenment and the New Age and correspondingly less of
philosophy. So much for the first false answer, which of course was
already too much anyway. Two other false answers appear to me to
be much more problematic. Which? Id like to refer here once again
to Badiou, who stresses that philosophy and politics should not be
confused with each other. He claims in his text on the end of
communism that the problem in relation to totalitarianism is that we
still dont have an appropriate socio-political theory with which we
can analyse these of course deplorable phenomena like Nazism and
Stalinism in their own conceptuality as political projects. To give a
philosophical fast food answer, passing itself off as a deep
explanation, which in truth is only a substitute that allows us to
dispense with thinking, would be the worst thing that a philosopher
can do here and unfortunately usually does. Perhaps you will be
surprised here, but my high regard for Adorno doesnt stop me from
saying that here lies the problem of the Dialectic of Enlightenment.
Instead of concrete analysis, we are offered a prime example of
philosophical (in the negative sense of the word) confusion, a type
of politico-ontological short circuit: the pseudo-transcendental

category of the project of the enlightenment is supposed to explain


immediately the totalitarian phenomena. A more recent version of
this pseudo and false philosophical gesture, whose philosophy
prevents us from thinking, is the postmodern short circuit of political
totalitarianism with the philosophical concept of totality: here one
evokes the ontological unveiling as immediate, almost transcendental
explanation of concrete political phenomena. Postmodern
philosophy offers the appearance of thought, in order to discredit
before the fact any event in the Badiouian sense of the rupturing
new. This is also what is afoot during the last ten or fifteen years in
regard to the Holocaust and other forms of unimaginable radical
evil: the prohibition to analyst these phenomena we are only
allowed to witness them, any explanation would already be a betrayal
of the victims ...
The foundation of this idea, I believe, is the idea that we have to live
with our imperfect world, since any radical alternative sooner or later
would lead to the Gulag. We are warned against any radical change.
Indeed, the whole discourse of opening ourselves to the radical
otherness is merely this warning of the radical change! So that is the
postmodern philosophical ideology. Next to this we find something
else, equally interesting: a type of neo-Kantianism. In France, it is
represented by Alain Renault, as well as Luc Ferry, who is even
Minister for Education at the moment; in Germany, its
representative is Habermas, who whether he likes it or not today,
as is well known, functions as a state philosopher; what is often only
implied was explicitly confirmed by Aznar when he suggested two
years ago the appointment of Habermas as Spains official state
philosopher. How can that be?
I have sought to solve this dilemma, as I believe, successfully. A
certain neo-Kantianism fits the definition of state philosophy
perfectly (I say that despite my love for Kant). What is the chief

function of state philosophy in the contemporary dynamic capitalist


society? It should endorse the development, indispensable for
capitalism, of new sciences, of technology and business, while at the
same time, however, it should obstruct their radical ethical and social
consequences. This is precisely what Habermas has done, at least
with his intervention in the biogenetic debate. He presents us with a
typical neo-Kantian solution: in the sciences you can do whatever
you want; remember however, that we are dealing only with the
narrow field of cognitive phenomena. The human as autonomously
acting moral subject is something else, and this field must be
defended from every threat. With that, however, all of these pseudo-
problems emerge: how far are we allowed to go into biogenetics?
Does biogenetics threaten our freedom and autonomy? In my
opinion, these are false questions; at any rate, they are not real
philosophical questions. The only real philosophical question is
instead the following: is there something in the results of biogenetics
that would force us to redefine what we understand by human
nature, by the human way of being?
It is quite sad to see how Habermas tries to control the explosive
results of biogenetics, to contain their philosophical consequences.
His whole intervention betrays the fear that something could
fundamentally change, that a new dimension of the human could
emerge and the old idea of human dignity and autonomy would not
be safely conserved. His overreactions are here characteristic, for
example, in the case of Sloterdijks Elmauer talk on biogenetics
forces us to formulate new rules of ethics, Habermas heard only the
echo of National Socialist eugenics. This attitude towards scientific
progress issues in a temptation of the temptation (to resist): the
temptation which we must resist is the pseudo-moralistic attitude
that represents the discovery of science as temptation, which lets us
go too far in the forbidden field (of biogenetic manipulation and

so forth) thus endangering the innermost core of our human being


itself.
The resent moral crisis provoked by biogenetics actually culminates
in the need for a philosophy that we are completely justified in
calling a state philosophy: a philosophy which, on the one hand,
tacitly tolerates scientific and technical progress, while on the other
hand, it tries to control its effects on our socio-symbolic order, that
is, to prevent the existing theological-ethical world picture from
changing. It is no wonder that those who go the furthest in this are
neo-Kantians: Kant himself confronted the problem of how he
could account for Newtonian science but at the same time guarantee
that there would be a realm of moral responsibility lying outside of
science. He limited the field of validity of knowledge in order to
create room for belief and morality. Dont the contemporary state
philosophers face the same task? Isnt their effort directed towards
the question of how by means of different versions of
transcendental reflection science can be limited to its fixed horizon
of meaning and its consequences can be denounced as inadmissible
for the moral-religious field? Interestingly, Sloterdijks proposal of a
humanist synthesis of new scientific truths and the old horizon of
meaning, even if he is more refined and ironic-sceptical than the
Habermasian state philosophy, only differs from it in the end by an
unverifiable line of demarcation (or to be more precise: Sloterdijks
proposal oscillates between the Habermasian compromise and the
New Age monstrosities).
While we are speaking about philosophy and politics: here, I believe,
also lies the general explanation for the demise of the Frankfurt
school. What is the outcome of the Frankfurt school? How can it be
conceptualized? Its fundamental statement is the Dialectic of
Enlightenment: the idea that the modern project of emancipation has a
structural flaw; all of these terrible things, totalitarianism and the

