You are on page 1of 13

Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.

com/abstract=2003531
Quadratic Vote Buying

E. Glen Weyl

February 2012
Abstract
A group of individuals with access to transfers seeks to make a binary collective decision.
All known incentive compatible mechanisms are inecient (e.g. voting), subject to severe col-
lusion problems (viz. the Vickrey-Clarke Groves mechanism) or require the planner being fully
informed about the distribution of valuations (viz. the expected externality mechanism). I
propose a simple, budget-balanced mechanism with limited potential for collusion that achieves
eciency in large markets in any Bayesian equilibrium under (conditionally) symmetric inde-
pendent private values. Individuals purchase votes with the cost of a marginal vote being
linear in the number of votes purchased; thus the total cost of votes is quadratic in the number
purchased. The revenues earned from that individual are then refunded to other individuals.
Please do not cite this extremely preliminary draft without my permis-
sion. I have made it available online at the request of several colleagues,
but it is closer to a set of personal notes than a polished paper and the
senses in which this is true are discussed throughout the paper.

I am grateful to Eduardo Azevedo, Eric Budish, Drew Fudenberg, Scott Duke Kominers, Steven Levitt and
Stephen Morris for helpful comments.

Department of Economics, University of Chicago: 1126 E. 59th Street, Chicago, IL 60637: weyl@uchicago.edu,
http://www.glenweyl.com.
1
Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2003531
(D)emocracy is the worst form of government, except for all the others that have been
tried.
Sir Winston S. Churchill
As Churchills quote emphasizes, existing mechanisms for collective decision making are un-
satisfying. Voting, while robust in many ways (Hellwig, 2003), does not incorporate intensity of
preferences and thus is rarely ecient, in the sense that it decides in favor of the option maximizing
the sum of individuals willingness-to-pay.
1
Vickrey (1961), Clarke (1971) and Groves (1973) pro-
posed a mechanism which is ecient if individuals act unilaterally, but is highly sensitive to even
two individuals colluding and often requires destroying resources (Ausubel and Milgrom, 2005). All
other mechanisms I am aware of either require the administrator to have detailed information on
the distribution of valuations or have no general benets over voting or the Vickrey-Clarke-Groves
(VCG) scheme.
2
This paper proposes a novel mechanism for binary collective decision making with
transfers that is approximately ecient in any Bayesian equilibrium with a large number of indi-
viduals that have symmetric independent private values, is budget-balanced, puts strong limits on
the potential benets from collusion by a small group and has no information requirements for the
planner.
This Quadratic Vote Buying (QVB) mechanism is simple both to describe and implement. Each
individual i may purchase any continuous number of votes v
i
for her favored outcome at a cost v
2
i
.
Whichever alternative has more votes in its favor is selected and the expenditures by individual i
is return to all individuals other than i according to some pre-specied rule, such as even division.
Why is QVB ecient? The key argument is that, in any Bayesian equilibrium in a large market,
it forces individuals to pay their expected externality on others. Suppose that the distribution of
the sum of all other individuals votes is uniform. Then the second (unit of) vote purchases the
same marginal probability of changing the outcome as the rst vote does. However, it will change
the outcome in a case when, on average, there is one unit of vote in the opposite direction while
the rst vote will change the outcome, on average, when there is one half of a unit in the opposite
direction. Thus the marginal externality created by the second vote is, assuming proportionality
between aggregate votes and values, twice that of the rst vote. The marginal price of a vote should
thus be proportional to the number of votes already purchased, just as QVB does.
This argument relied on two assumptions. First, uniformity of the distribution of the sum of
others votes. Second, proportionality of the sum of others values to the sum of their votes. The rst
assumption is valid in a large market because any individual who is a small part of a large community
must view the distribution of the sum of others values (or votes) as approximately uniform over
1
In particular, it is only ecient (in large markets) when the threshold corresponds to the quantile of the distri-
bution corresponding to its mean (Ledyard and Palfrey, 1994). In small markets, eciency is even less common.
2
For example, the Expected Externality mechanism of dAspremont and Gerard-Varet (1979) and Arrow (1979)
requires the planner to know the exact distribution of values and the linear vote buying (storable votes) procedure
of Casella (2005) does not generally improve eciency.
2
the small range her values traverse. The second assumption is valid because the derivative of a
quadratic function is linear and thus individuals equate the number of votes purchased to half the
probability of their being pivotal times their valuation.
Why is QVB budget-balanced and resilient against collusion? All revenues are refunded to one
of the individuals, ensuring budget balance. Intuitively, collusion cannot achieve much: the best any
group of individuals can do is pool all their values and act as if they were a single individual, behaving
optimally for that individual. This leads to approximately to an aggregate outcome diering from
that without a collusion by at most multiplying the inuence of the group members by the group
size and saves them at most the payments they were making without collusion. So long as the group
is small compared to the total population, both of these eects are relatively small. This contrasts
sharply with VCG where any two individuals can costlessly assure their desired outcome.
This very preliminary draft is intended only to express the basic idea of and results on the
mechanism. The draft is thus divided into three sections, following the introduction. Section 1 lays
out the model I consider and formally describes the mechanism. Section 2 proves the main results
discussed above. Section 3 discusses the directions in which I hope to extend the results in a more
developed draft. Proofs are more like sketches and all details are omitted. Those interested in the
spirit of details prior to my release of an updated draft should see Carroll (2011) who develops
many of the tools needed to ll in additional details beyond the arguments included in the text. I
am also happy to correspond with parties about my thoughts on some of these.
1 Model
There are n individuals i = 1, . . . , n. A collective decision must be made as to whether to take
an action A or not. Let 1
A
represent the indicator function for whether A is undertaken. Each
individual receives a utility u
i
1
A
t
i
where u
i
is her value and t
i
is the (net) transfer she makes.
Individuals evaluate uncertain prospects as risk-neutral expected utility maximizers. Individuals
know their own values, but not the values of other individuals. Individuals values are drawn accord-
ing to independent and identical distributions (possibly contingent on some aggregate, commonly
known statistic) with continuously dierentiable probability distribution functions f
i
with support
on an open interval in R (possibly the whole line), as in Carroll (2011). I assume that the rst two
moments of f
i
exist and are and
2
respectively. I also assume E [|u
i
|] exists and denote it by |u|.
I dene eciency of a rule for choosing A as (2 1
A
1)