like, are not residues of the past, but its logical product. Let me once
more approach this like a simpleton. I would then say: Stalinist
communism had to be the prime example of this. For to say it
with extremely simplified and stupid concepts fascism was a
conservative reaction. There were people behind it who again, to
express it in an admittedly nave way intended to do something
incredibly evil and actually did it (what a surprise!). The real trauma,
however, is Stalinism. The communist project I hope you agree
with me opened with a strong emancipator potential and went
wrong. That is the trauma of the dialectic of enlightenment; but
what do we find in critical theory? Nothing of this. There is
Neumanns Behemoth, the worst type of journalistic sociology that
can be imagined, based on the fashionable idea of a convergence,
according to which Roosevelts America of the New Deal, Nazi
Germany and the Soviet Union tended towards the same organized
society. There is Marcuses Soviet Marxism: a very peculiar book,
which never precisely explains its authors position. Then there are
some attempts by Habermasians, like Andrew Aroto, to play off the
idea of civil society as place of existence against totalitarian
communist dominance. But even here we dont have any theory that
helps us to explain Stalinist communism. By the way, I believe that
the theory of civil society is completely mistaken. At any rate, I
should say that in the break-up of Yugoslavia just as in most other
conflicts between the state and civil society, I was regularly on the
side of the state. Civil society meant democratic opposition; it also
meant, however, violent nationalism. The formula of Miloevi
described precisely this highly explosive mixture of nationalist civil
society and the party nomenclature. The dissidents demanded a
dialogue between the party nomenclature and civil society, and
Miloevi actually did this.

Lets take Habermas: does reading his books betray the fact that half
of his homeland, Germany, was socialist? No. It is as if this matter
of fact didnt exist. I believe that this is, with a fashionable concept,
a type of symptomatic gap, an empty place.
I will now speak a little more briefly. I want to conclude with a
remark about the possible role of philosophy in our society. There is
a whole series of false philosophical positions: neo-Kantian state
philosophy, postmodern neo-Sophism and so forth. The worst is the
external moralization of philosophy, the logic of which is roughly
the following: I am a philosopher, and as such I devise great
metaphysical systems; I am also however a good human and am
concerned about all the disaster in this world. We must struggle
against this disaster ... Derrida is weakest at that point when, in the
middle of his book Spectres of Marx, he becomes entirely
unphilosophical and lists the disasters in this world in ten points.
Unbelievable! I didnt believe my eyes as I read that; but there they
were, ten points; and they attested to an extreme lack of though:
unemployment and dropouts without money in our cities; drug
cartels; the domination of the media monopolies and so forth. As if
he wanted to give the impression of being not merely a great
philosopher but also a warm-hearted person. Excuse me, but here I
can think of only a relatively fatal comparison: at the end of works
of popular literature there is usually a short description of the author
and in order to valorise their curriculum a little, one adds
something like: she currently lives in the South of France,
surrounded by many cats and dedicated to painting ... That is more
or less the level were dealing with. It almost prompts me therefore
to add something mischievous to my next books: In his private life
he tortures dogs and kills spiders, simply in order to push this
custom ad absurdum. But I want to go on: if we philosophers are
asked for our opinion, often all one wants in truth is that we

introduce ourselves. Our knowledge is then a type of vague


reference that gives an authority to our opinions. It is just as if one
asked a great author what he likes to eat, and he answers that Italian
cooking is better than Chinese cooking. We should therefore only
concern ourselves with what is inherent to philosophy.
What is then the role of philosophy? Here we confront a paradox:
philosophy hardly ever, and least of all in its creative periods, plays a
normal role in the sense that it is merely philosophy. Here are a
couple of unrelated facts: in the nineteenth century, literature in
some nations, like Hungary and Poland, often played the role of
philosophy; for example, the philosophical or ideological vision that
lay at the foundations of the national movement was formulated to a
large extent in literature. Even in the United States, for example, in
ninety-nine out of one hundred cases, you wont find so-called
continental philosophy in the philosophy faculties (and that is to be
taken literally: out of 4,000 US colleges with a philosophical faculty,
only fifteen to twenty of them have any real representation of
continental philosophy). Instead, we find it in cultural studies, in
English, in French and German departments. If you want to read
Hegel and Badiou, you must paradoxically choose comparative
literature with majors in French and German. If, on the other hand,
you do research on the brains of rats and perform experiments on
animals, you go to the philosophical faculties. But it is not
uncommon that philosophy occupies the place of another subject:
when, for example, communism fell apart, philosophy was the first
place in which the resistance was formulated. It was more political
than ever at this point of time. However, here you might like to
object that great German philosophy was nothing but philosophy.
Absolutely not! Already with Heine, not just with Marx, we know
that philosophy was the German substitute for the revolution. That
is the dilemma: you cant have both. It is false to claim that the

French could have had philosophy if only they had been clever
enough. Conversely, the non-appearance of the revolution was the
condition for German philosophy. My idea is now the following:
perhaps we have to break with the dream that there is a normal
philosophy. Perhaps philosophy is abnormality par excellence. Thus
I would read Badious theory. (We, Badiou and I, embrace each
other, but in reality we hate each other. Our usual joke is: if I take
power, he goes to the camps; but that is another story.) I also follow
explicitly his thesis about the conditions of philosophy: that
philosophy is by definition excessive; that it literally exists only
through the excessive connection to external conditions, which are
of either an amorous, political, scientific or artistic nature.
Lastly, another critique, even if a very friendly one: our different
assessments of Kant could represent a disagreement between us.
And I would like to ask you, perhaps only rhetorically, if you are not
also of the opinion that there is despite the many terrible things
that I too have said about a specific neo-Kantianism something in
Kant that is worth saving. What? What interests me in philosophy
above all is that moment of foreignness to which you refer. Isnt
foreignness at the beginning of philosophy? The so-called Ionian
philosophers of nature emerged in what is now Turkish Asia with
the development of commodity production. I dont want to draw
here the vulgar-Marxist parallel that commodity production means
abstraction and that his abstraction of the commodity lies at the
foundation of philosophical abstraction; where I want to steer out
interest is towards this moment of foreignness that emerges through
displacement; that philosophy this is what Heidegger wants to tell
us was from the very beginning not the discourse of those who
feel the certainty of being at home. It always required a minimum of
breakdown of the organic society. Ever since Socrates we always
meet over and again this otherness, these holes, and interestingly we

can even discover the foreign in Descartes and thus show up his
slanderers. In the second section of the Discourse on Method there
is, I think, his famous remark about how he discovered through
travel not only the foreignness of other customs, but also that ones
own culture is not less strange, even laughable, if one views it with
other eyes. That is in my opinion the zero point of philosophy.
Every philosopher adopts this place of displacement.
And now my question to you: Im tempted here to rehabilitate the
too often lightly taken Kantian concept of cosmopolitan civil
society. This concept, I believe, must be brought into connection
with Kants differentiation between public and private use of reason,
whose particularity consists in running contrary to intuition: what
Kant names the private use of reason regards the work of civil servants
in the state apparatus. Intellectual debates, even when they are
conducted in private, he calls on the other hand the public use of
reason. What is Kant getting at? The private is for him, I believe, in
the first instance the particular community rooted in a place. Kants
idea, however, is that we as intellectuals should engage in the
position of the singular universal; thus, a singularity that immediately
participates in universality, since it breaks through the idea of a
particular order. You can be a human immediately, without first
being German, French, English, etc. This legacy of Kant is more
relevant today than ever. The idea of an intellectual debate that
breaks through the particular order belies the conservative doctrine
according to which only the complete identification with ones own
roots makes it possible to be human in the emphatic sense of this
word. You are completely human only when you are completely
Austrian, Slovenian, French, and so forth. The fundamental message
of philosophy, however, says that you can immediately participate in
universality, beyond particular identifications.

Discussion

ALAIN BADIOU: First of all, I would like to say that when I have
had an occasion to criticize Kant, it was really a critique of what you
have called neo-Kantianism, that is, of that sort of academic Kant
which has made its return in these last ten or fifteen years as a kind
of official philosophy. As far as Kant is concerned, I think it is
possible to connect two of your observations. First observation:
philosophy really needs to be able to grasp that in truths, in new
problems, there is something which is irreducible to any
preconceived idea of human nature. I think this is very important:
there is something inhuman in what the philosopher deals with. We
can give it many names. For a long time, the name for what
surpasses humanity was God, the infinite, the intelligible, the
absolute, and so on. We can change these names and change our
conception, but I believe that in what philosophy deals with there is
something that is not reducible to the human, which is to say
something inhuman. Some time ago Foucault had already remarked
that, after all, man is a kind of theoretical construction with his own
history, that we could see when man, or humanism, had begun and
Foucault added: well also see when it ends. Thats my first remark.
This is what in France was called theoretical anti-humanism, which
was Foucaults position, but also that of Althusser and many others.
When you said: The true problem is knowing whether there exist or
not forms of radical modification of what we call humanity , you
posed a very profound and natural question. Because man
designates an ideological construction, a historical construction.
There is no good reason whatsoever to think that philosophy must
indefinitely be used to consolidate this construction. I think that,
ever since Plato, philosophy has been faced with the inhuman, and
that it is there that its vocation lies. Each time that philosophy