i
u
i
in a particular instance and its
expected eciency as the expectation of this, while ineciency in a particular instance is
_
1

i
u
i
>0
1
A
_

i
u
i
,
and its expectation is expected ineciency. Other denitions, with the exception of the proposed
3
mechanism dened below, are omitted but are standard.
Denition 1. The Quadratic Vote Buying (QVB) mechanism with shares {s
i
}
n
i=1
has

i
s
i
= 1
and allows each individual to choose how many (positive or negative) votes v
i
to purchase. It sets
1
A
= 1

i
v
i
>0
and t
i
= v
2
i
s
i

j=i
v
2
j
1s
j
.
Before getting to our results, note that QVB is trivially budget balanced as

i
t
i
=

i
v
2
i
s
i

j=i
v
2
j
1 s
j
=

i
v
2
i

j=i
s
j
1 s
i
v
2
i
= 0.
2 Results
A simple way to analyze the equilibrium properties of QVB is to consider it from the perspective
of any individual is optimization. Let G
i
be the cumulative distribution function of equilibrium
values of V
i

j=i
v
j
, with corresponding probability density function g
i
; by independence, all
values of other individuals are independent of is value and thus, so long as v
j
is measurable with
respect to u
j
alone (as I will show it is in equilibrium), V
i
will be independent of u
i
. If individual i
purchase votes v
i
the probability of the action occurring is 1G
i
(v
i
). Thus individual is ex-ante
expected payo is, up to the receipts from others vote purchases which she cannot inuence,
u
i
_
1 G
i
(v
i
)