confines itself to humanity as it has been historically constituted and


defined, it diminishes itself, and in the end suppresses itself. It
suppresses itself because its only use becomes that of conserving,
spreading and consolidating the established model of humanity. The
second observation that one can connect, I think, to this one is when
you say that in Kant we find the theme of universal singularity.
Youre right. More than right, perhaps. Thats because in every great
philosopher there is the theme of the direct participation of
singularity in universality, without the detour via particularities,
cultures, nationalities, gender differences and so forth. In every great
philosopher there is a direct link between the singularity of thought
and its universality. Today, we are constantly told that particularity is
important, that the respect for particularity is fundamental. I agree
with you that we should fight this reactionary refrain of cultural
particularities. But we should add that the direct link between
singularity and universality presupposes that there is something
inhuman in universality. If we reduce universality to an ordinary
human datum, this position is no longer defensible. And I believe
that in Kant, this kind of direct relation between singularity and
universality is linked to the moment in which Kant defines the
human by means of something that exceeds humanity. The greatness
of Kant is not at all to be found in his having proposed a theory of
the limits of reason, a theory of the human limits of reason. This
aspect of Kant exists, but today it is devoid of any genuine force.
The greatness of Kant is to have combined the idea of a limit of
reason with its opposite, the idea of an excess of humanity with
regard to itself, which is given in particular in the infinite character
of practical reason. Is man destined to finitude, including the
finitude of humanity itself, of humanity as a finite humanity, or is
there instead a capacity for the infinite, that is a capacity for the
inhuman which is ultimately what philosophy is concerned with?

That is the real question. From this point of view I will answer that
yes, we can bring together your two observations, the one on the
connection between universality and singularity, on the one hand,
and the one on the necessity of overcoming humanism, on the
other. I apologize that once again I am here in agreement with my
friend Slavoj iek.
SLAVOJ IEK: Unfortunately, I must also agree with you. Marx,
in Class Struggles in France, has a very beautiful passage that explains
the political dynamic of 1848: the two royalist fractions, Bourbons
and Orleanists, united in the republican Party of Order (Parti de
lordre). Marx says that one could only be a royalist by acknowledging
the anonymous kingdom of the republic. In this sense, I agree with
you completely: the human as such appears only in the non-human;
the non-human as the only way to be human in the universal sense
in an immediate way. Why do I think that? Here I would like to
come back to Kant, since I believe that Kant provides us with the
conceptual instrument that allows us to think about this by means
of a seemingly secondary philosophical distinction, which, in my
opinion, however, is crucial for understanding him. In the Critique of
Pure Reason, he develops the distinction between a negative and an
infinite judgement. To put it simply: the negative judgement is a
judgement that denies the subject a predicate; what Kant names an
infinite judgement is the kind of judgement that ascribes to the
subject a negating predicate. A negative judgement exists when, for
example, one says: The soul is not mortal. The infinite judgement
would be: The soul is immortal. And what follows from that? Here,
horror novels could help us, if you will allow me to call on Stephen
King, my man for all seasons. We know the concept of the undead.
What does it actually mean? Dead is dead, and if someone is not
dead, they are simply alive. But when we say that someone is
undead, as is said in horror literature, that is not supposed to mean

that he still lives; he is dead, but not in the usual sense: he is the
living dead. One sees that here another realm opens up, and my idea
is that this undead is the Kantian transcendental subject. It is non-
human precisely in this sense; non-human not in the sense of the
animalistic, but rather, as the excessive dimension of the human
itself. Seen in this way, there is something unique in that which Kant
names the dimension of the transcendental. A few days ago, a friend
from Tokyo wrote to me he knows my penchant for curiosities
that in Japan one can now buy telephones for only 85 dollars that
function in a very peculiar way: you can hear the voice of the caller
clearly, but there is no longer a ring tone. You merely graft a little
disc onto your skull, and you receive the voice of the other vibrating
directly in the eardrum. You can thus hear the other but optimal
reception arises only when you shut your ears. We are dealing here
with the exception a direct sensory perception that bypasses the
sensory media. Taking a step further we can think of these
remarkable experiments in brain research which are based on the
idea that a feeling for example, desire or pain can be produced
by stimulating the nerve centre directly, without going via the five
senses. Why did I mention Kant here? You know the theory of
schematism: in order for something really to be, it must fit certain
categories. But do we not here have a type of pain that is abstract
and unschematized? Not a pain of this and that, but an immediate
pain? That is a little similar please allow me this ironic parenthesis
to the first Slovenian currency in 1990-1, after independence. I
loved this currency, certainly not due to pride that we had our own
money, but because people did not notice that there was something
a little fishy about it. After we had abolished the Yugoslav Dinar, for
two years there was money in circulation with the units five, ten and
so forth. No one remarked, however, that it didnt have a name: you
had only 500; 500 what? Nothing more. No dollars, no schillings ...

Kant opened up this realm for us. And in this sense, Lacan too, in
opposition to postmodernism, is correct: science is not merely a
language game; it deals with the unschematized Real.
BADIOU: It seems to me that the problem with philosophical
commitment is that it is often thought to be primarily critical. Very
often, one equates philosophy and critique. So that philosophical
commitment would ultimately amount to saying what is evil, what is
suffering, of saying whats not acceptable, or what is false. The task
of philosophy would be primarily negative: to entertain doubt, the
critical spirit, and so on and so forth. The essence of philosophical
intervention is really affirmation. Why is it affirmation? Because if
you intervene with respect to a paradoxical situation, or if you
intervene with regard to a relation that is not a relation, you will have
to propose a new framework of though, and you will have to affirm
that it is possible to think this paradoxical situation, on condition, of
course, that a certain number of parameters be abandoned, and a
certain number of novelties introduced. And when all is said and
done, the only proof for this is that you will propose a new way of
thinking the paradox. Consequently, the determinant element of
philosophical intervention is affirmative a point on which I agree
with Deleuze. When Deleuze says that philosophy is in its essence
the construction of concepts, he is right to put forward this creative
and affirmative dimension, and to mistrust any critical or negative
reduction of philosophy. When you just said that we should
understand inhuman as something other than a negation, I am
obviously entirely in agreement with you. Once again I regret to say
that we continue to be indefinitely in agreement, which besides
proves that we engage in affirmation and not negation. Inhuman
must be understood as the affirmative conceptual element from
within which one thinks the displacement of the human. And this
displacement of the human always presupposes that one has accepted

that the initial correlation is the link between the human and the
inhuman, and not the perpetuation of the human as such.
Let me take an ideological example. At the end of the seventies, we
witnessed the appearance, in France, of what was called nouvelle
philosophie [the new philosophy]. The real creator of nouvelle philosophie
in France was Andr Glucksmann, who just the day before had been
a Maoist: such are the reversals of History. Glucksmanns
fundamental thesis, which he continues to uphold today that is, in
his support for the USA and its war against Iraq is that it is not
possible to unify consciences around a positive vision of the Good.
One can only unify consciences in the critique of Evil: this is the
pivotal thesis of his entire intellectual itinerary. This negative
position defines a philosophical intervention of an entirely specific
sort: the philosopher is a kind of physician. He diagnoses evil,
suffering, and, if need be, he suggests remedies in order to return to
the normal state of affairs. For example: given that Saddam Hussein
is a horrifying despot, one must employ against him vigorous
therapeutic means and these were employed, as you know, at the
cost of a hundred thousand Iraqis, as of today. The American army
is in the process of killing the patient, but youve got to do what
youve got to do. Glucksmann is happy. He entirely subscribes to an
integrally critical vision of philosophical intervention.
For my part, I think it is important to defend a wholly other
conception of philosophical intervention. It is not for nothing that
the first great philosophical idea was Platos idea of the Good. Plato
had understood perfectly well that at a given moment it is the
element of inhuman affirmation which is decisive, that it is this
element which carries a radical choice. If tonight you havent exactly
witnessed a confrontation, it is because with regard to this crucial
point Slavoj and I are on the same side. So that there cant be a
major contradiction between us.

IEK: My paranoid reply to that would be: what if you are a liar
and only pretend to think like me? The more you agree with me, the
more you are in danger. Paradoxically, we share with the
postmodern critical pessimists the focus on the inhuman. In the
postmodern ideology of the inhuman, the inhuman is a terrifying
excess that must absolutely be avoided. This ideology can even
absorb a certain aspect of Lacan. There is this mythology of the
terrifying you shouldnt get too close to the fire, you have to keep
the right distance; that idea that we, as in Edgar Allan Poe, live in a
world on the edge of the abyss and that it is just a matter of
maintaining the appropriate distance: not in order to act as if there
were no radical evil, but merely in order to be sure that you dont fall
for it. That is of course the exact opposite of what we propagate as
the inhuman: the inhuman as a space of redefinition.
Here I want to go back briefly to Richard Rorty, who I admire, as I
have already said, because of his honest radicality. What is
problematic is that for him the ultimate truth consists in the truth of
the suffering of an individual: it should be open to each of us to give
expression to our specific experience of suffering. That leads us, I
think, to the assumption of a false type of incommensurability. At
the foundation of Rortys conception lies a reference to
particularism, whose disastrousness you have already criticized in
your Ethics. It is a version of political correctness: only a black,
lesbian single mother knows about the suffering of a black, lesbian
single mother and so forth. Deleuze already protested strongly
against this, because he said that this type of reference always
amounts even when it appears in the short term to be emancipator
to a reactionary position. Rortys concept of telling stories of
suffering correspondingly demands an ethics that holds the space
open in which anyone can tell their story. With this we lose any
serious concern with truth. The only bad thing, the model of moral