v
2
i
.
The rst-order condition for maximization is then
u
i
g
i
(v
i
) 2v
i
= 0 v
i
=
u
i
g
i
(v
i
)
2
. (1)
Now suppose one could show that g
i
was independent of i and v
i
, at least for v
i
(v, v). Then
one would have that v
i
= ku
i
for some k > 0 and at any equilibrium one would have eciency as
the the outcome is determined by the sign of

i
v
i
which is the same as the sign of

i
u
i
. Even
if one could only show that g
i
changed by at most a factor one could bound the ineciency of
the outcome to within this factor. The rst subsection establishes a tight bound on this factor as
the size of the market grows. The second subsection uses these results to formalize and prove my
eciency claim. The third subsection establishes the sense in which the mechanism is robust to
collusion.
2.1 Uniformity
In this subsection, I assume, based on the logic above, that v
i
= ku
i
where k is a constant to be
determined in equilibrium. Then g
i
is just the sum of n 1 i.i.d. random variables with the
4
distribution ku
i
. Carroll (2011) extensively analyzes the properties of g
i
in this case. He makes
more precise than I will in this preliminary version the sense in which the normal approximation is a
valid approximation to the properties of g
i
. From here on out I simply assume this characterization
holds. In particular, I assume g
i
is a normal distribution with mean (n 1)k and variance
(n 1)k
2

2
.
Under this assumption, lets rst calculate g
0
g
i
(0) and the necessary value of k.
g
i
(0) =
e

[k(n1)]
2
2(n1)k
2

2
k
_
2(n 1)
=
e

(n1)
2
2
2
k
_
2(n 1)
.
If g
i
(v
i
) is approximately constant over the range of interest, it is approximately constant at the
value g
0
as 0 is included in the relevant range. From the logic above
k =
g
0
2
=
e

(n1)
2
2
2
2k
_
2(n 1)
k =
e

(n1)
2
4
2

2
4
_
2(n 1)
= g
0
=
4

2e

(n1)
2
4
2

4
_
(n 1)
.
I would like to argue that g
i
(v
i
) is very at over the range spanned by likely equilibrium values
of v
i
. I focus on the case when = 0 as, intuitively this is the most challenging case for eciency;
when = 0 the vote should be overwhelmingly in one direction or the other when n is large. In
reality, I have thus far been unable to fully analyze the case the = 0 case. The last subsection of
this section provides a very informal sketch of why I believe this case is stronger for eciency, but
trickier to establish.
When = 0, the normal density is at its maximum at 0 and thus its local slope is 0. Instead
one must consider its local second derivative which is
1

2s
3
. Thus the curvature of g
i
at this
point is

2
4

2
(n 1)
3
4

3
2
e
3(n1)
2
4
2
(2)
and thus g
i
(v
i
) diers by at most
4

v
2
i
4

2(n 1)
3
4

3
2
e
3(n1)
2
4
2
from g
0
.
2.2 Eciency
When = 0 even with aggregate information, no simple rule yields eciency for large n. Total
gains in this case are of order |

i
u
i
| which is, in expectation,
_
2n

using the same central limit


theorem logic. Thus total potential eciency of the idea rule is of order

n.
5
For large n, g
i
(v
i
) g
0

n
2
v
2
i
. Because
n
0 as n grows large, one may approximate
this as
g
i
(v
i
) g
0

n
g
2
0
8
u
2
i
.
Note that the joint distribution of n

i
u
i
and n

u
3

i
u
3
i
is, letting M
i
denote the ith moment
of the distribution of u (I assume moments through the 6th exist), for large n approximately
n
_

u

u
3
_
N
_
0
M
3
,
_
n
2
nM
4
nM
4
n(M
6
M
2
3
)
__
.
Let
n
be any function of n. Then ineciency is
nE
_