negativity, would be moral violence: for example, if I dictate my


concepts to others. This concept is a catastrophe. I say that even
though I often find Rortys political attitude to be congenial and
even though he is often more progressive than many of the US
American careerist deconstructionists. And I must add: perhaps this
concept is today even the true moral catastrophe, since it prevents
what you call a clear and radical choice.
Only a small improvisation: in order to confirm what you said about
the negating attitude, I have to go back again to the Frankfurt
school. Here we recognize where the mistake of this attitude lies.
What shocks me above all about Horkheimer for me it is
Horkheimer much more than Adorno who is the actual culprit is
the glaring inconsistency of two attitudes: on the one hand, he
represents the typically pessimistic perception of the dialectic of
Enlightenment: all of Western history culminates in the administered
world, the world of the completely regulated one-dimensional man, in
the technological society that leaves no space for critique and so
forth. Everything is manipulated a version of catastrophe that he
unfolded in his last big publication, Critique of Instrumental Reason.
However, whenever the same Horkheimer was confronted with a
concrete political decision, he decided for the defence of this society
of the ultimate catastrophe and spoke against any alternatives. In this
case he was completely open. For example, he didnt want to
participate in any anti-Vietnam war demonstrations and said instead:
wherever American soldiers intervene, they bring freedom. I
support that. Adorno, here a typical opportunist, wanted just as
little to take part in Vietnam war demos; it was only that he found it
difficult to say this: he took refuge instead in excuses: he said once
to the demonstrators that he would gladly come, but was too old
and fat, and anyway the people would merely laugh if he were to
come classic Adorno.

I wanted to draw attention to this paradox: one paints a bleak


picture of the catastrophe of society and at the same time any
alternative to it is supposed to be much worse. In a Spiegel interview
that was published shortly after his death, Horkheimer speaks
extensively about the administered society and continues:
nevertheless we, the developed Western society, are the island of
freedom and this should be protected all around from barbarism ...
From this, I believe, we can deduce the sad philosophical teaching
that an apparently radical condemnation of evil can perfectly take
over the function of blocking any alternatives. That is a paradox of
negating thought to which you just referred.
BADIOU: I simply wanted to say that there is a different way of
speaking about this paradox. Today there is an entire strand of
political literature which carries out a radical critique of the
economic order, but which contains a no less radical support for a
certain political form. This is absolutely common. Today,
innumerable people are fierce anti-capitalists: capitalism is frightful,
it is an economic horror, and so on. But the same people are great
defenders of democracy, of democracy in the precise sense that it
exists in our societies. In truth, we are dealing with the same paradox
as the one you highlighted: one develops a sort of radical, objective
critique of the economic form, while remaining a great supporter of
the representative democracy. There is a statement by Rorty that
really struck me, a very important statement, which says that
democracy is after all more important than philosophy. While this
statement may appear banal, its propaganda content is truly
remarkable. Can a philosopher affirm that a political form is far
more important than his own activity? I think that in fact this
strange statement carries a repressive content. It is intended to
prohibit philosophy from asking what the veritable essence of that
which today goes under the name democracy is. I would absolutely

invert the traditional approach of critique. Todays great question is


not the critique of capitalism, on which more or less the whole
world is in agreement with regard to the appalling material injustices,
the thirty million dead in Africa because they do not receive
medications, the atrocious disparities in the planet, and so on. All of
this can be referred back to capitalism, in the wish for a capitalism
that is better, a more moderate capitalism, and so on, without
advancing an inch. Because the real question is not there, it does not
lie in the negative and verbal critique of capitalism. The real question
is that of an affirmative proposition regarding democracy, as
something other than the consensus on the parliamentary form of
politics. This is what the paradox that you point to tries to conceal,
in other words, that the truly risky philosophical imperative, the one
that really poses problems for thought, is the critique of the
democratic form as we know it. That is the heart of the problem.
And it is altogether more difficult than acknowledging along with
everyone else the extent of capitalisms injustice.
IEK: Now, I think, we are touching the really delicate theme
God, its becoming boring of our agreement: delicate, because I
have paid dearly for the agreement in this case. Do you know how
much this book on Lenin cost me?
2
I lost two-thirds of my friends
because of it. You can refer to Marx without any problems: Capital
what a brilliant description of the capitalist dynamic, of the fetish-
character of the commodity, of alienation. But if you refer to
Lenin, that is another story, a completely different story. It is
unbelievable how everybody said to me afterwards that it was merely
a cheap provocation. Excuse me, but when I organized a colloquium
in Essen, as I later found out, the German secret service popped up
and asked my secretary what we were doing. You see: it is not as
tolerated as it seems. That is the paradox of todays situation:
according to the official ideology, everything is allowed, there is no

censorship, and everything goes off neatly. But we shouldnt be


deceived. Id like to give you an example, a mad but true example
that is characteristic of our time. As I heard, in some radical
communities in the US Im using the word radical here ironically,
in the sense of political correctness, which in reality is pseudo-radical
the following idea is debated in all seriousness: What about the
rights of necrophiliacs? Why are they cruelly forbidden to play sex
games with dead bodies? The suggestion is thus: some of us consent
to donating our organs to medicine in the case of an unexpected
death; why not consent to having my body played by necrophiliacs,
should I die unexpectedly? Now that sounds extremely radical, but is
really nothing more than a typical example of what Kierkegaard
correctly, I think emphasized: the only true neighbour is a dead
neighbour; at least in a certain ideological version of love for ones
neighbours. That is what we really mean today when we treat the
neighbour politically correctly. He would be better as a dead
neighbour. For me that is the best metaphor for political
correctness. Why? Lets ask ourselves: what does this form of
tolerance really mean when it is practised in our Western societies? It
means the exact opposite of what we assume. Tolerance means: no
harassment. Harassment is a key word. Fundamentally, what this
says is: hide your desire; dont come too close to me. It means, as I
have experienced in the US: If you look too long at somebody, a
woman or whoever that is already a visual harassment; if you say
something dirty that is already verbal rape. That shows us that
tolerance in this context is precisely a form of intolerance:
intolerance for the closeness of the other.
However, I would like to come back once again to my real theme.
As we have seen, all possible excesses seem to be allowed. Just try
once, however, to touch the fetish of democracy and you will see
what happens. And I agree with you: we should try to do that today,

at least to express myself briefly for three reasons. First, we have


to ask ourselves: what does democracy really mean today? How does
it function? What we can least overlook is not, for example, that it is
of the people and for the people, but rather that we accept
determinate rules that we obey whatever the result may be. For me
Bushs election victory in 2000, if it was that, was the apex of
democracy. Why? Because no democrat in any moment even
thought of not acknowledging the election result and going to the
streets even though everybody knew that they had cheated in
Florida. It was clear the whole time that despite the manipulations
there were rules that had to be upheld no matter what. And
therefore democracy means today in the first place, even in the case
of vulgar injustice, injustice rather than disorder, as Goethe is
supposed to have said. So much for the first concrete meaning of
democracy and the first reason for laying hands on it. I would see a
second reason in the fact that there is an opportunism within
democracy, an opportunism in the sense of a flight from the act.
Here I would like to cite respectfully the German theoretician of the
risk society, Ulrich Beck. He gives us to understand that the risks
that confront us today are radical risks. It is not a case of breaking
the influence of the great entrepreneurs, those who are responsible
for environmental destruction, and of bringing in specialists in order
to manage to take the correct decision; rather, it is about having to
make a choice. We are all continuously confronted with a choice in
which we must decide without any reason. Often the democratic
representatives, however, speak only to the fetish of democracy. A
way of avoiding the risk of decision is to barricade oneself behind
the voters: it is not my decision, even if I legitimate it; we are all in
the same boat ... Our second point of critique thus aims at the fact
that democracy as process of decision is a way of concealing
decisions. That looks roughly like this: I am not the one who really

decides; I only make suggestions. You, the people, are the ones who
make the decisions. Here one would rather follow Lacan, who said
that also in the political act one must take the risk completely upon
oneself. On the third reason: in The Communist Manifesto, Marx
famously wrote that communism was accused of abolishing private
property: but capitalism itself had already done that. Something
similar, I think, is happening today with democracy. There is a whole
series of symptomatic indications of this; for example, the renewed
popularity of Ralf Dahrendorf or Leo Strauss. The usual story goes
like this: democracy? Yes but only for those who are also mature
for democracy. Now, we all know what sort of a dead-end the US is
facing in Iraq. If they introduce democracy and with democracy I
dont mean any authentic form of democracy, but rather, our
beautiful, corrupt multi-party democracy that would probably
mean the electoral victory of the Shiites. And one notes all the
current rethinking; it is a key word: some US philosophers, Alan
Dershowitz for example, are of the opinion that we should rethink
human rights and change them to the extent that in certain cases
torture is permissible. Here it is not just a case of the question:
democracy or not. It is decisive to see what actually goes on in
democracy. If there is a symbolic meaning I hate the idea of
September 11, then in my opinion we should look for it in
connection with the date 1989. For me, 1989 was not the end of
utopias, as it is commonly claimed, not the end of communism, but
rather the unleashing of the great utopia of liberal capitalism, marked
by Francis Fukuyamas End of History. And September 11 is the
answer to it; if it means anything at all, it means that this utopia is
today dead. The Americans, I think, are paying the price in the
meantime: look at American politics it has been completely
transformed. We dont have to believe their phrases about
democracy any more. They want to combine their world, their

power to be able to intervene militarily in the world wherever they


want, with a new isolationism, new walls, etc. And democracy is
defined in such a radically new way in this process that only its name
remains. Something similar happens with the economy, namely, with
the WTO and the IMF. Here I agree in part with a book that, in
other respects, I fundamentally reject: Hardt and Negris Empire.
People like Lafontaine in Germany were fooling themselves if they
believed that decisions could be democratized that are made on this
economic level. How do you democratize the banking institutions?
That is impossible already for structural reasons: should for example
four and a half billion people elect the supervisory board of the
IMF? We would have to conclude: economic growth and global-
capitalist processes structurally exclude democracy even in the
form that capitalism itself ascribes to it.
We should consider all this if we are supposed to come to a decision
for or against democracy. Im inclined here to bring in Lukcs, who
said in History and Class Consciousness that it is a question of tactical
consideration. Sometimes great things are achieved in a democratic
way, for example when there is a completely unexpected result in an
election. That is for me a beautiful, almost sublime moment: when
we leftists support a good thing, but secretly believe however that
the people are too manipulated, and yet there is ultimately a miracle
and the thing goes well. My problem is, however, another one: I am
prepared to advocate my views in a democratic way; but not,
however, to allow others to decide democratically what my views are
here I confirm my philosophical arrogance.
QUESTION FROM THE AUDIENCE: Mr Badiou: if one follows
your critique of democracy, what interest can one then have in
contemporary politics? What interested you for example in the
French presidential elections?