u
ng
0
4

u
3

<0
_
=
n
_
E
_

u
ng
0
4

u
3

<0

>
n
_
P
_

>
n
_
+ E
_

u
ng
0
4

u
3

<0


n
_
P
_


n
_
_

n
_
E
_

u
ng
0
4

u
3

<0

>
n
_
P
_

>
n
_
+ E
_

u
ng
0
4

u
3

<0


n
__

n
_
E
_

u
ng
0
4

u
3

<0

>
n
_
P
_

>
n
_
+
n
_
. (3)
Now I focus on the rst term.
E
_

u
ng
0
4

u
3

<0

>
n
_
P
_

>
n
_
= n
_
0

_ 4
ng
0

uh
_

u,

u
3
_
d

u
3
d

u + . . . (4)
where the second term is the corresponding expression for when

u > 0 and h is the density derived
from the joint normal distribution we discussed above, which I omit writing out explicitly to save
space. I focus on the rst term of the expression; the same logic can be used to bound the second
expression.
Conditional on

u,

u
3
N
_
M
4

u,
M
6
M
2
3

M
2
4

2
n
_
and thus the conditional probability that

u
3

4
ng
0

u is
_
_

4
ng
0

M
4

M
6
M
2
3

M
2
4

2
_
_
. For large n this is approximated by
_
n

u
_
where is a group
of constants as
n
g
0
is O
_
1
n
_
. By a well-known inequality
_
n

u
_

1
n

2n

u
e

2
n
3

u
2
2
. Whenever
6

u >
n
,
_
n

u
_

1
n

2nn
e

2
n
3

2
n
2
. Thus, for large n, we can bound the rst term from the
right hand side of Equation 4 by
n
n

2n
n
e

2
n
3

2
n
2
_
0

u
ne

2
d

u =
1

2n
n
e

2
n
3

2
n
2
_
1
2n
.
Letting
n
= n

3
2
+
for any > 0, we have exponential die-o of this term. The second term of
Equation (3) then becomes n

1
2
+
, which is clearly O
_
n

1
2
+
_
and yields the following quite strong
theorem
Theorem 1. If = 0 ineciency is O
_
n

1
2
+
_
, for all > 0 while total achievable eciency is
(

n).
Thus, in the most relevant case, QVB is highly ecient in large markets: while total attainable
eciency grows with

n, the ineciency of QVB shrinks at (nearly) the same rate. Thus the
relative ineciency of QVB shrinks at a (arbitrarily close to a)
1
n
rate.
2.3 Collusion
The eectiveness of collusion against QVB is tightly bounded: at most it can multiply the inuence
of a collusive group of size m by m while increasing their payments by the same factor or have
no inuence on the outcome while eliminating all payments. Similarly, one individual who is able
to pretend to be two is at most able to double her inuence and payment. Either way, if the
collusive group or the number of individuals one person can split herself into is a small fraction
of the population, there is little eect either on eciency or on the revenues dispersed to those
outside the collusive group. This contrasts sharply with VCG, where regardless of the size of the
population, any two individuals, or any one individual pretending to be two, may achieve their
desired outcome at zero cost.
To see this, suppose some subset M of all individuals join a coalition and coordinate their actions
to maximize their joint utility. Let G
M
denote the CDF of the distribution of the sum of all votes
outside the coalition. The total expected utility of the coalition is then

iM
u
i
_
1 G
M
_

iM
v
i
__

iM
t
i
.
Let x
M


iM
x
i
for x = u, v, t. In this subsection I assume s
i

1
n
and thus that
m1
n1
of the
revenue collected from the group is remitted back to it, where m |M|. The payo of the group is
given by
u
M
_
1 G
M
(v
M
)

_
1
m1
n 1
_
_
v
2
_
M
.
7
Notice that this expression depends only on v
M
and (v
2
)
M
and always negative only the second
assuming m = n. Thus an optimal allocation of votes among the individuals in the coalition always
requires minimizing (v
2
)
M
subject to a given level of v
M
. Because the square is convex, this always
requires setting the votes of all individual in the group to be the same. I can then rewrite the payo
as
u
M
_
1 G
M
(v
M
)