BADIOU: What interested me in the 2002 French presidential


elections was not the electoral choice, it was not the question of
knowing whether one should vote for Chirac or Jospin, or what one
was supposed to do in the second round. I think that this kind of
question has to do with the mechanisms of opinion. What interested
me in this election was the extraordinary movement that emerged
after the first round, when Le Pen came before Jospin. The
philosophical situation was not the election itself, it was the very
animated, very violent general debate marked by demonstrations
involving hundreds of thousands which took place after the
elections. What interested the philosopher once again took the form
of a paradox: an electoral situation mutated into a completely
different situation, a situation of demonstrations, indignation, rage,
massive protest. It was that aspect which interested me. In a general
sense, philosophy is not superior to journalism when it talks about a
situation which is absolutely different from what it seems to be. That
is why I spoke of a relation which is not a relation. In my view it is
always in this paradox between being and appearing, between
relation and non-relation, that philosophical intervention is situated.
As for the rest, knowing what the ballot one is to put into the box is
a question that belongs to another register. Having said that, I can
speak to you about my personal case: I havent voted since June
1968. I am a long-term non-voter ...
QUESTION FROM THE AUDIENCE: An attempt to make a
little mischief: in ieks book The Ticklish Subject he took over some
concepts from Badiou and used them for his own theory. Badiou,
do you have the impression that this happened in an adequate way,
or did iek misunderstand you, the way Heidegger misunderstood
everybody?
BADIOU: Slavoj iek just said that Kant didnt understand
anything about Descartes, that Hegel did not understand Kant, and

finally that Heidegger didnt understand anyone ... So, if we are


Descartes and Kant, surely neither of us has understood the other!
Fortunately, we have spoken here of the commitments and
consequences of philosophy, rather than of the organization of its
concepts. So that our agreement is all the greater inasmuch as we
havent exactly entered into philosophical construction itself. When
it comes to philosophical construction itself, there are certainly great
differences between us, and that would be another debate. In
particular, I think that there are probably differences to be found in
our respective notions of the event, in our conception of the real, in
the function of the imaginary, and finally on politics, not as a
decision but as a process. I think that on all these points there could
be important discussions. But we have dealt with the question of the
present, and the question of the present is, What are the principal
forms of philosophical commitment? And it is true that when it
comes to this very important question, as weve known for some
time, were on the same side. If the word didnt have a heavy past, I
would even say: we are among party comrades.
IEK: I would like to add a word to this. It is true that I
continually engage with Badiou: in all of my books since The Ticklish
Subject I refer to his works, every new work of his leaves a trace in
mine. Im thinking for example of the book The Century, which
unfortunately still hasnt been published even thought the
manuscript has been finished for three years a crime against
humanity if we think of the significance of this book.
3
There he
develops distinctions of logic, purification and subtraction, which in
my opinion are achievements of great significance. And thus, in my
latest book, which will appear in two or three months, without
advertising myself here, Ive taken a radical step that leads away from
my usual position, a step that was very painful for me.
4
Up until
now, Ive held on the idea that the authentic experience as such, to

say it simply, is that which Lacan once called going to the end of the
analytic process; and I told myself with doubts that this process is
political, even that any political activity correlates with it. Ive now
abandoned that. I dont believe any more that the conclusion from
psychoanalysis is, if I can say it like this, the authentic form of
political engagement. That is one thing. The other is: I have taken a
further very risky step for which I will probably once again pay
dearly in my personal relations. I have openly and crudely attacked
Jacques-Alain Miller. His latest political pronouncements are, in my
view, a scandal. In his book Le Neveu de Lacan he takes up a position
against dogmatism we know these commonplaces: one should be
flexible, subversive and takes up a particularly fatal opposition that
Julia Kristeva introduced, though in another connection: the
opposition of revolts and subversion, on the one hand, and
revolution, on the other. Revolts are good, they bring creative
energy, they make things dynamic; revolution is bad, since it
introduces a new order. That is unbelievable: in a certain way, an
absolute liberal vulgarity.
With Badiou, on the other hand, I feel as Ribbentrop said to
Molotov during his trip to Moscow in 1939 among comrades.

Translators Notes
1
Shurkamp 2003. This was the printed version of Butlers Adomo-
Vorlesungen 2002 at the Institut fr Sozialforschung at the Johann
Wolfgang Goethe-Universitt, Frankfurt am Main. A reworked
version is now available in English in Giving an Account of Oneself,
New York, Fordham University Press, 2005.]
2
iek refers to Revolution at the Gates. iek on Lenin: The 1917
Writings, London: Verso, 2002.
3
Le sicle was published by ditions du Seuil in 2005; English
translation: The Century, trans. Alberto Toscano (London: Polity,
2007)
4
The Parallax View (Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 2006).

You might also like