_
1
m1
n 1
_
v
2
M
m
.
The rst-order condition is then
u
M
g
M
(v
M
)
2(n m)
m(n 1)
v
M
= 0 v
M
=
m(n 1)
2(n m)
u
M
g
M
(v
M
) .
When n is large (both absolutely and relative to m) this simplies to v
M
= m
u
M
g
M
(v
M
)
2
. So long
as m is not too large, by the same arguments as in Subsection 2.1, g
M
is approximately invariant
to v
M
over its range and is approximately the same as f
i
over this range. Rather than repeat
arguments similar to the previous section to provide bounds, I simply skip to the limit and assume
g
M
is identically g
0
.
The optimal strategy for the coalition is approximately v
M
= m
u
M
g
0
2
. On the other hand, if the
individuals acted non-cooperatively their net votes would be (approximately) v
M
=
u
M
g
0
2
. Thus the
impact on the aggregate vote position of the collusive group is
(m1)u
M
g
0
2
.
On the other hand, if the collusive group operated independently they would each choose v
2
i
=
u
2
i
g
2
0
4
. Thus the total change in expenditures by the collusive group are
m
2
(u
M
)
2
g
2
0
4m

(u
2
)
M
g
2
0
4
=
g
2
0
4
_
m(u
M
)
2

_
u
2
_
M

.
To interpret this quantity, note that its positive part is determined by u
M
and its negative part
by (u
2
)
M
. Thus for a given u
M
the dierence is maximized when all group members have the same
value and thus
m(u
M
)
2

_
u
2
_
M
= m(u
M
)
2
m
_
u
M
m
_
2
= (u
M
)
2
_
m
1
m
_
=
m
2
1
m
(u
M
)
2
Thus, in this case, collusion actually raises payments by approximately m(u
M
)
2
. On the other
hand suppose that u
M
= 0. Then the expression is (u
2
)
M
, which is a lower bound on how much
payments may fall. However, note that in this case v
M
= v
M
= 0. This analysis is summarized in
the following theorem.
Theorem 2. For large n, absolutely and relative to m, a coalition M of size m acting optimally
against rather than unilaterally, and assuming all other players act as in equilibrium, never leads to
ineciency greater than (m1)

iM
u
i

and thus expected ineciency is bounded by (m1)m|u|.


It also never leads to a reduction in payments greater than
f
0
4

iM
u
2
i
and thus expected reductions
8
in payments are bounded above by
mg
0(
2
+
2
)
4
. So long as m does not depend on n, all ineciency
is therefore O(1).
A similar analysis applies to de-mergers. Suppose one individual i can pretend to be c individ-
uals. By the same analysis as above, she will choose to have each of her c representatives report
(approximately)
u
i
g
0
2
and thus she will cause ineciency of at most (c 1)u
i
while increasing her
total expenditures.
Theorem 3. For large n, absolutely and relative to c, an individual i who can pretend to be c
individuals will never lead to ineciency greater than (c 1)|u| and thus will not cause expected
ineciency greater than (c 1)E[|u|]. The individuals payments will always increase. Again if m
is not a function of n, lost revenues are O(1).
This compares to VCG where if the value space is unbounded, a collusion of any two individuals
can cause arbitrarily large ineciency (ineciency up to the total gains relative to a random rule).
Such ineciency is clearly (

n) if = 0 and (n) if = 0. If the value space is bounded then it


causes expected ineciency bounded only by the m1, or c 1, times the size of the value space,
which is typically much larger than u.
2.4 = 0
When = 0, it is more challenging to explicitly solve for the approximate equilibrium with a large
number of voters because second-order terms become relevant. However, I believe that eciency is
even more secure in this case and that ineciency dies o exponentially, the same as it would in
the rule which makes the decision in favor the ex-ante optimum. I have not had time to analyze
this case in detail, but provide a brief and informal sketch of my logic here.
Votes v
i
must be i.i.d. across voters by symmetry and thus the sum of distribution of n 1
individuals votes must be approximately normal by the central limit theorem. This leaves only
three possibilities:
1. The vote distribution puts exponentially all the weight in the limit on the ecient outcome.
In this case the result holds.
2. The vote distribution puts exponentially all the weight in the limit on the inecient outcome.
In this case, it must be that the mean of the normal distribution is on the opposite side of
0 from the mean of the value distribution. If this is the case, though, then the probability
of pivotality/a tie is always higher for individuals purchasing votes in the direction of the
ecient outcome. Thus they will purchase more votes per unit of utility than those going in
the wrong direction. But given that they are already with very high probability generate more
aggregate utility, this contradicts the possibility that an inecient outcome is exponentially
more likely.
9
3. The vote distribution puts some not-exponentially-small weight in the limit on both outcomes.
In this case, the probability of pivotality must not decline exponentially quickly. This means
that the distribution must become very at about the pivotal event, as in our argument above,
thereby establishing that (to the rst-order) individuals purchase votes proportional to their
utilities. But given that these utilities have a non-zero mean and the number of individuals is
growing either the mean of votes must grow large relative to the standard deviation and thus
the probability of the election going the wrong way must become exponentially small.
3 Conclusion
This extremely preliminary draft proposes a mechanism and sketches an argument for a number of
its attractive features. My rst goal in a future draft is to make the claims about the mechanism and
the arguments for these claims both more precise, while strengthening the eciency and collusion
bounds obtained. In particular, an analysis for the = 0 case is basely needed. This should be
available by the fall of 2012. However, I also hope to explore a range of other issues related to the
mechanism, either in a future version of this paper or in a follow-on related paper, by mid-2013.
These include:
I hope to extend the mechanism to case when there are several alternatives. I believe this
should be possible by allowing individuals to purchase votes in the decision for each pairwise
comparison between alternatives, as individuals will agree on (and view as locally uniform)
the probability of that binary comparison being close and binding. I also hope to explore
whether there is a way to simplify the mechanism in cases of a large number of alternatives,
to avoid individuals having to consider the large set of binary comparisons.
I hope to show how the mechanism can work in settings without transfers. The rst and
simpler of these would be the dynamic contexts considered by Jackson and Sonnenschein
(2007). They argue that repeated collective decision problems without transfers are easier
than one-shot problems because individuals can be forced to trade-o reports of their types
in one period against others. This requires a small type-space, however. A simpler way to
create inter-temporal trade-os may be to give each individual a number of tokens that may
be used in each period, similar to the storable votes of Casella (2005). Combining these with
my mechanism seems likely to yield eciency and to achieve convergence independent of the
size of the type space based on classical arguments about income eects becoming small in
each period for long-lived individuals (Bewley, 1980).
A more challenging extension would be to determine conditions under which the arguments
could be applied to a one-shot decision with a large number of alternatives. Intuitively if the
one-shot decision is just a composition of many independent decisions the logic is equivalent
10
to the dynamic case. Conditions under which such a decomposition is possible would be
interesting to explore. This might provide conditions under which a Bayesian mechanism can
soften the conclusions of the Gibbard (1973)-Satterthwaite (1975) Theorem and mechanisms
where individuals do more than report their rankings can soften Arrow (1951)s impossibility
Theorem.
I would like to relax the symmetric, independent and uni-dimensional, private values frame-
work I use. Relaxing symmetry should be straightforward as the central limit theorem I use
holds without it, but the calculations would require more care. Relaxing independence and
uni-dimensionality is a bit more challenging. I suspect that eciency would hold under some
form of lack of correlation between individuals beliefs about the probability of pivotally and
their value. Determining more primitive conditions implying this would be interesting. Relax-
ing the private values assumption is substantially more challenging and I have few intuitions
about how this might proceed at this point.
The mechanism in its current form relies on individuals reaching an estimate of the probability
of their pivotally and all sharing the same estimate. This makes it potentially vulnerable
to the Wilson (1987) critique. It may be possible to address this critique by calculating the
probability of pivotally for individuals based on the empirical distribution of other participants
reports in the spirit of the Azevedo and Budish (2011) Strategyproofness in the Large
construction. In particular, rather than choosing a number of votes individuals could report
their values and then have the number of votes purchased be determined by
g
0
u
i
2
where g
0
is computed by a bootstrap from the reported values of other individuals. It would also be
interesting to explore whether such a mechanism corresponds has a natural English auction-
like implementation. Such mechanisms would have dominant strategies in large markets, as
compared to my Bayesian solution concept.
While the mechanism seemed (at least to me) fairly novel when I rst thought of it, I now
believe it is better viewed as a formalization of common practices. In elections and committees
it is typically possible for individuals to exert more than their one vote of inuence, but the
more inuence they seek to exert the more challenging it becomes to exert a marginal unit
of inuence. I hope in a future draft to explore the relationship between the mechanism and
existing institutions more closely.
In future work, I hope to explore practical applications of the mechanism, including (eld)
experimental trials, applications to voting in elections and, perhaps more promising, to deci-
sions in the assembly of complementary goods as in my joint work with Scott Duke Kominers
(Kominers and Weyl, 2011).
11
References
Arrow, Kenneth J., Social Choice and Individual Values, New York: Wiley, 1951.
, The Property Rights Doctrine and Demand Revelation under Incomplete Information, in
Michael Boskin, ed., Economics and Human Welfare, New York: Academic Press, 1979, pp. 23
39.
Ausubel, Lawrence M. and Paul Milgrom, The Lovely but Lonely Vickery Auction, in Peter
Cramton, Richard Steinberg, and Yoav Shoham, eds., Combinatorial Auctions, Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press, 2005, pp. 1740.
Azevedo, Eduardo M. and Eric Budish, Strategyproofness in the Large as a Desideratum for
Market Design, 2011. Mimeo, Booth School of Business, University of Chicago.
Bewley, Truman F., The Permanent Income Hypothesis and Short-Run Economic Stability,
Journal of Economic Theory, 1980, 22 (3), 323333.
Carroll, Gabriel, A Quantitiative Approach to Incentives: Application to Voting Rules, 2011.
http://econ-www.mit.edu/les/7161.
Casella, Alessandra, Storable Votes, Games and Economic Behavior, 2005, 51 (2), 391419.
Clarke, Edward H., Multipart Pricing of Public Goods, Public Choice, 1971, 11 (1), 1733.
dAspremont, Claude and Louis-Andre Gerard-Varet, Incentives and Incomplete Informa-
tion, Journal of Public Economics, 1979, 11 (1), 2545.
Gibbard, Alan, Manipulation of Voting Schemes: A General Result, Econometrica, 1973, 41
(4), 587602.
Groves, Theodore, Incentives in Teams, Econometrica, 1973, 41 (4), 617631.
Hellwig, Martin F., Public-Good Provision with Many Participants, Review of Economic Stud-
ies, 2003, 70 (3), 589614.
Jackson, Matthew O. and Hugo F. Sonnenschein, Overcoming Incentive Constraints by
Linking Decisions, Econometrica, 2007, 75 (1), 241257.
Kominers, Scott Duke and E. Glen Weyl, Concordance among Holdouts, 2011.
http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract id=1591466.
Ledyard, John O. and Thomas R. Palfrey, Voting and Lottery Drafts as Ecient Public
Goods Mechanisms, Review of Economic Studies, 1994, 61 (2), 327355.
12
Satterthwaite, Mark Allen, Strategy-Proofness and Arrows Conditions: Existence and Corre-
spondence Theorems for Voting Procedures and Social Welfare Fucntions, Journal of Economic
Theory, 1975, 10 (2), 187217.
Vickrey, William, Counterspeculation, Auctions and Competitive Sealed Tenders, Journal of
Finance, 1961, 16 (1), 837.
Wilson, Robert, Game Theoretic Analysis of Trading Processes, in Truman F. Bewley, ed.,
Advances in Economic Theory, Cambridge, UK: Cabmridge University Press, 1987.
13

You might also like